Cornelia Hamann: Introduction To English Linguistics
Cornelia Hamann: Introduction To English Linguistics
Cornelia Hamann: Introduction To English Linguistics
Part I
Cornelia Hamann
Handout based on word by
Cornelia Hamann
And
Geneveva Puskas (Syntax)
For additional reading please consult
1
Fromkin, Rodman and Hyams: An Introduction to Language
Stand: 22.3.2005
2
Semantics and Pragmatics
Cornelia Hamann
University of Oldenburg
1. Introduction p. 3
2. Lexical Semantics p. 4
2.1. Semantic properties and semantic features p. 4
2.2. Relationships between words (nyms) p. 7
2.3. Levels of language p. 11
3. Phrasal and sentential semantics p. 12
3.1. Three basic approaches to meaning p. 12
3.2. Building up meanings p. 13
3.2.1. Important constraints p. 13
3.2.2. From atomic to complex expressions p. 16
3.3. Sentence meaning p. 21
3.3.1. Preliminary considerations p. 21
3.3.2. The definition of sentence meaning p. 23
3.3.3. Meaning relations between sentences p. 23
4. Pragmatics p. 26
4.1. Conversational Maxims p. 26
4.2. Speech Acts p. 28
4.3. Discourse and Situation (Deixis) p. 29
References p. 33
3
Chapter 4
Semantics and Pragmatics – the meaning side of language
1. Introduction
Semantics and pragmatics describe how meaning is assigned to the expressions of a
language. To understand an utterance we must know the meanings of words and
morphemes, we must know how the meanings of words combine into the meanings of
larger syntactic units and how the meanings of such phrases combine into sentence
meanings, and finally we must interpret the utterance according to the context in
which it is made. So there are several layers which contribute to the final
interpretation or “reading“ of an utterance. Normally, interpretation proceeds in three
steps.
Step 1: The meanings of words (mare) and morphemes (un) have to be defined.
Such meanings are discussed and defined in lexical semantics.
Step 2: The meanings of lexical units (mare, brown) must be combined to form larger
chunks of meanings (brown mare) in order to arrive at the meaning of phrases and
constituents. The rules for combining meanings are discussed in phrasal or
sentential semantics. The most fruitful way to define sentence meaning with respect
to the meaning of the parts of a sentence is truth conditional semantics.
Step 3: Some expressions and their “meaning“ can only be fully interpreted when the
situational or discourse context are taken into account. The contribution of context
(situation, discourse) to the meaning of a phrase or sentence is dealt with in
pragmatics. The situational context may tell us that a question like “can you pass the
salt?“ is not a question and should not be answered by “yes, I can“, but is actually a
request and that the appropriate “answer“ is to pass the salt.
Example (1)
4
WWW = male person (not the speaker or the hearer) salient in the
discourse context
LOVE: is a verb which takes a complement (and a subject) and…
Example (2)
human
a’ssassin murderer
murderer of important person
(3) The assassin of Thwacklehurst escaped.
Even if you do not know who Thwacklehurst is, you can deduce from your
knowledge of word meaning, see (2), that Thwacklehurst must be an important
person. You also know that he was killed and that he was killed by some other person
– not a wolf or a snake or some other animal, even though nothing of this is explicitly
mentioned in sentence (3). Such pieces of information on which speakers agree are
part of the semantic properties of a word.
In example (2) we have split up the meaning of assassin into several smaller
components. Such meaning components (pieces of information) of words (or
morphemes) are called semantic properties or semantic features. When trying to
define word meaning, one way to go is to find as many of these properties of a word
as is possible.
5
Some common, recurring properties are [animate], [human], [male], [female].
Such basic properties can be supplemented with more specific properties like [(very)
young], [married/single] or [was married and partner died]. Table 1 and table 2 give
examples of how semantic features approximate word meanings.
Table 1
father parent husband baby child widow student
animate + + + + + + +
human + + + + + + +
male + +/ + +/ +/ +/
female +/ +/ +/ + +/
young + + +
married +/ +/ + +/
was +
married,
partner
died
Table 2
father woman girl mare
animate + + + +
human + + +
male +
female + + +
young +
special parent equine
Consider the word list: lioness, doe, ewe, hen, mare, vixen, niece, debutante, girl,
maiden, wife, woman. The words all share the feature [female]. Words which share a
feature form a semantic class with respect to this feature. In the above list, two
classes emerge if you consider the feature [human].
Focussing on the feature [human], the semantic class includes doctor, father,
boy, widow, aunt, uncle, niece, girl, maiden, wife, woman. The words, niece,
debutante, girl, maiden, wife, woman, aunt have the feature [female] and the feature
[human]. They are both in the class of humans and in the class of females. They are
thus in the intersection of these two classes.
Considering similarities and contrasts in meaning helps to find the semantic
properties of words. Note that by considering such properties or features you arrive at
word fields.
6
Note also that the tables could be made more concise if one leaves out one of
the features [male] or [female] and uses only one of them. This works because
[+male] is the same as [female] and [+female] is the same as [male]. Table 1 and 2
are redundant in information with respect to these features (but not wrong).
In order to describe the meaning of verbs other features are needed. Again,
some features are useful in almost any verb description, whereas others specify
certain verb meanings or contrast the meanings of two verbs. An important feature is
[motion], as shown in table 3.
Table 3
walk run stalk
motion + + +
on foot + + +
slow + +
fast +
purposeful +
Contrasting walk and stand, the feature [motion] would be differently specified:
walk: [+motion, ….], stand: [motion,…]
Another verb feature is [cause]. It occurs in darken or kill which can be
described as [cause to become dark] and as [cause to die]. We also find verbs for
which [contact] is the important feature (touch, kiss), for which [creation] plays a role
(build, make, draw), or for which [result] is the dominant feature (reach, die, drown).
The tables we have drawn specifying features as +/ are a formal way of capturing the
semantic properties of words. Features have been used also in other fields of
linguistics (phonology, syntax). Such formal descriptions of linguistic expressions are
often called ‚structural linguistics‘. Decomposition of word meanings into semantic
features would thus sometimes be called ‚structural semantics‘.
Features can be relevant for a noun, but equally for a verb. Features can be
shared, or there can be a feature clash, in which case an utterance does not make sense
or cannot be interpreted.
If someone says „X swims“, you know that X is in a liquid. If „X splashes“,
again [+liquid] is a feature. Moreover, from example (4) based on your knowledge
about the features of swim (and container), you can deduce that goop has the feature
[+liquid], you can also figure out that goop is a noun from the way it is used here.
(4) I saw a bug swimming in a container of goop
7
Having figured out this feature of goop, you know that examples (5a) and (5b) make
sense, because pour and drink are also marked [+liquid]. Example (5c) does not make
sense because cut and eat are marked [+solid]. In example (5c) there is a feature clash.
Note that drink is marked as [+liquid], whereas eat is marked as [+solid] in English.
So only (6a) is a good English sentence, (6b) is not. German is different here, (6c)!
(5a) I‘ll pour the goop away
(5b) Bill always drinks goop for breakfast
(5c) *#Bill always cuts his goop and eats it
(6a) drink your soup
(6b) *#eat your soup
(6c) Ich esse meine Suppe nicht!
Some semantic features have consequences for syntax – for the way in which
words can be combined. The feature [+/count] is important for nouns and influences
the type of articles, determiners and quantifiers the noun can combine with or whether
the noun can form a plural or not.
I have a dog *I have a rice
I‘ll walk the dog *I’ll have the rice (?)
I have two dogs *I have two rice
I have many dogs *I have many rice, much rice
I have dogs *I have rices
If a noun has the feature [+count], it can combine with articles, with numerals, with
the quantifier many, and it forms a plural. If a noun is [count], it cannot take articles,
numerals, and cannot take the quantifier many, it takes much instead. It cannot form a
plural either. The features [concrete] and [abstract] do not predict whether a noun is a
count noun or not:
(8) [+concrete, +count]: book, dog, man, desk…
[+concrete, count]: rice, tea, flour, furniture…
[+abstract, +count]: idea, view, concept…
[+abstract, count]: love, hate…
2.2. Relationships between words ….nyms
If two words have the same pronunciation but different meanings, they are called
homonyms.
8
(9) file, trunk, tail/tale, to/two/too.
Homonyms create ambiguity: a long tail – a long tale. They can be disambiguated via
feature (in)compatibility: a bushy tail/*tale, a romantic tale/*tail.
The homonym bear/bare includes a noun, a verb and an adjective. Bear, the
verb, has several meanings which are related semantically: (i) tolerate, (ii) carry, (iii)
support. A word with several related meanings like bear is called polysemous.
Words which are spelled in the same way are called homographs.
Homographs can be homonyms, see (10).
(10) pen – enclosure for animals
pen – writing utensil, pencil.
However, they often are not homonyms, see (11).
(11) lead (verb) [i:]
lead (noun) [:]
Note that homonyms need not be homographs, (12)
(12) tale/tail.
Homographs like lead/lead with different pronunciations are called heteronyms.
Examples for heteronyms are: lead, wind (noun/verb). bow is a homograph with three
meanings. It is also a heteronym. One of these pronunciations is a homonym, see (13)
Words that sound different, but have the same meaning are called synonyms. Full
synonymy is difficult to find, mostly there are slight differences in meaning or in use.
Sofa and couch may be full synonyms, but if one considers
apathetic/phlegmatic/sluggish/indifferent these are listed as synonyms even though
they do not mean exactly the same things. So often an overlap in features is enough
and to be safe, one sometimes speaks of partial synonymy only. English is
particularly rich in synonyms (or partial synonyms) due to its history and the French
vocabulary which enriched the Anglo Saxon base, see (14)
9
begin – commence
hide – conceal
feed – nourish
wife – spouse
yard – court
drink – beverage
Sometimes synonymy exists in one use of a word, but not in others. In such a case, a
polysemous word shares one of its meanings: mature and ripe or profound and deep
are examples, see (15) and (16)
Replacing a word in a sentence with its synonym does not change the meaning of the
sentence. The two sentences are paraphrases of each other, see (17).
(17) She forgot her glasses = She forgot her spectacles
paraphrase
glasses = spectacles
synonyms
Sometimes several specific terms can be subsumed under a more general term. Red,
blue, yellow are all words for colours. In such cases, the more general term (here
colour) is called the hypernym and the more specific or subterms are called
hyponyms, see (18).
red, blue, green colour
dog, cat, whale mammal
lion, flea, ant, cat, hen animal
10
Red is a hyponym of colour/coloured. Coloured/colour is a hypernym of red etc.
The relation of hypo/hypernyms gives rise to a meaning relation between sentences:
(19) If X is hyponym (rose), then X is hypernym (flower). See (20).
The reverse does not hold.
(20) a. If a ball is red, it is coloured. (If a ball is coloured it is not necessarily red)
b. If an animal is a cat, it is a mammal
c. If John picked a rose, he picked a flower
d. If John ate an apple, he ate a fruit
If two terms express opposites of meaning, they are called antonyms.
There are two large groups of antonyms shown in (21).
If you negate one of the terms of the pairs of antonyms of group I you get a synonym
of the other term of the pair. Take dead, negate it, you get not dead which is a
synonym of alive. Do it in the other direction: take alive, negate it, you get not alive,
which is a synonym for dead as shown in (22). Note that you can do this in both
directions.
Group II is called the class of gradable antonyms because terms of this class
can be true of something to a certain degree, in some instances more in some
instances less. Gradable antonyms enter into a scale of comparison. They can take er,
est or more, most establishing a scale of comparison. John may be tall, Bill may be
11
taller still and Peter could be the tallest of the three. Dicky, on the other hand, could
be short, so that John, Bill and Peter are all taller than he is. Obviously we are
comparing the four boys on a scale of height with Dicky being at one end of this scale
and Peter on the other. So tall and short, the two terms of a pair of gradable antonyms,
are involved with the same scale, the scale of heights (for boys), with short boys on
one end of this scale and tall boys on the other end. These ends are called poles, the
negative and the positive pole.
(23) gives a list of some gradable antonyms and (24) gives a sketch of the
scale involved for tall and short. Note that gradable antonyms are always relative,
which means that Peter can be tall for a boy but need not be tall if you consider the
standards for men or for basketball players. These terms thus apply relative to the
class described by the noun: a big ant is not big in an absolute sense, it is not a big
animal, only big for an ant.
(23) beautiful – ugly
good – bad
big – small
tall – short
fast – slow
happy – sad
(24) xx][xx>
… …
1.50 1.80 2.00
short men tall men
height of men
(25) If x is alive, x is not dead. If x is not dead, x is alive.
alive => not dead, not dead => alive
(26) If x is ugly, x is not beautiful.
If x is beautiful, x is not ugly.
12
ugly => not beautiful
beautiful => not ugly
(27) a. If a model is not beautiful, she is not necessarily ugly.
b. If a boy is not tall, he is not necessarily short.
not beautiful ≠> ugly , not ugly ≠> beautiful.
We can make the deduction in one direction, but we cannot reverse the direction of
the deduction. The reason is that the terms of a pair or gradable antonyms are valid for
the end zones, the poles. In between these poles, however, there is a sort of grey zone,
and somebody with a measure in this intermediate zone is neither short nor tall, see
sketch (28) and example (29). If x in (28) is marking Bill’s height, then it would be
true to say (29) in such a situation.
short men tall men
(28) ]x[>
(29) Bill is not really tall, but he is not short either.
The surprising fact is that tall can be used in certain sentences, even if somebody is
short, see (30a, b).
(30) a. Silvio is only 5 feet and 6 inches tall – he is a very short man.
b. How tall is Silvio? – I don’t know, but he is quite short.
Because tall in this use only means the height on the scale and it does not involve any
expectation about Silvio’s height, it is called the unmarked term of the pair. If you ask
(30c) instead of (30b), you expect Silvio to be short, or already know that he is short.
Therefore, short is called the marked term.
(30) c. How short is Silvio?
Antonyms and especially complementary antonyms are evidence for the fact that you
can break up meanings into parts. These pairs exist on their own, but the meaning
relations pertaining between nouns are often due to the fact that their features are
specified differently as in a complementary pair. That a boy cannot also be a girl is
due to the fact that a boy is [+male] and a girl is [+female] and these terms are
complementary antonyms, see (31).
(31) If x is a boy then x is male.
If x is male, then x is not female (complementary antonyms).
Therefore x cannot be a girl, because girls are female.
13
Summary of meaning relationships
homonyms
same pronunciation, different meaning
pen, file, trunk
homographs
same spelling, different meaning
wind, bow, pen
heteronyms
homographs with different pronunciation
wind
synonyms
same meaning
helpaid, concealhide
antonyms
opposite meanings
complementary: deadalive, gradable: tallshort
hyponyms
„sub“meanings (more special meanings)
roseflower
2.3. Levels of language – a note on notation
Compare (32a,b,c). We can say (32a) when we are discussing the city Austin, the
object of the real word. In (32b) we are discussing words, the names for two cities and
the way these names sound. That is the objects we talk about are words of language.
The problem is that we are using language to talk about language. In order to
distinguish this special use of language we say that there is a metalanguage, which
is the language we use to talk about our object which is language. Our object
language is the language or the parts of language we talk about.
The words and phrases we investigate and talk about belong to the object
language. In order to avoid confusion, linguists use a special notation or a special
script: underline, italics, ‚…‘.
14
Note that you can create confusion if you do not mark the level of language you are
using. Consider (32) and the conclusion (32c), which is an example of bad reasoning
due to not keeping the levels apart.
(32) a. Austin is the capital of Texas.
b. Boston rhymes with Austin.
c. Therefore Boston rhymes with the capital of Texas.
3. Phrasal and Sentential Semantics
3.1. Three Basic Approaches to Meaning
A) Referential or Denotational Semantics
Approach A assumes that language is “about“ something. So the emphasis is on the
informational significance of language. In this approach, meaningfulness lies in the
links which exist between the symbols (words) and configurations of symbols
(phrases and sentences) to “objects“ of the real word. These objects can be of various
kinds. They can be individuals, properties, situations and events, etc.
Symbol Object of the real world
(expression of the language) Meaning
There is a straightforward way to establish such links to real objects (individuals,
properties, situations) for names, nouns, adjectives and verbs, which we will explore
in some detail.
B) Psychological or Mentalistic/Cognitive Semantics
In this approach meaningfulness lies in the links between the symbols or
configurations of symbols of language to the cognitive structure of their internalized
representations. For such internalized representations, the concept of metaphor has
often been used.
Symbol Mental representation
Cognitive construct
Meaning
Though there is little doubt that meanings imply some prototypical mental
representation, it is rather hard to make precise what exactly the mental constructs are.
Note also that you go from one representation to another representation in this
approach and there is no direct connection to the informational content of language.
15
C) Social/Pragmatic Approach to Meaning
In this approach, the first and foremost aim of language is defined as communication,
and communication is seen as a social activity. So meaningfulness lies in the way in
which agents use the symbols of a language. The idea is that language sounds are
produced with certain intentions and that meaning can be defined through these
intentions, i.e. only in the context of use.
Symbol Intention of the speaker
Meaning
Considering these approaches, it seems clear that each of them has something to
contribute to the meanings of language. Approach A seems to be basic, however, in a
certain sense.
A basic
B C
If you consider only approach B, we are stuck with the problem discussed above: The
expressions of language, which are representations, are mapped to representations
without getting at what these expressions are „about“.
If you consider only C, taking into account only the intention without first
looking at the basic or denotational content, you cannot really describe the meaning. It
makes more sense to first figure out the „literal meaning“ and then consider what the
context of use and the intention has to contribute. Consider examples (33a,b).
(33) a. I’d like a glass of water
b. Mr. Jones’s command of English is excellent
The literal meaning of (33a) is the statement that you desire or want a glass of water.
Now, if (33a) is uttered on a hike in the Grand Canyon, it remains just that. It is a
statement about a wish you have. If you are in a restaurant and there is a waiter taking
your orders and you utter (33a), then you are indicating that you want the waiter to
bring you a glass of water. So a statement about your wish is uttered with a different
intention in this situation and becomes a command or request.
(33b) can also change meaning dramatically if the situation of utterance
changes. If Mr. Jones is being evaluated for his language abilities, it means just what
it states: Jones is good and even excellent in English. If Jones has applied for a
position as a philosophy professor and you find this sentence in a letter of
recommendation, the sentence might imply that he is no good at philosophy. The
16
writer’s intention is to say only good things but he has also to be truthful in order to
obey a basic rule of communication and a basic rule about such letters. So if the writer
has to mention English as Jones’s good point, the reader starts to wonder why. What
if this is the only thing Jones is good at? So the inference may be that there was
nothing nice to say about Jones’s philosophical abilities. Hence Jones is no good at
philosophy.
Clearly the context of use plays a decisive role in interpreting an utterance.
3.2. Building up meanings
3.2.1. Important constraints
As we focus on the links between language and the real world, the notion of
reference or denotation becomes the central notion. We want to define what
expressions refer to or denote, i.e. what their referents are. If I think or say “the chair I
am sitting on is getting a bit uncomfortable”, the referent of the complex nominal
phrase “the chair I am sitting on” is a dark grey, rolling office chair bought at IKEA’s
about 18 years ago. As I am writing this on the 24/09/2004 in my home in France, this
chair is one of two such office chairs in my office at home. The nominal phrase refers
to a specific object of the real world and if you were to visit me you would be able to
see the chair. The expression “the chair I am sitting on” is an expression of language
and by your knowledge of what “chair” means, what “the” means, what the other
words mean and adequate information about the time and place of utterance and your
knowledge about who the writer/speaker was, you can identify the object.
Note, however, that even if you do not know who the writer was, when and
where the sentence was written, you still know what the sentence means. You know
what additional information you would need in order to pick out the chair in question.
Certain expressions refer to objects directly, you are able to identify the
referent or denotation without difficulty given the situation of utterance. In the
sentences “This is red”, “I am tired” you can identify the referents of “this” and “I”
directly, if you are a participant in the situation of utterance. For the expressions, “the
second student from the left in the third row in lecture hall 2 at the university of
Oldenburg on the 24/10/2004” , “Cornelia Hamann”, or “Pavarotti” there is a direct
identification even without being present in the utterance situation. As the important
step is to identify the referent, i.e. the real object or person, it looks as if knowing how
you grasp what such expressions refer to is part of knowing what they mean.
17
about. In other words we have to make sure that a sentence corresponds to some sort
of object – even if of a somewhat philosophical kind. When we set out to define
sentence reference and the referents of sentences, we must take into account two
important constraints on meaning.
First, our definition of sentence meaning should enable us to explain speaker’s
intuitions about meaning relations between sentences. Second, we have to pay
attention to the way the meaning of larger expressions depends on the meaning of
their parts.
Let us explore the first aspect. We have basic intuitions about meaning relations
which any semantic theory must capture.
We know that (34a,b,c) all mean the same thing and that (35a,b) basically mean the
same.
(34) a. They called up Bill
b. They called Bill up
c. They telephoned Bill
(35) a. John hit Bill
b. Bill was hit by John
If sentences mean the same thing, we say that they are paraphrases of each other.
Obviously (34a,b,c) are all describing the in the same circumstances or conditions and
this seems to constitute one aspect of the sameness of their meaning.
Now consider negations as in (36a,b,c).
(36) a. He is alive
b. He is not alive
c. He is dead
We see that (36a) can be truthfully uttered in a certain situation and if (36a) is true in
this situation then (36b) cannot be true in the same situation. Because dead = not
alive, the same meaning relation obtains between (36a) and (36c). Our definitions of
antonymy and of not must be such that we capture exactly these intuitions. Most
importantly, our definition of sentence meaning must be such that we can define these
relationships.
More intuitions:
Sentences may be true in several sets of circumstances, in such a case they are
ambiguous. Such ambiguity may be due to homonymy (37a) or to a structural
ambiguity as in (37b):
18
(37) a. I need to have the file tomorrow.
b. The boy saw the man with the telescope
It may also be the case that if one sentence obtains/can be truthfully uttered/ is true in
certain circumstances then another sentence must also be true in exactly those
circumstances: one sentence implies the other or one sentence entails the other.
(38) a. If John picked a rose then it follows that he picked a flower.
b. If John is a bachelor, he is not married.
c. If John has a red house, John has a house.
d. If John is intelligent and handsome, he is handsome.
If you look at how we have formulated these intuitions, we are always referring to the
circumstances in which the sentence obtains/ can be truthfully uttered/is true. This
was inspired by the observation about the office chair which you would be able to
pick out given enough information. You know what circumstances have to be met in
order to match the sentence to a situation. If a sentence matches a situation or a set of
circumstances it is true in that situation. The circumstances in which a sentence is true
seem to be an important notion when talking about the meaning of sentences.
(39) I saw a pink whale in the parking lot
Consider (39). It is an unusual sentence, yet you know what it means because you
know what would have to happen or what the circumstances would have to be for this
sentence to be true. You also know that it is very unlikely that these circumstances
come to happen so that the speaker must either be joking, lying or must be
intoxicated.
Let us keep in mind that we want to define sentence meaning so that knowing
the meaning of a sentence is related to knowing in which circumstances it is true.
In approaching this aim, we have to obey the second constraint about meanings. We
have to build up meanings of larger units from the meanings of the parts. It is obvious
that the meaning of a phrase or sentence depends on the meaning of the words
contained in the sentence and on some structural building principles. So “there must
be some kind of compositional account of the interpretation of complex expressions
as composed or constructed from the interpretations of their parts”. (Chierchia and
McConellGinet 1992.)
Let us recapitulate the guiding ideas for constructing sentence meanings. We have to
define what the denotation of a sentence is and we have to build this up from the
meanings and denotations of its parts starting from those expressions which refer
19
directly. In doing so, we have to respect compositionality and the meaning relations
obtaining between sentences and the fact that we have to arrive at a set of
circumstances which the sentence describes and in which it would be true.
3.2.2. From atomic to complex expressions
The meaning of proper names cannot be fractured up into features or meaning
components. They do not “mean” anything, they are used to refer, designate or pick
out a specific individual.
John (an individual called John)
Fido (a specific dog called Fido)
Compare the proper name Fido to noun dog. Dog has a meaning or sense that is
defined by the typical properties dogs have and ultimately by all the properties dogs
can have; there is a class of dogs with similar properties, a natural kind. Fido on the
other hand need not be a dog, but could be a cat or a pet rabbit. So the expression
Fido, a proper name, does not have a sense, but only a fixed reference where the
referent is determined by the act of naming. So you can hug Fido, he is an individual,
but you cannot hug or pet dog.
The individual referred to by a proper name can exist now (Cornelia Hamann),
it can have existed in the past (William Shakespeare), or it can be fictional (Luke
Skywalker or Harry Potter). Proper names are inherently definite: one unique,
specific, definite individual is directly picked out by the name. Therefore proper
names do no combine well with definite articles in English as indicated in (40).
(40) *the John is always late
If you know several persons called John, articles may occur and descriptions may be
added as in (41) to make clear which of the possible referents is meant.
(41) We are talking about the John who is always wearing woollen scarves
For the same reasons, proper names do not occur with adjectives unless you want to
distinguish several persons. Hence (42a) is normally ungrammatical, but (42b) in a
context where a distinction is intended is possible.
(42) a. *blond John
b. No, it’s the English Bill who is coming
20
There is one use of names with appositive adjectives, these adjectives describe
standard attributes of the individual and are not used to give a restriction in order to
facilitate identification. This use is quite extensively found in Homer, see (43).
(43) coweyed Hera,
Some proper names may even have a meaningful component:
(44) Lake Geneva, Mont Blanc.
Let us now consider nouns and noun phrases. We already discussed that the noun dog
has a sense and that dog seems to describe the class of dogs. We build up reference
via the sense in this case.
Adjectives can be part of a noun phrase. Normally they restrict the meaning of the
noun. Restriction can be taken literal here in that a set is restricted to a smaller set.
sense reference
Now we add the article and get an individual, not a set.
The definite article makes the noun refer to an individual not a set. So an expression
of the type (the NOUN) functions like a proper name. However, the reference is
determined via the sense of the individual words. The reference of the dog is mediated
by the sense/intention of dog. This helps to identify a set of individuals, here a set of
dogs. The definite article tells us to pick one specific individual from this set.
We sum up that
21
proper names have no sense but refer directly to individuals
nouns
have a sense
do not refer directly to individuals
refer to sets via their sense
noun phrases (singular), Article + Noun
refer to individuals (like proper names)
reference is mediated by the sense of the noun
reference to an individual is introduced by the article
The article picks out an individual from a set. Consider (45).
(45) I was walking in the fields with my uncle.
A dog came running out of the woods.
The dog attacked us quite savagely.
Definite article: unique individual, already identified in discourse.
Indefinite article: any, some individual of the set, which is not necessarily unique.
In attributing a meaning to the noun phrase the small dog we have respected
compositionality. We have considered the contribution of each word and we have
combined the words in a certain order: (article (adjective (noun))). As the noun
flavours the whole phrase it makes sense to start with the meaning of the noun. It is
the nucleus of this phrase. In the following steps we have chosen to first add the
meaning of the adjective and then the meaning of the article. We could have tried
something else. We could have argued that we first pick an individual dog the dog,
and that the small dog says that this dog is a small dog.
Before we decide which is the better way to deal with complex noun phrases
let us consider what adjectives do.
(46) red balloon
Some adjectives add a property. The adjective red adds the property of redness to the
properties of balloons. So a red balloon is a balloon and it is red. In many cases,
however, adjectives are relative concepts and their meaning cannot be captured by
just adding a property. Consider the adjective large in (47).
(47) large balloon
22
As we have already pointed out for other gradable adjectives, a large balloon need not
be a large toy, there are bigger things than balloons. So a large balloon is large for a
balloon but not large in an absolute sense. It is a balloon, however. Consider (48). A
false friend is no friend at all, so when you add false to a noun, the sense of the noun
gets cancelled.
(48) false friend
So adjectives add to or modify the sense of a noun, either by relativising it or by
radically altering it. We get the following schema:
x is an Adj N
absolute adjectives
relative adjectives
nonstandard adjectives
Adding an adjective to a noun restricts the possible reference set by adding a property
or by relativising a noun property.
Now reconsider the possibility of building up the noun phrase meaning in a different
way.
The grey brick
x1 x3
brick set of bricks x2 bricks
x4
sense
reference, extension
x1 x3
x2 grey
grey set of grey things x things
4
sense reference, extension
the brick contextually given unique
23
individual from the set of bricks
Possibility 1 (false)
combine the meaning of grey with the meaning of the brick
the grey brick contextually given unique
individual from the set of bricks
and this individual is grey
As the individual is already fixed, adding the adjective does not help in narrowing
down the possible referents. It just adds information. This is not the usual function of
adjectives. If adjectives normally functioned like that, then we would expect them to
be normal with proper names. But we have seen that they are not.
Context:
We have already identified the highest brick as the brick we are talking about.
Then “hand me the brick” would make sense. “Hand me the grey brick” would not
make sense. The adjective adds information but somehow this is unwanted and
unhelpful: the adjective has not done its job in narrowing down the possible referents:
restricting a unique referent is impossible.
Possibility 2 (good)
First narrow down the set by adding the adjective meaning, ideally this should
identify a unique individual. If the adjective has done that, then the addition of the
definite article makes sense.
Context:
Hand me the grey brick
The use of the adjective narrows the set of possible referents to one unique individual
in the context. The addition of the makes sense.
24
grey brick x1 x3 x1 x3
sense x
x2 bricks x2 grey
x4 x4 things
the (grey brick) the unique individual which is
grey and a brick
We have used the restricting function of adjectives as an argument for a certain order
of composition. There is another argument.
It is desirable to have one procedure for all article + adjective + noun combinations.
So let us now take the combination article + adjective + noun in the example the false
friend. If we first pick one unique individual from the set of friends, it is hard to add a
property to this individual which makes him or her a false friend. The individual is
from the set of friends, so being a friend cannot be cancelled.
We retain that the principle of compositionality is important and guides how we put
together meaning in respecting the meaning contribution of the parts.
Compositionality:
The meaning of an expression is a function of the meaning of its parts.
There are exceptions to compositionality in idiomatic expressions. Here you cannot
even guess at the meaning of the whole even if you know the meaning of each word.
Compare (49a, b) with (50) and (51).
(49) a. John broke the vase
b. John repaired the vase
(50) John broke the ice
(51) Mary kicked the bucket
Idioms are frozen in meaning and structure. Some chunks are more frozen than others
as (52a,b) demonstrate.
(52) a. The ice was broken by John
b. *The bucket was kicked by Mary
25
3.3. Sentence Meaning
3.3.1. Preliminary considerations
The sentence is the basic unit of communication (not single words), so it is very
important that we arrive at a good definition of sentence meaning. The question we
ask now is what the sense and the denotation of a sentence can be. We have already
talked about “the situations or circumstances in which a sentence is true”. This seems
rather abstract and very complicated. It would be much simpler to say that a sentence
describes a situation. So let us briefly consider why this simpler approach does not
work.
We have assigned the following referents:
names individuals
Fido
nouns properties or sets of individuals
(predicates) dog, is a dog
So now let us be simple and do the following:
sentences situations
The problem is that it is now very difficult to make precise why one sentence implies
another one. Consider the entailment between (53) and (54):
(53) Pavarotti is an Italian singer (54) Someone is an Italian singer
Both describe totally different situations. How can we capture the relationship of the
sentences if the only thing we can relate is these different situations?
Other problems are posed by sentences like (55).
(55) Pavarotti is French
What sort of situation can we ascribe to this sentence? A nonsituation?
Unfortunately we seem to be stuck with the rather complicated observation that you
know what a sentence means if you know under which circumstances it is true. So let
us be bold and define the extension or the referent of a sentence as its truth value.
Truth values are the values true (T) and false (F) or 1 and 0.
The denotation, extension or referent of a sentence is its truth value
26
sentence {T,F}
Now consider (56a) and (56b).
(56) a. Pavarotti is an Italian singer T
b. Cesar is dead T
As both sentences are true, they have the same referent. Obviously, however, the
sentences do not mean the same. So there must be more to meaning than reference.
What becomes very important now is the notion of sense.
We already said that proper names do not have sense, but that nouns and
descriptions have sense. When you hear the word dog you have a sort of mental
picture of some dog or you are aware of the properties an individual called a dog
should have by the sense of the word dog. So if you are presented with a set of
different animals and someone says “there’s a dog” you will be able to pick out the
dog from the animals due to your knowledge of dogproperties or due to your mental
picture.
The distinction between sense and reference or between intention and
extension was first explored by the German logician Gottlob Frege in the late 19 th
century. Frege’s example involved the expressions: Venus, the evening star and the
morning star.
(57) a. Venus is Venus
b. the evening star is the morning star
Venus is a proper name that refers to a particular planet. The sentence “Venus is
Venus” is always true and not very informative. The sentence “the evening star is the
morning star” may tell you something new. It is informative. A puzzle arises,
however, because it is also true that the morning star is Venus and so is the evening
star. So how can one sentence be informative and the other not be informative? The
reason for this is that the expressions the evening star and the morning star pick out
their referent, the planet Venus, via a description. They have a sense, whereas the
proper name Venus does not have a sense, it only has reference. So sentence (57a)
amounts to saying that the referent of Venus, the planet x, is the referent of Venus,
namely the planet x, i.e. we are saying x=x, which is trivially true.
Let us build up the meaning in the two other cases.
morning star sense: star which is bright and clear late in the morning sky
the morning star: sense: one, unique individual which is a star and which appears
bright and clear late in the morning sky
evening star: sense: star which is bright and clear early in the evening sky
the evening star: sense: one unique individual which appears bright and clear
early in the evening sky
27
The meaning of sentence (57b) clearly is not x=x, but
“The unique star which appears bright and clear late in the morning sky is the same
individual as the unique star which appears bright and clear early in the evening sky”.
We are in fact saying that both expressions which have quite different senses have the
same referent. This has to be verified against fact and therefore is informative.
the morning star the evening star
Venus
3.3.2. The Definition of Sentence Meaning
We have defined the reference of a sentence as the truth value it takes on in a
situation. The circumstances under which a sentence is true are the sense of a
sentence. These circumstances are called the truth conditions.
(58) a. The fifth of November is Guy Fawkes’ day
b. The fifth of September is Guy Fawkes’ day
You know that only one of these sentences can be true, because you know the
conditions under which each of them can become true. They are mutually exclusive.
Now, if you know English history and English customs or nursery rhymes, you know
that (58a) is true and (58b) is not. Knowing the truth conditions together with factual
knowledge about the world makes it possible to match the conditions against the
actual situation and assign the value T (or F) to a sentence.
The truth conditions (sense) together with factual knowledge lead to the truth
value (reference) of a sentence. So you may not know whether a sentence is true or
false because you do not know the facts (you do not know who Guy Fawkes was and
what he did), you still know the truth conditions, the sense. Even worse, you may be
principally unable to decide if a sentence is true or false – you still know its truth
conditions. Consider (59).
28
(59) On the day of his death, Cesar breathed 24501 times
Parts of a sentence may be false, the whole sentence can be true and you can judge
this because you can construct the truth conditions. Consider (60a) and (60b).
(60) a. Guy Fawkes’ day is the fifth of November or the fifth of September
b. Mary believes that Guy Fawkes’ day is on the fifth of September
So knowing the circumstances under which a sentence is true amounts to knowing the
meaning of a sentence, it does not amount to knowing the facts of the world.
3.3.3. Meaning relations between sentences
We are finally in a position to give reasonable definitions of the meaning relations
obtaining between sentences (not words!).
Def. Two sentences are paraphrases if they have the same truth conditions.
Having the same truth conditions can arise either through word meanings (61a,b) and
(62a,c) or through structural relationships (62a,b) and (63a,b).
(61) a. John was sitting on the sofa (61) b. John was sitting on the couch
(62) a. John called up Bill (62) b. John called Bill up
(62) c. John telephoned Bill
(63) a. John hit Bill (63) b. Bill was hit by John
Note that being both true does not make sentences into paraphrases. The pairs in (64)
and (65) are both true but they do not have the same truth conditions, so they are not
paraphrases of each other.
(64) a. The Declaration of Independence was signed in 1776
b. The Magna Carta was signed in 1215
(65) a. John is married or John is single
b. Mary is married or Mary is single
There is a difference in how truth comes about in the pair of (64) and in the pair of
(65). The sentences in (64) are true because history developed as it did, the facts
obtain. The sentences in (65) must be true anyway, we do not need to check whether
they match the facts of John’s or Mary’s life. This is so because of the laws of logic,
29
to the meaning of the little word or and to the fact that married and single are
complementary antonyms. So one of them must obtain, and if one of them obtains the
whole sentence must be true.
Sentences which are always true due to some law of logic or due to some semantic
relationship called tautologies, see (66a,b) for more examples. If a sentence is true
because its analysis shows that it describes the facts (64), then it describes an analytic
truth.
(66) a. dogs are animals b. uncles are male
Def. Entailment
Sentence X entails sentence Y iff (if and only if) whenever X is true, Y is also true
(the circumstances which make X true, make Y true)
Note that the reverse does not normally hold!
Note that the reverse does not hold: “John is married” would be true if he is married
to Jane. So there are circumstances which make “John is married” true, in which
“John is Mary’s husband” is not true. Examples (68) to (73) are similar. All are
entailments.
Some declarative sentences are always false, see (74) to (77).
30
(75) My aunt is a man word meaning, feature clash
(76) My brother John is an only child word meaning, feature clash
(77) John is a boy and John is not a boy laws of logic, negation, conjunction
(78) a. John is my brother (78) b. John is an only child
c. John is my bother and John is an only child
Sometimes a sentence makes sense (has truth conditions) only when certain other
conditions are fulfilled. Such conditions are not explicitly mentioned, they are
understood or presupposed. If someone says (79), you understand that (80) holds,
even if this is not explicitly mentioned. If (80) were false, you could not say (79), you
simply could not construct a truth value. This leads to the following observation:
If X presupposes Y, then X does not have a truth value in the case that Y is false.
(79) John wants another beer
(80) John already had a beer (79) => (80)
A surprising fact is that presuppositions stay valid even if a sentence is negated (81)
or questioned (82).
(81) Mary regrets that John came to the party
=> John came to the party
Mary does not regret that John came to the party
=> John came to the party
(82) Does Mary regret that John came to the party?
=> John came to the party
This property gives rise to the following definition.
Def. Presuppositions
X presupposes Y iff (X entails Y) and (not X entails Y).
31
(83) I claim that John was sick
(84) I believe/doubt that John was sick
Presuppositions belong to the common ground a speaker and hearer are supposed to
share. But they can also add information without mentioning it. Compare the two
fragments of conversation (85) where it is explicitly mentioned that John was sick a
week ago and is now sick again, whereas in (86) John’s earlier sickness is
presupposed.
(85) John is sick today and he was sick a week ago. I’ll go visit him.
(85) John is sick again and it starts to be annoying to take his workload.
Such implicit information is prohibited in court as it is hard to deny. You can cancel a
presupposition, but it is not easy. In (87) a simple denial does not achieve anything, it
denies the statement not the presupposition.
(87) Have you stopped selling crack?
a. No! (you have not stopped selling crack – you are still selling crack)
b. Yes! (you have stopped – but you admit that you were selling crack)
c. I cannot stop selling crack because I never was selling crack
Only (87c) says that the whole thing is nonsense because the presupposition does not
hold – it cancels the presupposition.
Presuppositions and their peculiar contribution to the background information of a
discourse are actually a border case of semantics and pragmatics. On the one hand, a
sentence does not have a truth value without the presupposition being true, so they are
related to the semantics of propositions. On the other hand, it does not make sense to
use a sentence if one of its presuppositions does not hold. It is simply inappropriate to
utter John wants another beer if John did not already drink a beer. The sentence is
inappropriate or infelicitous. It is inappropriate because conversations are guided by
maxims and one of these maxims is: do not make unsupported claims. So if you utter
John wants another beer and you know he did not drink a beer before, you have
violate this maxim even though you did not make an explicit claim. Such maxims
regulate the use of sentences in conversations or discourse and are part of
pragmatics.
4. Pragmatics
4.1. Conversational Maxims
32
Let us start with the Conversational Maxims which define conditions of appropriate
use of sentences in conversations. H. Paul Grice formulated the following rules or
maxims.
Maxims of
Quality Do not make unsupported claims. Be truthful.
(Jones, Hamlet)
Manner Be brief and orderly
(Hamlet)
Relevance Be relevant
(Jones, Hamlet)
Quantity Say neither more nor less than the discourse requires
(Hamlet)
Polonius finds that “though this is madness, yet there is method in’t” because Hamlet
systematically violates the conversational maxims in his answers to Polonius’
questions.
Hamlet II.ii. 193 ff
P: ...What do you read, my lord?
H: Words, words, words.
P: What is the matter, my lord?
H: Between who?
P: I mean the matter that you read, my lord.
H: Slanders, sir; for the satirical rogue says here that old men have gray beards, that
their faces are wrinkled, their eyes purging thick amber and plumtree gum, and that
they have a plentiful lack of wit together with most weak hams...
33
Another border case between semantics and pragmatics is metaphor where
again the conversational maxims help us interpret the expressions. Normally truth
conditions are not met, we find feature clashes and a general break down of semantic
rules. By the Maxim of Relevance the hearer assumes, however, that there is some
sense in this utterance and so interpretation cannot be on the literal level but must be
transferred. Note that generally some prominent feature of the literal meaning is
transferred so even metaphors cannot do without a straightforward semantic
interpretation as a first step. See the examples in (88). Some metaphors have frozen
into idioms.
(88) a. Walls have ears
b. This story is a regular cliff hanger
c. He’s been on the water wagon for several years now
d. He’s always been trigger happy
e. John broke the ice
4.2. Speech Acts
Language is not only used to make statements or to inform about something. Often an
utterance is not only an utterance but an act which influences or even changes the
world. See (89).
(89) a. I hereby declare you man and wife
b. Passengers are requested to use the rear exit
c. I promise to put the copies in the handapparat
In this case making the utterance is performing an action. Therefore this type of
utterance is called performative utterance or speech act.
Austin (1962) speculated about the idea that on the one hand one has constative or
declarative utterances and on the other hand one has the performative utterance. He
asked whether there really is a difference and concluded that there is not. So called
declaratives as in (90a) according to Austin are just special speech acts, see (90b).
(90) a. The morning star is the evening star.
b. I state/assert that the morning star is the evening star.
Austin in fact claimed that “one can’t issue any utterance whatever without
performing some speech act…”. This idea has actually taken hold in semantic theory
34
and even in syntax so that special notations are added to sentences indicating the
‘force’ of the utterance, i.e. the kind of speech act it is.
Austin himself introduced the following terminology:
locutionary act – utterance, the act of uttering
illocutionary act – performative utterance
(warning, stating, promising…)
perlocutionary act – result, effect which speaker’s act has on the hearer
Such speech acts are indeed of high importance if one considers the
communicative function of language. From this point of view, speech acts become the
important unit, not sentences. Searle (1969), in his paper “What is a Speech Act”
formulated: “It is the production of the token in the performance of the speech act that
constitutes the basic unit of linguistic communication.” We can sum this up as (91).
(91) The illocutionary act is the minimal unit of linguistic communication
Speech acts cannot have truth values, but they can be appropriate or not. If a speech
act is appropriate, it is also called felicitous (happy, good, successful). So the
important concepts for speech acts are appropriateness or felicity. A speech act can
be infelicitous for three types of reasons. It can be null and void. This is the case if
someone said (89a) when he is no priest or no justice of the peace, i.e. does not have
the power to marry people. If the university president says “I promise that there will
be no more cuts” this is an infelicitous utterance because he cannot control the
Ministry and there may be further cuts anyway which are totally out of the
universities’ control. If the Minister of Education says this, it could be infelicitous for
another reason. The promise may simply be insincere and uttered to shut people up
for the moment with no intention of ever keeping this promise. The sentence could
also become infelicitous, because there is a breach of commitment, i.e. the Minister
gives the promise and then the cabinet decides on further cuts in education and so he
is unable to keep the promise.
Statements, as special speech acts, can be inappropriate in case of
presupposition failure (see pp. 2526). Sentence (92) is decidedly odd.
(92) All John’s children are bald – but John has no children
One intriguing fact about speech acts is that there is no consistent linguistic
sign to tell you that something is a promise or a warning. A good indication that
35
something is a speech act is that you can add the word “hereby” as in (89a). This does
not always work, however, as it is hard to imagine how you can add this to (93c).
(93) a. Cave Canem
b. Warning! Dog
c. picture of a dog on the gate
If you centre your intention on the idea that an important function of language is
communication and define the illocutionary act as the minimal unit of linguistic
communication, then language sounds are always produced with certain
(communicative) intentions. Starting from this idea, H. Paul Grice tried to define
meaning through the speaker’s intention. Searle (1969) argues against this idea in
pointing out that the intention cannot be basic and that there is something else. He
invents the following scenario. Imagine an American officer captured by Italians in
the Second World War. He has the impression that these guys are pretty simple and
that they do not know much about Americans. What they do know, however, is that
Italy and Germany are allies. So the American officer thinks that he might have a
chance if they think he is German. The only German words he knows are the
beginning of a poem by Goethe: “Zeig mir das Land wo die Zitronen blühen…”.
Searle’s point now is that the meaning of “Zeig mir das Land wo die Zitronen
blühen…” is not “I am a German officer” even if the intention of the American
soldier is for the Italians to believe just that.
We see that it makes sense to start with the literal meaning and then examine
conditions of use (as in the case of metaphor). In this sense, pragmatics adds meaning
layers which are conditioned by the communicative intention, but semantics and truth
conditions (literal meanings) remain basic.
4.3. Discourse and Situation (Deixis)
Some expressions of language depend on the previous discourse. In (94b) the use of
the definite article depends on the fact that the person has already been mentioned.
The same is true about the personal pronoun in (94c). The use of articles and 3rd
person pronouns depends on the discourse.
(94) a. secretary: there is a man here who does not want to give his name
b. boss: well, show the man in
c. boss: well, show him in
Some expressions depend directly on the situation of utterance. Consider the personal
pronouns in (95), the adverbial expressions here and there (96), the temporal adverbial
now (97), and verbs like come and go (98).
36
(95) I you he she
“s e n s e”
s i t u a t i o n
“I need to see you” “he needs to see her”
place of utterance not place of utterance
place talked about,
place of reference
Oldenburg Hamburg (Geneva, Bremen, Paris…)
“John is here” “We’ll go there soon”
time of utterance not time of utterance
can be future or past
s i t u a t i o n d i s c o u r s e
37
“I am giving a lecture right now” “I’ll give a talk then”
“Then he gave a talk”
(98) come (to) go (to)
motion towards motion towards a place different
place of utterance from place of utterance
motion towards Oldenburg motion towards Bremen, Geneva…
towards speaker’s exact location
John came here often John went there often
*John went here often *John came there often
Expressions which rely entirely on the situation and context of the utterance are called
deictic expressions or deixis. (100) gives a(n incomplete) list of deictic expressions.
(100) I, my, mine, you, your, yours, we, ours, us
he/she, this person/that man,
now, two weeks from now, last week, tomorrow, yesterday, today, next week,
a week ago
38
In interpreting the deictic expressions in (95) till (100) we have to go through
two procedures. First we identify the sense of the expression (I speaker), second
we need factual knowledge about the situation (who is the speaker) to assign a
referent to the expression. From one point of view this is pragmatics because we are
considering what an expression means in a condition of use, from another point of
view, this can be straightforward semantics as we finally assign a truth value to a
sentence containing such an expression. The only thing which has to be added to truth
conditional semantics is a component taking context into account. This is indeed the
way semanticist treat deixis – which in itself has a decidedly pragmatic flavour. The
border line between semantics and pragmatics therefore is flowing and not very sharp.
The cartoon on the next page shows how deixis can go wrong if false
assumptions are made about the identity of the speaker and hence about his/her
location. You should figure out for yourself how the deictic expressions are
interpreted by the lady and by Dennis and where the problems are.
39
References
Austin, J.L. (1962): How to do things with words. Cambridge, Mass, Harvard
University Press.
Chierchia, G. and A. McConnellGinet (1990): Meaning and Grammar. Camridge,
Mass, MIT Press.
Grice, H.P. (1989): Logic and conversation. Reprinted in: Studies in the way of
words. Cambridge, Mass, Harvard University Press.
Searle, J.R. (1969): Speech acts, An essay in the philosophy of language. Oxford
England, Blackwell.
40