Theoretical Responses To Navajo Questions: B.A. Brandeis University
Theoretical Responses To Navajo Questions: B.A. Brandeis University
Theoretical Responses To Navajo Questions: B.A. Brandeis University
by
DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF
PHILOSOPHY
at the
MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF
TECHNOLOGY
June, 1975
Signature of Author...........................-.....---
Department of Foreign Literature & Linguistics
April 23, 1975
Certified b.............--...--.----..-----.
Thesis Supervisor
ARCHIVEr
gs INST.
JUN 30 1975
&.I8RARI e
To Jay,
by
ABSTRACT
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
This author, in turn, benefited not only by completing a thesis, but also
debts are deeply felt personal ones as well, none more so than to Ken Hale.
As advisor, scholar of both linguistics and Navajo, teacher and friend, his
dedication, even at the expense of his own research and tranquility, was as
For the Navajo consultants who made this project possible I offer
the sincere hope that its findings will in some small measure repay their
cooperation. Special thanks and credit are owed to Lorraine Honie who
Begay and Linda Platero for their long hours, friendship and insightfulness
which truly made this thesis a combined effort. I am also very grateful to
and assistance.
Noam Chomsky who gave most generously of his time and expertise
provided invaluable insights and challenges. He, Ken Hale and Dave Perl-
goes also to our chairman Morris Halle whose dedication touches all
Erteschik, Jorge Hankamer, Jim Kari, Jan Koster, Susumo Kuno, Paul Platero,
Marga Reis, and Haj Ross go sincerest thanks for comments, critiques and
and Yvonne Bordelois are owed not only credit for significant enhancement
but also my thanks for their warm friendship and bravery in the face of my
for a summer research grant, and to the faculty at M.I.T. for its finan-
cial support under N.I.H. grant 5T01 HDO0111 and N.I.M.H. grant 5P01
MH13390.
my parents whose love and stimulation began it all goes an equal measure
smiles made these last eight months so very special goes a promise of
the long summer walks that the busy winter precluded. To Waffle I offer
thanks for cuddling so very closely when the going got rough. And to Jay
goes the greatest measure of love and thanks for sustaining me throughout.
His loving, encouraging, cheering, prodding and editing surely made this
dissertation possible.
6
TABLE OF CONTENTS
Page
INTRODUCTION ....................................................... 11
Page
1.2.2 Insufficiencies of the Relative Clause
Explanation ...................................... 60
1.2.3 EP's As Relative Clause Heads ........................63
1.2.4 The Inability of the Relative Clause Explanation
to Replace Movement .............................. 66
1.2.5 Recapitulation ..................................... 68
Page
2.4.5 Arguing From Negatives ...................... 179
2.4.6 Arguing From Second Position ................ 181
2.4.7 Topicalization and Unbounded Movement ....... 183
2.4.8 Speculations: The Genesis of the Movement .. 184
2.4.9 Speculations: Why So Confusing? ............ 185
2.4.10 Speculations About Case (4) ................. 190
2.4.11 Question Particle Placement ................. 192
Page
3.3 Are /-go/ and /-i/ Clauses Semantically Identical? ......... 240
3.3.1 Differentiating /-go/ and /-I/ ...................... 240
3.3.2 The Semantics of /-/ ......................... 243
3.3.3 /-1/ and Semantic Subordination ..................... 248
INTRODUCTION
0.1. Prologue
work done on the language (cf. especially Hale, Platero, Creamer), signi-
ficant factors emerge in the study of Navajo that are less easily perceived
language. The natural word order is SOV, relative clauses precede their
than prepositions, are used. It is well recognized that there are signi-
languages. Thus, Japanese and Turkish, the verb final languages studied
constraints on language.
12
thought not to exist. Since there is some reason to believe that the
plain the use of the unbounded rightward movement and help account for
tions, incomplete but sufficient for understanding the basic Navajo yes/no
of embedded question also thought not to exist in verb final (or COMP
completely different, I will suggest that the rationale for both rules
examining the case considered typical of a verb final language, i.e., the
when it is necessary for semantic reasons to remove the WH word from the
working under the further handicap of not being a native speaker of the
are not only patient relaters of facts about their speech, but interested
linguists doing significant work of their own, I feel I have been able to
techniques used in collecting the data to get some feeling not only about
quite clear that many of the crucial grammatical examples are considered
less than natural by at least some of the Navajos consulted. What is not
cality by also giving the sentences in Navajo to see if they are acceptable
and then asking for English translations. Since I created many of the
examples myself, this technique does not differentiate very well those
examples which are preferable. Nor does this technique guard against
slight changes in meaning. I have tried to cope with this latter problem
vant information and made suggestions about other sentences and directions
to investigate.
found that certain types of sentences vary so markedly among the relatively
few people I have consulted that the description should really be reinforced
15
will be considering, I will limit as much as possible the claims made about
tree would look like at the time a transformation applies. I will also
take the liberty of creating forms for expository purposes without making
any claims about their exact correlation in underlying structure. And when
underlying forms.
questions, I will describe some facts about Navajo that will be relevant
In the Navajo sentence, the verb is the main source of information. Notice
that the gloss on the nouns are only English nouns. This is because Navajo
I have made no effort to gloss the verb fully since doing so would not aid
the reader. 3 I have noted only the subject and object prefixes and, where
useful, the verb tense or aspect. The direct object prefix is ordered be-
fore the subject marker in the Navajo verb. Thus, in the above gloss, the
first 3 refers to the third person object, and the second to the subject.
P stands for perfective, and F for future. I will discuss specific pre-
changed so long as the inversion does not lead to ambiguity. Thus, the
Sentence (2a) exhibits the natural word order, a sentential subject follow-
ed by the object and then the verb.4 In sentence (2b), the sentential
object.
It is not evident from the English sentence that sentence (2) has
reads "That the boy saw the dog is known with John". Thus translated, the
that there is in fact some overlap in the types of S's each complementizer
cannot argue whether they occur in underlying structure, nor whether there
is a COMP node and if so how it is adjoined to the tree. For the most part,
these matters are irrelevant to the discussion. Whenever they would make a
not the only use for the /- / complementizer, the sentences in (2) are in
6
fact typical of this complementizer.
/i/. In addition, the /- gii/ is suppressed when the past tense variant
Notice the gloss of the embedded verb in both (4b) and (5b). The Navajo
(6)
NP NP V
NP NP V COMP
(5b)
NP NP V
Jaan nai
John 3.say
Si
NP NP V
both contain the same first person verb /naha;rnii'/. The difference be-
who bought the car. However, in direct discourse, first person is under-
stood from the point of view of the subject of the immediately dominating
correct.
(7)
NP SV
Jdan ni
John 3.say
NP S V
Mary nizin
Mary 3.want
NP NP V
correct, the first person would refer to John, the subject of the matrix
S, i.e., (7) would be talking about John's buying a car. However, this
23
is not a possible meaning for (7). In this sentence, it is Mary who will
Mary, the subject of S1 , the immediately dominating S,and not the subject
of So, the matrix S. (7) demonstrates that the point of view of each
way, the scope of a direct discourse verb is only one S, and not every-
immediately dominating subject. Thus in (8) and (9), the matrix subjects
are identical, the embedded verbs are identical, but the subjects of the
Notice that the second person verb form does not refer to the hearer as
by the object of the matrix verb. (8) could be paraphrased, "John told
24
Mary, you work", and (9), "John told me, you work". (8) and (9) can be
The second person form of the verb will not always be used when an
In this case, John is not talking to Mary, but about Mary, so that we find
are still left with a question as to how the speaker refers to himself.
third party. Sentence (9) above demonstrates that a second person embedded
verb will refer to the speaker if the matrix verb contains an object pro-
noun which denotes the speaker. Another way to indicate the speaker in a
sentence (11), the embedded verb gets interpreted from the point of view
ject in /sh 'n / (expect me) that /nahizhdoolnih/ (buy) refers to the
speaker. Thus, if the object pronoun changes, so does the reference for
only if the governing verb refers to the speaker, either with /sh 'n /
(expect me) and an embedded fourth person verb, or with /shilni/ (tell me)
and an embedded second person verb (cf. example (9)). There is no way to
use the verbs which do not contain such a reference and still refer to the
speaker. For example, "John wants me to buy a car" can only be paraphrased
Sentence (13) means only that one person said of somebody else that he/she
reason to assume that the subject of the embedded S deleted under identity
Although the verb agreement in (13) does not indicate that this
following:
It thus seems clear that direct discourse correlates with the absence of
/yo'n /, meaning expect (him). Although all three are verbs of thinking
semantic class. Notice that believe in example (15) is not a direct dis-
which would fit into the same semantic class. I will therefore make no
attempt to characterize the direct discourse verbs, but will only consider
direct and indirect discourse involve embedded S's where only the latter
In the first case, one could try to treat the Navajo direct dis-
will become clear that, for the purposes of movement rules, direct dis-
discourse within Navajo. Although the verbs /ni/ (say) and /nizin/ (in
the sense of think) can be used in quotations, the direct discourse verb
/yo'n / does not take quotations. One way to differentiate direct dis-
course sentences from quotations is to use the particle /ya'/, the Navajo
y / I/
20. *Jaan Bil chidi neidiyoolnih ya' yo'ni
John Bill car 3.3.F.buy right 3.of.3.say
/ya'/, like an English tag, can only appear in non-embedded S's. When
direct discourse, it does not take embedded quotations (just like the
an embedded quotation but /yo'n$/ allows only direct discourse, not quota-
discourse, and quotations. Only the last will not involve embedded S's.
discourse S's are also NP's (as implied in the trees for (6) and (5b)
above). The Navajo verb morphology supports this claim. Consider the
following:
The /yi-/ prefix is a direct object agreement marker. It occurs when and
only when there is a third person subject followed by a third person direct
are direct objects. Since direct objects, by definition, are NP's, we can
by claiming that they are not dominated by NP, at least at the stage of
the derivation at which this /yi-/ agreement occurs. Consider the following:
The sentences in (22) affirm the fact that the /yi-/ prefix must appear on
in (23) proves that these direct discourse sentential complements are not
31
discourse complements are direct objects, since the matrix verb has a
/yi-/ prefix.
are not dominated by NP. This fact can be used to distinguish these com-
possible structure for /- gi/ complements. Recall that this is the normal
discourse to see how these two different types of embedded S's interact
with enclitics.
one may render /-go/ with participial ... j.ng, or conjunctive 'if, when, in
case that' or, possibly, ignore the enclitic" (Haile (1942), 11.32). While
I will be discussing the more unusual uses of /-go/ in Chapter 3, the fol-
lowing are typical examples of the use of the /-go/ complementizer, in-
interpreted from the point of view of the speaker and not the subject of
/shaa/ (to me) is interpreted as referring to the speaker and not to John.
0.5. Conclusion
In summary, the basic Navajo facts described thus far which will
direct objects.
the rationale for the complex system of questions found in Navajo and the
FOOTNOTES TO INTRODUCTION
Hindi and Telugu that there are rightward movement rules which are
being the singular form. Those that are inflected for number normally
3. See Kari (1973), Stanley (1963), etc. on verb morphology and phonology.
4. For some people, (2c), rather than (2a), is considered the most
that it is not clear what the underlying word order is. It may be
would be present for both (3a) and (3b). If /yje/ were a simple past
/-I/ complementizer.
discourse interpretation.
of the verb to refer to the verb since stems can be used in a variety
of verbs. Note that I gloss /yo 'n/ (expect) as including the stem
10. I am using the term root sentence as used by Emonds (1970). Emonds
11. (21c) is of course good, meaning He saw the boy. Also although con-
12. I am using the term complement to describe sentential subjects and ob-
14. Note, for example that there is no Navajo word in these sentences for
adverbial clauses.
37
CHAPTER 1
1.0. Introduction
cause they require reconsidering some of the most widely accepted work in
not they made crucial use of a variable. Rules that did so were con-
proposed the Right Roof Constraint, which claimed that all transformations
which move elements rightward are upward bounded. That is, no element will
ever move rightward out of its own S. The Right Roof Constraint thus
Although linguists have recently begun to question the Right Roof Con-
has been widely accepted (based especially on the data from Greenberg
(1962)) that verb final languages have no special rule for moving ques-
tioned constituents and that in those other languages where such a rule
(ii) "there is only one possible movement rule for questions, which
differs in different languages only in the particular forma-
tive mentioned in place of the English wh:
Q X NP Y
1 2 3 4 -- 1 3+2 4
He further explains that "those SOV languages which had particles posi-
tioned with reference to the sentence as a whole put them at the end of
Bach (1971) takes Baker's work one step further, using Ross's
concept of unbounded rules and the Right Roof Constraint to derive Baker's
conclusions. Bach presents four assumptions, and I repeat the three rele-
vant ones (the first being irrelevant to the conclusions here under
discussion):
39
From assumptions (b) and (d) he derives the obvious conclusion that:
(i) the WH phrase will always be to the left, never the right.
Joan Bresnan (1972) refines even more the explanation for known
conclusions.
(42).
40
While the hypotheses vary in each case, all three sets are designed
I believe that such a comparison will help to explain why unbounded right-
ward movement had gone unnoticed for so long. Thus, as I look at other
enclitics from enclitic phrases, I will first identify and define the
3. Kii kinla'niji'
C.
ni'nilbdz
LA.
"in the direction away from" (/-dle'/), "in the direction toward" (/-g6'd/),
2
"motion up to or as far as" (/-j{'/), "located in or at" (/-di/). /-go'ne'
in sentence (5) means "located in", but refers only to things that have an
and the word it modifies. The enclitics themselves divide into two cate-
motion verbs (/-dde'/, /-goo/, and /-ji'/) and the locative enclitics
42
verbs. As we will see, both directional and locative enclitics may modify
some enclitic phrases do act like NP's: locative EP's can be subjects
8. bikoohgoyaa hotsaa
canyon.down in area.3.be big
The canyon is big.
9. a'a'a'ngone' hozaad
hole.in area.3.be deep
The hole is deep.
postposition. More literally it means "it is good with me". Thus, the
objects. However, final confirmation of this claim must await the dis-
the following:
marker /ho-/ in the verb, just as for any subject or object. This agree-
marker. Notice, however, that this same sentence with /ho-/ is acceptable
44
(cf. (7)).
The presence of the prefix /yi-/ in sentence (10) shows that /bikooh/
both (10) and (11) the same logical relationship holds between the action
and the two nouns: John is seeing the canyon. It therefore seems that
that in (10) the canyon is simply named, while in (11) the area occupied
shows that EP's act like NP's in triggering locative object agreement.
Thus, if /ho-/ is considered a direct object marker, then EP's are not only
3
NP's, but also direct objects.
counts for the fact that it does not mark directional phrases. Directional
phrases never function as direct objects because they only occur as com-
plements of motion verbs and motion verbs do not take such objects. Notice
that there is also no /ho-/ when locatives are complements of motion verbs
(cf. (4)-(6)).
I have so far said little about the constituents of the EP, except
to point out that there is an enclitic and that in the examples thus far
ever, that a noun is not the only constituent an enclitic will attach to:
In all the above sentences, the enclitic appears in the same word as the
embedded verb. In each case, the /- / which precedes the enclitic is the
which corresponds to the English "(the place) where". In other words, the
these examples) just as they did in all the previous examples. Yet this
clauses that they have no NP complement. Sentences (20) and (21) show that
the /yi-/ prefix marks direct objects and can only occur when there is a
tences:
1.father 3.3.P.eat
My father ate.
Bill 3.3.P.steal
Bill stole (something).
As in English, the Navajo verbs for "eat" and "steal" are transitive. Thus,
what. Navajo has an indefinite object marker /'i-/ to designate such a PRO
direct object.6 (In (26a) the underlying /'i-/ has become /'a-/.) Since
/'i-/ occurs only when no object appears, one could argue that /'i-/ is a
ment marker. In any case, the ungrammaticality of (25b) and (26b) demon-
strates that the /yi-/ prefix does not function as a nonreferential marker.
an object. We know from the /yi-/ on the verb that there must have been
therefore a general fact that WH words do not have a surface form in the
a noun which does not appear on the surface in the Navajo. We have shown
lying subject in (24). Just as (20) and (21) are analogous to (22),
The enclitic may not appear on the verb if there is a noun for it to
49
The only difference between (20) and (27) is that the enclitic /-gdd/ (to)
was attached to its noun in the former and to its verb in the latter.
there would be no way to account for (27). However, we can account for
only in phrases with an NP. Since enclitics by their very nature cannot
Under the hypothesis that all enclitics originate in phrases with NP's,
enclitic is stranded in its own phrase through deletion of its NP, a trans-
formation will move it so that it attaches to the end of the embedded verb.
either to the clause final morpheme or to the COMP. As we will see, the
late a single source for EP's and predict when there will be movement.
50
We have thus far considered cases with only one embedded verb. The
Notice that the verbs to which the enclitics are attached are incapable
On the other hand, enclitic phrases may occur as complements to the lower
verbs, and such complements are semantically accurate for the above sen-
tences.
one underlying source for spatial enclitics (an EP with either a specified
NP or a 4), then we can express the generalization that the logical re-
lationship is the same in all the examples considered. Notice also that
that the enclitic may appear on a verb any number of S's away from its
It is obvious from the meaning of (33) that /-go/ (to) must have originated
clear that neither want nor say takes EP complements. There is no other
which verb an enclitic will move to. Let us first rule out the possibility
While the enclitic does not necessarily attach to the highest em-
/ /J //
Enclitic Raising
W - ME]EP - X - Y
1 2 3 4 5 6
1 2 0 4 5+3 6
to the right of the complementizer. However, I have said nothing about how
only evidence that the /-I/ complementizer must be present in an S for the
is, however, some evidence that the enclitic is not Chomsky-adjoined to the
sentences with more than one enclitic. In fact we find two enclitics
(37)
NP EP V
Jaan NP E naagha
John 1 3.come
defe
from
a dinya -
to 2.go
55
(37')
N15- EP
Jaan NP naagha
John T 3.come
dff
from
NP EP C
We have said that an enclitic normally attaches to the end of its NP. But
therefore attach to the end of S1, which is in fact the same thing as
attaching onto the COMP of S1, a lower S. Thus, we find the surface word
/diniyahigood'/.1 2
The pronunciation of the word /dinya'higo'de6'/ involves a curious
there is almost a pause between /-goo/ and /-d'/. I would describe this
rule Chomsky-adjoins the enclitic onto the S, then there should also be a
word boundary and therefore a lengthening or pause between the COMP /-I/
and the following enclitic. However, no such phenomenon occurs. It is
1.1.10. Chorus
source for the enclitics, an EP. The noun in the EP may or may not be
occurs. If it is, the enclitic will attach to it. If it is not, and the
enclitic is stranded, the enclitic will move rightward to the nearest /-I/,
passing over as many S's as necessary. In other words, this is a case of
with leftward movement (e.g., English) and those without (e.g., Japanese).
While unbounded movement exists in the former, the latter were said to have
movement within a clause only. The facts about Navajo enclitics, however,
and (2) If we are in fact dealing with a movement phenomenon, does it have
that we are dealing with relative clauses rather than headless NP's. As
I discuss in more detail below, one could argue that the above facts are
The "missing NP" would then be an EP deleted through relative clause forma-
Once I have demonstrated that there must in fact be movement, I will re-
(28)
EP
NP E
(shf) A g adeesbqs
(I) to l.F.drive
there is no good output. Because the noun in the EP is null, the string
Since under this theory there is no movement, one could say that deletion
of the head is unconstrained and that the sentence is thrown out by virtue
sentences so far discussed, there are many reasons why these sentences
no S node between /-i/ and the spatial enclitic. Since an enclitic which
is from the head of a relative clause would be separated from its relativiz-
Thus, the existence of (44) should predict a good sentence in (45). (45),
however, is bad.
can occur as the subject of /-1 b64hozin/ (know). We would expect that
(44) would be formed from a relative clause with an EP head. Any head
Pat Brogan (n.d.) has shown that there are "strange NP's" in English
which cannot occur without a relative clause. He gives the following ex-
One could argue that (45)-(46) are ungrammatical because (44) is really a
The difference between the English and the Navajo is that tell
allows some simple NP's while /-1 bee'h'zin/ requires sentential subjects.
"to be acquainted with". Contrast (45) and (54) with the following:
The contrast between /bee'honisin/ and /shil beehdzin/ provides yet another
Sentence (58) does not have the relative clause reading of (57). If the
verb /-- bedho'zin/ can have relative clause complements, as in (44), then
not be either.
4
59a. ga;lbah a'aIngoneI yah eelwodig hatl'' '
rabbit hole in into 3.P.run.REL area.be dark,
It is dark in the hole that the rabbit ran into.
Sentence (59a) appears to contain a relative clause where the head has
a relative clause with an EP head, then one would have to postulate that
(59a)
area.be dark
NP EP V REL
NP E
//I
I1 I
ga ;Lbahi a'aan gone' yah eelwod i
ra bbit hole in into 3.P.run
We know from the meaning that the head includes /a'an/, but do not know
be able to occur without the relative clause, one would normally decide
between the two by seeing which conforms to the requirements of the main
verb (/hatl'ee'/). In this case, however, both can occur with /hatl'te/.
The /ha-/ in /hatlie'?'/ is the /ho-/ locative marker discussed above. Re-
However, the locative marker /ho-/ may also be used with simple nouns
/afa'n/ is not the head. If the head of the relative clause were the
simple NP, then (59b) should be good since the main verb in (59b) is not
locative and therefore takes a simple NP but not an EP (cf. (61) and (63)).
the grounds that a noun cannot be used both neutrally and spatially in
the same sentence: once a noun is specifically made spatial, the inter-
The /yi-/ prefix in the embedded clause shows that /bikooh/ as the object
however, /bikooh/ is being used in its locative sense (note the locative
66
at once.
between (65) and (28)-(30), blocking backwards deletion in (65) would also
questions would be derived through deletion of the head noun, but the
direct questions can derive from relative clauses. Relative clauses assume
bush, one could use (66) to describe the area under the bush as dark.
Sentence (67) does not mean that John works on the field. That is made
clearer by (68), which means that I will be working near John. It does
relative clauses.
1.2.5. Recapitulation
lying relative clause structure for these indirect questions does not
time, I tried to argue that the indirect questions were not relative
clauses at all, but could only conclude that at least some of the cases
sider the possibility that I have been describing two different types of
It has been argued for English (Baker, 1970; Bresnan, 1972; Brogan,
n.d. ; Jespersen, 1927) that there are three phenomena which are super-
respect to strange NP's and relative clauses, I have not actually given
Navajo examples and relative clauses and then turn to the problem of
EP, for although I have been discussing EP's throughout, I have yet to
investigate the nature of the constituent parts. I have also said that
EP's act like NP's and yet if they were normal NP's, they should be able
Having noted both that EP's act like NP's (can be subjects and
exclusive with other subject and object markers, etc.) and that EP's are
different from NP's with respect to relative clauses, I will now compare
provide significant information about the character of the EP. To see that
6
9a. hooghang/ne' sida
house in 3.sit
He is sitting in the house.
house.to 2.drive
Drive to the house.
Thus in the above examples, the enclitic and the postposition seem to be
similar both by virtue of their meaning and in that they combine with a
that the enclitic but not the postposition forms a phonological unit with
71
Navajo has a rule which changes a stressed high tone to a falling tone
when followed by a low tone within the same word. 9 This phenomenon is
apparent when an enclitic was added above to the town name /ch'ini4/.
seems that postpositions do not form a single phonological word with their
nouns.
b. dii bii'
this 3.in
In this
72
(72b) may be used to refer to the area in which one is standing. That is,
its noun.
/gone'/ means only in. The postposition /-ii'/ takes the full complement
of person markers, /sh-ii'/ (in me), /n-ii'/ (in you (sg. and pl.)),
/b-ii'/ (in him, her, it, them), /hw-ii'/ (in one), /nih-ii'/ (in us).
helps explain why they can be independent of their heads: the agreement
its head is quite different from that between an enclitic and its head,
1.3.3. The Classes of NP's Which Can Occur With EP's and PP's
those lexical items which by themselves can refer to place.20 That is,
can create a locative interpretation for almost any noun. Thus, unlike
the above grammatical examples with PP's, in all the good examples I have
tl'do'di
at outside
from there
kodi
at here
74
locative subjects and objects. Since the above definition requires that
b. hooghan hotsaa
house area.be big
The house is big.
b. bikooh hozaad
canyon area.be deep
The canyon is deep.
b. a'a'an hatl'e'e
hole area.be dark
In contrast, the sentences in (73a) and (74a) are bad because (78) and
its ability to stand alone is the fact that it is possible to form a rela-
6
80a. yii' sidihigi kin shil yal't'le' h
3.in 3.sit.REL house 1.with 3.be good
I like the house he is sitting in.
The relative clause in sentence (80a) results from the deletion of the
embedded NP. (80b) is the result of deleting the head NP. Note that it
is clear that the head of the relative clause in both (80a) and (80b) is
the simple NP /kin/ and not the PP /kin yii'/. Thus, if a PP head were
possible, (81a) should be good. The fact that (81a) is bad and (81b) is
sentential clitics which go into second position after phrases will come
between an NP and its postposition but not between a noun and a spatial
enclitic.
suming that both EP's and PP's are NP's, it is still necessary to deter-
mine whether that NP is formed from another phrase or from a simple noun,
(a) NP (b) NP
NP N
Since the head of a relative clause is an NP, its antecedent must be also.
and therefore must postulate that the head is an NP, not an N (structure
all the differences already noted between EP's and PP's. A phrase is
tions refer to phrases more than categories, phrases are more likely to be
postposition.
A final strong argument that the head of a PP, but not an EP, is
an NP comes from Platero (1974). He notes that PP's but not NP's may
78
is not an NP.
the following:
to PP's but not to EP's. Sentences (88a)-(88b) show that movement by the
(87A) NP (87B)
P E
NP P E
(87C) PP (87D) P
NP P NP
N E
k
I I/I 'ki g
kin gone' yiiI kin yii' gone,
The tree in (87A) is an example of the type of constituent structure I
and would then move to the /-l/, creating a sentence such as (89).
(87A).
wrong surface order. Besides the fact that enclitic movement is not
precedence and about surface order. It also makes the correct claim that
important, I argued above that there should be only one source for en-
I would like to suggest that even (87D) is suspect and that these
enclitics have no status of their own. Instead, I would suggest that some
no direct evidence for this hypothesis, there are other contraction rules
to me, /to'biih/ (water in) may contract to /taah/. Consider the follow-
ing:
b. taah y3'a
water.in 3.1.P.handle
I put it in the water.
lexical item. Since these phrases act like PP's, that single item should
for PP's, that of (a) on page 77 above. More importantly, we will be able
to retain the claim that there is only one source for enclitics, (b) above.
In either case, however, notice that the generalization still holds that
last case of possible relative clauses involving PP's and EP's. We have
and enclitic and saw that the first was possible but the second was not.
on the entire PP and EP. Since both are NP's, such relative clauses
should be possible. To see that the entire PP can be the head of a rela-
The fact that (94b) is ungrammatical proves that the head had to be the
occurred. (93a), formed through forward deletion, proves that the ante-
cedent is also the full PP, as we would expect given the PP head in (93b).
(95)
8P hodiiltlah
3.P.fire breaks out
kin di
house at
l\P P REL
NE
Sentences (96a) and (96b) prove that the tree should be well formed. Yet
enclitic phrases and the implication of that behavior for other syntactic
whether the sentences I have argued are indirect questions are also am-
provides an explanation for why indirect questions do not come from rela-
rather than an EP: "I am aware of the place" makes sense; "I am aware of
from the place" does not. However, the embedded clause contains an EP:
"John comes from A," not "John comes /". Thus, to be a relative clause,
(97) would have to be formed from a relative clause within the EP, not on
(97)
NP
NP E
Jaan d ) naagha'
John from 3.come
This, however, is precisely the class of possible relative clauses that has
on the object of an EP (as opposed to the object of a PP) has been shown to
would now like to try to provide positive proof that these sentences are
the proof by process of elimination which I have used so far may be con-
sidered inadequate.
1.4.1. Identification of
that enclitic raising exists because the enclitic has been left stranded;
(2) the noun deletes; or (3) the noun has been moved away. We can
eliminate (1) on the basis of the character of the EP, verb morphology,
and meaning.
enclitics were found to attach only to lexical items which are inherently
Saying that the enclitic is really attached to the verb does not help
In this case the L is not part of an EP, but is the direct object. In
section 1.1.4. I argued that the presence of /yi-/ proved that there had
Recall that /'i-/, not /yi-/, agrees with PRO direct objects. Thus, un-
less there were some way to interpret a dummy node before direct object
is, however, nothing in (99). We therefore must conclude that 4\, has a
has been a gap in the Navajo, there is a WH word in the English. While
for.
Navajo WH question words, the words which appear in the English transla-
The (b) sentences are typical direct questions. The question word is
the sentence they are attached. I will discuss the system in more detail
relevant to the present discussion. However, the third part of the "where"
and the indirect questions. Compare each "where" word with the correspond-
to replace the enclitic in (a) with the full WH word (with or without the
interrogative particle).
4 shil beehozin
104a. *ha'd'41 Jaan yig i/gi
word and the (a) and (b) sentences had the same underlying form for that
WH word.
The above questions really contain two questions, the direct question "do
you know?" and an indirect question, asking in (105) what my brother shot,
and in (106) where John is going. That there are two questions is clear
from the responses. One would reply "yes" or "no" only to a direct ques-
tion and only to a yes/no question. On the other hand, one adds more
Since (107) asks only whether you knew about something, i.e., were aware
no new information.
is answered with a simple "yes", the questioner will feel the answer is
only partial and therefore inappropriate and will request more information.
Thus, if (105) had been answered as in (107), the questioner would come
back with
93
In sum, the way these sentences are used also argues that they are
indirect questions.
and is not responsible for the indirect question. Recall that the indirect
questions discussed earlier did not contain the particle. To see that my
In the examples I have been using, the interrogative particle was attached
question, i.e., is not a leftover of the deleted WH word. The fact that
the WH interrogative particle /la/ may not be used ((110)) also proves
R2 : naashnish
1.work
I am working.
swering (111). The fact that this expression can be used in the following
there must have been a question word underlyingly although there is none
in the surface.
In sum, all the examples discussed argue that we have in fact been
tion rule which deletes the WH is unusual. But then so is the rightward
movement of the spatial enclitic. Perhaps one unusual fact can be used
gating other factors in detail, such as the other Navajo question types
the underlying forms involved in the movement, I will now return briefly
to the question of whether this movement phenomenon has any special pro-
reflects not only on the Right Roof Constraint but on the putative question
only one possible movement rule for questions, and it moves the questioned
other hand, Bach claims that question movement is toward the "governing
verb" and Bresnan (1970) and Chomsky (1971) claim that all movement out
then one could postulate that the actual question formation is the WH
deletion and that the movement rule is not in fact a question formation
rule. Thus, while WH deletion remains unusual, it does not violate the
Universal is.
tion now includes a deletion site. If Hale and Platero are correct, then
the environment for movement can no longer be based upon deletion because
whether WH-deletion occurs before or after movement and whether the raising
sense that the enclitic moves across a crucial variable, it is not un-
course, it has often been noted that question formation in English also
words from indirect questions move to the front of their clause, not to
sentence-initial position.
Bach uses the concept of movement toward but not past the governing verb
the movement is only across the direct discourse segment of the sentence,
the movement is truly across an indefinite number of S's. One might argue
that some kind of clause reduction has occurred, perhaps through pruning,
and the enclitic therefore moved to the main verb of its clause. Under
As we have already seen, go, but not want, takes directional complements.
word).
would also trigger pruning in the above examples. There is, however,
suggest any raising. The most convincing way to show that the lower verb
has not been raised is to produce sentences with material from the lower
the right of the verb. Thus, (119) is considered awkward but acceptable.
far as the /-I/ complementizer. The fact that there is no clause reduc-
tion simply means that it may be some other property of the /-I/ which
Chapter 3.
ment to the first S. One must then question whether the Right Roof
direct discourse S's are "reduced S's", as infinitival S's are in English.
1.4.7. Conclusion
whether the rule can even be generalized for Navajo itself. I have just
argued that this movement occurs in indirect questions and that these ques-
tions contain an underlying WH word rather than an empty node. Since there
the WH rather than the deletion site. If triggered by the WH, then it may
because the explanation for the movement that I will propose in Chapter 3
FOOTNOTES TO CHAPTER 1
2. There are two forms of the locative enclitic, /-di/ and /-gi/. I
act alike: they have much the same meaning, occur in the same places,
their surface string. However, most, if not all, are cases of direct
strate, sentences with missing NP's can mean who or what, but not why,
enclitic.
102
7. Note that (24) also means "Tell me about his stealing my car". Since
more than three S's. One reason is that the complex sentences are
reason is that I know of very few verbs which take no /- /, and the
directly to the verb, i.e., without an /-Q/. However, the exact status
10. Note that if direct discourse S's have no underlying COMP, it may not
11. Although I do not argue for the existence of a COMP node, I have
to attach the raised enclitic to the COMP node rather than directly
From the meaning of these examples and what we know about EP be-
the surface.
104
b. kingoo deeshaka
store.to 1.F.go
I will go to the store.
I would argue that there are two enclitics underlyingly and propose
(1) When there are two identical adjacent enclitics, delete one.
(2) When /-di/ (and possibly /-ji'/) occurs before another spatial
13. Cf. Chomsky and Halle (1968) for a discussion of word boundaries.
natural pause.
15. If this argument is valid, then one should consider whether it helps
plementizers into the verb. That is, one must account for the fact
to get another word in the same S to the right of the verb when there
17. This argument does not hold in a theory in which the -/ and the
REL or COMP position. See also section 1.4.5., section 2.5.7., and
18. The sentence should in fact be ambiguous, but with a third reading:
19. So far as I know, this rule applies only to stem vowels. However,
there is a word boundary between the stem and the suffix. This
whether there is a word boundary between the verb and the comple-
Chapter 3.
which are not spatial and thus the generalization would be lost.
21. Obviously, the /ho-/ is relevant only insofar as the lexical items
23. This sentence is grammatical with the meaning, "The baby I put into
24. And then, of course, the enclitic raising transformation would have
107
25. There are two WH morphemes, /ha'/ and /haa/. I have only discussed
the former in this chapter. The latter occurs incorporated into the
26. I am assuming that the sentential subject readings (e.g., "I know
that he ate it") do not come from A's but from anaphoric pronouns
27. Although as we will see in Chapter 2, not all Navajo questions are
28. This idea was first discussed in Hale and Platero (1973). Also see
LEFTWARD MOVEMENT
necessary to have some idea about the general method of forming questions
i.e., questions in sentences composed of only one S, for even here we find
Since Young and Morgan list the three forms separately, they
differentiate their uses, but it is clear from the examples that they
question marker.
enclitics. Elgin (1973, IV.2.2), for example, says that the interrogative
1
suffix /- sh/ appears on both yes/no questions and WH questions. Phono-
logical evidence, however, argues for two distinct particles. The crucial
low tone vowel. Since vowels assimilate in Navajo (cf. sentence (5)), the
vowel quality is often irrelevant. However, when a high tone vowel cliti-
cizes to a low tone vowel, a rising tone results. Consider example (3).
Since the tone has remained low, we know that /-sh/ and not /-ish/ was
110
7. *haash yinflghe
suffix. This is apparent because the words the enclitics are attached to
do not end in vowels. Once again, substituting /-sh/ for /-Ish/ is im-
possible:
Lest it be assumed that /-sh/ can only attach to vowels, and that
ended in consonants, (9) shows that /-sh/ also cannot attach to vowels in
yes/no questions.
Since an enclitic beginning with a high tone vowel would affect the vowel,
the interrogative enclitic in these cases cannot begin with such a vowel.
Haile concludes from this evidence that "the reduced form /-sh/
any real argument, why I disagree with Haile's position that /-sh/ is a
To begin with, some speakers of Navajo use /-sha.'/ for yes/no ques-
If, as I argue, /-sh/ and /- sh/ are distinct, then how can they both be
reduced forms of /-sha'/? On the other hand, if /-sh/ and /- sh/ are not
distinct, then how come some people use /-sha'/ only for WH questions?
one.
/- sh/ that I see no reasoned way of collapsing two enclitics into
As Elgin notes (112), only /-sht'/ typically occurs on single words in-
Y: Merisha? 3
L
How about Mary?
112
12. Jaansha?
Where is John?
mately "and does the preceding statement apply to Mary as well?" (ibid.).
On the basis of this, she suggests that /-sha/ (sic) may be a compound,
would suggest that /-shg'/ appears to break down into the above components
the following:
Note the pause between /Jdanshg'/ and the rest of the sentence. Note also
words, while /-sha'/ serves to indicate both topic and question, either
question about the whole sentence, can be observed more clearly by com-
For people who use /-shg'/ as a yes/no question particle, (14) can be used
while accepting /-sh '/ in WH questions. Linda Platero, one such speaker,
accepted (14) but did not accept the yes/no question reading ((14i)). She
pointed out that (14) was not identical to (15). Requiring a pause after
topic marker will account for this meaning of (14). It will also account
for the fact that there may be two interrogative particles in one sentence.
114
(17) and (18) demonstrate that if there are two such particles, the first
people and with WH words for everyone. That is, we must account for the
which there is no pause after the first word and /-sha'/ is the only
marker. People simply vary as to which categories they have put /-sha.'/
into. Given this option, /-sha'/ will be generated the same way the other
are analogous to (20), then all words marked by /-sha'/ must be topics.
Such a claim is consistent with the fact that it is impossible to get two
/-sh '/'s in one sentence. While (13) and (16) are fine, (21) and (22)
are not:
It is also consistent with the fact that even for those who use /-sha'/ as
a yes/no particle, /-sha'/ cannot be substituted for /- sh/ when the latter
6
is not in second position.
The use of word order to designate topics seems to be a very common pro-
position and that /-sha'/ is always a topic marker, then this difference
since /-shq'/ ends in a glottal stop which creates a pause of its own.
correct, then a deletion rule for the extra question particle is required.
WH words. It has always been assumed that question words may not be
topics, but it is also unclear exactly what the import of question word
behavior is. I therefore leave unanswered the question of how many ways
-sht/ is generated.
and because its behavior is not precisely identical to that of any of the
other particles. On the basis of the above facts, I will thus assume that
the three enclitics are all independent, and will refer to /-shg'/ as the
Young and Morgan do not include the particle /la/ in their list of
It thus seems that /l/ and /-sh/ are interchangeable. Both occur with
done to find out whether there is any substantive difference in the cur-
/la/ should cause a lengthening of a high tone word final vowel. None
of the WH words end in a short high tone vowel. However, /la/ does not
are enclitics. Because it does not seem that /la/ is an enclitic, I will
word of the clause, i.e., in what has been referred to as second position.
While this is the most common position, it is not the only possible one.
in second position, (28) also demonstrates that WH words need not be moved
to the front of the sentences (at least in these cases) as, for example,
they must in English. That these are two separate facts is clear from
Although I do not argue in depth for any hypothesis about where the
late a bit about some aspects of possible explanations because they involve
some conceptions about other principles in Navajo. With Young and Morgan,
I assume that Navajo has a rule moving clitics into second position.
This Second Position rule is probably necessary for other clitics besides
the question clitics (cf. Perkins, 1973). However, it was previously be-
lieved that the Second Position rule was obligatory. Although it is not
in (25) as well as the work done by Perkins demonstrate that clitics need
not end up in second position. I therefore assume that this rule is op-
the simplest explanation for the above data would involve postulating
that occur in WH questions with the WH words accounts for the fact that
the two together, the Second Position rule which is needed anyway derives
121
therefore generate the question particle with the WH word, but will not
sentences.
Second Position rule for particles, there is some rule which optionally
applying the Second Position rule but not WH-movement. If (31) were
not the Second Position rule. Notice, however, that (31) cannot be
not apply to the same constituent. However, the assumption that the
question marker is part of the same constituent as the WH word does allow
entire constituent, then when the WH word is moved, the Q particle will
changing the subject and object, but leaving the Q marker behind. The
that WH-movement applies before the Second Position rule. Consider the
A. ashkii ha'at'iilayiyiil-tsa/
Second Position: ashkiila ha'at'll yiyiilts
L
to account for surface linear order will not apply until all rearranging
of constituents has occurred. One should expect (B) but not (A).
the Second Position rule even though the Q marker ends up in second
will always be in second position before the Second Position rule has had
Let me now mention briefly the possible rules that could account
Object Inversion (cf. Hale, 1973; Creamer, 1974). Thus, when Subject
Object Inversion interchanges the subject and the object, it also changes
the direct object prefix on the verb from /yi-/ to /bi-/. However, in
(25) the object occurs before the subject and yet the /yi-/ has not changed
when the subject or object is a WH word. Thus, the order of the subject
1974). That hierarchy, among other things, requires that. when there are
formation rule.
While such rules are not expected in SOV languages, the formulation
the one Baker formulates for languages in general. The fact that there is
variable would be null.12 Second, Baker does not say that question move-
optional one. Third, Baker's statements about verb final languages are
sentence.
125
/-sh/ and /-Ish/, I have so far said nothing about Young and Morgan's
As can be seen from their one example with /da'/ ((6)), it introduces
yes/no questions. Young and Morgan do not mention it, but /da'/ cannot
There is, however, one problem with trying to claim that all Navajo yes/no
occur in the same sentence, one could postulate that they both appear
126
underlyingly and that there is an optional rule (or rules) which can
c. * sh hastiin nihaanya
Q man 1pl.3.P.come
c. hastiinish nihaanya
man Q 1pl.3.P.come
/ //' 14
39a. da' hastiin nihaanayaash
Q man 1pl.3.P.come.Q
c. hastiin nihaanyaash
man pl.3.P.come
1ma
127
ferent underlying forms. On the contrary, one could account for the
for this fact by having a question formation rule which either moves /-ish/
or deletes one of the elements. Since I have no evidence to argue whether
Perhaps it should also be noted that /da'/ cannot occur with /-shat/
when the latter is being used as a yes/no question particle. On the basis
of the earlier discussion about /-sha'/, this fact is not a true problem
probably still a topic marker. It thus seems that the normal yes/no
question is formed with /-ish/ and not /-sha'/. One could therefore claim
that Baker's claim about the correlation between initial particles and
question movement holds for Navajo, since the normal yes/no question is
formation rule, I have not argued that the movement must be the result
when I asked people to contrast (25) and (28) (i.e., WH objects in first
that the first word is "what you're talking about," or "what you're most
concerned about." Thus, if the discussion has been about John or the boy,
and the interest is on his movements, his name rather than the question
want more information about it, in asking what John or the boy saw, it
This description suggests that using the first position for topics
is a major factor in deciding word order for questions with /-sh/ and /l'/
the WH-movement rule, the fact that Navajo is a language which permits a
certain amount of scrambling (except that the verb is usually final) and
the fact that topics are frequently reflected in the Navajo word order
eliminated lightly. The fact that /-shg'/ can be used instead of the
129
other question particles when they are in second position may also suggest
are considered indefinite pronouns. As Bach has pointed out, the fact
that they are indefinite means that question words will never occur as
themes (1971,115). Bach does not attempt to give a definition to the term
relationship is between themes and topics. One point that Bach makes is
that themes are always presupposed and one cannot presuppose the truth of
universal question rules, the use of topics,and the principles behind these
of the WH word into any higher S is also possible, which creates even more
SO
Si
-WH-
WH
1. 1 OK subject S
2. l WH *
3. l *
4. WH la OK subject SO
WH
5. OK subject S
6. l WH *
WH
7. la OK speaker
8. WH 1 OK speaker
9. WH 1 *
131
The first thing to establish is that the WH word must have originated
matrix verb.
b. hago6l deesh/a/l
where.to.Q 1.F.go
Where will I go?
133
Notice that in all the (b) sentences it was necessary to change the form
of the verb in order to retain the same reference as that of the embedded
embedded verbs are from the point of view of the subject of the matrix S
rather than from that of the speaker. Thus, in (40), although John is
doing the "going", the verb is in the first person rather than the third.
subject of the immediately dominating S rather than from the point of view
of the speaker. Since the subjects of the matrix and embedded S are core-
ferent in (40), the first person is used. When the speaker is reporting
what the subject said to a third party, the second person is used instead
of the third (cf. (41)). The third person is used in a direct discourse
segment only when the subject of the higher S says or thinks something
about a third party. Notice that that leaves none of the usual person
grammatical relations a verb may enter into. That is, the first person
form of a verb can take any complement the third person form takes. (48)
is as good as (44b).
134
The fact that the embedded verb in (40) is in the first person
proves another point: the noun is the subject of the matrix verb, not
the lower verb. The subjects of the lower verbs in these cases must have
b. Jaan doog I4
John 3.F.go
John is going.
c. deeshaA
1.F.go
I am going.
While the embedded form of the verb can stand alone as a separate sen-
tence, it cannot have /Jdan/ as its subject. 1 9 This proves that the WH
words have moved across the subject of the matrix verb as well as that of
the embedded verb. In other words, there is no question that the WH word
has ended up in the matrix S. Given my claim that direct discourse clauses
moving out of one S, but can involve movement across an indefinite number
Sentence (50) would evolve from a tree something like the following:
(50)
J san nI
John 3.say
nisin
1.want
The above tree is incomplete because it does not include the question
that the WH word itself may move unboundedly leftward. However, the
136
underlying position of /la/ will effect both the form of the WH-movement
clude a COMP node, that also has been omitted. The crucial points depicted
by the tree are that the EP originates in the lowest S, S2 , and is moved
For these particular examples, it seems that Navajo has the same unbounded
The problem is, of course, that such rules are not supposed to
They say both that the only way a constituent can move out of an S is
through COMP position and that the question formation transformation moves
node (as well as matrix S's) does not solve the problem because the COMP's
would be on the right, at the end of each S, rather than to the left. 21
In the most extreme case of trying to save the claim that all movement
out of an S must be through COMP position, one could postulate that each
S contains a COMP node and that the movement occurred rightward rather
than leftward. After reaching S, another rule would then move the WH
generally position particles at the ends of S's. And Navajo does have at
The one factor that might prove a problem for Baker is his claim
that SOV languages will never have an obligatory movement rule. However,
rule is not invariant in the sense that it is not used to form all WH
in that, if not applied, the string will still be well-formed. For some
not applied.22 If one includes the meaning difference in the tree before
movement takes place, the rule may still be obligatory. I will be dis-
There are also people for whom the question movement is optional
and the meaning remains the same, that of a direct question from the
for some, there are others who allow a question reading even when there
and when it must apply. I will now turn to cases in which there is no
ferent people. After that, I will look at cases of movement where people
(51)
Ja'an
John 3.say
NPNP V
We know that there are two NP's underlyingly in the S with the embedded
verb /yizhbizh/ (Sl) since /yi-/ is the direct object marker only for verbs
S by itself means, "what did Bill braid?". Recall, however, that S's
change their point of view when embedded under direct discourse verbs:
but that of the subject of the matrix sentence. The problem in (51) thus
is who said "what did Bill braid", John, or the speaker?. If, for the
purposes of (51) John uttered those words, then when the speaker says
them he is not asking a question but merely reporting what John had said.
140
Thus, following the definition of direct discourse given above, (51) may
that in all previous examples, the only word that changed from indirect
to direct discourse was the verb. It is thus possible that the term
S's, and therefore not to object NP's for example. However, I have
tacitly assumed all along that direct discourse applies to full S's by
using as an argument the fact that subjects must agree with their verbs.
Thus, I claimed that in sentences like (53), /Jaan/ could not be the sub-
ject of the lower verb /adessbas/ because the latter is in the first
One aspect of Navajo grammar that is not in doubt is the fact that the
subject and verb agree in person and number. Note, however, that since
there must be some rule anyway to make the subject and verb consistent
141
with one another, the fact that both take a direct discourse point of view
is not definitive proof that direct discourse is defined over S's. What-
ever rule makes them agree in person and number could also be sensitive to
To see that direct discourse must be defined on S's, not V's, con-
/shizhe'e/ is composed of the noun /-zhe"6'/, father, plus the first person
pronoun /shi/. And-yet, when asked whose father John is talking about in
(54), the answer is John's father, not the speaker's father. In other
words, the first person pronoun is being interpreted from the point of
view of the subject of the sentence, i.e., as part of the direct discourse,
and not from the point of view of the speaker. The interpretation of the
of view cannot be defined for verbs only. There is nothing in the verb
dominating S) and not the speaker who is asking the question. In fact,
for some people, (51) cannot be a question. Thus, for these people, it
142
B: #t-'6/' yizhbizh ni
rope 3.3.P.braid 3.say
He said he braided a rope.
There are, however, some people who will accept the discourse in
though there has been no movement. However, these people would render
In other words, when the speaker is asked whose father is being talked
about, the response has changed from John's father to the speaker's father.
The point of view is now that of the speaker, not the subject of the sen-
there are people who will allow both a direct discourse and an indirect
143
rather than a direct discourse one. Notice, however, that when a logical
direct discourse point of view and another part from an indirect discourse
words, the fact that (56b) is not a translation of (54) can be explained
by claiming that the entire S must be interpreted from the same point of
view.
an indirect discourse verb. To see that this is the case, consider the
following:
(57). However, for those who accept (56a) as a possible rendering of (54),
becomes a question of the point of view for the verb: (58a) is the direct
discourse point of view; (58b), like (56a) and (52), is the indirect dis-
course point of view. (56b) which requires mixing the two is not acceptable.
I will refer to those people who allow ambiguity between direct and in-
Given the sentences described so far, the decision is made for the entire
way to explain this is to consider the choices when faced with a desire to
Consider (59) in terms of the following tree which depicts the proper
(59)
Jaan nizin
John 3.want
N E
Under the assumption that there is no question movement rule, (59) could
remain as is. If (59) remains as is, however, the WH word and question
The first alternative is in fact a very attractive one. That is, these
sentences which are very common in English are in fact unusual in Navajo.
indirect questions and that once the WH word deleted, the spatial en-
clitic moved to the nearest /-:i/. Using the same rule for the questions
under discussion here thus creates two problems: first, indirect questions
delete the direct question particle. If the particle were not deleted,
the question would still be from the point of view of the subject, i.e.,
John. If the particle were deleted, the sentence would not automatically
found for the spatial enclitic because there is no /-:/. (Deletion of the
enclitic will not suffice because then the specific WH word would be lost,
sentence-initial position:
147
(59')
E EP
NE
Bil doogla/
Bill 3.F.go
While I do not intend to make any claim about the type of adjunction used,
will not receive that interpretation. This explanation assumes that the
same cycle as the movement and is ordered after the movement, or the de-
termination is made at any time, but the reference of the moved constituent
the point of the rule is not so much to get the questioned word to the
front of the sentence, but to get it out of the scope of the direct
discourse point of view. In (59), moving /ha 4gd&l/ to the front of S1
question.
(60)
since there can be an indefinite number of S's within the scope of the
149
known and completely consistent. Unfortunately, however, the data are not
but not (56b) as a possible meaning for (51) do accept the following with
This is a case in which the WH word is not in initial position, the verb
words, the WH word is given an indirect discourse designation but the verb
is not. (61) thus seems to be a counterexample to the claim that the em-
from the speaker's point of view. This is clear when put into a dialogue.
Notice, however, that given the linear order in (61), the phrase
(63) or (64).
but then I must explain why the WH word is not in first position where
question from the speaker's point of view. I believe that (64) is the
correct bracketing and that the sentence is the result of having a topi-
which both the WH word and the question particle must be bracketed as
part of the lower S, the sentence will not be a direct question. Thus,
when a sentence is a direct question, we should expect that the WH word
fact that it is a direct question from the speaker's point of view argues
of view. That is, (61) can also be translated as "John asked what he
should buy." This reading corresponds to (63). When used this way in
Note that (67) is not an appropriate answer to the direct question reading
a comment. The fact that one responds to a sentence does not mean that
someone else, a direct question from the point of view of the subject of
the two for two reasons. First, the direct discourse point of view is
explain why some indirect questions contain question particles and others
we can maintain the claim that question particles always signal direct
questions.
2.3.2. Chorus
attached to it.
In all these cases the interrogative particle has remained with the WH
ticle could be attached to a word other than the WH word, without changing
does not.
154
the sentence, the only acceptable positions for the question particle
were with that word or in second position. To see that the same is true
for sentences containing direct discourse S's, consider case (5) first.
To say that the question particle may occur in second position is not
The ungrammaticality of (73) confirms the fact that the question particle
is that the question particle cannot remain in the lower S when the WH
word is moved out. Recall that when discussing simple sentences, I sug-
gested that WH-movement moves the question particle with the WH word and
that the Second Position rule does not apply until all rearranging has
occurred. These two stipulations are sufficient to rule out (70). More
that the question particle cannot remain in an S lower than the one the
WH word ends up in. In proceeding to cases (4) and (6), I will there-
about second position follows naturally from the rules, there is no need
to stipulate it.
Since the facts are even murkier for case (4) than they are for
case (6), let us begin with case (6). Consider the following:
Rl: *auu'
yes
R2 : kingdo' deeya ni
store.to 3.go 3.say
He said she's going to the store.
ly part of the WH word, i.e., that these are direct WH questions from the
speaker's point of view rather than a WH question from the subject's point
Assuming that /la/ and /-sh/ (as opposed to /-/sh/) are used only for WH
questions, this fact is obvious. In other words, the use of /la/ in (74)
second question particle (an /- sh/ or /-sha'/), the sentence could not
particles is far from completed and we already know that people vary in
158
the way they use them, I further substantiate this claim through use of
dialogues. The fact that (74) cannot be answered by a yes, but can and
The next thing to consider is how forms like (74) would be produced.
1. leftward WH-movement
2. topicalization
(74A) /
discourse S, it has in fact been moved out of S, and therefore out of the
scope of the direct discourse point of view by a rule we need anyway, the
unbounded leftward movement. It is the fact that the WH word has been
moved out of the scope of the direct discourse which makes these direct
questions; it is not its occurrence in first position which does so. How-
the theory that WH-movement out of the direct discourse segment of the
variant of (78a).
structure:
to S1 instead of SO'
Notice that, while the same linear string is produced by (74A) and (74B),
however, the WH word is still within S1, although the question particle
questions is determined, I have assumed that both the WH word and the
is the part one least expected to find moved. However, in all previous
cases the question particle and the WH word have always ended up in the
the question, and how it gets its interpretation. If both (74A) and
(74B) are permissible derivations, then one must question whether the
example of case (4), the next case to be discussed. However, since the
existence of (74B) creates more doubts about (74A), I will further justi-
fy the rules which give rise to (74A) before continuing to case (4).
speaker's point of view with the WH word and question particle second
a derivation of Navajo.
The argument that (61) requires bracketing the WH word plus question
particle in the higher S is based on the fact that it can be a direct ques-
tion. Let me turn to another example which does not rely on the interpre-
the lower S would refer to John, not to the speaker, and therefore first
person possessive refers to John's father, not the speaker's father. This
is in the lower S. That is, /yo'n/ takes only two NP's, /Jaan/ and /Mary/.
(The moved WH word does not create confusion since /yo''n:/ requires an
the lower S, a fact which is confirmed by the translation. That is, only
In summary, the contrast between (79) and (80) reinforces the claim
to case (4). We have already seen examples like (61) with two possible
163
the two is that no matter how (61) is bracketed, the WH word and questionpar-
the WH word can be in the lower S, the question particle cannot be. It
is easy to see how (61) is ambiguous, but what happens when the question
word is divided up? That is, I have claimed that anything within a direct
discourse S is from the point of view of the subject of the matrix S, while
everything else is from the point of view of the speaker. If the question
because that word remains within the domain of the subject of the matrix,
to determine the acceptability of (74B) and sort out its meaning if good.
There are, however, WH elements which can never be moved away from their
particle can move unboundedly without the WH word. Such cases do exist.
b. *haala' 1i' LL
neel'/4
how.Q horse 3.there be
C. 11' haalaneela'
horse how.Q.3.there be
Examples (8l)-(82) demonstrate that the WH element /haa/ can never move
away from the verb. 27 Therefore, in (83)-(84) there is no doubt that the
doubt that the WH question particle is in the higher S, since /Jaan/ can-
not be the subject of either a first person verb ((83)) or a neuter con-
of (83)-(84). It therefore seems that case (6) does exist in Navajo for
165
the WH question particle has moved but the WH word has not. Consider
(85):
We know that /ni/ does not take NP objects, so that /Mary/ cannot be the
object of /ni/.
In addition, we know that particles are attached to the end of the first
and therefore not under the scope of the direct discourse. How then
who is asking the question (the speaker or the subject of the S immedi-
not within the direct discourse S, (85) is a direct question. Since /1/
the WH word is within the scope of the direct discourse, the /la/ forces
from the speaker's point of view, just like (74). If this theory is
why move it at all? Note, however, that the interpretation of the question
the correct point of view for the question. The difference is that this
asked.
iii) Both the question particle and the WH word get marked for
point of view. Since the question particle is outside the scope of the
either known to the speaker but not specifically mentioned (/hag 6da/),
or not known to the speaker but the speaker assumes a specific reference
there is nothing about the Navajo WH word which makes it a question ele-
ment. To leave the WH word in the direct discourse segment of the sentence
does not therefore indicate that the speaker is asking a question. (85)
using that WH word in his report of what the subject of the sentence said.
One could consider the WH word a PRO substitute for what was actually
said, similar to the English "Bill told me what to buy". Under this
theory, (85) would be asserting that John named the place Mary is from
and requesting the hearer to repeat that name. There is then, no real
difference between (85) and any other WH question asked by the speaker.
168
Although theories (i) and (iii) make different claims about the
point of view designations of the WH word and the question particle, they
end up with the same result, i.e., interpreting (85) as a direct question
ing the two through the data. However, it should be possible to decide
a direct question from the subject's point of view, and, therefore, from
tion is difficult to make, since speakers will say that these sentences
best test I know is the use of dialogues. But these also present diffi-
The most natural responses are therefore not the most useful ones. Yet,
as far as I can judge, and this with some trepidation, the following data
169
I therefore conclude that these are direct questions, i.e., that the point
question particle is in. I will leave open the factual question of how
in the next section when speculating about how this dialect of Navajo
2.4.1. Summary
particle. The particle may remain with the WH word or move to second posi-
tion in any S, with the caveat that the question particle may not end up
1. Both the WH word and the question particle end up in the indirect
(p. 130). These sentences vary greatly in acceptability, both from speaker
2. Both the WH word and the question particle end up in the same
direct discourse segment of the sentence, i.e., alternatives (1) and (5)
which are under consideration from the point of view of the subject of
ous, adding a second interpretation from the point of view of the speaker.
remains within the direct discourse segment, i.e., alternatives (2), (3),
(6), and (9) in the table. Everyone agrees that these examples are un-
grammatical.
remains behind, i.e., alternatives (4) and (8). These sentences create
the greatest problem for most people. When accepted, however, they are
direct questions from the speaker's point of view; if the question particle
which had been asked by the subject of the S immediately dominating the
question particle.
172
transformation, moving both the WH word and the question particle to ini-
tial position. This rule applies before Topicalization and the Particle
Placement rule, accounting for all the acceptable word orderings. Type
(2) is generated when unbounded WH-movement does not apply. Since the
movement includes the question particle, type (3) will never be generated.
follow nicely from a theory which says that point of view is determined
solely by the nature of the S an element ends up in, and therefore un-
brings into question both how point of view is determined and why there
(the WH word) to remain within the direct discourse S and yet be inter-
with the WH word as I have been assuming, this type still requires an
ists allow type (4) questions because the data are too murky to support
ways in which these rules and sentence interpretations may have developed.
consideration the fact that these sentences are not used in normal con-
versation. While one commonly hears questions in English like "Where did
John say he's going?", "What do you want to buy for Mary?", etc., these
questions are not heard in Navajo. The reason why such questions are not
there are two most likely explanations: either the unbounded leftward
movement does not really exist in Navajo or the factors involved in these
less, there are some examples which are pretty universally accepted. These
are examples of type (1) (not type (2)), usually with a single NP, for
example:
since when first presented with such sentences, most Navajo speakers
position. Like a simple sentence, (93) has only one subject. In fact,
174
while admittedly ungrammatical, people will even say (94) instead of (93):
I reject the hypothesis that all these examples are in fact un-
grammatical and that unbounded WH-movement does not now exist for any
Thus, if analogy were the only criterion, any sentence with two subjects
(and therefore obviously two S's) would be equally unacceptable and every-
one would agree. Everyone should agree that (95) is both unacceptable and
as bad as (96).
4
95. haa~'g/6la' Jaan Mary doog l nzin
where.to.Q John Mary 3.F.go 3.want
Where does John want Mary to go?
While some people hesitate over (95), others find it as acceptable as (93).
And having no trouble with (95) does not mean equal comfort with (96). The
difference between (93) and (95) is that in the given form of the verb,
/nizin/ takes only one NP. Since (95) has two NP's, it looks less like a
simplex sentence than does (93) with only one NP. (96) has the same number
of NP's as (95), but has the added complication that one NP has a possessive
175
the part of the speaker which takes into consideration the fact that the
preted as within a direct discourse segment, while the verb in (95) could
the data derive from the fact that there really is no unbounded movement.
People have at least as much trouble with type (2), the case with no
movement at all, as with type (1) which involves the application of un-
bounded WH-movement. This fact seems to suggest that some factor other
than (or in addition to) unbounded movement makes these sentences con-
fusing.
Navajo, one must still account for why some examples are considered
I now have, I see no principled way of accounting for the reactions under
separate S at the time the movement rule applies. The problem of proving
fact separate S's has already been discussed in Chapter 1. While I have
little proof that the S's are considered separate after WH-movement, there
is syntactic evidence that the surface strings without movement are in-
Notice that the WH word and the WH question particle are positioned so that
The first translation of (98) is the same as that in (97).31 The fact
and WH question in the same S, adding the yes/no question as in (97) dis-
The same result occurs with the particle /ya'/, the Navajo equi-
lower S.
Another and perhaps stronger argument that there are separate S's
is based on the use of the emphatic particles /ga'/ and /yee'/. These
c. *haila A
1' gal nablilgo'
who.Q horse emph 3.3.P.throw
The direct translation into Navajo of (103) and (104) without emphasis
Adding emphasis in the normal fashion, by placing /ga'/ after the word to
as the /ga'/. The fact that (104b) is grammatical means that the /ga'/ and
The use of the Navajo negative /doo. ...da/ provides another argument
probably the best argument that the S's are still separate at the time
of the unbounded movement. /doo/ can generally precede any segment within
32
the same S, although any differences still need to be investigated.
(106a) and (106b) prove that the two verbs have not become one, one of
the ways the lower S node could be eliminated (cf. Chapter 1). The un-
grammaticality of (106c) follows from the hypothesis that there are two
the /doo/ and /da/ cannot be interpreted as part of the same S. If ac-
ject of expect. The fact that movement is possible when the lower verb
is negated proves that the lower S is still there when question movement
The last argument that the direct discourse segment of the sentence
not attached to its WH word, it can appear in second position and only in
should be defined, some of the type (2) examples make sense only if second
182
subject so that /Mary/ as well as /Ja'an/ can belong to the higher S. Since
the embedded verb is in the second person, not the third, /Mary/ cannot be
in the lower S. Thus, under the assumption that there are two S's, (109)
marker. Navajos often use word order to mark topics. In general, topics
therefore also argues that there is an embedded S. That is, /Bil/ is the
(112) is the neutral, and more normal, word order, but (111) is acceptable
Sentences (113) and (114) thus revive the possibility that there is no
cient evidence to argue for any theory of change, I would like to speculate
on the genesis of these cumbersome rules. On the basis of the facts pre-
As discussed above, (93) but not (95) would then be acceptable. Since
accepting (93) creates the ability to ask a whole new set of direct
adds little to the expressive power of the language. There is thus more
confusion.
Let me now return to the central claims of this chapter and try
use of direct discourse is the root of the problem: the difficulty with
but it's difficult to translate." This remark might mean that the sen-
not just difficult to translate. There are several ways direct and in-
of the matrix.
186
and object pronouns are marked in the verb, they seem to be no more diffi-
the most natural place in a sentence for particles is after the first word
of the entire sentence, i.e., linear second position. People vary in how
For example, there is no doubt that a question particle can always occur
with its WH word. Yet, some people find (115) much less desirable that
For sentences which are reports of questions, the question particle re-
mains within the direct discourse S (type (2)). If the question particle
is to remain within the direct discourse segment, the use of linear second
187
position is impossible given a full matrix subject and normal word order.
That is, second position in the embedded S is not linear second position.
interpret.
direct question and the fact that the entire sentence is really a declara-
tive sentence. In fact, some people will answer sentences like (120), at
In other words, the question being answered is "Where is Mary from?" and
not "Where does John say Mary is from?". The WH word and question particle
are not being interpreted as a question about the entire sentence as they
are when moved out of the direct discourse S. Rather, (120) is being in-
request for an answer and the direct discourse indication that John is
They propose that the following parsing principle is employed with varying
following:
(122) was rejected because the string /Jaan Bil yishxash/ ("John bit Bill")
said 'John bit Bill'?". People vary in how strictly they adhere to the
not make sense. Thus, since inanimates don't speak, some people will look
intended meaning, "What did John say bit Bill?", and thus accepting it.
However, nobody would interpret (123) as "Who did John say bit Bill?",
Sentence (123) is only given the one translation. There are thus factors
and because the question particle is not in second position when bracketed
the matrix S. The fact that /la'/ must be in the matrix already indicates
191
NP's, and since Navajo has the surface parsing constraint, I would expect
interpretations of the /la/ and the WH word, which accounts for the con-
people to come to accept type (4) sentences, sentences in which the question
particle can only be in the matrix S and the WH word can only be in the
the sentence. But then when trying to figure out the meaning, /ha'a't' f/
of /la/ already signifies a direct WH question and the WH word must always
be associated with the embedded S,to figure out the meaning of the sentence,
some people might begin to ignore the actual position of the WH word. It
may be that type (4) examples seem grammatical because, ignoring the
and using (124) as a model for finding the meaning, the type (4) examples
are easily interpretable. That is, the only conflict for WH words posed
the question. There is no problem about what the word means within the
figuring out who is being referred to. Since the only conflict can be
become interpretable.
This line of reasoning which suggests that type (4) sentences are
acceptable by analogy says nothing about whether type (4) sentences are
the WH word, this rule also involves unbounded leftward movement. Since
fact, people who accept both types of movement differ as to which they
position and the WH word remains in the position bearing the underlying
fore reasonable that people differ in which they prefer, depending upon
whether they are more concerned with syntactic form or an easily acces-
sible interpretation.
Having described, explained, and justified the data and the types
the exact formulation of those rules. Thus, under the assumption that
the WH question particle is generated with the WH word, and then will turn
the Second Position rule, one part of a general question formation rule,
or a separate rule. I will now consider several options that would handle
194
the facts, taking into consideration the purpose of each rule, whether or
not a rule is cyclic, and how the rules interact with point of view de-
signation.
2.5.1. Are Particle Placement and Second Position the Same Rule?
they are one rule. However, I believe the two cases should be separate.
The unbounded movement of the question particle differs from the Second
ment affects the meaning of a sentence, while second position rules are
(cf. Chapter 3), the yes/no particle /-Ish/ generally goes into second
necessary, but it may be that the Navajo negative /doo... da/ is most
neutral when /doo/ occurs in second position. /doo/ can precede any
particle from one S to another, i.e., from one point of view segment to
use the Second Position rule to move a particle from one point of view
segment to another.
The second reason for not using the Second Position rule to move
the WH particle from one point of view segment to another is that the
Second Position rule is normally a bounded rule. That is, other elements
that move into second position normally go into second position in their
own clause. The /doo/ part of the Navajo negative, for example, will not
its own clause. And, as we have already seen, even the WH question
that rule will need an extra case involving a crucial variable. That case
196
will have to apply only to WH question particles and not to any of the
other particles which can go into second position in their own clause.
In other words, since the Second Position rule is bounded and the WH
handled by the former even though they both apply to the WH question
into the Second Position rule, how then should the Question Particle
Placement rule be written? One option is to have a rule which does not
interact at all with the Second Position rule. Such a rule would take
a /la/, /-sh/, or /-shg'/ from anywhere in a tree and place it after the
feeds the Second Position rule. This option claims that WH Question
unboundedly from one point of view segment to another, and then placing
position does not affect the meaning of the sentence. Recall that in
both simple and complex sentences the WH question particle need not end
up in second position; it may remain with the WH word which need not occur
197
initially. So far as I can tell, when the question particle and WH word
occur in the same S, the movement of the question particle off the WH
word does not affect the meaning of a sentence.35 That is, (128) and
People differ only as to whether they prefer leaving the question particle
rule. It would be nice to collapse them because they both have the same
purpose, moving a question element from one point of view segment to an-
other. Creating one rule captures the generalization that one or the
other, but not both, will be used in a given sentence. In addition, they
both need to refer to the WH question particle. Recall that the WH word
may not move and leave the question particle behind, i.e., type (3) sen-
moves with the WH word. If the two types of movement are collapsed, one
could say instead that the WH word optionally moves with the question
particle. That is, the rule would collapse the following two cases:
i) X -WH Q- Y
1 2 3 >2-1-3
ii) X -Q - Y
1 2 3 42-1-3
iii) X - (WH) Q - Y
1 2 3 >2 - 1 - 3
Notice, however, that when case (ii) should apply, there is still a WH
that one could choose whether to consider the WH word part of the Q or part
of the X rather than signifying that the presence of the WH word in the
parenthesis notation.
before the question formation rule has applied. That is, one could opt
separate out the question particle. But then the question particle would
be stranded sentence-initially.
199
It is only when the WH word moves with the Q particle that the question
tion must therefore follow the Second Position rule in order to insure
both (130)-(131).
it brings forward several interesting facts about the Navajo case (Chomsky,
He then says that the WH feature may be placed on either the PP or the NP.
Looking back at the Navajo, I have so far said nothing about any
the yes/no ones. Such a distinction is necessary when the WH word is not
reason therefore why the feature used to distinguish WH and yes/no ques-
tions could not also be used instead of the WH word in case (i).
word in English can never remain in any intermediate tree. Such cases,
strings of verbs and of nouns. They are of course made even more difficult
by the changing points of view, and probably by the repetition of the same
verb. While nobody would ever choose to use such sentences, so far as I
201
(132)
iP 1 V
Ja'an ni
John 3.say
NP 2
NP
N E Q
I I .Ile I
(ni) h goo la diinda l
(you) where.to.Q 2.F.go
Whatever mechanism is used to throw out (136) should also throw out
(135). Whatever the proper solution for English, it should not be based
of the COMP node because such a solution is not available for Navajo.
that once a choice is made, it is made for the entire derivation. Another
2.5.5. Chorus
desirable because the rules are disjunctive, apply in part to the same
constituent, and have the same semantic intent. Having one rule makes
whether the WH word should be considered part of the Q. Given one rule,
it is easier to see how type (4) sentences do not require the addition
an element in the Q. As separate rules, the two would share the problems
Having one cyclic rule also creates the problem of how to avoid stranding
There is one other factor about the Navajo that should be considered.
Each of the sentences has a different meaning because the point of view of
the question changes. Is it thus possible to use the point of view desig-
nation as a controller?
will never change its point of view. There is nothing in the tree which
stipulates who should be asking the question unless one adds a Q node, or
use point of view to control the movement of the question element becomes
a decision about whether a given tree should generate sentences with more
than one meaning. Let me just note that once the point of view is intro-
That is, one could postulate that in addition to an S-final COMP, Navajo
the Second Position rule which is needed anyway would insure that the WH
WH word in another S. That is, given such a theory, the following would
(137) (138)
9S V ~
la
S
N V
la'
-WH- -WH-
unbounded movement, requiring only the Second Position rules to move the
/la/ from initial to second position. That is, (137) generates (137a),
and (138) generates (138a), the two acceptable cases in which the WH word
(137) by unbounded WH-movement, and (138b) from (138) by the same rule.
the Q. That is, WH-movement would now be written as a rule which optional-
Navajo still requires an S-final COMP for /-go/ and /- (gI )/, such an
some functions. Bresnan has suggested for example that for English the
In Navajo, [+WH] would signify an initial COMP, and [-WH], a final COMP.
that complementizers are to S's what determiners are to NP's. Both are
subsumed under the term Specifier (cf. Pope, 1972).37 One could hypo-
thesize that some of the functions of the English COMP, including indi-
implausible to hypothesize both initial and final COMP nodes of the same
complementizer. Under such a theory, one could then say that all unbound-
to the usual point of view interpretation rule. That is, the point of
the WH word, but by the Q, whose point of view interpretation in turn will
terpretation is done on the surface, then only WH words which do not occur
208
in the same simplex S as their governing Q's (i.e., type (4) cases) will
distinguishes type (4) cases from the other cases, a distinction which
seems to be necessary.
a theory does not generate /l/ and the WH word together, a filter is
no WH word for the /l/,39 and those in which the WH word is in a higher
a result of applying neither the WH-movement rule nor the Second Position
rule. If, however, the /1/ is generated initially, a new rule is needed
such a rule is natural, given the existence of the optional rule which
including the yes/no particle /-ish/, one could hypothesize that whatever
rule positions the other focus particles also positions the /1/. Such
questions, the WH word is the only possible focus (since /l// cannot
say that a WH word is a focus is to use the term focus in a new, but not
unfamiliar, fashion. Just as nobody has been able to define for English
the relationship between WH words and foci, I can find no positive evi-
suggested by the fact that the emphatic particle /ga'/ which creates foci
which attracts a /la/ to a WH word still would not explain how the fol-
(expect) allows direct questions from the speaker's point of view only
(i.e., *"John expects what his father will buy" vs. "John asked what his
father will buy"), (140) could have only one possible interpretation.
In other words, the /1,/ in (140) would be generated in So, i.e., sentence-
initial position. The WH-movement rule would then attract the WH word to
for any WH-movement rule which moves the WH word into initial position.
Recall that I have said that the purpose of the unbounded WH-movement is
not to get the WH word into initial position, but to move it from an S
So far as I can tell, the Navajo facts can be handled equally well
separately from any WH word, or whether one generates the WH word and Q
211
and extent (i.e., to which S) of the WH-movement for any given sentence.
However, such a theory does not explain why these direct questions are
also cannot explain why type (4) sentences create so much more confusion
than the other types. If anything, this hypothesis suggests that type
(4) sentences should be the most acceptable since they require no movement
movement and Question Particle Placement are one rule, the choice between
order to move the question word from one point of view segment to another.
Since this theory provides no other way of specifying how far the WH word
and question particle will move, it leaves open the question of whether
the rationale for the movement should be incorporated somehow into the
2.5.10 Conclusion
in order to move a question word from one point of view segment to another.
Who is asking the question depends upon the point of view interpretation
of the S that the particle and (usually) the WH word end up in. Since a
dominating subject, only the matrix S must be from the speaker's point of
view. For the speaker to ask a question, movement to the matrix S is re-
says nothing about the direction of the movement. Whether or not a Pre-S
FOOTNOTES TO CHAPTER 2
1. Reichard (1951) also says that /-sh/ and /- sh/ are the same interro-
nominalizer /-I/.
4. Among other things, the vowel in the enclitic is /g'/ while her
ing creates added emphasis, if /-sh/ were a reduced form, one could
7. I avoid the term neutral because questions with /-ish/ need not be
8. Note that the semantic hierarchy does not seem to apply to WH words.
disagree about how preferable they are. That is, some have a strong
than the syntax. That is, if the noun ends in a vowel, it is diffi-
cult to differentiate the yes/no enclitic /-ish/ from this /-sh/, i.e.,
13. This class was part of a summer workshop on the Navajo Reservation,
sentence-finally.
215
16. The table ignores the problem of describing where within an S the
WH word and the /1/ end up. I also discuss this below.
17. The point of view given in the table is that permitted by a Strict
say "What does John want?", but that when want has a direct object,
more than three S's. One reason is that the complex sentences are
216
reason is that I know of very few direct discourse verbs, and the
I am assuming here that COMP refers to the position in which the com-
22. As I discuss below, some people can use unbounded WH question particle
ly optional.
23. As Reinhart (1973) points out, adverbs are often interpreted different-
when I talk of whole S's, I am referring only to NP's and verbs. Fur-
made.
means if grammatical.
25. It is also possible that, although /ha'ati' sh/ has moved from one S
26. Such a rule is necessary only under the assumption that the WH ques-
generated with the WH word, since the Q particle may occur between
28. In all the examples so far given, the Q particle has in fact been in
the highest S or the one it originated in. I will give examples be-
direct discourse segment other than the WH word also receive a direct
discourse interpretation.
30. Some people will allow more than one yes/no question in a simple
the cases I know about, using more than one /-ish/ is linked to the
31. As I discuss below (pp. 187f. ) one can show that (i) is a possible
(i) shows that the question can be what to buy and not what John
32. But cf. Perkins (1973) for some discussion of /doo... da/ as contrasted
does not allow quotations or are ungrammatical for some other reason.
35. However, the order of the WH word may affect the meaning. That is,
while (128) and (129) are identical, (i) may be slightly different.
37. The term Specifier has been used in an even broader sense. Chomsky
Therefore, the filter would have to throw out any sentence with more
(26). While the intent of this definition seems correct for most
CHAPTER 3
3.0. Introduction
We have now examined two types of Navajo subordinate clauses and the
questions that are formed when there is a WH word embedded in each type.
transformation and that it has been applied in this particular case to re-
move the question word from within the scope of the direct discourse. It
is due to the unbounded leftward movement that direct questions are pos-
languages. Using this type for contrast, I will generate a rationale for
totally different, I will claim that the rationale behind both atypical
223
forms is the same: some rule is needed to get the question word out of
the scope of an element which gives the question word an undesired or con-
because I believe the question formation facts are related to the nature
under /-go/, I will compare /-go/ and /-I/, demonstrating that although
their most common uses are very different, there are cases where they
will then use that difference to explain the different forms of embedded
3.1.1. Overview
will not detail how adverbial clauses get their meanings, it will be useful
224
to examine somewhat superficially this most common use of the /-go/ com-
have always made the assumption that /-go/ is an adverbial marker, as well
as help justify my claim that the same morpheme may be found as a nominal
buy it". Notice that there is no word in any of these examples that
reading is so much more natural than the other. Thus, example (1) could
225
to mean
If, however, the matrix clause is put in the perfective, the sentence does
Since the only difference between (2) and (5) is the aspect relationship
between the two clauses, it is clear that aspect is one of the factors
which determines the relationship between the two clauses. Since /-go/
appears in both sentences, it is also clear that /-go/ itself does not
that there is no single word in the above examples which performs this
function.
that example (6) makes it clear that Navajo possesses more specific ways
verbial clause and its independent clause than are found in examples(1)-
content provides a unique meaning for the sentence, one that requires such
clear, however, that /-go/ does not mark any specific relationship since
of such words as if, when, and because. Adverbial is being used here as
argue that /-go/ in fact has no semantic content at all. What is important
to note is that there are two ways in which /-go/ could be an adverbial
verbial clauses. I will consider both possibilities and show that neither
is in fact possible.
227
to find any semantic content for /-go/. Consider the following pairs with
However, it is now even less clear what the content of adverbial would
be. In examples (8)-(9), /-go/ could be said to be doing more than just
changing the part of speech. The English dark, darkly or night, nightly
the notions if, when, or because has been added with /-go/ to (7b). In
this case, /-go/ merely signifies a change in the part of speech. Thus,
/nizhonigo/.
228
It thus seems that if /-go/ has any semantic content at all, the
be defined as the common denominator of if, when, and because is too speci-
tactic marker. If the /-go/ marker appeared in only one syntactic con-
clauses, the only evidence given was the translations. To see that they
really are adverbial clauses, notice that in the above examples, the
1' da'Idiidil
We will eat.
4'. shaanlya
He came to see me.
(3) has a deletion site where horse would be, and (4) one where John would
be. It is clear from the meaning, however, that it is the noun and not the
for example, replace /-go/ in these adverbial clauses. Contrast the fol-
11.e'? /
11. *:1'L-L sinlohigi shizh(e'6 neidiyoolnih 4
horse 2.P.ropeCOMP 1.father 3.3.F.buy
A V S
rS
230
I am using the node ADV to depict the claim that these clauses are adverbi-
als and that they are subordinate clauses, i.e., that the /-go/ comple-
that the claim that /-go/ clauses are syntactically subordinate is suffi-
ordinating node. 5
/-go/ clauses are found only in such a configuration and how its syntax
adverbial S's; the latter marks sentential NP's. The following, however,
identical to the /-I/ clauses? In other words, can the /-go/ complementizer
mark sentential NP's? And, if so, are /-go/ and /- / in those cases seman-
tically identical?
232
I will use two general types of argumentation. The first is based on the
then the /-go/ clause must be. However, since pronouns generally delete
It is thus necessary to show that a subject could not have been deleted by
could have triggered the agreement, then the /-go/ clause must have done
Notice that neither type of argument proves that the /-go/ clause
structures and all /-go/ clauses are dependent adverbial clauses in the
ture, I believe it will be sufficient to show that /-go/ and /-f/ clauses
the /-i/ clause in (12b) is a sentential subject (see Chapter 1). If the
is therefore clear that it is not the surface subject. The only other
word appearing in (12a) is the verb. Thus, if the /-go/ clause is not
the subject, then the subject must have been deleted. Since pronouns
subject has been deleted. We can test this hypothesis by deleting the
that when adverbial /-go/ clauses are left out, the sentence remains well-
formed, i.e., non-elliptical, even when the subject is a pronoun which has
is incorrect.
Since there is nothing else in (12a) which could be the subject, nor is
the subject a deleted pronoun, the /-go/ clause must be the subject. The
Contrast these with the verbs we are considering which do not have
Once again, the incompleteness of (19) and (20) demonstrates that there
With the verbs that have no other subject, the /-go/ clause is translated
subject, the /-go/ gets its normal adverbial translation. Again, it seems
the above conclusion by replacing /-go/ with /-I/ in the above examples.
As we expect, the sentences are good only in those cases in which /-go/
clauses have been postulated to be NP's.
morphological evidence. I will use the verb and the negative to show that
adverbial clauses.
The most obvious cases are those with verb agreement. /yi-/ and
its variant /bi-/ appear in the verb only when there is a direct object
direct object marker. /yi-/ occurs instead of /bi-/ because the subject
is third person.6 /naldzid/ also marks objects when the subject is non-
29. nisdzid
I am afraid.
We know from the morphology that there is an object. From the translation,
we see that the /-go/ clause must be that object. Further proof that it
is in fact the /-go/ clause which is the object is provided by the fact
I will conclude my argument that /-go/ clauses are NP's with the
following sentence:
Notice first the position of the negative. The two-part negative surrounds
both the /-go/ clause and the matrix verb. While it is true that /doo/ gets
placed to enclose the entire scope of the negation, Navajo does not permit
the two parts of the negative (/doo/ and /da/) to be placed in different
S's (cf. section 2.4.5). The position of the negative therefore provides
more evidence that the /-go/ clause is not a separate subordinate clause.
Since adverbials are separate clauses, the negative demonstrates that /-go/
clauses are not always adverbials, but may be NP's. The use of the nega-
tive is therefore consistent with my claim that the /-go/ clause is the
object in (34).
(someone) and not the whole /-go/ clause is in fact the object of hear.
The sentence would then translate more like "It's not the case that I hear
7
/,a'/ requires a so-called fourth person marker. Since there is none in
(35), the /-go/ clause and not /la'/ must be the object of /diists'a/.
the part of Navajo speakers that /-go/ clauses are always adverbial. When
240
clause. It is only when such an attempt fails that they will translate
tion of whether /-go/ has any semantic content, a content somehow related
marker, then it is necessary to give up the idea that it has any semantic
have so far argued that there is an area in which /-go/ and /- / overlap.
The next step is to differentiate the two within that area. Doing so
will, I believe, clarify the function of /-go/ and therefore the problem
of its semantics.
mentizer, I have not yet looked closely at the semantics of /-go/ when it
ly. Thus, I will now contrast sentences in which the matrix verbs permit
only /-go/ on sentential NP's with ones which permit only /-1/. The dif-
that the sentences with /-i/ presuppose the truth of the complement of
9
/-i/. In contrast, the /-go/ complements require no such presupposition.
In (37b), for example, Mary is not afraid of the fact of her driving. One
cannot fear a fact, only the driving. Nor as we see in (38b) can one
imagine facts. On the other hand, one can point out a fact, consider a
provides further evidence that the complements of /-// but not /-go/ must
be presupposed:
42. shile'echaa'
LLC
nahal'ingo shil t' e 'chidi yilwo- 1
1.dog 3.barkCOMP 1.with 1.imagine pst car 3.go by it happened
I imagined that my dog was barking, but it turned out that a car was
going by.
complement.
could substitute "the fact that", "the story that", "the idea that", etc.
Navajo is a lie", or, better still, "this business about John's being a
Navajo is a lie". So far as I know, there are no Navajo nouns for "fact",
In other words, the speaker is not assuming the truth of the pro-
has said, for example, that (46) could be taken as an elided form of (49).
given is that something was said. /-// in (46) specifies that the pro-
position that John is a Navajo has previously been a part of the discourse.
reason why a language should combine the two. In fact, the two factors
term for the union of the two. However, others have also argued that the
definite NP's and factive S's (as well as generic NP's) share the property
245
priate only when anaphoric (p. 7). The definition of anaphoric used by
Pope is the broader than usual one first introduced by Kuno (1972): any
they are known or familiar to both speaker and hearer. Within Pope's
/-I/ is not that they are presupposed true, but that they are presupposed
identifiable.
tion and /-"/ is necessary, the problems become clearer when the referen-
tial hypothesis is examined through the functional notion of semantic
scope of /-i/. There are two ways to describe this fact. One is to say
This alternative relies on the condition that X may not command /-I/.
Notice, however, that under the assumption that the /-i/ and the spatial
(A)
S0
COMP
must be included in the scope of /-i/. The tree in (B) solves this
problem.
247
(B) S
COMP
Since the COMP node is Chomsky-adjoined to S2, COMP commands S2 , but nothing
-1/ and /-go/ has brought forth requirements for /-i/ clauses. So far,
however, the uses of /-go/ have not been defined any better. Although the
ungrammatical sentences with /-go/ in this section suggest that /-go/ pre-
cludes any presuppositions, we have already seen examples which show that
this statement is too strong. In (12a), for instance, /-go/ occurs with
/-;L belhozin/ (know). I return to this issue in 3.3.5. For the present,
subordinator.
248
semantically dominant "if it is not presupposed and does not have contextu-
Navajo and also affects syntactic processes in that language, among them
question formation.
249
emphasize either the /-go/ clause or the matrix clause. Erteschik has
are based on "the principle that it is only the dominant part of the
sentence which it is natural to comment on" (p. 16). One test says that
type and a particular clause fails that test, then that clause cannot be
51. Bil Ja'an dine' nil{'go yinishdla nigo doo kot 'e'eda
Bill John Navajo 3.beCOMP 1.believe 3.say.COMP neg thus.be.neg
It is not right that Bill said he believes that John is a Navajo.
4
(a) Bil e doo hwididooniilda
Bill that neg thus.3.say.neg
Bill wouldn't say that.
The fact that the /-i/ clause in example (50) cannot be denied is proof
In (51), however, the idea that John is a Navajo could be new information
to dominance: it is the context and not the /-go/ which determines the
dominance. This point is even more obvious when a sentence is put into
heard".11
there are two ways in which these two sentences could be considered dif-
ferent. First is the case where the embedded clause must be semantically
dominant. Thus (13a) but not (13b) could answer the following direct
question:
(54) is not asking whether you heard about something. It is asking for
information about where Mary has gone. (54) could not be answered
Therefore, as an answer to (54), the embedded and not the matrix clause in
sponse to (54).
Although both (13a) and (13b) talk about hearing that Mary went to Flag-
staff, the two convey different information. In (13a), the speaker need
not know whether or not Mary has gone to Flagstaff. He is neutrally re-
porting what had been said by others. In (13b), the speaker is reporting
what he considers to be the truth, what he had heard from reliable sources.
58a. Mary kin]a/nigo6' iiyaago yishniih, ako ndi Mary hooghandi sida' nisin
Mary Flagstaff.to 3.P.goCOMP 1.hear but Mary home at 3.sit 1.think
I hear that Mary has gone to Flagstaff, but believe she's at home.
/-1/. It is not so clear, however, how (13b) relates to the dominance hy-
Yet I have claimed that /-,/ clauses are always semantically subordinate.
both the speaker and the hearer. However, Karttunen (1973) has pointed
out that factive verbs can be used to convey information. Consider the
following:
already knew that information. The use of a factive verb indicates that
S is conveying the new and most important information in the sentence, (59)
to include only those cases where the speaker assumes that the presupposi-
Although not all clauses with /-5/ can be subsumed under the defini-
the entire subordinate clause of (13a) which is the answer to (57). There
255
of it. I will return to this point below. For the present, note that when
constituent of the main clause, an /-/ clause is part of the dominant main
clause. But as an NP, the clause must also be taken as a single element,
However, unlike the English equivalents, Navajo /-5/ clauses never act
contrast to help describe the Navajo facts. Also for this reason, the
other concepts developed for English are not exactly appropriate for
more like the complement of factive verbs in that its complement must be
It should now be clear how an /-i/ clause can seem semantically dominant
is known to both the speaker and the hearer, either through presupposition
However, /-i/ must denote reference only with respect to the speaker.
When the reference is not shared with the hearer, an /- / clause need not
be semantically subordinate according to Erteschik's definition. However,
with respect to syntactic rules, anything that is referential in Navajo
Let us now return to the other examples in which /-go/ and /-I/
seemed to be identical.
the meaning of the verb know, the reason for the identity in this particular
of a fact. 13
Since in (12) /-1 bee'h'zin/ is unqualified, there is no dif-
lated as "I think I know...". So far as I am aware, this is not the case.
In all the other cases where /-go/ has been used to cast doubt, the doubt
has not been about the accuracy of the matrix verb, but about commitment
saying he's not sure what he heard, but that he's not sure he believes
/-I b46hdzin/ requires doubting the assertion involved in the matrix verb
The (b) sentences are perfectly consistent with my claim. (60b) is ungram-
proposition. One cannot be in the state of knowing and not knowing simul-
Sentences (60a) and (62a) are the first cases given in which
Sentence (63) may be the most obvious evidence of the identity. From
section 3.1 that /-go/ contains the notion "adverbial". /-go/, in con-
of the sentence. To say that two S's are logically connected is to require
to the independent clause which causes that interpretation, i.e., the fact
that there are other subjects and complements. I suggest that the tendency
are normally used that way, and not on the semantics or syntax of /-go/.
English one may use when instead of if to imply that one expects the con-
65. When you rope the horse,my father will buy it.
66. If you rope the horse, and I don't think you will, my
father will buy it.
67. *When you rope the horse, and I don't think you will, my
father will buy it.
Both (64) and (65) require you to rope the horse in order for my father to
pectations, as can be seen from (66) and (67). Since /-go/ itself is
/-sh'/ to the /-go/ clause. While the precise uses and meaning of /-shfV
(68) says nothing about whether the speaker believes that the condition
(your not breaking in the horse) will be met. It is also neutral about
261
how this condition might not be met. You may not even try to tame the
horse. Sentence (69), on the other hand, would be uttered only when the
doubting your ability to do it. He is really saying, "if you should fail,
I'll do it", or "when you fail to break in the horse, I'll take over".
English if can be used neutrally, much like /-go/. Notice also that it
is the auxiliary verb (do vs. can) which provides the shift in meaning.
As we saw in section 3.1, Navajo also uses its verb to provide information
sentence may be left vague, or other factors can be used to fill in the
in behavior.
262
exactly how second position should be defined because there are many
the yes/no question clitic need not go into second position at all.
Kenneth Hale and Ellavina Perkins, investigating the uses of one negation
particle /hanii/, discovered that Navajo has the option of placing /hanii/
The result is that the rest of the S becomes presupposed. It seems that
6
72. Jaan -4 ' biztal shl
John horse 3.3.P.kick.Q
Is it kicking that the horse did to John?
263
tion, the focus is on the constituent immediately to the left of the clitic
what did then?". Since (71) presupposes that something kicked John, a
denial implies that the speaker knows what did. A simple "no" is thus
or simply,
negative /doo... da/ when a proposition has already been asserted and the
Notice once again that it is unnecessary to repeat the entire sentence when
The first part of (80) denies that it is sheep the boys are herding. In
addition, however, it presupposes that the boys are herding something. The
265
assumption, therefore, is that the second part of the sentence need not
-kal/ can only take certain animals as its object. Thus, one herds
sheep and goats but not girls. /at'ele/ could be a subject of /yinoolkal/.
The fact that /at Ie'ke/ is an incorrect continuation while /tl' z/ in (81)
is fine, shows that it is the object and not the subject which must be
constituent and presuppose the rest of the sentence. Now let us turn to
complex sentences.
concerned here with focus and presupposition rather than the scope of the
the embedded clause, the scope of the denial is the entire embedded clause.
More precisely, the semantic effect of /hanii/ "is clearly to deny the
reason, i.e., the rational connection between the subordination and the
main clause" (p. 19).19 What is germane to the present discussion is the
fact that /hanii/ has the same effect on embedded /-go/ clauses as it does
(her (15))
88. Mary hanii nfyaago baa shil hozho, Jaan ga'
Mary neg 3.P.comeCOMP 3.about 1.with 3.happy John emph
It's not that Mary came that I'm happy about, but (that) John (did).
/Jaan/ is being contrasted to the focus /Mary/. Since the rest of the sen-
Notice that the only good question sentences are those in which /- sh/ acts
ment within the proposition. The only grammatical sentences with /hanii/
are the ones in which there is no focus within the embedded clause. When
/hanii/ is placed after the embedded clause (e.g., (94)), the entire pro-
3.4.2. The ungrammatical sentences here are identical to the good sen-
assume that it is the choice of the complementizer and not the placement
is a restatement of a claim that has been made (the horse kicked John) and
One must either accept or deny the whole. He may then, if he wishes, pick
apart the proposition, explaining which parts he believes and which he does
not.
Sentence (97) states that the horse threw the boy and inquires whether you
are aware of that fact. If something is stated as the truth, how can part
Although the above examples suggest that /hanii/ and /-Ish/ can
never occur in certain positions when used with /-i/ because these particles
While not apparent in the above examples, the crucial factor which causes
clause, but that this use of a focus excludes the focus from the presup-
supposition that something kicked John, but denies that the horse did it.
horse be excluded from the presupposition. That is, I claim that a focus
believe that the horse kicked John and simultaneously to deny that it was
the horse who kicked John. In other words, in this case, denying something
about the horse with respect to the matrix verb entails separating horse
271
main verb but still include that element in the presupposition, the use
(99) is possible because it does not deny that the horse kicked John. It
denies only that I had heard about it. In fact, my consultant explained
that (99) presupposes that the horse did kick John. She contrasted (99)
with (100), explaining that with /-i/ both the horse and the mule kicked
John, but when /-i/ is replaced by /-go/, only the mule kicked John.
Notice that the English translations are the same in both cases.
Consider the following Navajo relative clause and its English translation:
101. ;11'
LI.
hanii nabi ;lgo'e'q ashkii shik'ihod i'4
horse neg 3.3.P.throw.REL boy 1.3.P.blame
It's not the boy whom the horse threw who blamed me.
272
In (101) the proposition "the boy fell off the horse" is not being negated.
that someone blamed me. What is being denied is that the boy, identified
as the one who fell off the horse, did the blaming.
associated with /-i/ requires that the entire clause have the same re-
/-go/ to those discussed in Chapter 1 with /- /, and show how the referen-
Since /-go/ clauses are most commonly adverbs, I will begin the
Since these sentences have no direct English translation, I have given two
English, but misrepresents the syntax of the /-go/ clause. The second one
gives the proper syntax to the /-go/ clause, but no ordinary English ques-
cussed.
274
the /-go/ clause is not being used as either a subject or object by de-
leting it:
106. yishcha
I am crying.
incomplete about (106) as there would be if the /-go/ clause were an ob-
These examples are significant for several reasons. For one, these
ordinate clauses where both the WH word and the interrogative particle
actually appear. For another, these questions are direct questions rather
because they don't clarify the full extent of the questions. In (103),
for example, the question is not only "what happened?", but what happened,
and how is its happening connected to your being angry? The closest English
The crucial point is that what is being questioned is not only the
WH word, but its connection to the main clause. This phenomenon is the
275
being a part of the clause" (p. 19). Analogously, insofar as its scope is
another and thereby requiring a real world connection between the clauses.
That connection, and therefore the /-go/, plays a crucial role in the mean-
ing of the question. That is, the main clause enters into the question in-
empty complementizer that the question can have the meaning that it does.
/-I/ is substituted for /-go/ (in those environments where both comple-
mentizers are normally possible). The following examples substantiate
these claims:
276
b. *halat ' la biniinaa Ja'an Mary yich'i' haadzi' gii nil b6(h6zin
112a. haala' yit 'lego Jaan dine' bizaad yihool' a'go nil be'hzin
The above examples have all the crucial properties of the WH questions
from adverbial clauses: they are direct questions; as far as the scope
part of the matrix; both the WH word and the interrogative particle are
present; and such questions are either impossible or not normal in English.
While not apparent in the previous examples, notice also the crucial pro-
cannot replace /-I/ in the syntactic form required for embedded WH ques-
and
/-i/ are indirect questions formed through deletion of the WH word
above sentence:
Answers to questions with /-i/ but not with /-go/ require an answer about
whether the person knows the information. Contrast the following re-
sponses:
R: doo deeyahigooda
neg 3.P.goCOMPto.neg
He's .not going anywhere.
"do you know?" and the indirect form of the question "where is John going?".
It is this word which changes form from (114) to (115), from a direct to
an indirect question.
The difference between the two syntactic forms should thus be re-
lated to the difference between direct and indirect questions. Why should
not /-i/ clauses, can be semantically dominant, it follows that the former
explain why we find both direct and indirect embedded questions in Navajo.
We still need to ask, however, why we find different syntactic forms, and,
more specifically, why the WH word deletes when embedded under /-f/. If
tinguishes between direct and indirect questions, why must the WH word
However, the hearer of sentence (117) could only interpret it to mean "do
you know that John went?". If (117) were considered to have a deleted WH
tains a clitic, the clitic does not delete with it, but moves to comple-
mentizer position. Thus, the /goo/ in (115) tells us that the deleted
not contain clitics, who, what, how, why. In fact, it is only possible
to form indirect questions with /-i/ with the first two. Navajo minimizes
text. It is not the case, however, that question words are normally
anaphoric from the speaker's point of view. That is, the speaker is not
question (118) is in fact ambiguous (or perhaps vague) about the speaker's
assumptions.
It may be used with the knowledge that John is going somewhere. Thus, if
Bill and Mary are walking down the street and see John pull out of his
driveway, one might turn to the other and utter (118). In this case, the
speaker assumes that where does have a reference, but may have no assump-
tions about the identity of the reference. On the other hand, if Mary is
trying to find out what John is going to be doing, she might ask Bill
(118) without any assumption that John is in fact going anywhere. In this
case, (118) could be paraphrased, "Do you know if John is going anywhere,
unique reference for the WH word. The use of these questions therefore
reference is required. It is clear that the speaker does not have know-
ledge of the reference for where in (118). It is also true that the
speaker need not presuppose that his companion has that knowledge in
Bill may assume that where has a reference but have no reason to assume
that his companion knows any more than he. It would still be natural to
ask Mary (118) in order to find out whether she has any such knowledge.
/-I/. If the WH word were to remain in the embedded S, the semantic in-
have a reference. Yet we have just said that the question word is to be
question word deletes. Notice that when enclitic movement takes place
of /-i/. (See the following section for more evidence.) It was thus
know?".
From what has been said so far, /ha'at' shff/ does not seem to be
referential. How then can it stay within the scope of /-1/? While I do
used referentially:
ha / deeyaigif hi
123. Jan ch'aa deeyada'f, "'shj
beehodooz ;k
3.F.know
however that since it is not certain in (123) that John will be traveling,
in the sense that the speaker is indicating that he presupposes that the
that John wants something that I cannot identify but I think you can, so
will you tell me? Notice that, given this interpretation, sentences like
(121) need not be indirect questions at all, but only a yes/no question
Navajo has still another form for what, /ha'tt' ida/. Although the
facts are not as yet completely clear, it seems that this variant is em-
ployed when the speaker not only assumes there exists a reference, but in
fact knows what that reference is. Thus, when an indirect question is
125. Ja'an ha'a'tI'ida yinizinig 1 Mary bil be4hozin, ndi doo e' niida
John what -da 3.3.wants Mary 3.with 3.be known but neg thab 3.say.neg
Mary knows what John wants, but she isn't saying.
286
question involving a specific reference for the WH word. This type in-
among some speakers to move a spatial enclitic out of its S when there are
two non-identical third persons. Thus, some speakers will accept (126b).
However, if good, (126b) means that the place (where) has previously been
words, if for some reason a spatial enclitic does remain within the scope
the scope of /-i/. These WH words are semantically consistent with the
So far I have tried to account for why there are embedded direct
questions with /-go/ but not /-a/ and why the WH word deletes in embedded
that it is impossible to form indirect questions with /-go/ the way they
for a translation from the English, the answer is always a sentence with
I/2 with one exception. The only indirect question type that is
know, however, that WH words do not delete within /-go/ clauses. However,
question, as in (129).
I believe the problem with (129) is that the embedded question cannot be
singles out the element it is attached to, thereby requiring that clause
stantiated by the fact that, when accepted, (129) is not answered /auut/
direct discourse cases because the questions were from different points
Since /-go/ clauses are indirect discourse clauses, the point of view
would be, "*did Bill hear and where that Mary ran away from?".
not contain a question particle: the only question particle is the yes/no
particle /- sh/. One might therefore expect that an indirect question with
particle, as in (130).
Such sentences are occasionally accepted, but the response rarely includes
are possible. However, the sentences still create confusion. More in-
with /-go/, they would be formed either by deletion of the WH word (with
25
enclitic raising) as in indirect questions with /-i/, or by leaving the
necessary to account for the fact that these alternatives are impossible.
raising from applying to /-go/ clauses. I opt for using /-i/ to trigger
do occur embedded under /-go/. They occur in direct questions with the
fore that indirect questions with /-go/ are impossible because, while WH
move out of the embedded S, just as it does in the direct discourse cases
direct discourse S's also allows movement out of /-go/ clauses, those
WH particle movement, leaving the WH word within the embedded /-go/ clause.
(133)-(134) are examples of both the WH word and question particle moving
out of the embedded clause. Note that in (135), the WH word appears to
have moved, but it has not ended up in initial position. In other words,
all the possibilities that occur with direct discourse sentences can also
occur for some speakers with /-go/ clauses. The difference is, of course,
that these are the only possibilities for direct questions from embedded
direct discourse clauses, while the normal method for question formation
from /-go/ clauses is to leave the WH word and question particle within
zation from the movement out of direct discourse clauses. That is, I am
suggest that, whatever the proper formulation of the rule may be, there
these cases. That rule is not normally used in SOV, COMP-final languages
but exists in Navajo, I claim, because of the problem created by the use
rule is at times generalized for /-go/ clauses, but never for /- / clauses,
even though it is the latter which cause problems. This difference should
plete theory, I will make some claims about such a theory in the Conclusion.
294
FOOTNOTES TO CHAPTER 3
for some people. Also, it is still not clear whether indirect ques-
The sentence then means, "the horse you roped my father will buy".
5. Since I argue that not all /-go/ clauses are adverbial, the node ADV
section 3.3.4.
6. /yi-/ and /bi-/ both occur with the third person subject and object
When the object precedes the subject, /bi-/ instead of /yi-/ appears
7. The use of the fourth person is much more complicated than my ex-
when /la'/ refers to a person. Thus (36) is good with the meaning
why it can occur there, but discuss the problem further in section
3.3.4.
if (1) neither A nor B dominates the other; and (2) the S-node that
167).
Note that as defined, the head of a relative clause is not
wards deletion of the antecedent. In the former case only the entire
ferences in meaning. The reason could be that all definite NP's are
clauses, which are S's, but not NP's, and I argue that it is the same
enclitics.
words, what makes /-1 be'ehd'zin/ different from the true factives
14. While I have been told of such readings by more than one person,
17. I have probably left out some possible readings. A ? in this case
18. See Hale (forthcoming A) for a comparison between the scope of /hanii/
19. It is not clear whether the presence of /hanii/ in the embedded clause
(1973).
20. Notice that these sentences require a new definition of focus and/or
exclude the focus from it, i.e., as "an expression derived by replac-
ing the focus by a variable" (26). Since in these cases the focus is
concepts.)
298
21. The other logical possibility is that the WH word itself moves out-
side the scope of the /-1/. In the Conclusion I discuss some hypo-
theses concerning the claim that WH words will never move rightward,
and try to account for why the WH word does not move leftward out of
fact that Navajo has these direct question sentences which cannot be
24. It is also not clear whether these sentences can be used temporally
as well. (128) has also been translated "Do you know when John will
26. This argument is possible only in a theory in which the question par-
ticles are generated with the WH word rather than in a pre-S node.
27. The English translation is misleading because the Navajo is not asking
where Bill heard a fact, but where Mary ran away from, according to
CONCLUSION
for their existence. In addition, some new criteria must be found to ex-
plain when and in which direction unbounded movement will occur. I believe
tizerAttraction Universal which was meant to account for the fact that only
unbounded leftward movement had been found in natural languages. Many more
movement. I have claimed for Navajo that the existence of unbounded move-
Such a requirement is certainly not universal--it does not hold for English,
found for the other SOV, COMP-final languages which have unbounded movement.
traction states that "extraction can occur only out of clauses or phrases
300
which can be considered dominant in some context" (27). Since /-go/ but
for the fact that unbounded leftward movement does not occur from /- /
clauses, it must be stated so as to be irrelevant to indirect questions
with /-i/ since in that case spatial enclitics may be extracted, but
a restriction is not ad hoc, and that the correlation between the concept
or leftward.
mined by word order. Since the COMP in English will always be to the
if A bears heavier stress than B." Movement rules therefore "have the
Since semantic dominance refers only to the clause out of which an element
may move, and not to the element itself, I have introduced the term
word moves leftward but not to the matrix S, i.e., not to initial posi-
the scope of the question. That is, WH words in English move leftward
suggest that what makes COMP position significant is that the COMP is a
the question.
movement) both condition (i) and condition (ii) result in leftward move-
I hypothesize for Navajo that the two conditions plus the scope
is the verb which determines the point of view: movement is out of the
scope of one verb into that of another. Notice that the element governing
the scope determines the extent but not the direction of the movement.
ment were toward it, we would find rightward movement, not leftward. It
words in direct questions are prominent they cannot move rightward (con-
dition (ii)). Since the WH word must move because of scope factors, it
moves leftward.
and still be prominent. However, since in these cases the entire sentence
is within the scope of the question, the WH word may also occur in any S
in the sentence. I am not claiming for Navajo that the scope of a ques-
semantically associated.
304
tial, creating a conflict. The WH word must therefore be removed from the
and the scope of the WH question will be the entire S. Since /i/ clauses
clause to control the scope of the entire sentence. If the WH word moved
it would still be interpreted as within the scope of the /-i/. That is,
Navajo marks the end rather than the beginning of a clause with a comple-
(A)
(
305
(B) O
NP V
. NP V C MP
(C)
(NP) . P
M
producing the same linear string. Since Navajo marks the end rather than
whether or not the element has moved out of the embedded S. For Navajo,
condition (i) could be stated either in terms of the verb or the COMP since
both are used to mark clauses. (Recall that direct discourse S's have no
COMP rather than the governing verb since it is in general COMP position
which marks one boundary of an embedded clause. Notice that such a state-
ment does not commit me to postulating underlying COMP's for direct dis-
given the rightward movement, why does the WH word delete leaving only the
beyond the scope of the /-i/ is also movement beyond the scope of the
are simply ways of stating that, for whatever reason, unbounded rightward
near the beginning rather than the end of a sentence has long been con-
couched in more formal terminology to claim that what comes first sets the
crucial.
(i) and (ii) are in conflict, the language is less likely to use unbounded
rules. There are two major factors which lead to movement, prominence and
require the latter. I suggest that since the most natural movement in SOV,
theory of movement should take into consideration both syntactic and seman-
tic factors. Further refinement of these factors will depend upon examina-
FOOTNOTES TO CONCLUSION
1. Recall the one case where /-I/ clauses were considered dominant
from the English cases. In other words, the rider "in some context"
prominence.
3. I use the notation (NP) to describe the fact that S may be either
an NP.
COMP, and movement were to COMP position, these sentences would not
REFERENCES
197-219.
Mass.
and M. Halle (1968) The Sound Pattern of English, Harper and Row,
New York.
Grosu, A. (1973) "On the Status of the So-Called Right Roof Constraint,"
Haile, B. (1942) Learning Navaho, Vol. II, St. Michaels Press, Saint
Michaels, Arizona.
Illinois.
Particles."
tics IV:1.
positions.
the Complementizers."
III, 269-321.
312
63o-664.
Perkins, Ellavina (1973) "The Semantics and Syntax of the Navajo Particle
dissertation, MIT.
MS, MIT.
313
dissertation, MIT.
Sgall, P., E. Hajicova, and E. Benesova (1973) Topic, Focus and Generative
BIOGRAPHICAL NOTE
The author, born in New York, N.Y. on April 23, 1946, lived in
Roslyn, N.Y. during her youth and graduated from Friends Academy High
magna cum laude in June, 1968 with a major in philosophy and a chronic
Under their guidance she began graduate work, taking time off to get
married and accompany her husband to the wilds of Belgium and New York
tion, and hopes for a university career. Her article "Navajo Spatial
life with her husband Jay, baby son Ian, and proud canine Waffle after