P.singer - Voluntary Euthanasia A Utilitarian Perspective
P.singer - Voluntary Euthanasia A Utilitarian Perspective
P.singer - Voluntary Euthanasia A Utilitarian Perspective
VOLUNTARY EUTHANASIA:
A UTILITARIAN PERSPECTIVE
PETER SINGER
ABSTRACT
Belgium legalised voluntary euthanasia in 2002, thus ending the long
isolation of the Netherlands as the only country in which doctors could
openly give lethal injections to patients who have requested help in dying.
Meanwhile in Oregon, in the United States, doctors may prescribe drugs
for terminally ill patients, who can use them to end their life – if they are
able to swallow and digest them. But despite President Bush’s oft-repeated
statements that his philosophy is to ‘trust individuals to make the right
decisions’ and his opposition to ‘distant bureaucracies’, his administra-
tion is doing its best to prevent Oregonians acting in accordance with a
law that its voters have twice ratified. The situation regarding voluntary
euthanasia around the world is therefore very much in flux.
This essay reviews ethical arguments regarding voluntary euthanasia
and physician-assisted suicide from a utilitarian perspective. I shall begin
by asking why it is normally wrong to kill an innocent person, and whether
these reasons apply to aiding a person who, when rational and competent,
asks to be killed or given the means to commit suicide. Then I shall con-
sider more specific utilitarian arguments for and against permitting vol-
untary euthanasia.
UTILITARIANISM
There is, of course, no single ‘utilitarian perspective’, for there
are several versions of utilitarianism and they differ on some
aspects of euthanasia. Utilitarianism is a form of consequential-
ism. According to act-utilitarianism, the right action is the one that,
of all the actions open to the agent, has consequences that are
better than, or at least no worse than, any other action open to
© Blackwell Publishing Ltd. 2003, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK
and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA.
VOLUNTARY EUTHANASIA 527
the agent. So the act-utilitarian judges the ethics of each act inde-
pendently. According to rule-utilitarianism, the right action is the
one that is in accordance with the rule that, if generally followed,
would have consequences that are better than, or at least no worse
than, any other rule that might be generally followed in the
relevant situation. But if we are talking about changing laws to
permit voluntary euthanasia, rather than about individual deci-
sions to help someone to die, this distinction is not so relevant.
Both act- and rule-utilitarians will base their judgements on
whether changing the law will have better consequences than not
changing it.
What consequences do we take into account? Here there are
two possible views. Classical, or hedonistic, utilitarianism counts
only pleasure and pain, or happiness and suffering, as intrinsically
significant. Other goods are, for the hedonistic utilitarian, sig-
nificant only in so far as they affect the happiness and suffering
of sentient beings. That pleasure or happiness are good things
and much desired, while pain and suffering are bad things that
we want to avoid, is generally accepted. But are these the only
things that are of intrinsic value? That is a more difficult claim to
defend. Many people prefer to live a life with less happiness or
pleasure in it, and perhaps even more pain and suffering, if they
can thereby fulfil other important preferences. For example, they
may choose to strive for excellence in art, or literature, or sport,
even though they know that they are unlikely to achieve it, and
may experience pain and suffering in the attempt. We could
simply say that these people are making a mistake, if there is an
alternative future open to them that would be likely to bring them
a happier life. But on what grounds can we tell another person
that her considered, well-informed, reflective choice is mistaken,
even when she is in possession of all the same facts as we are? The
difficulty of satisfactorily answering this question is one reason
why I favour preference utilitarianism, rather than hedonistic util-
itarianism. The right act is the one that will, in the long run, satisfy
more preferences than it will thwart, when we weigh the prefer-
ences according to their importance for the person holding them.
There is of course a lot more to be said about questions inter-
nal to utilitarianism. But that is perhaps enough to provide a basis
for our next topic.
2
John Stuart Mill. On Liberty. First published 1869. Various editions:
Chapter 5.
3 For further discussion see: Peter Singer. 1993. Practical Ethics. Second
edition. Cambridge. Cambridge University Press. Peter Singer. 1995. Rethinking
Life and Death. New York. St Martin’s Press.
4
See Kant’s discussion of the ‘first example’ in Part II of the Groundwork of
the Metaphysics of Morals.
to make their own judgements and decide what risks they prefer
to take?
Contemporary Moral Issues. Second edition. Lawrence Hinman, ed. Upper Saddle
River, NJ. Prentice-Hall: 169–70.
PALLIATIVE CARE
I return now to another of Nat Hentoff’s objections to the legal-
isation of voluntary euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide.
Hentoff thinks that many physicians are not only unable to recog-
nise depression, but also not good at treating pain, and that some-
times good pain relief can remove the desire for euthanasia. That
is also true, but most specialists in palliative care admit that there
http://www.rnw.nl/society/html/courts010723.html
ill, and are making choices that will, or may, end their lives earlier
than they would have ended if the patient had chosen differently.
To support the right of patients to make these decisions, but
deny they should be allowed to choose physician-assisted suicide
or voluntary euthanasia, is to assume that a patient can rationally
refuse treatment (and that doctors ought, other things being
equal, to co-operate with this decision) but that the patient
cannot rationally choose voluntary euthanasia. This is implaus-
ible. There is no reason to believe that patients refusing life-
sustaining treatment or receiving pain relief that will foreseeably
shorten their lives, are less likely to be depressed, or clouded
by medication, or receiving poor treatment for their pain, than
patients who choose physician-assisted suicide or voluntary
euthanasia. The question is whether a patient can rationally
choose an earlier death over a later one (and whether doctors
ought to co-operate with these kinds of end-of-life decisions), and
that choice is made in either case. If patients can rationally opt
for an earlier death by refusing life-supporting treatment or by
accepting life-shortening palliative care, they must also be ratio-
nal enough to opt for an earlier death by physician-assisted
suicide or voluntary euthanasia.
13 Oregon Reporting 15 Deaths in 1998 under Suicide Law. New York Times
Assisted Suicide, and other Medical Practices involving the End of Life in the
Netherlands, 1990–1995. New England Journal of Medicine 1996; 335: 1699–1705.
16 Helga Kuhse, Peter Singer, Maurice Richard, Malcolm Clark & Peter
Flanders, Belgium: A Nationwide Survey. The Lancet 200; 356: 1806–1811; see also:
http://europe.cnn.com/2000/WORLD/europe/11/24/brussels.euthanasia
Those who, despite the studies cited, still seek to paint the sit-
uation in the Netherlands in dark colours, now need to explain
the fact that its neighbour, Belgium, has chosen to follow that
country’s lead. The Belgian parliament voted, by large margins in
both the upper and lower houses, to allow doctors to act on a
patient’s request for assistance in dying. The majority of Belgium’s
citizens are Flemish-speaking, and Flemish is so close to Dutch
that they have no difficulty in reading Dutch newspapers and
books, or watching Dutch television. If voluntary euthanasia in
the Netherlands really was rife with abuses, why would the country
that is better placed than all others to know what goes on in the
Netherlands be keen to pass a similar law?
CONCLUSION
The utilitarian case for allowing patients to choose euthanasia,
under specified conditions and safeguards, is strong. The slippery
slope argument attempts to combat this case on utilitarian
grounds. The outcomes of the open practice of voluntary
euthanasia in the Netherlands, and of physician-assisted suicide
in Oregon, do not, however, support the idea that allowing
patients to choose euthanasia or physician-assisted suicide leads
to a slippery slope. Hence it seems that, on utilitarian grounds,
the legalisation of voluntary euthanasia or physician-assisted
suicide would be a desirable reform.
Peter Singer
5 Ivy Lane
Princeton, NJ 08544
USA
psinger@princeton.edu