Cognition and History: The Evolution of Intelligence and Culture
Cognition and History: The Evolution of Intelligence and Culture
Cognition and History: The Evolution of Intelligence and Culture
Henry Plotkin
University College London
Mailing address:
Department of Psychology
University College London
London WC1E 6BT
England
e-mail address:
henry.plotkin@ucl.ac.uk
2
qualities of the human mind that we call intelligence, and how each has influenced
the other. Human intelligence has evolved, and human evolution has been
intelligence is our unique capacity to enter into that thing we call culture. So we are
concerned here also with the evolution of culture and the way in which culture has
S.J.Gould's phrase (Gould, 1986). However, this has not always been a universally
accepted position in science. Two examples of how causes are framed in science
will illustrate different approaches to the issue of history as having causal force.
The first is that of the Russian chemist Mendeleev who invented in the middle of
3
the last century the Periodic Table of the elements, building on Dalton's earlier
proposal that each element has a characteristic atomic weight. The Periodic Table
was a brilliant insight, being based on Mendeleev's understanding that atoms have
an internal structure. It is this structure that causes elements to have the properties
upon which Mendeleev ordered the elements in his Table; and it is this structure
that enabled him correctly to predict the existence of elements, and their properties,
not then known. When later they were discovered, the Periodic Table and the
theory underpinning it was vindicated and Mendeleev's fame was ensured. Now the
point is this. The Periodic Table, a fabulously successful scientific insight, was
based on the assumption that the laws of chemistry are absolutely constant and
have always held. Had Mendeleev lived and worked 4.5 thousand million years
ago, when the Solar System formed, he could have used the same observations and
insights then to construct the Periodic table as he did in the 19th century. For
example, since the beginning of time on this planet, when the elements sodium and
chlorine have been mixed together they have formed a compound, table salt, which
has rather different properties from those of its constituent elements. This accords
with the principles upon which the Periodic table was constructed and as a 19th
century chemist, Mendeleev assumed not just that observations that he made of
table salt on Monday would be the same on Tuesday and Wednesday, but that he
could have made the same observations and drawn the same scientific insights
thousands of millions of years ago. He was correct in this, but the general
4
conclusion that was drawn that there is no temporal element to the laws of
chemistry, that time in the form of historical antecedence does not have causal
Our second example comes from Darwin, who learned from 19th century
geologists another way of thinking about causation. When Darwin visited the
unique to different islands in the group and each distinctive, especially in their
beaks and feeding behaviour. He concluded that these different species were all
sometime in the past found their way to one of the islands, the descendent species
resulting from the gradual migration of birds to other islands and the relative
isolation of the islands from one another. This explanation of Darwin's finches was
just one case, one illustration, of Darwin's wider thesis which asserts that all living
things are related because all of life forms a tree-like structure that is descended
that drive evolution, and these processes have the same quality of apparent
these processes must be present. But the nature of causal explanation of Darwinian
theory embraces historical antecedence as cause, and hence is very different from
that espoused by Medeleev. In order to understand why a finch has this beak shape
now, today, one has to invoke not only those universal and timeless processes of
5
variation, selection and the transmission of selected variants, but also the form of
evolutionary biology from the covering law model of explanation of the logical
which is the covering law, to explain the specific instances of how far golf balls
will travel when struck with equal force here on Earth or on the moon. In
form of a finch in the past is part-cause of the current form of beak; that if the past
beak form had been different, then so likely would be its current form. In
evolutionary biology, where you are coming from is a cause (not just an instance)
of where you are now. The very essence of evolutionary explanations is that history
We now understand that even the Periodic table and the laws of chemistry
that it entails have not been constant in time. Shortly after the origin of the universe
no elements existed; the elements emerged over a period of millions of years as the
universe developed. Thus, cosmologists and astrophysicists tell us that history has
causal force in chemistry too, and that with the exception of the deepest laws of
quantum theory, there is no causal constancy in the universe - 19th century science
was just fooled by the slowness of change. But evolutionary change in biological
6
occurring over just tens or hundreds of years. This is a drop in the ocean of
geological time. Much of evolutionary change does, it is true, occur over longer
periods, but nonetheless the rate of change is such that it is measurable and hence
tangible: you can put your hand on a fossil of early humans, or a stone axe, and
actually feel the historical causes that have shaped our present existence. We can't
Well, Darwin's finches are just one very, very tiny branch on the tree of life
that extends back thousands of millions of years. Another, even smaller, branch is
that of the Hominoidea, a grouping of apes within the Primate order that includes
human beings. Best present evidence, which is molecular, points to the chimpanzee
to have lived around five to six million years ago. Of significance to the issue of
happened during the period extending from the first appearance of human-like
creatures, which is usually put at about two to two and a half million years ago, to
the origins of Homo sapiens, around one hundred and fifty to two hundred and
fifty thousand years before the present. In that two million year period the human
brain doubled in absolute size and quadrupled in size relative to body mass. Over
this same period there was little or no increase in the brain size of any other species
7
short a period of evolutionary time in any other species at any time in the history
of life on Earth.
So, whatever else human beings are, we are a relatively recently evolved
species and our evolution has involved unprecedented change in the organ system
that subserves those mental capabilities that we call intelligence. If we are really
to understand the human mind then, it seems to me, we have to take into account
the evolutionary, historical, causes that shaped our minds and made them what they
are now. There has been, to some degree there still is, a reluctance on the part of
social scientists, and other scholars within the humanities, to accept that the human
mind is a product of evolution just as is the anatomy of our hands or the way in
understand how to do this and what its implications really are, but I will try here
have, that is measured by IQ tests, and which varies from individual to individual,
is not the conception of intelligence that I am considering here. There may be some
8
quality of mind that can be measured in this way, but it is an irrelevance to any
living things are localized gradients of negative entrophy, regions of order and
The only way in which such states of negative entrophy can be developed and
negative gradients. Unable to utilize the energy of the sun directly in the way that
plants are able to do, which trap solar energy within a complex chemical web, most
animals have to make contact with and feed off the energy of organisms that are
able to do this. Putting it rather abstractly, animals need to maintain some form of
matching relationship between themselves and these indirect solar energy sources,
and their principal way of doing this is by moving about in, and acting upon, the
via genes that direct nervous system wiring such that sensory inputs lead to
some of that information comes from memory stores in the brain that have been
laid down by individual learning, then the behaviour is intelligent. The internal
intelligence is probably quite ancient, first appearing some five hundred million or
more years ago. Obviously, it is not confined just to humans, and it takes many
costs and benefits must have evolved. G.C.Williams' (1966) principle of the
economy of information which asserts that living things will evolve in such a way
expression of such a trade-off. Now, because instincts cost less than learned
behaviour both in genetic and nervous system terms, and because the nervous
system is one of the most metabolically expensive tissue in our bodies, Williams'
principle tells us that there had to be powerful and pervasive forces selecting for
the evolution of intelligence. We think we know what the source of these forces
are.
The rate at which information can be acquired by a species and stored within
the gene-pool of that species is limited by the rate at which individuals can
reproduce themselves, that is, the period that extends from individual conception
These are finite periods of time that sometimes occupy significant proportions of
the average life-span of an animal. In humans it approaches one fifth of our lives.
10
Any changes in the world that occur at rates higher than this rate of generational
time cannot be detected by, and hence information about such changed conditions
cannot be incorporated into, the gene pool. If these changes are important to
survival, and many, like the spatial position of vital resources or the identity of
social allies and enemies, are, then such animals will have evolved additional,
changes in their world. In most general terms, this temporal sampling limitation of
individual intelligence in animals, and maintains it in place despite its high energy
costs.
Some Implications
argument that derives from a number of sources, which have recently been brought
together between single covers (Plotkin, 1995). This thesis on the origins of
intelligence as rooted in the need for some animals to track high rates of change
has a number of important implications, just two of which are presented here. One
is that the tabula rasa view of mind and intelligence is untenable; the other is that
genetic reductionist accounts of the evolution of any species whose individuals are
The British Empiricist philosopher, John Locke, argued that the mind is at
birth like a blank slate upon which experience writes. Hence he denied the
important part of empiricist thinking and has also had a strong following in the
associationist learning theory and of behaviourism, and it has been applied as much
to animals as humans. It has also usually had an appeal to the liberal-minded non-
scientist, suggesting as it does that humans as cognitive generalists can learn and
inadequate teaching. In the context of the age-old debate about the relative
contribution of nature and nurture to human disposition and behaviour, the tabula
rasa position is a vote for nurture and against nature. The evidence, however, tells
us that this is wrong. I will give just two examples. One comes from the study of
animals the significance of which is that what we know has been achieved with
rigorous experimentation.
We know with the certainty that experiments give that songbirds have to
hear the song of their fellow males at a certain age if they are to acquire normal,
species-typical song. What is extraordinary is that if they are exposed to the song
of another species during this song-sensitive period, they acquire neither their own
species' song nor that of their "mentor". They have to hear their own species' song
for normal song to be acquired. In other words, these are animals that come into the
12
world knowing what it is that they have to learn. This wonderful contradiction,
this paradox for any follower of Locke, is resolved by the realization that cognitive
abilities are the products of evolution. All of the processes that we tend to think of
as being in the service of nurture themselves have nature, that is, they have
coming from the genes. There are other examples from other kinds of animals,
ranging from insects like honey bees to mammals like voles, of similarly
constrained learning. As a general rule, animals learn what is good for them,
Konrad Lorenz's (1965) great insight, and that can only mean that learning is a
product of evolution.
our case, because of the limitations placed on experimentation, the evidence is less
sensitivity to human speech sounds; this rapidly narrows to the speech sounds
specific to the linguistic environment in which they are being raised; the pattern
of which of the world's five and a half thousand documented languages is being
acquired; the rate at which new words are learned is breathtaking given that it
occurs without formal tuition from caregivers or others; the same extraordinary
effortlessness marks the acquisition of syntax and grammar, which again is almost
always entirely untutored - this must be so because few adults are aware of the
13
rules governing their own language. All of this, apart from the sensitivity to speech
sound, applies as much to deaf children who are raised within a linguistic
raised to speak Dutch or Zulu. The fact that language is a human-specific learned
trait, and that its acquisition has never been explained using generalist learning
principles like those of associative learning, adds further weight to the Chomskian
view (see Pinker, 1994 for a recent review) that language is the product of an
innate organ of mind, and that learning a language is the result of a specialized,
predisposed, cognitive module. In the same sense that I applied the phrase to
songbirds, we humans come into this world knowing that language is one of the
intentional mental states to others (see Johnson and Morton, 1991; Hirschfeld and
Gelman, 1994; Sperber, Premack and Premack, 1995 for reviews). Any one of
these examples destroys the notion of the mind as a tabula rasa. But there is yet
another reason to doubt the blank slate concept. When we come into the world, it
virtually infinitely large number of ways. That is, the number of things that we
could learn from our quite limited sensory input combined with our ability to move,
is huge. We live within this vast space of things we could learn, and if our
14
cognition were not predisposed, if it did not point us into the right parts of this
massive search space, the chances of our learning the things that it is important to
know are very small indeed. This is because the tabula rasa principle says that if
you can learn anything, if the slate is really blank, why then given enough time,
you will learn everything. But you would have to be given enough time. Learning
the important things then becomes a ponderous and chance-ridden process. Yet the
very reason why it evolved was because of the need to track rapid change. Slow
and haphazard is just what cognitive processes are not because if they were they
would have little adaptive value and would not have evolved at all. We know that
in those species that have evolved intelligence, cognitive skills are indeed rapid and
economical mechanisms that fit with the general life-history style of the learner;
intelligence and instinct are closely interwoven to the point that it is not inaccurate
the point is so important it bears repeating many times, resolution of the old nature-
nurture argument comes with the understanding that nurture itself has nature. In
the correct way to think of intelligence is, first, that it is a characteristic that is
highly constrained by a species' evolutionary history; second, that the word is best
15
cognitive skills; and fourth, that neither humans, nor the members of any other
species have the capacity to learn and think about anything and everything. One
way of saying all this is that the ideal of a rational, free-thinking, human being is
course, existed but was probably not very good with mathematics, or might have
been less than skilled with his hands. Newton was good with sums but couldn't
write sonnets. And most of us are entirely ordinary in all these respects. We
humans are not general-purpose thinkers and problem-solvers who can turn our
minds to anything. We are very restricted in what it is we can learn and how we
think, yet within these limitations we are economical and effective cognitive
agents.
biological science taking over the social sciences with unstoppable reductionist
arguments and explanations, which has been with us for over a century. However,
rasa nature, tells us that such reductionist arguments could never succeed. The
counter-argument goes like this. Nature is rather clever in the way that it equips
learners with knowledge about what it is they have to know if they are to survive.
appears, for the individual, as a priori knowledge. The empiricist denial of innate
knowledge is wrong; the age-old rationalist view is closer to the truth and Kant's
notion of the a prioris is much closer to the way modern science views these
matters. (It is worth noting in passing that science can now adjudicate in such
because it is not prescient. And in doing so, it in effect passes some of the causal
creatures construct in their own minds and brains the detailed picture of the world
that their genes only hint at, crucial as those hints might be in navigating through
to the right place in knowledge space. In so doing, they construct for themselves
the causes of their own behaviour. Were this not the case, if the slate were
completely written on by genes, then we would be dealing with instinct and the
causes would reside in genes and in the developmental processes by which they are
translated into action. The fact that we do make life and death decisions concerning
who we co-operate with, which resources we exploit, where we live, how we move
through space, and with whom we choose to reproduce ourselves, all on the basis
gaining devices, means that any proper causal analysis of the evolution of species
whose individuals are intelligent has to locate some of those causes within the
17
brains and minds of those individuals. Towards the end of this lecture I will give
some specific examples. The general point being made here is that genes and
development are not enough. Social scientists and scholars of the humanities quite
simply have nothing to fear from a powerful, reductionist biology. What has
happened in molecular biology since the genetic code was unscrambled by Watson
and Crick over forty years ago has been magnificent. And I don't doubt that it will
help in developing the human sciences. But it is never, on its own, going to do the
whole job.
The image I would like to leave you with is this: the slate is not blank. Both
evidence and argument tell us it is not and cannot be so. But neither is it wholly
written upon. The temporal sampling limitation of genes requires that some part of
the slate is not filled in at birth. However, because of the operation of Williams'
principle, what space is left open for experience to fill in is the least amount Nature
will allow, and it will vary with the general life-history and life-style of a species.
Nature is forced into this delicate balance in the matter of how much must be
written on the slate, but one thing is clear. At birth, something is always written
there. We are all possessors of innate knowledge upon which we then build.
change and adjusting to it, powerful and effective as it is, nonetheless is like any
18
memories and the products of reasoning and thought, remained confined within
each individual organism for hundreds of millions of years in all but a single
species, or perhaps the species of the single genus Homo. Any population-level
effects came about only by the adaptive consequences of having the capacity for
usual route of overall individual fitness gains and reproductive success. The precise
form or content of the adaptations formed by intelligence - this food is safe, that
face is not to be associated with - could not be transmitted to others and remained
locked within each intelligent creature that had gained the information. In the
context of major evolutionary events (Szathmary and Maynard Smith, 1995), the
of life the consequences of which we are seeing unfold before us - this was the
Literally hundreds of definitions of culture have been offered over the last
150 years, which can be classified in a large number of ways (Kroeber and
Kluckholm, 1952; Keesing, 1974). Many revolve around the products of culture,
culture in ways that make for an analysis of the phenomenon in terms of processes
and mechanisms. For that reason I define culture simply as shared knowledge. If
you can share what you know with others, and are able to acquire knowledge from
others, then you are a creature capable of entering into culture. There are
documented cases of a few other species, like bees, songbirds and chimpanzees,
being able to acquire information from one another. There are, though, several
features of the human capacity for learning from others that make human culture
different from anything that birds and bees can do (Tomasello et al, 1993).
Primarily, these differences concern the way in which, pathology apart, literally
every member of the social group shares in knowledge, and that knowledge is of
many different things - linguistic, dietary, dress, and abstract beliefs amongst many
bees, while most members of a hive are able to share information about the
location of resources, that is all that is shared. The sheer astonishing richness of the
range of what humans share with one another marks culture out as different from
anything seen in any other species. A second unique feature of human culture is
Tomasello calls this the "ratchet effect". The conservation and elaboration of stone
tools over hundreds of thousands of years is one example; the growth of the form
and use of computers in the last four decades is an example of a spectacular ratchet
20
detail of shared knowledge which no other animal exhibits. What this all means is
that the richness, the precision, the range, and the durability of human cultural
knowledge is such that if one is looking for insights and understanding of culture
from biology, comparisons with other living species will not help.
event, and the reason for their choice is that with the appearance of language came,
for the first time in evolutionary history, the means of transmitting large quantities
truly is a major evolutionary event, but language cannot be the only crucial
psychological process that was necessary for culture to appear in humans, and it
does seem to me that it is culture, not just language, that is the major event, with
language being one of the necessary component processes of culture. The other
processes necessary for culture can, perhaps, be gleaned by considering one of the
constructions like money, marriage and justice. All social constructions are based
on agreement. It is only because we agree that a fifty Guilder note has sufficient
value that it can be exchanged for enough goods to make a meal, or for the
purchase of a book, that it has that value. In itself, the piece of paper has miniscule
intrinsic worth. And it is only because we agree in societies like our own that
fairness should underpin our notion of justice that our beliefs and practices with
21
regard to justice have the characteristics that they do. The notion of fairness as
biochemistry and present in all humans. Some cultures have quite different social
is what it is in Holland or England because we agree that it should be so, and for
no other reason. Put simply, some things exist only because we all agree to think
that they exist. Parenthetically, some biologists are sceptical about the existence
of social constructions and suggest that they are part of the mythology of the social
sciences. This is a curious stance to take because it is manifestly the case that
social constructions have real causal force. People live in the manner that they do,
and die as they do, often in large numbers in wars, because of them.
Now, language alone cannot explain social constructions. I agree with Searle
function cannot be performed solely in virtue of the sheer physical features of the
phenomenon" (Searle, 1995 pp 228). The power of money does not lie in the coin,
nor that of justice in the buildings that house our courts or the people that operate
the system. "Collective intentionality" is where the power lies, and this is a very
difficult thing to explain. In the last 18 years or so, centre stage in developmental
understanding that other people have minds as well as ourselves. We now know
22
something of the way in which children come to understand that intentional mental
states like wanting and knowing exist in the minds of others; and we have also
come to understand the catastrophic consequences for normal social function when
the ability to attribute mental states to others fails to develop. We now believe that
Although the phrase theory of mind was first used in a classic paper with regard to
any other species is able to attribute intentional mental states to other indiviuals.
It is, like language, a human-specific characteristic, and it must have a crucial role
that the capacity for attributing mental states to others is a necessary prerequisite
for the capacity to recognize that one's own mental states match those of others.
The kind of agreement that social constructions require can only come into being
has been known to social psychologists for many years. Social forces such as
conformity, obedience and cohesiveness are known to operate with real causal
effect to establish or shift intentional states, and the direction of shift is usually
towards some social norm, towards an agreed or "collective" intentional state. The
23
classic studies are those of Muzafer Sherif, which were carried out in the 1930s.
social force, were the elements necessary for the appearance of human culture.
states and values on matters that relate in large part to the existence and continuing
this is another reason for believing that biologists armed with reductionist strategies
cannot succeed in explaining the social sciences. It must be added for those who
are knowledgeable about the problems raised in the past for the notion of group
selection by evolutionary theory that there is now an increasing acceptance that the
of information at times rather than language. This is a caution born of our not
knowing, and perhaps we will never know, the order in which these essential
There are some experts on human evolution, for example Tobias (1995), who
advocate the view that a form of language may even have existed in our
hominid evolution some four to five million years ago, and certainly existed in
24
Homo habilis, the earliest known species of the genus to which modern humans
belong; and others, for example Lieberman (1984) who believe that language first
appeared when Homo sapiens evolved, in the region of two hundred thousand
years before the present. Yet even if Lieberman is correct, two hundred thousand
years is a long time. Nobody suggests that human language appeared suddenly and
and intensity. It must have evolved alongside imitation and mimesis and would
have formed, across a not insignificant period of time and many generations, an
hands, ears and eyes. Entangled somewhere within this complexly evolving set of
communication skills is the cognitive module that allows the attribution of mental
states to others. It is likely that developmental studies will tell us more about the
dependencies of language, imitation and theory of mind, and give us some glimpse
into the evolution of the human capacity for culture, but I would not hold my breath
on it. Lacking any evidence from other existing species, I suspect that these are
I want here to flesh out the argument presented earlier that genetic-
literally, untenable. The argument, remember, is that the evolution of the cognitive
modules; and that if intelligence has had a causal role in the evolution of our, and
others, species, then the argument has to be extended. Reductionist accounts of the
evolution of intelligent species are no more tenable than are reductionist accounts
intelligence affects survival and reproduction, then that intelligence is one of the
causes of the changing gene frequencies in that species, which means that
evolution a much more dynamic and complex process. The history of this kind of
approach is to be found in Richards (1987) and Plotkin (1988a), and the details of
evidence and theory in Laland (1992) and Plotkin (1988b). Here I will offer just a
1983). In broad terms, imprinting refers to the way in which exposure to particular
individuals affects later choice of mating partner. Imprinting is not an absolute and
imprinting looks like other forms of learning in occurring repeatedly and hence in
affects what genes are propagated and in what combinations than does mating
a direct causal fashion into the determination of the genetic constitution of sexually
reproducing species that imprint. Here is a form of learning that does indeed have
causal force in evolution. The same argument can be run for birdsong, which we
know is learned and which has been shown to affect subsequent mating behaviour
The conclusion is stark and simple. In some species there is clear evidence
that intelligence is one of the causes of evolution. Does this apply to our own
trait that derives from certain human-specific cognitive characteristics. The causal
the notion that cultural injunction constrains human mate choice; yet few social
scientists are comfortable with following through on the implications of this - that
mating, which have been causal forces in human evolution. In this sense, it is the
27
social scientists who should and must intrude into the biological sciences.
There are other examples apart from reproductive behaviour. The case of
lactose tolerance and intolerance is becoming famous for the way it demonstrates
the interweaving of culture and biology (Durham, 1991). Approximately two thirds
of all people in the world have varying degrees of difficulty in digesting lactose,
a sugar found in mammalian milk. Prior to weaning, the enzymes that allow lactose
absorption are present in the alimentary tracts of all people. Around the time of
weaning these levels decline in most people, and the illness that results from
drinking milk in those who are lactose intolerant can be severe - in the nutritionally
stressed, or those suffering from other illnesses, it can be fatal. Most people from
Africa and south and east Asia are lactose intolerant, whereas 95% of
gradient in the ability to absorb lactose, being high in the north and declining to the
south and east. Correlating with this gradient are customs of milk and milk product
unprocessed milk and its products like cream which are lactose rich, whereas as
one moves towards the Levant, processed milk products like yogurt and kefir,
which have greatly reduced lactose levels, become common. Accompanying the
dietary and food preparation practices are culturally propagated myths about milk
consumption, such as it being the food of the gods. It is now widely accepted that
lactose tolerance is caused by a mutant gene which became fixated at high levels
28
in populations that combined high nutritional stress with vitamin D deficiency, the
latter being prevalent amongst people who live in regions of low sunlight levels
(unless they have other components of their diet that make good this deficiency,
but this is a detail of a much more complicated story than there is space for here).
through their ability to consume milk without it making them ill, and so the mutant
gene was strongly selected for in certain populations; however, the important point
is that the engine driving this evolutionary event was not the mutant gene but the
invention and propagation of animal husbandry and dairying practices, part of the
evolution.
The final example of how human intelligence and culture might have
affected human evolution is rather more tentative, but no less fascinating for that.
Earlier I mentioned the doubling (or quadrupling in relative terms) of brain size
during human evolution. In fact, the increase has not occurred gradually and
smoothly. There have been periods of relatively rapid expansion in brain size and
longer periods of stasis. One of the periods of most rapid increase occurred in the
middle Pleistocene epoch, around six to seven hundred thousand years ago, and it
coincides with evidence for the first use of fire in food preparation. The
spread and became commonplace amongst archaic humans, and it could only have
done so by cultural innovation and transmission, so the need for the large digestive
systems that characterize the great apes was reduced. Earlier in human evolution,
the switch to high energy foods, notably meat consumption in quantity, coincided
with another period of accelerated increase in brain size. What links these two
organ systems, brain and gut, is that they are the metabolically most expensive
organ systems in our bodies. Raise dietary quality or invent cooking and gut size
can be reduced allowing brain size to increase. The controlled use of fire was
a landmark event in human evolution. It is most likely that the practise spread
culturally, and if Aiello and Wheeler are correct, then this is an exquisite example
Many other examples, drawn from warfare, genocide, science and medicine, would
drives on the process of evolution. It brings to mind the image of a complex causal
dance in time in which effects become the causes of effects which themselves
become causes. To social historians who study the causes and consequences of
kind of image is, I should imagine, a familiar one. You people have always known
that history matters. I hope that I have shown you that an extension of that view to
understanding ourselves, and demonstrates how links can be forged between the
A footnote
Institute of Social History who have given me the opportunity to present this
September 1996
References
Aiello, L.C. and Wheeler, P. (1996) "The expensive-tissue hypothesis: the brain
and the digestive system in human and primate evolution." Current Anthropology
36, 199-221.
Bateson, P.P.G. ed. (1983) Mate Choice. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
31
Gould, S.J. (1986) "Evolution and the triumph of homology, or why history
matters." American Scientist 74, 60-69.
Hirschfeld, L.A. and Gelman, S.A. eds. (1994) Mapping the Mind: Domain
Specificity in Cognition and Culture. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
Johnson, M.H. and Morton, J. (1991) Biology and Cognitive Development: The
Case of Face Recognition. Oxford, Blackwell.
Kroeber, A.L. and Kluckholm, C. (1952) "Culture: a critical review of the concepts
and definitions." Papers of the Peabody Museum of American Archaeology and
Ethnology 47, 1-223.
Plotkin, H.C. (1988a) "Behaviour and Evolution." In H.C.Plotkin (ed) The Role
of Behaviour in Evolution. Cambridge Mass., MIT Press. pp 1-17.
Plotkin, H.C. (1988b) "Learning and Evolution." In H.C.Plotkin (ed) The Role of
Behaviour in Evolution. Cambridge Mass., MIT Press. pp 131-164.
Plotkin, H.C. (1995) Darwin Machines and the Nature of Knowledge. London,
Penguin Books.
32
Searle, J.R. (1995) The Construction of Social Reality. London, Allen Lane.
Tobias, Ph.V. (1995) "The communication of the dead: earliest vestiges of the
origin of articulate language." Seventiende Kroon-Voordracht. Amsterdam,
Nedelands Museum voor Anthropologie en Praehistorie.
Tomasello, M., Kruger, A.L. and Ratner, H.H. (1993) "Cultural Learning." The
Behavioural and Brain Sciences 16, 495-511.
Wilson, D.S. and Sober, E. (1994) "Reintroducing group selection to the human
behavioural sciences." The Behavioural and Brain Sciences 17, 585-608.