(1986) Cottingham - Partiality, Favouritism and Morality
(1986) Cottingham - Partiality, Favouritism and Morality
(1986) Cottingham - Partiality, Favouritism and Morality
Andrews
Scots Philosophical Association
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
This content downloaded from 129.100.253.85 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 16:56:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 36 No. 144
ISSN 0031-8094 $2.00
BY JOHN COTTINGHAM
This content downloaded from 129.100.253.85 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 16:56:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
358 JOHN COTTINGHAM
But what exactly is meant by the vague phrase 'one's own'? The phr
implies that those picked out for special treatment are specified not in
of some descriptive (and therefore universalizable) quality or feature
they possess, but in terms of some particular relationship which they
the agent. Thus, in the fire case, my decision to favour my child is b
3 This (erroneous) impression was given by the exclusive focus on "public" exam
Cottingham, op. cit., p. 96.
This content downloaded from 129.100.253.85 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 16:56:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
PARTIALITY, FAVOURITISM AND MORALITY 359
This content downloaded from 129.100.253.85 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 16:56:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
360 JOHN COTTINGHAM
(4) Patriotism
(5) Racism
(6) Sexism
(7) Planetism (S favours X because X is a creature from S's own
planet.)
The final item in the above list belongs in the realm of science fiction, but in
a futuristic setting one might imagine having to make a choice between an
earthman and a creature such as one of Asimov's "Chloros" - repulsive
looking creatures who have stalk-heads (their brains are in their abdomens)
and breathe chlorine gas, but who are intelligent, sensitive and respectful of
others, and thus from an impartial standpoint as worthy of moral considera-
tion as we are. In Asimov's story, an Earth-patriot known as Colonel
Windham displays unashamedly "planetist" behaviour. He has little time for
"the blasted green fellas", and when a member of his party agrees to mount
an attack on them, hails him as a fellow patriot: "Dash it, let me shake your
hand. I like you. You're an Earthman, by heaven. Do this and, win or die, I'll
bear witness for you."4
Even planetism does not exhaust the scope of ever widening partialisms.
One could presumably imagine "galaxism" - the policy of giving preferential
treatment to members of one's own galaxy. Or one could go even wider. A
well known joke-button worn at astronomy conferences reads 'Support your
local group'. The term refers not to some particular faction of astronomy
departments, but to what astronomers, with mind-numbing matter-of-
factness, refer to as our "local" group of galaxies (the group to which our
own Milky Way galaxy and the Andromeda galaxy belong).
In the above list of partialisms, racism is the "leading" term: it controls the
dynamic of our moral response, functioning as a paradigm of moral inde-
fensibility. It is striking, for example, that the liberation movements of recent
history - the Women's Movement and the Animal Rights Movement - have
been able to exert great pressure by comparing the male chauvinist and the
speciesist with the racist. The central argument of the liberationists here is
that for me to favour X over Y just because he's one of "my lot" (my gender,
my species, my race), is, in the absence of some further morally relevant
difference between X and Y, a piece of purely arbitrary, and hence improper,
discrimination. The case of patriotism at first sight seems rather different
from that of speciesism and sexism. For one thing, the two latter "isms" have
never in the past been regarded as virtues; the terms were coined to denote
unconscious, or at least unreflective, patterns of conduct which had largely
gone unchallenged. To challenge them, to exhibit them as cases of arbitrary
discrimination, was eo ipso to expose them as vices. 'Patriotism', by contrast,
This content downloaded from 129.100.253.85 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 16:56:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
PARTIALITY, FAVOURITISM AND MORALITY 361
TWO STRATEGIES
5 See, for example, J. Glover, Causing Death and Saving Lives (Harmondsworth,
and P. Singer Practical Ethics (Cambridge, 1979) chs. 1, 2.
6 Oldenquist, op. cit., p. 186.
This content downloaded from 129.100.253.85 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 16:56:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
362 JOHN COTTINGHAM
This content downloaded from 129.100.253.85 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 16:56:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
PARTIALITY, FAVOURITISM AND MORALITY 363
This content downloaded from 129.100.253.85 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 16:56:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
364 JOHN COTTINGHAM
AGENT-RELATED PARTIALISM
This content downloaded from 129.100.253.85 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 16:56:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
PARTIALITY, FAVOURITISM AND MORALITY 365
This content downloaded from 129.100.253.85 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 16:56:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
366 JOHN COTTINGHAM
SELF-DIRECTED PARTIALISM
This content downloaded from 129.100.253.85 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 16:56:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
PARTIALITY, FAVOURITISM AND MORALITY 367
that natural and perfectly proper sense of special concern and regard for
oneself that is essential to human flourishing."
The second point to be made about self-favouritism is that some degree of
self-directed partiality is so deeply ingrained into the psychological make-up
of most of us that it is not easy to see how any ethic which outlawed it
completely could survive. How many times does each of us, every day, give
special preferential attention to his own private interests? Consider the cost,
in terms of time and resources, merely of our everyday recreational and
leisure activities. If we weighed our own interests no higher than anyone
else's, could we justify such activities? From a strictly impartial standpoint
would not these resources be better devoted to more deserving or more
needy recipients? If the impartialist replies that indeed we should eliminate
such self-favouring uses of time and resources, then he would seem to be
proposing what Mackie called a "fantasy" ethic - an ethic which people may
pay lip service to as a shining ideal, but which they do not and will never in
practice subscribe to, in the sense of incorporating it into their actual strategy
for living.12
The third point to be made about self-favouritism is that it may well have a
valuable role to play in the promotion of non-self-interested goals. For most
of us, it is very difficult to embark wholeheartedly on some committed course
of action unless the chosen project, either in its fulfilment, or in the progress
towards it, involves at least some element of personal enrichment. It is
important not to misunderstand this point by interpreting it as a piece of
cynicism. Clearly people can and do "devote their lives to the cause" without
its being the case that the cause necessarily involves some reference to their
own interests. But experience suggests that continuing devotion to the cause
is nearly always accompanied by some degree of what may loosely be called
'ego-satisfaction'. Thus the Christian works to promote the Kingdom of
God not just because of an impersonal recognition that this is a morally
desirable goal, but also because he finds, or expects to find, that he can "live
life more abundantly" as a result. Again, devotees of revolutionary causes
characteristically report that their own lives are enriched or given meaning by
the struggle on which they have embarked. From a historical perspective
there seems little doubt that ego-satisfaction is the motor that has powered
most moral projects, irrespective of whether the projects themselves have a
self-directed content. So it seems possible that a further defence of self-
directed partiality may be developed by reference to the thought that even
the most worthy ideal is unlikely to gain many adherents or to progress very
This content downloaded from 129.100.253.85 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 16:56:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
368 JOHN COTTINGHAM
PHILOPHILIC PARTIALISM
This content downloaded from 129.100.253.85 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 16:56:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
PARTIALITY, FAVOURITISM AND MORALITY 369
people are easier to live with). All genuine love, then, is altruistic; but it also
has a non-eliminably self-referential aspect. As we noted earlier (p. 359), the
reason for showing partiality to one's own children is not that they possess
some universalizable feature or set of features that merit special recognition
(otherwise we would not have an example of partialism but of impartial
evaluation); rather, a parent should give extra (again: extra, not infinite)
weight to his children's interests precisely because they are his. And the
same goes for relationships with wives, husbands, brothers, sisters, close
friends and lovers, and for other relationships involving what has been called
"self-referential altruism".'4 In each case the partiality is exercised towards
the philos, the loved-one, precisely in virtue of the special relationship which
the loved one has to the agent. (Interestingly, Aristotle calls the philos an allos
autos, a "second self', implying that the agent exercises the same kind of
special concern towards the loved one as he does towards himself).'5
Now the principle of philophilic partiality cannot be regarded simply as a
case of arbitrary or capricious favouritism. Its ethical plausibility flows from
the fact that genuine love finds a place in almost all viable blueprints for
human welfare. Special concern towards particular human beings is essential
to the functioning of those close relationships which the overwhelming mass
of mankind seek as a major source of psychological enrichment. And if such
concern has a successful outcome, so that the agent is able to witness the
flourishing of the loved one, and if, further, it is reciprocated, so that the
parties are bound together in mutual ties of affection, then the resulting
situation constitutes what is one of the principal satisfactions of human life.
The justification of philophilic partialism is thus extremely simple. If I give
no extra weight to the fact that this is my lover, my friend, my spouse, my
child, if I assess these people's needs purely on their merits (in such a way as
an impartial observer might do), then that special concern which constitutes
the essence of love and friendship will be eliminated. Partiality to loved ones
is justified because it is an essential ingredient in one of the highest of
human goods.
A natural question to raise by way of a footnote to the above argument is
whether it rests on some supposed conceptual truth about what it is to be a
human being, or simply on a psychological generalisation about the way most
humans are constituted. A decisive objection to resting the argument on a
supposed conceptual truth is that clearly there have been human beings
(hermits, wandering friars, and so on) who have managed to live without the
ties of special affection. Such non-philophilic lives, particularly when they
are devoted to some worthy end (helping the poor, tending the sick) are
regarded as morally praiseworthy. So philophilic partiality evidently cannot
14 J. Mackie, op. cit., p. 132.
15 Nicomachean Ethics 1166 a32.
This content downloaded from 129.100.253.85 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 16:56:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
370 JOHN COTTINGHAM
OTHER PARTIALISMS
This content downloaded from 129.100.253.85 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 16:56:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
PARTIALITY, FAVOURITISM AND MORALITY 371
This content downloaded from 129.100.253.85 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 16:56:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
372 JOHN COTTINGHAM
16 I avoid any general comments on speciesism since this has been extensively discussed in
recent literature, and raises special issues that are beyond the scope of this paper.
17 For a development of this point in connection with urban "alienation", cf. Oldenquist,
op. cit., pp. 187ff.
This content downloaded from 129.100.253.85 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 16:56:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
PARTIALITY, FAVOURITISM AND MORALITY 373
University of Reading
This content downloaded from 129.100.253.85 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 16:56:52 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms