Franz Steiner Verlag ARSP: Archiv Für Rechts-Und Sozialphilosophie / Archives For Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy
Franz Steiner Verlag ARSP: Archiv Für Rechts-Und Sozialphilosophie / Archives For Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy
Franz Steiner Verlag ARSP: Archiv Für Rechts-Und Sozialphilosophie / Archives For Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Franz Steiner Verlag is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
ARSP: Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie / Archives for Philosophy of Law and
Social Philosophy
This content downloaded from 152.118.24.10 on Mon, 20 May 2019 12:45:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Jan-R. Sieckmann, Bamberg/Buenos Aires
Abstract: This paper aims at reconstructing Radbruch's relativistic conception of law within the
framework of a model of principies. The idea of relativism remains a disputed issue in current legal
and moral philosophy. In spite of the fact that Radbruch's legal philosophy lacks cohérence, it includes
elements that resemble modem conceptions of law as a System including principies to be balanced
against each other. Therefore, a reconstruction within a model of principies might as well prove the
fruitfulness of the model of principies as render a more appropriate theoretical framework for Rad
bruch's legal philosophy. After an outline of Radbruch's relativism, I will discuss some critical points
of his approach and, subsequently, présent a reconstruction according to the model of principies,
which makes plausible at least some of Radbruch's contentions.
I. Introduction
Ethical relativism Claims to offer a third way between moral objectivism and moral
scepticism, suggesting that différent agents may correctly hold incompatible normative
views.1 Although this might well describe the seemingly irresolvable disagreements that
entangle normative discourse, the cohérence of ethical relativism is contested. In which
sense can one claim a normative view to be correct and at the same time concede that
incompatible views may be correct as well? By holding a normative view one excludes
incompatible alternatives. Stating that, for example, one should pay one's debts, but
admitting that this is merely a personal view and anyone eise may think differently on
this matter, appears to be irrational, for one obviously lacks sufficient reasons for mak
ing this Statement.2 At least, it remains unclear what such a statement means.
The phenomenon of persistent disagreement on ethical or normative issues is a
central problem of current legal and moral philosophy. For example, the "fact of plural
ism" is a central concern of the political philosophy of John Rawls.3 Ronald Dworkin
emphasizes that normative assertions carry claims to objective validity, but déniés that
this claim could have an epistemic or metaphysical foundation.4 Robert Alexy suggests
in his theory of discourse that ail discursively possible solutions are correct, although
they might be incompatible with each other.5 Richard Rorty rejects ail claims to cor
rectness of normative discourse,6 thus denying even the présupposions of ethical
relativism.7 Ail these approaches struggle with the problem of which epistemic status
normative claims have, and relativism might provide an answer.
More precisely, this expresses a meta-ethical relativism, not to be confused with normative or evalua
tive relativism suggesting that ail normative views are equally valid, or descriptive relativism suggest
ing that norms are not universally valid but differ according to context or culture. On various forms of
relativism in general Bayon 1991, 210.
Cf. Bayon 1991, 211, regarding what he calis „internalism".
Rawls 1995, 146
Dworkin 1996, 87pp. Interpreting Dworkin in terms of relativism, Rodríguez-Blanco 2004, 153p.
Alexy 1983, 256; id. 1995, 110, 121
Rorty 1989, 53, 73. Cf. Veitch 1999, 32
Cf. Veitch 1999, 33
This content downloaded from 152.118.24.10 on Mon, 20 May 2019 12:45:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Reconstructing Relativism 15
This content downloaded from 152.118.24.10 on Mon, 20 May 2019 12:45:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
16 Jan-R. Sieckmann
The method of relativism implies that the correctness of value judgements can only be
determined in relation to other value judgements, within the framework of a particular
"Weltanschauung", but not regarding the value judgement as such. (Radbruch 1950,
57; 1932, 17)
"The method which is here presented is called relativism, because its task is to determine
only whether any value judgment is right in relation to a particular suprême value judgment,
within a particular outlook on values and the world, but not whether that value judgment and
that outlook on values and the world are right in and of themselves." (Radbruch 1950, 57)
On the basis of his relativism, Radbruch rejects natural law and justifies legal positivism.
Radbruch claims that law must serve the idea of law, that is, justice, but the content
of justice cannot be discerned, as it dépends on contested assumptions about the
purposes of law, and moreover can conflict with requirements of legal certainty and
This content downloaded from 152.118.24.10 on Mon, 20 May 2019 12:45:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Reconstructing Relativism 17
According to Radbruch, if one cannot determine what is just, it must be decided what shall be legal. This
must be done by an institution that is able to enforce what it will determine as law.Thus, the positivity of
law itself becomes a presupposition of the correctness of law (Radbruch 1950,108; 1932, 73f.; cf. also
1932, 82; 1950,117). Accordingly, the factual validity or effectiveness of law becomes a criterion for its
validity.
The principies of justice, legal certainty, and expediency are relevant in determining what the law is.
Radbruch rejects the idea of a division of labour between them, which restricts and demarcates the
scope of application of these principies. Although the aim of justice determines whether a prescription
is to be qualified as law at ail, whether it conforms to the concept of law, all three principies decide upon
the content of law (Radbruch 1950,110; 1932, 76). Therefore, the validity of unjust and wrang positive
law cannot be asserted without qualification. The issue of validity is capable of being judged not only from
the perspective of legal security, but also from the point of view of justice and of expediency (Radbruch
1950, 111; 1932, 77). Radbruch concludes that all three sides of the idea of law jointly domínate the
law in all its extensions, although they may get into Sharp conflict with each other (Radbruch 1950,111 ;
1932, 77).
This content downloaded from 152.118.24.10 on Mon, 20 May 2019 12:45:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
18 Jan-R. Sieckmann
III. Discussion
Accordingly, there is not only one type of relativism, but one must distinguish various
aspects.22 Although Radbruch embraces also cultural relativism, of central importance
for his theory is epistemological relativism with regard to norms and values. This is a
form of metaethical relativism. However, it is not clear how it differs from scepticism.The
différence to scepticism follows from the further thesis that normative judgements may
be made even though they cannot be objectively justified. Thus results the meta-ethical
relativism suggesting that differing normative judgements may all be correct.
This content downloaded from 152.118.24.10 on Mon, 20 May 2019 12:45:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Reconstructing Relativism 19
The problem of relativism is how one can rationally make evaluative statements whil
acknowledging that those judgements cannot be objectively justified.23 A statemen
includes the claim that the stated sentence is true. It seems to be irrational to make a
claim to validity of a statement that one cannot justify.
Even if one disregards the issue of truth, a problem of the relativized statement is
whether it can be normative. One might understand relative ethical judgements as a
pure description of an individual's opinion, but as such it would not carry any normative
claim and be useless for a normative theory of law. The point of Radbruch of interest
here is, however, to carry on with normative claims in spite of ethical relativism. To
profess ultímate values is not only a description of one's own opinion, but is meant to
be a contribution to moral or legal discourse. However, one cannot make normative
claims without at least attempting to justify them. But Radbruch's relativism seems to
exclude this.
Radbruch regards relativism as the foundation of the validity of positive law. If a nor
could without doubt be recognized as unjust or incorrect its legal validity could not
be justified. However, it is not clear how on the basis of relativism the validity of la
could be established. This cannot follow directly from a metaethical relativism.24 Als
it is not clear why relativism should be a décisive argument in favour of the validity
positive law.
The structure of Radbruch's argument is to treat legal certainty as a second order
value that decides a conflict of first order values, but is not involved in this conflict.25
However, one cannot isolate second order arguments from the conflicting first order
arguments. If positive law enforces one of several ethical positions in dispute, it conflicts
with those positions it sets back.This is just another conflict of normative positions that
needs to be solved. There is no reason to believe that positive law itself provides the
solution. For example, if human rights are in dispute and positive law decides against
This content downloaded from 152.118.24.10 on Mon, 20 May 2019 12:45:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
20 Jan-R. Sieckmann
4. The Scope of Re
Notwithstanding his
about law. These ref
legal certainty and t
cipies of the constit
democracy.26 Accordi
uses relativism as a h
characterizes his posi
207) as close to that o
ism became fashionab
his legal philosophy
and more from exist
than the récognition t
justification, and that
Relativist elements are included also in the doctrine of antinomies of the idea of law,
suggesting that justice, legal security, and expediency (Zweckmäßigkeit) conflict with
each other (Radbruch 1950, 109; 1932, 74). In case of a conflict between the ideas
of law the conflict can only be resolved by the decisión of individual conscience (Rad
bruch 1950, 118; 1932, 84). Radbruch assumes that relativist elements are not only
to be found in issues of expediency but also regarding the ranking of these elements
in relation to each other. Thus, Radbruch acknowledges the necessity of the balancing
of values but denies that a solution to value conflicts may be objectively valid.28
Accordingly, Radbruch denies that the antinomies between legal values (justice, legal
certainty, expediency) or between the various doctrines of the purposes of law can be
decided rationally. However, regarding the conflict between justice and legal certainty
he himself presented solutions, in his "Rechtsphilosophie" in favour of legal certainty,
later, in the famous "formula" of Radbruch, a restricted priority of legal certainty as far
as the déviation of positive law from justice does not reach an intolerable degree. One
may ask which status these theses should have, if there is no rational solution to the
conflict? Obviously, Radbruch regarded them more than mere professions.29
This content downloaded from 152.118.24.10 on Mon, 20 May 2019 12:45:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Reconstructing Relativism 21
IV. Reconstruction
The problems of Radbruch's relativistic conception of law ask for some clarification.The
aim of my analysis is a reconstruction of this conception within the model of principies
that is, a conception of law and morality based on the idea of principies that - in case
of conflict - figure as normative arguments to be balanced against each other, and the
method of balancing such principies.30 A basic hypothesis of this reconstruction wil
be that Radbruch's relativism results from his awareness of value conflicts within the
law, and that this brings his conception of law close to the model of principies of law.
Thus, one might regard Radbruch a predecessor of the model of principies, however,
without the conception of principies and a method of rational balancing. Nevertheless,
the reconstruction of his relativistic account of law in the framework of the model of
principie might provide a better foundation of Radbruch's views and, on the other hand,
preserve valuable insights of Radbruch for the current philosophical discussion.
The central features of the model of principies are the logical distinction of principies
and definitive norms and the détermination of which norms are definitively valid by
means of balancing principies. This model, as understood here,31 includes the follow
ing theses.
(1 ) The distinction of normative arguments and normative statements: Normative argu
ments include requirements of which norm should be accepted as definitively valid,
whereas normative statements include assertions of which norms are definitively
valid.32
(2) The two-level-structure of law: Law includes not only definitively valid norms but
also principies that have the character of normative arguments.33
This content downloaded from 152.118.24.10 on Mon, 20 May 2019 12:45:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
22 Jan-R. Sieckmann
2. Radbruch's Relativ
Radbruch's conceptio
as outlined above, alt
Firstly, in Radbruch'
the one hand, legal id
This corresponds to
not use the distinctio
normative argument
have common charac
do not have directly
are, according to Rad
according to the mod
There is a différenc
ancing, requiring a c
neo-Kantian legal phi
justice belongs to the
criticizes Stammler's
of positive law.39 Th
ture of law. Law is n
suggests that legal va
Radbruch, moreover
positive law. Whatev
to strive for realizin
This content downloaded from 152.118.24.10 on Mon, 20 May 2019 12:45:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Reconstrucling Relativism 23
3. Restatement of Radbruch's Re
(1) Idea of law and legal principies: Radbruch's thesis that law must attempt to realize
the idea of law, which includes justice, but also legal certainty and expediency, may
be restated as the thesis that legal Systems include legal principies. Some of them
are conceptually necessary, namely the principies of justice and of legal certainty. The
This content downloaded from 152.118.24.10 on Mon, 20 May 2019 12:45:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
24 Jan-R. Sieckmann
principie of justice in
principies, which be
contingent and are l
confers legal validity
This content downloaded from 152.118.24.10 on Mon, 20 May 2019 12:45:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Reconstructing Relativism 25
V. Conclusion
This content downloaded from 152.118.24.10 on Mon, 20 May 2019 12:45:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
26 Jan-R. Sieckmann
The reconstruction s
dation. Radbruch sho
this philosophy in a su
features of law, in pa
presented a very mod
The reconstruction a
of this model does no
its basic structure in
certain problems of l
fact that Radbruch st
indeed présents an ad
Bibliography
Adachi, Hidehiko (2
tsphilosophie Gusta
Alexy, Robert (1985),
of Constitutional Rig
- (1994), Theorie der
of the 1. ed.: A Theo
- (1995), Probleme de
furt/M. 1995, 109-12
Bayon, Juan Carlos
para la acción, Cent
Besson, Samantha (2
the Law, Oxford/Po
Binder, Julius (1925)
Dreier, Ralf (1999),
(1999), 497-509
Dreier, Ralf/Paulson,
in: Gustav Radbruc
Paulson., 2. ed., He
Dworkin, Ronald (197
- (1996), Objectivity
fairs 25, 87-139
Jansen, Nils (1998), D
Kaufmann, Erich (1
1921
Klug, Ulrich (1968), Thesen zu einem kritischen Relativismus in der Rechtsphilosophie,
in: Gedächtnisschrift für Gustav Radbruch, hg. v. A. Kaufmann, Göttingen 1968,
103-106
Kriele, Martin (1963), Kriterien der Gerechtigkeit, Berlin 1963
Meyer, Lukas H. (2002), "Gesetzen ihrer Ungerechtigkeit wegen die Geltung a
sprechen". Gustav Radbruch und der Relativismus, in: R. Alexy/L.H. Meyer/S
Paulson/G. Sprenger (Hg.), Neukantianismus und Rechtsphilosophie, Baden-Baden
2002,319-361
Lohmann, Wolfgang (1964), Versuch einer methodologischen Erörterung der Rad
bruchschen Rechtsphilosophie, Diss. Tübingen, 1964
This content downloaded from 152.118.24.10 on Mon, 20 May 2019 12:45:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Reconstructing Relativism 27
Anschrift des Autors: Prof. Dr. Jan-R. Sieckmann, Otto-Friedrich-Üniversität Bamberg, Fakultät Sozial- und Wirtschafts
wissenschaften, Feldkirchenstraße 21, D-96045 Bamberg
This content downloaded from 152.118.24.10 on Mon, 20 May 2019 12:45:51 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms