Matilal, Bimal Krishna - Logic, Language, and Reality - Indian Philosophy and Contemporary Issues-Motilal Banarsidass (1990) PDF
Matilal, Bimal Krishna - Logic, Language, and Reality - Indian Philosophy and Contemporary Issues-Motilal Banarsidass (1990) PDF
Matilal, Bimal Krishna - Logic, Language, and Reality - Indian Philosophy and Contemporary Issues-Motilal Banarsidass (1990) PDF
Also available at :
MOTILAL BANARSIDASS
41 U.A., Bungalow Road, Jawahar Nagar, Delhi 110 007
120 Royapettah High Road, Mylapore, Madras 600 004
24 Race Course Road, Bangalore 560 001
Ashok Rajpath, Patna 800 004
Chowk, Varanasi 221 001
PRINTED IN INDIA
BY JAINBNDRA PRAKASH JAIN AT SHRI JAINENDRA PRESS, A - 4 5 NARAINA INDUSTRIAL
AREA, PHASE I, NEW DELHI 1 1 0 0 2 8 AND PUBLISHED BY NARENDRA PRAKASH
JAIN FOR MOTILAL BANARSIDASS PUBLISHERS PVT. LTD., BUNGALOW
ROAD, JAWAHAR NAGAR, DELHI 1 1 0 0 0 7
FOR
INDEX 439
PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION
A is B.
Because of C.
Whatever is C is also B, e.g. X.
{A is such, i.e., Ç,
Therefore A is so, C: i.e. B)
This is similar to a deductive argument and ensures deductive
certainty. Indian logicians however showed lack of interest in
the deduction technique, and instead concentrated upon the
examination of truth and falsity of the universal premiss. They
insisted that the supporting examples, both positive and negative,
would be necessary. Besides, they left it open that a counter-
example, if it can be found, would falsify the universal premises.
This is what I have called the empirical character of Indian
logic.
Regarding the question of universals, I wish to add the follow-
ing. I have chosen, following Quine, the 'natural kind' reading
of the Nyâya theory of universal, while Sen prefers, the following
Strawson, the 'sortal' reading of the Nyäya universals. I now
believe both readings are possible, and in either case, some
modifications of the traditional Nyâya doctrine would be requir-
ed. My preference for the 'natural kind' reading is based upon
the fact that I am not sure whether the reality of sortal universals
can be maintained and argued for against the Buddhist alterna-
tive, the apoha theory of Dinnaga and Dharmakirti. Again, the
matter requires more careful study, which I intend to do later.
Apart from logic and theories of knowledge, Indian philosophy
was intimately connected with a sort of soteriology. This may
divulge the pre-modern character of Indian philosophy. But the
issues raised inthis context are important to get a well-rounded
picture of the subject. I Mve discussed these issues in Chapter 4.
I believe this balances our modern discussion of Indian philoso-
phy, the charge of one-sidedness may thus be answered. I have
not (consciously) distorted anything, but I claim originality in my
presentation and in relating some of the topics with some con-
temporary issues. On the whole in our pursuit of modernity and
the post-modern trend, the authority of the past should not be
xii Preface to the Second Edition
Example II
1. This body is not without a soul.
2. For, this body is not without life.
3. Lack of a soul goes always, etc., with lack of life, wit-
ness : a piece of rock.
4. This is not f.o (not without life).
5. Therefore, this is not without a soul.
To underline the essential form of these arguments, we may
represent them schematically as follows :
I
1. A (or, A applies here).
2. Because B {or, B applies here).
3. B goes with A always, or in all cases, or in all places;
witness case C.
4. It is a case of B.
5. Therefore, it is a case of A.
II
1. Not A (or, A does not apply here).
2. Because not B (or, B does not apply here).
3. A goes with i? always, etc., witness C.
4. It is not so (not a case of B).
5. Therefore, it is not a case of A.
It is easy to see that both I and II (i.e., both examples) can
be transformed to fit into Aristotle's first figure and, thus, I can
be mapped into Barbara and II into Celarent. But, such
transformations, though certainly permissible and legitimate,
disregard certain important and specific characters of the model
of arguments examined by the Indian logicians.
Let me point out at least two significant features of the Indian
model, features that would not be immediately visible in their
mappings in the Aristotelian system, Barbara, and Celarent.
First, instead of presenting the thesis or conclusion in the usual
subject-predicate form, I have presented it, following the Indian
tradition, in what may be called a 'property-location' form. The
theory is operating mainly with the predicate and the reason,
i.e., the major term and the middle term in Aristotle's termino-
logy: The role of the so-called minor term, if there is any
Logic in Ancient and Medieval India 7
I
All S are F
This (M) is S
Therefore, this (M) is F
(where S ~ smoking things, F = things with fire,
M = t h e mountain).
II
No L is S
This (B) is L
This (B) is not S
(where L= Living things, S= soulless, B = body).
This brings us to the second major contrast. The thesis/con-
clusion in the Nyäyasütra demonstration is what is called a
'singular proposition, which is distinct from both the universal
(using such quantifiers as "all" or "each") and the particular
(using "some"; proposition. In Aristotle's system, however, the
conclusion is either a universal proposition ('A' or CE') or a
particular one (using 'some'). The singular propositions are
assimilated into either positive or negative universals, 'A'
or 'E', so that the syllogistic rules may work. In the early
1
Udayana, op. cit., p. 620.
2Searîe, J.R., Speech Acts, p. 32-33.
18 Logic, Language and Reality
1
Evans, J.D.G. Aristotle's Concept of Dialectic, p. 50.
2
Ibid.9 p. 94.
Logic in Ancient and Medieval India 23
1
Pratyak sägamäsritamanumänam, son vïksâ—Ibid.
%
Yat punaranumänampratyaksägamaviruddham nyäyäbhäsah sah—Ibid.
^ Yasmin visaye et at prayujyate sa pratyaksenäpahrtah—Nyäya- Värttfka, on
above.
Logic in Ancient and Medieval India 25
1
See G. Jha, (note 1 in p. 29 of the book) p. 165, footnote.
H follow here the numbering of Candränanda. See Vaise$ika-sütra, ed. by
Muni Sri Jambuvijayaji, Gaekwad's Oriental Series 136, Baroda, 1961.
38 Logic, Language and Reality
It is explained :
A pot is an entity that is tangible (can be touched) and it is
seen to be non-eternal. Sound is not tangible in the same
way. Therefore, (one may argue) sound is eternal because it is
* intangible. (Answer :) In the example, tangibility and
eternality are not grasped as being connected by way
öf being the reason (or evidence) and what is to be proven
{sädhya). For example, an atom has touch and it is eternal.
When the soul, etc., are examples, the (purported) reason
bears resemblance with the example and hence purports to
prove the sädhya (the desired property, eternality). But the
reason, intangibility, deviates from the property, eternality.
For a cognitive episode is intangible as well as non-eternal.
Since the (purported) reason deviates from the (desired)
property in both examples (atoms and cognitive events), it is
not a (proper) reason, for the definition does not apply.
Eternality and temporality are two mutually exclusive oppo-
sites. If a reason belongs to one or the other (not both), it is
non-deviating. Violation of this rule generates an inconclusive
pseudo-reason, for it belongs to both.
This is only a clumsy way of stating the principle that a pro-
perty in order to be adequate to prove the presence of another
property in the same location must belong only to the cases
where the second property is seen to belong, and should not
belong to a case where the second property is seen to be absent.
The pseudo-reason viruddha is enigmatically defined in NS
1.2.6. Most probably, it meant something very different from
what the later tradition in nyäya understood as viruddha. If we
keep ourselves within the bounds of Nyäyasütra and Bhä$yay
we have to explain it as an 'incoherent' pseudo-reason.
NS 1.2.6 siddhäntam abhyupetya tad-virodhi viruddhah
"An incoherent reason is one which contradicts what has
already been conceded as a tenet."
Vätsyäyana gives an example which tries to show that the
Sätfikhya doctrine of change in the midst of permanence (cf., the
sat-käryaväda) is incoherent, for the reason adduced therein
contradicts what has already been accepted in the system.
The so-called 'mistimed' pseudo-reason (kälätita), the fifth in
Logic in Ancient and Medieval India 45
the list, remains as another enigma of the old school. The basic
idea was probably that the proper formulation of what we are
going to prove (i.e., the proposition to be proved) would be
enough to show that it cannot be proved. Hence, the adducing
of the reason would not even be necessary. It would be mistimed.
I shall now give a detailed analysis of Vätsyäyana's comments
on the other two pseudo-reasons : sâdhyasama and prakarana-
sama. Since H.N. Rändle wrote a somewhat pioneering work on
these issues (Indian Logic in the Early Schools, Oxford, 1930), I
shall examine some remarks made by Rändle in this connection.
Scholars have usually translated the term sâdhyasama occurring
in early Sanskrit philosophical texts as petitio principii. Curiously
enough, H. N. Rändle used 'petitio principii9 to translate
prakaranasama, one of the five defects of inference mentioned in
the Nyäyasütra.1 While commenting on sâdhyasama, however,
Rändle remarked :
This clearly resembles the preceding fallacy (prakaranasama)
in being a kind of begging the question: and this kinship with
the previous fallacy is, no doubt, indicated by the word *and?
with which the present sxitra commences.2
Rändle expressed also a word of caution regarding the use of
'sâdhyasama9 in the Mädhyamika texts. Professor K. Bhatta-
charya in his recent note 3 shows that Randle's misgivings about
the interpretation of sâdhyasama in the Mädhyamika texts were
right. It is also to be noted that the usual translation of sâdhya-
sama in the Nyäya context as petitio principii (which even Rändle
seems to have suggested) is not only imprecise but also
incorrect,
Sâdhyasama, like petitio principii, is a defect in the argument
and, hence, can be better explained in the context of an argument.
First, we must be clear about what we understand by petitio
principii as well as what we understand by a defect or a logical
fallacy. It is better to clarify here the notion of fallacy.
Let us define a fallacy as an invalid or unsound form of
argument. An argument or reasoning involves a transition from a
l
Nyäyasütra I.2.4.
2
Randle, p. 197.
3
SeeK. Bhattacharya's article in Journal of Indian Philosophy (1974),
pp. 225-230.
46 Logic, Language and Reality
*Randle, p. 251n.
2
See Geach, Reference and Generality, Cornell: Ithaca pp. 3-21.
52 Logic, Language and Reality
it may be used to confuse the issue for the time being. Thus, the
sophistical device (i.e., the use of jäti) is explicitly excluded from
a debate which the Nyäya calls the väda variety of debate.1 Most of
the sophistical refutations found in the Nyäya list assume that
the argument used as a rejoinder is not based upon the required
implication-rule of inference, but only on some superficial simi-
larity or analogy. The very fact that the early Nyäya school
recognized these rejoinders as sophistical and also discussed the
means by which one should solve problems posed by such
rejoinders (cf., uttara), goes a long way to show that the early
Nyäya theory of inference was not based upon analogy and
examples. And the doctrine of hetväbhäsa 'fallacious reason'
certainly required that inference in the early Nyäya school must
be based on sound implication-rules.
A brief comment on the use of the term sädhyasama in the
early Mädhyamika texts may be in order (for more on this
point see the article by K. Bhattacharya). In the Mädhyamika-
kärikä, Chapter IV, Nägärjuna notes in the two concluding
verses (8, 9) a general pattern of most Mädhyamika arguments.
" The simple meaning of verse 8 here seems to me to be this: If
a reason is adduced to refute the Mädhyamika thesis of empti-
ness in a philosophic dispute (where an opponent is present),
It will not constitute a refutation, for, it will enjoy the same
predicament along with the proposition to the proved. The
second verse, verse 9 in the context, says the same thing with a
slight variation : If a reason is adduced for questioning the validity
of the Mädhyamika thesis of emptiness in the context of an
explanation of the doctrine to the disciples (cf., vyakhyäna) ^ it
will not be a proper question, for, the reason will have the same
predicament as that of the proposition to be proved. Or, the
point may be that in either case (i.e., either in a dispute or in
vyakhyäna) the supposed refutation of\ the doctrine of emptiness
will be baseless, since it will be a f^lse refutation (a jäti) liKe
the sädhyasama. We should note here that no matter whether
sädhyasama is interpreted as a fallacy or as a sophistry, the
Mädhyamika thesis of emptiness will remain unharmed, i.e.,
unrefuted.
Thus, I venture to suggest that the term sädhyasama as it
*See Nyäyasütra 1.2.1-1.2.3.
58 Logic, Language and Reality
1
Mîrnamsa'éîokavârttika, Chowkhamba, Varanasi, 1898-1899, Anumäna-
pariccheda verses 23-24.
2
Nyäyavärttikatätparyatikä, Kashi Sanskrit Series, Varanasi, 1925, p. 180.
The verses are : {Pramänasamuccaya, Chap. II) :
kecid dharmäntaram meyam lingasyävyabhicäratah\
sambandham kecid icchanti siddhatvâd dharmadharminoh //8//
Ungarn dharme prasiddharn cet kirn anyat tena miyatej
atha dharmini tasyaiva kim-arthatn nänumeyatä //9//
sambandhe 'pi dvayam nâsti sas thi tniyeta tad-vati/
aväcyo 'nugrhitatvän na cäsau linga-samgatah //10//
lingasyävyabhicäras tu dharmenänyatra drsyate /
tatra prasiddham tad-yuktaifi dharminam gamayisyati / / l l /
3
Tibetan Tripitaka, Peking edition, Mdgho-rel XCV, Ce. No. 5701 :
Vasudhararaksita. No 5702 : Kanakavarman.
^Fragments from Dignäga, The Royal Asiatic Society, London, 1926,
p. 18-21.
60 Logic, Language and Reality
x
Richard Hayes : "An Interpretation of Anyâpoha in Dignâga's general
Theory of Inference," Buddhist Logic and Epistemology, éd. B. K. Matilaî
and R. D. Evans, 1986, Reidel.
CHAPTER TWO
hand, that they are not actually perceived in any case, then we
are bound to give up the idea that they are yogya.
Thus the Naiyäyika chooses to hold such terms e.g., the 'hare's
horn' etc., as impossible objects just in the sense we take 'the
round square', 'circular triangle' to be impossible. Just as a
round thing cannot by definition be square, a hare also by
definition, cannot grow horn, and a horse cannot be winged.
(See also § 5.5, the last section.) If, however, the long, erect ears
of the hare are mistaken as horns under any condition of error,
then, of course, the erring person, who knows also what 'hare'
means will never identify the seen animal with u hare. If an
animal resembling a hare in every respect is found to grow horns
in addition, then it will make a new species of animal, and not
a hare. Thus, in the Naiyäyika's view both the objects, hare's
horn and round square, sail in the same boat.
Suppose, theNaiyäyika is asked to explain the statement "There
is no hare's horn". First, he would say that here the subject of
negation, i.e., thenegatum, is not at all the hare's horn. What is
negated here is simply the horn, and the locus of such negation
is a hare, Or, from the other viewpoint, the occurrence in a hare
i.e., sasavrttitva) is being negated and the locus of such negation
is a horn. In plain language, the said sentence is to be read in
this view as "horns do not occur in a hare". Thus, "There is no
round-square" is to be read as "the round thing is not square".
Another way of meeting the problem has been suggested by an
indigenous theorist who is generally known as Sondada or Son-
dala. He tries to show that the negation of a self-contradictory term
as an entity is actually felt to occur in any loci. When an entity,
say a pot, is negated, potness resident in a pot is ordinarily
held to be the limiting property (avacchedaka) of the abstract
property, absenteehood or negatumhood (pratiyogita) tagged to
the negatum-entity pot. This is shortly spoken as the negation
of a pot limited or qualified by potness. Sondala holds that an
object limited or qualified by a property actually non-resident
in it may also be negated, and such negation will occur every-
where, because nowhere can we realize such a self-contradictory
object—an object, (say a pot or a horn) qualified by a non-
resident property (say, cotness or occurrence-in-hare). Thus,
Sondala recognizes such statements like 'the hare's horn is
absent in a cow', 'the pot qualified by cotness is absent in the
84 Logic, Language and Reality
cannot exist (viz., the rabbit's horn), and also (d) things of
which it would be a logical contradiction to say that they exist
(viz., the son of a barren woman). One point is common to all
of these four groups, and this is that we can think about them
and our mental activities can be directed toward all of them. In
their theory of objects, the Buddhists were not interested in
ontology or in the metaphysics of being. If this opens the door
to idealism, it may be welcome to the Buddhist (because that
would simply prove the Yogäcära point that objects are integral
parts of, in fact, indistinguishable from, consciousness). Even
without giving in to idealism the Sautrântika Buddhist may
maintain this theory of objects with due modification while
emphasizing that the real objects are only momentary point-
instants which are beyond the range of ordinary experience. (For
further discussion of these issues see Chapter 3 specially § 3.3.)
By way of documentation, I give below the translation of an
excerpt from Udayana's, Ätmatattvaviveka, pp. 56-69. Order of
the paragraphs here follows that of the Sanskrit text which is
reproduced after the translation.
By such arguments, the negative method of inferring
momentariness of an entity from its existence is also
rejected.
Besides, there are some other defects in this negative
inference. The minor term (the 'subject' paksa), the middle
term (the 'inferential reason' he tu) and the example cited in
such an inference cannot be established by any means of
knowledge. There cannot be any me,ans of knowledge to
establish a non-entity (i.e., a fiction, avastu). If it could be
established by some means of knowledge it ceases to be a
non-entity.
(Opponent :) If so, then your talk about the non-entity
becomes self-contradictory.
(Proponent :) Does this self-contradiction point out that
there is a means of knowledge to establish the non-entity ?
Or, (second question) does it reject the prohibitive statement
that we should not talk about non-entity ? Or, (third
question) does it imply that we must concede such state-
ments (about non-entity) which are unauthenticated, i.e.,
not established by any means of knowledge ?
104 Logic, Language and Reality
SANSKRIT TEXT
Cognitive states
Navya-nyäya analyses cognitions in terms of property and
location or locus. More correctly, Navya-nyäya analyses what
I have elsewhere called judgemental or qualificative cognitive
states in terms of qualifiers and qualificands.1 Such a cognitive
event is usually represented by a sentence. Because of the use
of the term "cognitive" or ''cognition" here, a logician trained
in the tradition of Frege and Carnap may immediately bring the
charge of "psychologism" against Navya-nyäya. But I have argued
elsewhere that this charge is not always relevant.2 Navya-nyäya
is concerned with the objective' content of a cognitive event
and analyses the sentence that is supposed to represent the
structure of such, a content. It is not concerned with the psy-
chological act of cognition as such. Thus, in Navya-nyäya
logic when one cognitive event is said to be contradictory to
another, it is not just their psychological impossibility that
is appealed to. In other words, what is appealed to here
is the impossibility that is completely determined by the logical
relation between p and not-p.
Dignäga suggested a dharma-dhannin (/'property and locus")
analysis of a qualificative (judgemental) cognitive event. In
X
B. K. Matilal (1968), p. 12.
*See B. K. Matilal (1986), p. 121-122.
Problems of Philosophical Logic in Navya-nyäya 115
Properties
A cognitive eyent is usually said to locate a property in a
locus : the form is 'x has p* or '/? (is) in x\ Simple predicate
formulations, such as 'x is FJ are noted, but only to be
rephrased as {x has F-ness' (where "F-ness" stands for the
property derived from "F"). Thus, we have here two types of
individuals—properties and locations or loci. Correspondingly,
we can talk about two sorts of individual constants : property-
terms (r, s, t, u, w, h....) and location-terms (/, m, n, o, p).
The best example of a property-term is "blue-colour" which
is locatable in a cup that is blue, or the property expressed by
"cowness" that is locatable in a cow (in any cow). Such
physical materials as a cup, lire, smoke, water, and a pot
are also treated in Navya-nyäya as properties, inasmuch as
they are locatable in such loci as a table, a mountain, ground,
the kitchen and the plate. Hence, terms expressing such
physical materials are treated as property-terms in the specific
sense of being a property-particular, that I have alluded to in
the beginning of this section. The apparent oddity of treating
such things as properties can be resolved if we conceive
anything to be a property that purports to have a location and
allow a sort of stipulative identity between having a cup on it
and cup-property. In other words, we have to stipulate a sort
of referential identity between such expressions as "cup-possessor-
hood" and "cup"'(used as a property). One may even suggest a
distinction here between two uses of the expression "cup": one
use of "cup" ("a cup" or "the cup") is to refer to the locus
of properties, the other use ("a cup" or "the cup") is to refer
to a property. Both refer to the same ontological entity but to
different logical constructs.
116 Logic, Language and Reality
Negation
Navya-nyäya basically recognizes two types of negation :
absence and difference. Most peculiar features of Navya-nyàya
emerge in connection with its interpretation of negation of
properties. Sentential negation is usually avoided. A negation
is construed as a term-negation in either of the following ways.
We get an absence when it is a negation of occurrence or location,
a difference when it is a negation of identity. When a negation
or a negative statement negates location or occurrence of a
property in a locus, it is construed as ascribing the absence of
a property to that locus. Thus, absence of a property is treated
as another property. "The pot is not blue" is first rephrased
here as "the pot does not have blue colour'* which is further
rephrased as "the pot has the absence of blue colour."
Using the complement sign '-' for term-negation, we can
represent the above statement (m -= the pot, s =blue colour) :
i(
m has ~.ç."
When a statement negates an identity between, say, a table
and a cup, it is construed as "a table is different from a cup"
("s^£t"). Navya-nyâya argues that to say that a table is different
from a cup is equivalent to saying "a table lacks the essence of
a cup, or simply, lacks cupness". In other words, 'difference
from a cup' is said to be extensionally equivalent to 'the
absence of cupness' (which means that both these properties
are locatable in the same set of loci).
The iinlocatahles
Navya-nyäya demands that^the presence-range of a non-fictitious
(real) property should be non-empty. Navya-nyäya argues
that if the presence-range be empty then the property in
question would be unbeatable. 1 An unbeatable property is a
suspect in Navya-nyäya. It is regarded as a fictitious property
which cannot be located in our universe of loci. It is called an
a-prasiddha property "unexampled' property, i.e., 'unestablis-
hed\ imaginary property.2 Using modern terminology, we may
say that it is a property which has location in a possible
world, but not in the actual world, (i shall come back to this
problem in the last chapter.) Navya-nyäya hesitates to perform
logical operation on such a property. For example, one cannot
negate such a property and thereby obtain or derive another
(negative) property ! For, they would not be locatable in the
actual world. Thus, we have the following restriction on
negation : If s is a property with a non-empty presence-range,
then by negating it we get another property, a negative property
s; but if s is uhiocatable, it cannot even be successfully negated.
Properties in Navya-nyäya are either atomic (or 'simple') or
composite. A. composite property is formed out of atomic ones,
and, hence, such a property is analysable into atomic cora-
1
Sec before; sections 2.1, and 2.2. The 'unlocatable' is another way of talking
about the non-existent entities, and, hence, is connected with the problem
of empty terms.
2
D.H.H Ingalls, p. 61.
118 Logic, Language and Reality
The unnegatables
If the presence-range of a property is empty, it is unlocatable.
Nyäya calls such a property fictitious. What about properties
whose absence-range is empty ? Nyäya admits such properties
as real, i.e., non-fictitious. They are called ever-present
properties (cf., kevalänvayiri). They are said to be locatable in
all loci of U. Examples of such properties are : knowability,
expressibility and provability (see next section).
An ever-present property is non-fictitious in Navya-nyâya, for,
its presence-range is non-empty (in fact, the presence-range is
the whole universe LJ). We have to assume that such a property
is locatable also in itself, for, it must belong to the universe U.
But since its absence-range is empty, Navya-nyäya regards such
a property as unnegatable ! In other words, just as an unlocat-
able property is said to be not negatable in Navya-nyàya, an
ever-present*property is also regarded as not negatable. For, we
cannot derive a real, non-fictitious (negative) property by
negating an ever-present property. Thus, we have another
restriction on the operation of negation : If s is an ever-present
property, it is locatable (i.e., real), but it is, nevertheless,
unnegatable.
It is obvious that the introduction of ever-present properties
in the system involves many logical difficulties. Thus, some
pre-Gangesa Nyäya logicians were definitely not in favour of
using such a concept. They argued that a true property should
have a non-empty presence-range as well as a non-empty
absence-range. If we rule the unlocatables as fictitious, we might
also B.K. Matilal (1971), pp. 83-91.
Problems of Philosophical Logic in Navya-nyäya 119
Partial location
We face a further oddity about negation when Navya-nyäya
introduces the notion of partial location (cf., avyäpya-vrtti,
Ingalls : "incomplete occurrence'') of properties. Most
properties are wholly or pervasively occurrent or locatable in
their loci, but some properties are said to be only partially or
non-pervasively occurrent or locatable in their loci. (We may
imagine a 'propQrtyXdhanna) in this sense to be a paint-coating,
with which the locus is besmeared partly or wholly.)
To explain this notion we have to develop some further
120 Logic, Language and Reality
Property
real fictitious
w not-w
p N
N P
U U
Property
! _
locatable (real) uniocatable (unreal)
lf
This is a very short but illuminating manual of logic written by Dignäga.
It consists of a table of nine forms of inference" and only 17 explanatory
verses. The Sanskrit original is lost but the Tibetan translation is available.
2
I am using the term "everpresent" to translate the Sanskrit "kevalânvayiri"
although there is a touch of neologism here. "Omnipresent" and ''ubiqui-
tous" are not acceptable for this purpose because they express just the
opposite sense. The physical space, for instance, is omnipresent or ubiquitous
because everything exists in space, but it is not kevalânvayin. " Kevalânvayin"
means a property which is present in everything. "Unnegatable" (used by
Ingalls) may be all right inspite of the periphrasis, but I fear that it is more
suitable to be an adjective of "term" rather than of "property". I refrain
from using "universal property" in order to avoid confusion with "universal
class".
3
Thus see the previous section. Also see VALLABHA [1927-1934] (c.A.D.
1175) p. 500, line I; MANIKANTHA [1953] (c. A.D. 1300) pp. 45-46; and
GANGEéA [1926] p. 141. For an English version of the argument see INGALLS
[1951] pp. 61-62, 86 and 151.
4
See MANIKANTHA[1953] p. 62; and GANQESA [1926] p. 391. Ingalls gave a
rough idea about the structure of this definition (Ingalls [1951] p. 62).
Problems of Philosophical Logic in Navya-nyäya 131
x
For a brief outline of the relevant history, see § 2.2 before.
2
See Vaise$ika-sütra of Kanada (with the Commentary of Candränanda),
ed : Muni Sri Jambuvijavaji, Baroda, 1961.
3
Quoted by Väcaspati Misra in Nyäya-värttikatätparya-fikä, ed : Rajeswara
Sastri Dravid, Benares, 1925, p. 165.
4
See PraÈastapâda-bhâ?ya, Varanasi, 1963, pp. 503-505.
142 Logic, Language and Reality
does not use any universal quantifier, but makes use of a generic
absence, i.e., an absence whose absentee is qualified by a generic
property. Gangesa inserts here a discussion to show how and
why the generic absence must be regarded as separate from the
integration of specific absences. Gangeéa next offers three
different formulations of the definition of pervasion where no
use of the notion of generic absence is made. Gangeéa finally
accepts definition 10, i.e., 'unconditionally' as pervasion, as an
alternative definition, and gives four acceptable formulations of
this definition. This is followed by three different formulations
of the notion of 'associate condition' upädhi.1
bottom, Nyâya will claim in such cases that the tree is qualified
by c as well as by the absence of c. Now, if V is substituted for
'x' in III we get an obvious falsehood. For, the same tree is
also regarded as a locus of the absence of c (by Nyäya) and,
hence, "difference-from-the-tree" cannot possibly qualify the
same tree which is qualified by c. We cannot say of the tree that
this is NOT what possesses the absence of c. One may wonder
that II can possibly be salvaged even when one uses V for 'x\
For, it is quite possible to say of the tree that it is NOT DIFFE-
RENT from what has c. But Gadâdhara in many places disallowed
the identification of c with the DIFFERENCE from what is
different from the locus of c. For, it is argued, although the tree
is qualified by c (so that it is a locus of c) it is not (known to be)
DELIMITED by c. (Roughly, a delimiting property has to be
pervasively occurrent, not non-pervasively occurrent.) Thus, the
original version of II uses the notion of delimitation. Hence, it is
concluded that both II and III fail to be satisfied by a non-per-
vasive property, and this should be regarded as a sufficient argu-
ment against their acceptance as rules of identification, i.e., as ver-
sions of the law of double negation (in Udayana's sense, of course).
Some might have the following rejoinder : The above counter-
examples may require us to narrow down the scope of application
of II and III; they may not force us to reject them totally. Thus,
one may hold without embarrassment that as long as we speak
in terms of pervasive properties, II and III are acceptable. If,
however, such delimitation of the scope of application is not
allowed, then, so the argument goes, it would be difficult to
maintain even I as acceptable. For, using the Nyâya ontologicaî
scheme, it is not hard to find a value of x which will render the
status of the universal acceptability of I dubious. For example,
gagana or the sky, in Nyâya ontology, is regarded as a non-
occurrent entity. (In other words, while most entities qualify or,
are occurrent in, some entity or other, the sky does not qualify,
or is not occurrent in anything.) Now, if we substitute 'the sky'
for 'x' in I, we shall face a peculiar Nyäya problem, which will
render I invalid ! To wit : since the sky is not occurent in any-
thing, its absence will be occurrent in everything including
itself (for, as long as the sky is not occurrent in itself, the
absence of the sky can be said to be occurrent in the sky). Now,
since the absence of the sky is occurrent in everything, the absence
152 Logic, Language and Reality
substituted for '*' in (iii). Now, '— blue' will refer to difference-
from blue-colour which is a property shared by all and only
non-blue things. Let us call this property eulb.1 Now, there are
many other properties (and things) besides eulb, and all of them
will belong to the class defined by the property difference-from-
eulb, that we may express by c —eulb' (i.e., by *—-blue'). In other
words, the last property cannot be a unique property of only
blue things. Hence, it cannot be identified with blue, for, the
necessary condition, equi-locatability, is not satisfied. Similarly,
it can be shown that 'difference from the absence of blue'
(derived from (iv)) expresses a property which is shared by every-
thing except the absence of blue. Hence, from Nyâya point of
view, these two properties are not very interesting.
Let me emphasize that the above has not been an exercise in
what may be called 'comparative logic'. My attempt here has
been an humbler one. I have tried to understand (myself) and
explain some of the issues which Navya-nyäya (and by the same
token, Indian logic in general) thought important, interesting and
relevant to their way of philosophizing. In my exposition I have
made use of certain modern (logical) terms. Some of these terms
have acquired very specialized and technical meanings in the
writings of modern logicians. I have, however, taken some liberty
with these terms (such as double negation and equivalence) for
the purpose of my exposition and translation. I think their
intended meanings will be clear from the context of my discussion,
and I sincerely hope that such uses will at least help our under-
standing of the problems of Indian logic.
x
The idea of'eulb' is from a comment of A. J. Ayer, 'Negation', p. 51-52
(See his Philosophical Essays, 1963 edn.) One note for caution : Taking
for granted the object/predicate distinction, as is normal In first order
logic, and using 'Fy for 'pot\ we have to say thlflo say that x is —F (in
our sense of ' — ') is not to say that (y) (Fyz^y^x). Rather to say that x
is—F is to say that x={y : NOT Fy}. Note that the sense of «—F' is distinct
from the sense of 'Not F' or 'is Not F' as used normally in predicate
calculus. Thus it is that if eulb is taken to be the class of non-blue things,
then things (classes, individuals, or properties) that are distinct from eulb
will form the class of -eulb (or - - blue), i.e., to say that the —eulb is the
class of things different from the class of non-blue things.
This note owes its origin to a criticism of Mr. Christopher Peacocke of
All Souls College, Oxford, who very kindly read my typescript, and whom
I wish to thank here.
Problems of Philosophical Logic in Navya-nyäya 155
same, but they are two distinct cognitive events. (In modern
terminology, one may say that the above-mentioned ambiguity
of (2) is reflected, at least in part, in the suggested alternative
ways of symbolizing the structure t>f (2), e.g., "Fa" or "a=6").
A Navya-nyäya theory insists that a säbdabobha or a hearer's
cognition or knowledge of (2) would always be like C12,
while the speaker's cognition could be either (G2 or C12). (see
also § 5.4 and § 5.5).
In its affirmative form, the ambiguity of (2) is seldom resolved.
But, as soon as negation is involved, Navya-nyäya resolves the
ambiguity by talking about two types of negation, absence and
difference, which the cognitive episode concerned is said to have
taken into account.
(3) "This is not white."
(4) "This is not a cat."
If we follow the previous model of Cl and C2, we shall have
cognitive events having the following structures :
C3. The qualificand, etc., is qualified by the lack of being
white, i.e., absence of being white.
C4. The qualificand, etc., is qualified by the absence of the
property of being a cat.
But there is a strong feeling in the utterance of (4), that the
cognitive event involved is given by.
C14. The object referred to by "this" is different from, i.e.,
non-identical with, the object or qualificand cat that is
qualified by the property of being a cat.
C4 recognizes an absence as the qualifier (i.e., the main quali-
fier) while C14 recognizes a difference as the main qualifier.
Very roughly this amounts to saying that C4 involves a denial
of a purported relation (other than identity) between the object
and the property concerned, while C14 involves a denial of the
possible relation of identity between the two objects. That is
why, Navya-nyäya says that the first involves a relational
absence {samsargähhävä), while the second a difference or (as
it is sometimes called) mutual absence {anyonyäbhävd).
One curious connection between absence and difference,
according to Navya-nyäya, is this : Wherever one finds absence
of potness, i.e., the property of being a pot, one can find, or
158 Logic, Language and Reality
î translate :
"Otherwise, difference itself need not be considered as an
additional category. Everywhere we can imagine a property
p identical with any other property q which occurs in all
and only substrata of/?. This is what they say."
I pointed out earlier that if the same principle on the basis
of which the absence of absence of x is identified with x, or the
absence of difference from a pot is identified with potness, is
insisted upon, then one may also identify difference-from-pot
with absence-of-potness, for, these two properties have also the
same locus. If this is conceded, then one may as well eliminate
the category (or sub-category) difference and talk of only one
category, absence. But apparently, Navya-nyäya feels strongly
about a separate category difference; for, there is, Navya-nyäya
argues, a stronger epistemie consideration in its favour. How
about properties denoted by "DDDa" or "DDDDa"! Navya-
nyäya does not discuss them, as far as I have read, and so I
cannot tell either.
^These antinomies are usually named after their discoverers. For a good
exposition of them one may consult S. C. Kleene, Introduction to Meta-
mathematics (New York, 1962), Ch. Ill, § 11, § 12.
2
The traditional Nyäya holds the curious doctrine that the jätVs are real
(sat, satsvarüpa) but do not possess reality (sattä) by inherence. They were
forced into this position by difficulties of hierarchy and of the relations
between categories. If sattä could possess sattä there would be the faults of
ätmäsraya and of infinite regress. Cf. Kiranâvali.
3
The principle in Nyäya language has been stated as follows : "sva-sämänä-
dhikaranya-svâbhâvavadvrttitvâitad-ubhaya-sambandhena jâti-visisfa-Jâtitvâ-
Problems of Philosophical Logic in Navya-nyäya 175
vaçchedena sva-samänädhikaranatyantabhäva-pratiyogitväbhäva-niyamah"
Note that the expression "jâtitvâvacchedend" has the force of a universal
quantifier.
iSeeGâdâdharî{^Chowkhamha Sanskrit Series, Vol. 42>, p. 91.
176 Logic, Language and Reality
property. The Vaisesika used the word "earth" for every naturally
solid material substance as distinct from "water", etc., and
believes that smell is the natural property of such substance.
Thus, it is that, earth is defined in the Vaisesika system, as that
which has (natural) smell. This definition, according to Udayana,
will make the following inference possible :
Step I : Earth differs from non-Earth.
Step 2 : For Earth has smell.
Step 3 : Whatever does not differ from non-Earth does not
have smell, e.g., (pure) water in this glass.
Step 4 : Earth has the absentee (pratiyogin), smell, whose
absence pervades the absence of difference from non-
Earth.
Step 5 : Therefore, Earth differs from non-Earth.
"Whatever is earth differs from such non-earth as water and
air." Udayana claims that in Step 3, the example is easily avail-
able meeting the two requirements stated above. He further claims
that the conclusion is here in the required negative form so that
it directly records the 'perlocutionary' effect, viz., differentiation
(vyävrtti), of the act of definition. It may be argued that the
property we infer (predicate of the conclusion) is called'difference
from non-earth', and such a property is unfamiliar and, hence,
unknown to us, unless we observe it instantiated in a particular
earth, a pot, for instance. If we are asked to leave such a pot,
etc., out of our consideration, for, they are included in the
domain of what is expressed by the subject term, then we might
face another difficulty. Nyäya requirement is that where we infer
a property as qualifying something in an inferred conclusion, that
property cannot be, prior to the inference, entirely unfamiliar
to us. In other words, we must have some general acquaintance
with the property before we can infer it as qualifying something
else. The point is technically called the fault of unfamiliar pro-
perty as the inferred predicate (cf., aprasiddhasädhya). I cannot
infer something to be circular in shape, if I do not have even the
vaguest notion of what 'circularity' is. Udayana, however,
counters this objection by saying that familiarity with the pro-
perty 'difference from non-earth'is to be derived from acquain-
tance with such individual earth, a pot or a table; and we do
not beg the question here, for, j h ç coiiclusian we derive is
Problems of Philosophical Logic in Navyanyäya 191
1
What 1 am calling tautology is to be distinguished from the rather techni-
cal use of the term in modern logic, where any sentence that is necessarily
true by virtue of its truth-functional form is called a tautology. Roughly,
I am calling such sentences tautologous here as ''A is A" or "A has ,4-ness."
An inference which uses such a premise or such a conclusion is sometimes
cailed siddha-sadhana.
Problems of Philosophical Logic in Navya-Nyäya 193
X
S. Kripke, "Identity and Necessity," in Sehwartz, S. P. Naming, Necessity
and Natural kinds, Ithaca, 1977. Also "Naming and Necessity," in David-
son and Harman's The Semantics of the Natural Language, Dordrecht,
1972/
2
H. Putnam "Is Semantics Possible ?" pp. 111-8 (in Schwartz, S.P.).
Problems of Philosophical Logic in Navya-Nyäya 201
PROBLEMS OF KNOWLEDGE
AND PERCEPTION
by some real cause. But Säntaraksita rejected all these four posi-
tions. Kamalasîia, while commenting on Sântaraksita, elucidated
the position of the Buddhist as the fifth possibility.1 According
to this view, both truth and falsity can very well be intrinsic in
one case and extrinsic in another. In the case of our first acquain-
tance (anabhyäsadasä), that is, in the case of a new cognition,
truth and falsity should be apprehended extrinsically. In other
words, we depend on an extraneous condition for confirmation
or disconfirmation of such cognitions. In the case of our repeated
acquaintance (abhyäsadasä), however, truth or falsity of
cognition becomes intrinsically known. For example, because
of bur repeated acquaintance, the truth of such cognitions as
"water will quench our thirst," and falsity of such cognitions as
"the conch shell is yellow," will be revealed automatically with,
the cognitions.
A few wordson the prakäsathQory—the theory of the apprehen-
sion of an instance of cognition—may be in order. The main
problem under consideration here is "How do I know that I
know?" In order to precisely understand what the Indian phi-
losophers meant by raising and suggesting possible answers to
this philosophic question, we should keep in mind that some
philosophers hold cognition itself to be a perceptible object.
However, they differ as regards the nature of the perception of
an instance of cognition. There are yet other philosophers who
maintain that cognition is not at all a perceptible object. We
know a cognitive event through inference.
Sâlikanâtha, an exponent ofthePrâbhâkaraMimânisaka school,
holds that cognition is self-revelatory (sva-prakäsa) in the sense
that a cognitive state in the form *I know this' always reveals not
only the object expressed by "this" but also the knowing subject
as well as the knowledge in question. Thus, 'I know this' becomes
logically equivalent to 'I know that I know this.' On the analogy of
light revealing also the light itself, 'reveal' is claimed to be a reflexive
relation when applied to knowledge. The Vijnänaväda school of
Buddhism also regards cognition as self-revelatory, but they
maintain that a cognitive state reveals nothing but itself. Their
1
Cf. na tu bauddhair esârri catuniâm ekatamo 'pi pakso' bhi§to niyamapaksas-
yestatvät, Tathä hi ubhayam apy etät kincit svatah kincit paratah iti pürvam
upavarnitam." Tattvasantgrahapanjikä under verse 3123, p. 811. For Säntara-
ksita's critique of different prâmânya theories, see Tattvasarngraha (Baroda,
1926), verses 2813-3123 (vol. II). '
Problems of Knowledge and Perception 207
It may be that for the Nyäya theory the model was the typical
rope-snake example, where there is a psychological basis (viz.,
intervention of memory or the snake-idea) for error, while for the
Präbhäkara theory the model was the case of a defective or disea-
sed sense-organ, where there is a physical basis for error. Thus,
for the Nyäya it was, to begin with, the misconstruction of a
relation, whereas for the Präbhäkara it was a mechanical failure
obscuring the factual disconnection. But both theories were ex-
tended and modified to cover all patent as well as recalcitrant
cases of error.
Mohanty has given a penetrating explanation of the Nyäya con-
ception of jnäna.1 The postulate of nirvikalpaka perception, that
is, prejudgmental cognitive state, was associated with a number
of important philosophical problems. The controversy over this
seems to have started with Dignäga (ca. 500 A.D.), although the
definition of perception stated by Gautama (ca. 100-200 A.D.) in
Nyäya-sütra 1.1.4 was, under the simplest interpretation, applic-
able more directly to our sense-perception rather than to our
perceptual judgment-The peculiar interpretation of Nyäya-sütra
1.1.4 offered by Väcaspati Misra (ca. 900 A.D.) was at best an
innovation, as evidenced by Vacaspati's own remark that although
the explanation he offered was not to be found in the earlier com-
mentary of Vätsyäyana ( ca 350 A.D.) or in the sub-commentary
of Uddyotakara (ca. 600 A.D.) he had followed his own teacher
(guru) Trilocana in this matter. 2 Thus, the clear-cut classification
of perception into non-judgmental (nirvikalpd) and judgmental or
constructive (savikalpa) was an aftermath of Dignäga's criticism
of the Nyäya theory. For Kumârila Bhatta (ca. 625 A.D.), a pre-
judgmental cognitive state is the direct grasp of the reality with-
out differentiation and conceptualization. This cognitive event
is held to be psychologically prior to our perceptual judgment.
The Nyäya-Vaisesika writers like Väcaspati and Srïdhara follo-
wed mainly Kumärila in their exposition of the pre-judgmental
state. But in Navya-nyäya, the status of this non-judgmental
cognitive state is reduced to a logical construction. According
to Navya-nyäya, the non-judgmental cognitive state is never
revealed to us, that is, never apprehended by our inner per-
*See J. N. Mohanty: Gangers Theory of Truth, pp. 25-37. See also
Matilàl : The Navya-nyäya Doctrine of Negation, pp. 6-21.
2
See Nyäyavärtiikatätparyaiikä(Benzres, 1925), p. 133, lines 9-15.
Problems of Knowledge and Perception 211
x
Cf. The Navya-nyäya Doctrine of Negation, pp. 27-29.
3
J. N. Mohanty, "On the Nature of the Prâraânya Theory," Our Heritage
[Calcutta], 8 (1960), pp. 43-47.
3
Op. cit., p. 17, n.
*See A. Tarski, "The Semantic Conception of Truth," in H. Feigl and
W. Sellars, eds., Readings in Philosophical Analysis (New York : Apple-
ton Century-Crofts, 1949), p. 53.
Problems of Knowledge and Perception 215
raised his hands and said, "Here is one human hand, and here is
another. Therefore, two human hands exist. And therefore, two
physical objects exist." Both Johnson and Moore were concerned
with a very persistent philosophic problem: When we are said to
be seeing an external thing, do we perceive what it is that we think
we perceive? One may ask further whether the external things are
at all what we tend to believe that they are, and further whether
there are any external things at all, These problems exhibit them-
selves embarrassingly in almost every discussion which is philoso-
phic in nature. My purpose here is to discuss some theories of
Indian philosophy concerning them.
Modern philosophical studies of perception have often centered
around a controversy over what are called ''sense-data." The
sense-datum theory had its heyday in the past decades, although,
much like logical positivism, it is now on the decline. But a re-
ference to it can hardly be left out in any modern discussion of
perception, and what I will have to say about the views of Indian
philosophers here may, from time to time, be reminiscent of
points made by both" the sense-datum theorists and their critics.
This is so because sense-datum theory, like positivism, reacted
against a form of idealism. The positivist, for example, has tried
to imagine an ideal "protocol language" which is evidentially
prior and hence forms the basis of scientific empricism. Most
Indian theories of perception were also attempts to combat a
radical form of idealism which theMaitreya-Asanga-Vasubandhu
school presented. The fact that the two versions of idealism differ
does not always cause a corresponding difference in the philoso-
phies of the anti-Idealists. Moreover, perception, illusion, and
hallucination are global enough to form a common ground on
which philosophers of different persuasions and traditions may
converse and debate.
It is difficult to find an exact counterpart of the term "sense-
datum'5 in Sanskrit, although it is true that Indian philosophic
reflection on perception and knowledge began as it did in the
West, with questions about the reliability of the senses. The main
problem these questions lead to is that of justification of our
belief in the existence of the external world, although in the
Indian context it takes on a slightly different shape with some
l
See next section § 3.3.
Problems of Knowledge and Perception 217
are confronted with in the situation, the interplay of hot air and
the sunrays.1 This appearance of water in a mirage-illusion may
be a sense-datum, but the perceptual consciousness here already
involves a judgment, an interpretation of the datum. The philoso-
phic motivation for introducing the sense-datum or even the
"appearance" language was the Cartesian search for certainty,
for the data are supposed to be incorrigible and indubitable.
They are also called "the given" because they are felt to be
independent of our judgments. They are self-evident and our
beliefs, to fulfil their claims to be knowledge, must be based
upon them in some way or other. But the pratibhäsa (appearance)
is not an indubitable datum, for the Indian epistemologists
argue that as long as it is describable in language it becomes the
datum interpreted, or taken to be something F (for example,
water). So our "F-appearance" in a state of (perceptual) con-
sciousness implies that something is being identified as an F, or
the property of being an F is attributed somewhere. If what we
seem to cognize on a particular occasion is expressible in langu-
age as "this is F " or "this is an F" then the cognition in question
is said to have an "F-appearance." The dispute among the Indian
philosophers centered, to a great extent, on the exact (ontological)
status of the "F-appearance", mainly the "F-appearance" of
what we call a nonveridical perceptual experience (such as, a
mirage-illusion of water).
The word "älambana" is a flexible term in Sanskrit. It is not
the sense-datum, but rather the "foundation" or "support" of a
(perceptual) sensory experience. The Buddhists call it a pratyaya
(causal condition) on which the arising of a state of perceptual
consciousness depends. For example, a visual perception depends
upon what may be called the visible {râpa). This is enough for
the Buddhist to call it a sort of "causal" dependence.* But it is
not depended upon in the way the visual organ (the eye) is depen-
ded upon for the arising of a visual perceptual state. It is depen-
ded upon by way of being its object (visaya), to use, again, an
already problematic term. The Abhidharmakosa notes thefollow-
^ e c Vätsyäyana, Nyâyabhàsya 1.1.4.
2
For the Buddhist use of the term pratyaya as "causal condition" see § 4.2.
Also see Vasubandhu's Abhidharmakosab/wsya, Varanasi (éd. S warn i
Dwarikadas Sastri), Î97Î, pp. 279-82.
Problems of Knowledge and Perception 219
x
The situation is not very different with the sense-datum theorists in the
West, although very few philosophers today would go as far as Vasuban-
dhu would ask us to go. Thus, W. H.F. Barnes criticizes, "...once the
sense-datum theory is developed in the form stated above, it follows that
even if physical objects exist, they are never present in perceptual experi-
ence; and it becomes an open question whether they have any existence
at all." ( 'The Myth of Sense-Data," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society
[1944-1945], included in R. J. Swartz's Perceiving, Sensing and Knowing
(New York : Anchor Books, 1965), p. 142. Most modern philosophers
would like to maintain a 'double-standard' that would enable them to eat
their cake and have it. Thus, it is claimed that when 1 "directly see" the
sense-datum, I also "see", in (to use Moore's term) a Pickwickian sense,
the physical object.
Problems of Knowledge and Perception 221
., pp. 3-4
234 Logic, Language and Reality
We may now look into the other side of the story. Since Yogâ-
cära idealism was a challenging philosophical position, it evoked
criticisms from all sorts of realists, the Nyäya-Vaisesika, the
Mïmârnsakas, the Jainas as well as the Buddhist realists. In what
follows, I shall limit myself to the criticisms of some Nyäya-
Vaisesika philosophers, as well as of Kumârila, the Mîmàrnsaka.
In most Nyäya-Vaisesika texts, one finds an elaborate defence of
their theory about the constitution of matter out of atomic parts.
The notion of atoms can be made compatible with creation of
gross bodies. For example, the Nyäya posited the dyads as inter-
vening between the impartite atoms and the gross particles, the
motes. The dyads are atomic in dimension and size, but are
divisible and have parts. Thus, conjunction of several dyads can
give rise to the gross motes or bodies without running into the
absurdities that Vasubandhu mentioned. Elsewhere I have discus-
sed the Nyäya answer to the Buddhist critique of atoms, and
hence Ï will not elaborate the point further.1
For a critique of idealism on epistemological ground let us first
turn to Uddyotakara. The oldest, perhaps pre-Vasubandhu, form
of idealism cited dream-experience etc., as examples where non-exis-
tent objects appear in consciousness. Uddyotakara countered : on
what grounds are the objects of dream-experience etc., thought to
be non-existent ? In fact, there are two senses of 'non-existence'
which are distinct, and should not therefore be confused. One is
what we can call temporal non-existence, and the other is non-
temporal non-existence. When a thing does not exist before its
coming into being and after its going out of existence, we can say
that it has this temporal non-existence, i.e., it is temporally non-
existent. But this temporal non-existence is hardly equivalent to
what we understand by the term 'unreality'. The non-temporal
non-existence is, on the other hand, equivalent to unreality.
An unreal object, e.g., a sky-flower, is non-existent only in
the second sense. To prove his contention, the idealist must
show that dream-objects or objects of memory are non-existent
not in the first sense, but only in the second sense. Usually, we
declare dream-objects to be non-existent, because they are not
1
See my Epistemologyt Logic and Grammar in Indian Philosophical Analysis,
pp. 52-4. My arguments there were based particularly on Uddyotakara;
pp. 213-16.
240 Logic, Language and Reality
'Kumârila, p. 221.
cf. "na smarämi maya ko 'pigrhito "rthas îadeti hi
smaranti grahakolpada-gràhyanïpavivarjitam
tasmâd abhinnatâyâm ca grùhye 'pi smaranam bhavet
grâhakasmrfinirbhâsât taîràpy esaiva grhyate"
tadatyantavinâbhâvân naikâkâram hi jäyate
anvaya-vyatirekäbhyäm siddhaivam bhinnatä tayoh
Sünyaväda, verses 83-85.
%
NyäyamahjarU p. HO.
kvacic ca grahyakaranupaslitfakevalagrahaka-
Problems of Knowledge and Perception 245
l
Nyäyabhü}anat pp. 137-9
248 Logic, Language and Reality
to concede the oddity that millions oï latent traces are also dying
every moment, and creating new latent traces. Asanga and Vasu-
bandhu developed the älayä doctrine, 'storehouse consciousness,'
to account for the continuity of latent traces in the form of seeds
through ever-fluctuating states of consciousness. But this alaya
again, has to be conceived as an ever fluctuating series receiving
new seeds and dispensing with some old seeds through fruition
at every moment. For further discussion see 4.7.
Realists like Kumârila and Jayanta found this concept of âlaya
very difficult to accept. For, under this theory, not only one has
to imagine the momentary, fleeting states of consciousness (no
matter whether it is the base consciousness or alaya, or the
surface consciousness or vijhapti) as the container or substratum
of innumerable latencies or traces, but also one has to concede
the actual and instantaneous arising and destruction of such
innumerable latencies. Only when a latency or seed reaches its
maturity (vipâka), it produces a particular form of experience.
But the question is: why should we talk of the dying of innumer-
able latencies when we will have to say that these latencies as
latencies come to life again in the next moment.1
Some Buddhists draw the analogy of 'perfuming' one thing
with the other. In other words, latencies are transferred from
one consciousness state to the other just as the perfume of one
thing is transferred to the other by association. Jayanta argued
that this analogy was misconceived. Perfume is a (physical) part
of the thing that possesses it, and transference of the perfume is,
in actuality, the transference of this subtle 'physical' part of one
thing to the other. But the Buddhist postulates that one state of
consciousness is totally annihilated before the other state arises
in its place (cf. niranvaya-vinäsä). But the notion of 'perfuming'
will involve not total destruction but only partial destruction with
traces left behind. Besides, if the state of consciousness is only
momentary, how can it transfer its perfume to the other state.
For, ordinarily, a thing has to stay longer than just a moment in
order to transfer its perfume to another thing.2
Wyäyamanjari, p. 114. na câlayavijnânam
kincld astiy saty api tasminn a§esaväsanäsahasra-
samâsraye îatk§anikatvât sakrdeva
tathâvidhavasanànukfdajnânavinasah syâf.
%
Nyâyamanjari, p. 113, continued next page.
Problems of Knowledge and Perception 249
Last but not the least, if the idealist challenges the realist to
prove conclusively and beyond doubt the reality of the material
world, it might only be a good strategy in public debate. For even
if the realist fails to prove his thesis conclusively (as he may very
well fail if he falls into the trapset by the idealist), this will not, in
my opinion, constitute a good vindication of idealism. A realistic
interpreation of error, hallucination and dream, is indeed possi-
ble, and the Nyäya theory in this regard is not, in my opinion,
very far from the truth. But construction or consistent description
of a realistic metaphysic is another matter. Partial failure in
this respect will not constitute a justification of idealism. A
realist may even refuse quite consistently to describe an
ontological system. For, it is the idealist who has challenged
the commonly shared beliefs, and so it behoves him to establish
his thesis conclusively.
By way of documentation, I wish to present here excerpts from
certain relevant texts in translation:
3. yâtsyàyana
[The translation is by the author.]
Nyäyasütra 4.2.31-32
Supposition of'the means of knowledge' (pramäna) and
4
the objects of knowledge' (prameya) resembles the supposi-
tion of dream-objects.
Vätsyäyana : Just as in a dream objects do not exist but are
supposed to be there, similarly the means of knowledge and
the objects of knowledge do not exist but we (only) suppose
that there are objects of knowledge and means of knowledge.
NS 4.2.33 [Answer] This argument is not established because
it is not based on a reason.
Vät. :
There is no reason to prove (conclusively) that the means
and the objects of knowledge are only supposed to be there
like the supposition of objects in a dream, and that they are
not known like the objects of waking experience. Therefore,
the (above) argument is not established for there is no
reason. (See NS 4.2.33)
Moreover, there is no reason to maintain that unreal
objects are cognized in a dream experience.
[Objection] (The reason in the latter case is:) "Dream objects
are not cognized when one wakes up."
[Answer] Since the objects of waking experience are cogni-
zed their existence is notrefuted. (To explain): If the objects
in a dream are proven to be non-existent because they are not
apprehended when one wakes up, then (at least) those objects
that are apprehended by one at one's waking state are proven
to be existent because of their being apprehended (at the wak-
ing state). For, the reason becomes adequate in the 'contra-
positive' case. If existence is established through apprehen-
sion then non-existence can be established through non-
apprehension. If not the first, then non-apprehension cannot
be an adequate reason for proving non-existence. For
254 Logic, Language and Reality
result will have different substrata (but cause and effect are
supposed to have the same substratum).
[Answer:] This is not true, for I do not concede the point. I do
not concede that the action and its result are occurring in
different substrata. The action is located in the self (ätman)
and the result is also in the same locus. Thus, the (supposed)
fault (in my position) is rejected.
The objects (of my consciousness) are different from my
consciousness because they possess generic features as well as
spécifie features. They are distinct just as my consciousness-
series is distinct from the consciousness belonging to another
personality-series (i.e., another person).
The objects, are different from consciousness because they
can be established (as external) by means of knowledge. Also
because they are 'effects' (kärya, 'causally conditioned'),
they are temporal, and they are preceded by residual traces
of action (dharma).
5. Madhyänta-Vibhäga-bhäsya 1.4
"na tathä sarvathä bhävät"
The meaning is admittedly not clear. Sthiramati comments:
na tathä 'stitvän na ca sarvathä nästitvät tadgrähyagrä-
hakapratibhäsam utpadyate. I wish to thank Dr. S. Katsura
for pointing this out to me. The possible translation
would be ^{Abhutaparikalpatva is established), because
it does not exist as (it appears) and because it is not non-
existent in every respect."
§ 3.4 : MEMORY
^dayana, p. 110
2
Vacaspati, p. 35
266 Logic, Language and Reality
ONTOLOGICAL PROBLEMS
But, in truth, the two lines cannot be torn apart in this way;
and we find that a wavering balance between the two is a char-
acteristic of the greater number of philosophers. Plato found
his permanences in a static, spiritual heaven, and his flux in the
entanglement of his forms amid the fluent imperfections of the
physical world.... Aristotle corrected his Piatonism into a some-
what different balance. He was the apostle of'substance and
attribute', and of the classificatory logic which this notion
suggests.
In the Indian context, one may observe that the Buddha's search
for nirvana, the unconditioned state, freedom from suffering
or duhkha, spelt out a philosophy for the later Buddhists, accord-
ing to which the flux of things, impermanences, "the fluent
imperfections of the physical world" are identical with suffering
(duhkha, cf. whatever is impermanent, is suffering). And NIR-
VÄI^A, the unconditioned state, is actualized with the cessation
of this duhkha. The Vaisesikas, on the other hand, were, much
like Aristotle, the apostles of substance-and-attribute duality.
§ 4.2 : CAUSALITY
is more like the Buddhist view than the Nyâya view. For Nyäya,
invariable sequence is discovered by the mind but it exists
between extramental realities like universals or class characters
Perhaps Nyâya shuns the Humean empiricism while it asserts
its doctrine of real universals. In fact, although the early Nyâya-
Vaiéesika doctrine of universal was modified by Navya-nyâya,
it still maintained that certain class-characters were real in
order to explain, among other things, the relation of cause and
effect.1
Thus, it was felt in Navya-nyäya that the criterion of invari-
able sequence was not enough for distinguishing causal conditions
of a particular effect. For example, the production of a pot is
preceded invariably not simply by the potter's wheel, but also by
the colour and circularity of the potter's wheel. But the colour of
the wheel is immaterial and irrelevant to the production of the pot.
To exclude such irrelevant items from being considered as causes
of the particular effect in question, such Navya-nyäya authors as
éaéadhara and Gangesa introduced the notion of what they
called ananyathäsiddhatva 'unconditionally'. The invariable
presence of the colour of the wheel before the pot is produced is
conditioned by the presence of the wheel itself, and hence, it need
not be taken into account while we consider the relevant (causal)
conditions for the effect in question. By the same token Navya-
nyäya excludes the cause of a cause from being considered as a
cause of a particular effect. This takes care also of a conceivable
case where each time a pot is produced on the potter's wheel, a
donkey always walks by immediately before the event. Experience
of invariable sequence may demand that we construe the two
events as causally related. But Nyâya claims that the 'unconditio-
nality' criterion can save the situation, since it is possible to find
a reasonable explanation of each case of such appearances of a
donkey. If such a reasonable explanation is found, the donkey's
appearance will no longer be an 'unconditional' antecedent.2
If the Navya-nyâya analysis of the causal relation seems to be
somewhat embarrassing to a Humean empiricist, we may intro-
1
See my Epistemology, Logic and Grammar in Indian Philosophical Analysis,
(The Hague : Moutoii, 1971), pp. 71-77.
2
See, for a discussion of ananyathäsiddhatva, Tattvacintâmani of Gangeéa,
ed. Kamakhyanatha Tarkavagisa (Calcutta : Asiatic Society of Bengal,
1884-1901), Part 2, vol^J, pp. 154-5.
Ontoîogicaî Problems 291
The Jainas too, identify the notion of "it is" (existence) with
that of substance, but they add also that "it is" or "it exists"
means only that it is endowed with the triple character of origin,
decay and stability.
The idea of 'own-nature' (svabhäva) in the early Indian philo-
sophy was, perhaps, the nearest analogue of the notion of'essence'
found in the Western tradition. Nâgârjuna and his followers,
the Mâdhyamika Buddhists, were the champion critics of the
'own-nature,' the immutable core, as well as of the notion of
existence which is necessarily dependent. "It is," as the Mâdhya-
mikas will argue, should mean that 'it always is,' and "it is not"
should mean that it always is not. The Mädhyamikas, in fact,
argued: all things (beings) are empty of their own-nature (own-
being) because they are dependently originating (pratttya-samut-
panna).1 It is thus clear that the 'emptiness' doctrine has been
propounded by Nägärjuna in order to avoid the paradoxical
situation under which existence or own-nature would have to be
admitted as dependent and conditioned. It is probably because
of Nägärjuna's trenchant criticism that the Vaiéesikas never
explicitly stated the 'own-nature' theory of substance,
although such a theory might very well have been implicit
in their doctrine of substance. The Vaiéesikas in fact held a
modified position. There are, according to the Vaisesikas, two
types of substance: permanent, and impermanent. The atomic
constituents of the material substance, and the non-corporeal
substances, such as, the sky, time and space, are regarded as
permanent substances and independently existing, but the things
like the clay-pot and the wooden chair are impermanent and
existent only being causally dependent.
The idea of substance as the logical subject was another im-
portant notion which became the concern of Aristotle and his
followers in Western philosophy. But this notion is no longer
appealed to by the logicians today, although some modern
philosophers have revived the issue in a different way. Strawson
does not mention the word "substance" but shows that material
bodies and persons are central notions of our conceptual scheme,
and he calls them the basic or fundamental particulars. He also
shows the connection of the notion of a 'particular' with that
1
Cf. tkpratïtya-samutpaniiatvâii-nilisvabhavam, uilisvabhävatvät sQnyam
iti upapaanain." Nâgârjuna, Vigrahavyavaria ni, under verse 22,
Ontological Problems 299
1
of an object of reference or logical subject. This can be seen
as the explication of the old problem of substance as the logical
subject. In the Indian context, the Vaisesikas never explicitly
considered the connection between the logical subject and the
notion of substance, although it was probably implied in their
early doctrine of substance. The later Indian logicians (includ-
ing the Buddhists and the Naiyäyikas) coined a new term, dharmin
("property-possessor"), which was their nearest analogue for
"the logical subject." The Indian logicians developed the notion
of dharmin independently of that of substance, and, thus,
some of the problems connected with the notion of substance
as the logical subject were somehow not raised in their discussion.
Amrtacandra Süri, commentator of Kundakunda, explains
that when a pot is produced from a lump of clay, both the
origin of the pot and the destruction of the lump amounts to
maintaining the persistence of the clay-substance. In order to
prove his contention, Amrtacandra uses the following reductio
(prasanga): (For Kundakunda's remark see § 4.1.)
If we do not accept it as true, origin, decay and continuity—all
three, none will then be really different from one another. In
that case, when the mere origin of the pot is sought after, then
either it will not originate, for, there will not be any (real) cause
for its origin, or there will be origination of the non-existent
(an untenable paradox). If the pot does not originate, no
bhävas (things) will originate. If there is origination of the
non-existent (asat), then sky-flower, etc. will come into being.
Similarly, if mere destruction of the lump of clay is attempted
(to the exclusion of the production of the pot), then either
there will not be any destruction of the lump for want of any
(real) cause for such destruction, or there will be destruction
of the existent or being (an untenable position).2
We may again refer to the triple character of the substance.
The Jaina authors have dealt with this point very frequently. I
have mentioned Samantabhadra's comment in the previous
section (§ 4.1). Kumarila, the Mïmâmsaka, elaborated the point
in this way:
l
Strawson P.F., Individuals, p. 136ff.
2
Ami tacandra Suri, in Kundakunda, Ch. II,v.8, p. 125.
300 Logic, Language and Reality
1
Kumàrila, Mîmàmsâêlokavârttika* p. 613.
2
Tattvärthasütra 5.41 : "Dravyäsrayä nirgunägunäh"
3
Siddhasena, Sanmati, Ch. Ill, verses 8-9.
OntologJcal Problems 301
All these (four) are approved (by you) with reference to the
doctrine of standpoint (naya) only, not absolutely". (Äptamimä-
msä, V. Î4).
In this way, Samantabhadra has formulated the first four of
the seven alternative predicates. We can symbolize these four
basic propositions as ' + ' , ' — ' , ' ± ' and ' 0 \ The fourth predica-
tion, "it is inexpressible", is actually interpreted as the joint
(combined) and simultaneous (cf. sahärpanä) application of both
the positive and the negative. It is distinct from the third pro-
position, because in the latter there is joint but gradual (one after
another, non-simultaneous =*kramärpana) application of the posi-
tive and the negative, Since it is believed that the language lacks
any expression which can adequately express this simultaneous
and combined application of both the positive and the negative
characters, the Jainas say that they are obliged to name this
predicate "inexpressible", and we have symbolized it by c 0'
accordingly. The idea is that since we cannot say "yes" and " n o "
simultaneously in answer to a question, we can name thisvariety
of our answer as 'inexpressible'.
Although the predication "inexpressible" (or <Q') has been
reached in the above manner (as is evident from the Jaina texts),
the Jainas, however, still regard it as a unitary predicate, a unit,
like the positive or the negative (i.e., "it is" or "it is not").
Probably, it was thought that since the two components, positive
and negative, are here perfectly balanced and totally neutralized,
being applied simultaneously (in the same breath), the predica-
tion had lost the compound character and melted into one uni-
tary whole. In other words, a predicate that was compound in
character in its inception (or when it was first thought out)
turned into a non-compound, primary predicate, because of its
internal structure, so to say. I have thus used the neutral symbol
'0' to indicate it.
The Jainas have, in this way, three primary and non-compound
predicates, positive, negative and the neutral ( + , —, Ö). Nowit is
easy to see how the Jainas reached the seven possible varieties.
Let the three predication-units be represented by x, y and z. A
simple mathematical computation will generate only seven varie-
ties, if we use these three units in three ways, one at a time, two
at a time and three at a time :
308 Logic, Language and Reality
Traditional Objections
Critics of the Jaina sevenfold formula have mentioned many
faults or anomalies that are supposed to arise if the doctrine
is accepted as a philosophical method. The Jaina writers
beginning from Akalanka and Vidyänanda have analysed these
objections and tried to answer them in detail. Let us make a
brief survey of these objections and answers.
1
Cf saptabhahgï-prasâdena éatabhangy apijâyate; Kumârila's Slokavarttika,
ed. R. S. Tailanga, Benares, 1898.
a
See Vidyänaiula, op. cit., p, 126.
310 Logic, Language and Reaîijty
One may facetiously put : Both the Mädhyamika and the Jaina
fi
cook the metaphysical goose9 quite well enough, so that all
metaphysical doctrines can be eventually disposed of. While the
former says that all beings or things ((bhäva) are empty of its
own-being or own-nature (essence ?), the latter says that they
can have only a 'non-absolute' nature. Both deny that there
could be any absolute conception of Reality (any God's eye view
of reality that we humans can possess, except of course the
omniscient Mahavira), but while the former is emphatic
in. his denial and rejects ail such attempts (to construct
a metaphysical doctrine) to be futile and fundamentally flawed
(cf. they grasp the snake at the wrong end), the latter is more
receptive, for, he accepts a plurality of such 'conflicting* concep-
tions of the absolute reality. In fact, the Mädhyamika claims
that the sooner we can get rid of all such wrong conceptions
the better. The Jaina claims, on the other hand, that by pro-
visionally accepting all such 'partial' (but not absolutely wrong)
and 'non-absolute' conceptions of reality we get closer to the
truth, for, plurality is the nature of the reality. The Mädhyamika
view is exclusive (it is not even a view, and hence the designation
'emptiness'), while the Jaina view is inclusive (it is, in fact, ail-
inclusive), for it aims at totality. If a view includes everything,
even the conflicting views, then, in a way it also ceases to be a
view.
It will be interesting to compare the Jaina dialectic with the
Màdhyaniika dialectic. The Jainas argue that different philsophers,
when they construct durèrent philosophical systems, represent
only different 'standpoints.' The Jainas further point out that as
long as we emphasize one aspect or standpoint (say the stand-
point of 'substance'), while being fully aware that this is only
Ontological Problems 315
that the assertion in both the cases is identical and the difference
lies merely in what motivated such assertions. Thus, as a report
oh what the case is, both assertions will enjoy the same 'truth-
value'! But this kind of argument only exemplifies how much
one can be misled by over-extending the point of a parable. In
fact, the usefulness of a parable no longer holds as soon as we
stretch it too far.
We have to understand, with great care and caution, the
implication of the 'emptiness' doctrine. For, it was Nâg-
ärjuna himself who gave the following warning against any
misunderstanding of the doctrine : "Like a snake caught at the
wrong end, or like a craft learnt in the wrong manner, the
'emptiness' doctrine may destroy the stupid person when it is
misunderstood by him!"1
That the pluralistic order of the universe is only a convenient
myth and lacks essence or svabhäva in the ultimate sense is well
expressed by the following Lankâvatâra verse :
Since the essence or 'own-nature5 of things, when they are
critically examined, cannot be established, such things have
been declared (by the Buddha) to be inexpressible and without
essence.
The Mâdhyamika comes very close to the spirit of the Advaitin
with regard to his attitude toward phenomenal plurality. But the
Advaitin seems to me to be more committed to a metaphysical
absolutism in relation to which he seeks to evaluate ordinary
thoughts and experience. The Mâdhyamika, however, tries to
maintain a non-committal attitude in ontology.
The ultimate truth, according to the Mâdhyamika, always
eludes our ordinary experience and conceptual thought. But it is
admitted to be accessible only to a direct but somewhat mystical
experience, a sort of penetrating insight or prajnä. If this unlocks
the door to mysticism in philosophy, be it so. 'Mysticism', at
least 'cognitive mysticism', need not be, it is argued, treated as a
derogatory term. For, as we realize more and more the limits of
language in our analytical struggle, the idea of something in-
expressible may well dawn in our mind, although it would be
difficult to make a logical appraisal of this 'inexpressible'.
My point is that proper understanding of the Mâdhyamika
position ought to produce an incentive to strike a middle course
iMädhyamika-KärikäXXlV.U.
318 Logic, Language? and Reality
The term avidyä is one of the most important terms not only in
Buddhism but also in all important schools of Indian philosophy,
it is thus an extremely difficult task to find an adequate English
(or Western) equivalent of this term. In modern writing inter-
pretation of this term ranges from ambiguous (and evasive)
explanation to total misinterpretation. A satisfactory inter-
pretation of this important concept in the context of Bud-
dhism is hard to find. In the present section, I shall try to clarify
certain misconceptions that are usually generated around our
understanding of the meaning of the term avidyä. It will be a
preliminary attempt to find a satisfactory explanation of the
concept of avidyä. To put it facetiously (but not incorrectly, I
believe), the present section is being written in complete aware-
ness of our present avidyä of avidyä. We may not be able to
remove the second avidyä, but we can hope that more light be
thrown on the first.1
I shall concern myself here mainly with the notion of avidyä
that is explained and analysed in the Buddhist and related texts.
For comparison and contrast, I shall refer to other interpreta-
tions of this term in non-Buddhist sources. But to maintain
uniformity and to avoid complication, I shall refrain from
1
Several students in my class first drew my attention to the fact that a reader
of even the Venerable Rahula's excellent book, What the Buddha Taught,
may be in doubt as to the exact distinction between avijfâ and micchu
diîîhi (false views); p. 3.
320 Logic, Language and Reality
along with him. And for the sake of the economy of words, one
does not mention the followers.1
Vasubandhu also deliberates upon the etymological meaning
of the term avidyä. Let me fully quote the discussion from the
Ahhidharma-kosa-bhäsya.
Now, what is meant by 'avidyä' ? If it means that which is
not vidyâ then even the eye, etc. will be designated as avidyä.
If it means lack of knowledge, then it would be a non-entity.
And it is not proper to call avidyâ a non-entity. Therefore,
Avidyä is a dharma (element of reality), a different one, which
is the opposite (reversal) of vidyä. The negative compound
here is to be explained in the manner of amitra ('a non-friend')
or 'an-rta' (untruth*) (v. 28cd). A person who is the reverse
of a friend is called a non-friend (an enemy). We cannot
call just anybody an enemy. Nor can we designate the
absence of friend or friendship as enemy. 'Rta' means truth.
'An-rta' means untruth, and any statement that is opposite
of the truth is called untruth. Similarly, terms like 'adharma',
'anartha' and 'akärya' are explained as the opposite of dharma,
artha and kärya. Thus, avidyä is to be understood as the
opposite of vidyä9 Why so ? Because avidyä has been described
as a pratyaya 'condition' (in the chain of conditions).2
Vasubandhu has quoted further evidences from the sästra to
show that avidyä cannot refer to mere negation of vidyä. The
word 'avidyä' has been used in the sacred texts in connection
with many action-words such as, 'combining'. A mere negation,
Vasubandhu argues, cannot be the object of any such action-
words, and hence avidyä should be construed as a positive
dharma (cf. dharmäntara).3
Since in the Abhidharma, avidyä is used as a blanket expres-
sion for all the defilements (klesas) of the previous birth, a
genuine confusion may arise regarding the import of the term
avidyä as such. Thus it is that Bhadanta Srïlâbha held to the
view that avidyä actually means all the defilements. But Vasu-
bandhu has explicitly rejected this view of Srïlâbha for reasons
we have already discussed above.4
ilbid., p. 437 : 'Räjägamanavacane tad-anuyätrkägamanasiddhi-vat.'
2lbid., p. 463.
3ibid,, Ch. Ill, p. 4G3 : 'Tasmäd dharniäntaram evävidyä.'
4
Ibid., Yaéomitra's Comm., Ch. Ill, p. 465.
Ontological Problems 331
iThe process of active thoughts arising out of the 'passive' mind is descri-
bed in detail in the Abhidhammatthasangaho, Chap. IV. See also Aung's
Introductory Essay, pp. 27-30.
2See P. S. Jaini, Introduction, r>p. 101-10.
3For Vasubandhu's critique of prapti, see Abhidharma-kosa-bhasya under
verses 11/35-36. Yasomitra, explains in Sphutârthâ why this notion is not
exactly the same as the samyoga 'conjunction' of the Vaisesikas.
Ontological Problems 337
Only one of them operates at a given time, the one that has
reached its vipäka i.e., maturity. 1
Now, we can take a close look at the Yogäcära classification
of vijiïâna. Asanga, in his Yogäcärabhümi, studies the 'plane of
mind' (rnanobhümi) in its five aspects: its'own nature' (s vabhäva),
its locus, its intentional reference, its accessories, and its action.
Its 'own nature' has three forms: citta, manas and vijhäna. Citta
is älaya-vijnäna, manas is the 'ego-shrunk' or 'ego-centered'
mind, and vijnäna is the 'consciousness of six senses'.2
The locus of consciousness can be of three types: a causal
concomitant (cf. sahabhü), or a causal precedent (cf. samana-
ntard), or a causal seed (cf. bïjâsraya). The causal concomi-
tance of the five types of sensory consciousness are respectively
the five senses themselves. The causal precedent is the 'mind',
which is interpreted, following the Sarvästiväda principle, as
the immediately preceding consciousness moment. 3 The locus
which is the causal precedent to the 'mental' consciousness is
distinguished as the 'ego-shrunk' mind {klistam manah), which is
attendant (samprayukta) with ego-sense, pride, etc. (asmimäna,
etc.). The causal seed, however, for all types of consciousness,
is älayavijnäna. Thus, it is clear that the idea of a causal seed
of the Sauträntikas and the idea of a subterranean current of
consciousness continuum which was vaguely present in the
Sthaviras' talk about the bhavähga-vijnäna, and contributed to
the development of the notion of älayavijnäna in the Yogäcära
system.4
things and happy feelings. They are called duhkha, for, they
change and decay and do not stay long enough to impart happi-
ness. At this level impermanence and duhkha become co-exten-
sive concepts. The third type of duhkha is called samskära-
duhkha, the most pervasive type of unhappiness. It is the reali-
zation of the essentially conditioned nature of our existence.
Our entire psychosomatic existence is called suffering from this
point of view. For, to a man with wisdom, it appears to be
a self-perpetuating imprisoned state dotted by craving drive for
pleasure, the agony of search, dissatisfaction and further craving
happening in cyclic order. In Yogasütra 2:15, where it is declared
that to a person with discernment everything is duhkha, a similar
threefold classification of suffering has been made. It is interest-
ing to see that the samskära-duhkha is regarded there also as
the most pervasive concept.
Duhkha is sometimes explained by the modern Buddhist
scholars as a mental state born out of, probably, frustration due
to the transcience of objects of our craving. If this is accepted,
sukha or .happiness can also be deemed as duhkha. But however,
I think, such an Interpretation refers only to the second category
of duhkha mentioned above. Danto's characterization (see
above) of duhkha as a profound realization fits well in such a
second level interpretation of duhkha. An adequate explanation
of the notion of duhkha requires us to reach the third level—
the notion of samskära-duhkha. An adequate explanation of
duhkha must encompass an adequate explanation of nirvana,
both constitute a whole, and thus one cannot be understood
or explained independently of the other.
Duhkha, as the first Noble Truth, is thus neither physical
suffering nor mental frustration, nor is it simply the obsession
(or a state of paranoia) with the uncontrollable transcience of
our pleasures. It is a profound awareness—a realization that
our existence is necessarily conditioned; samsara is a prison-
house. Cessation of duhkha implies that unconditioned state of
freedom called nirvana. The remark just made about nirvana
brings our discussion closer to an ago-old controversy. I am
sure I shall be criticized by others for giving, perhaps inad-
vertently, a positive characterization of nirvana. Let us formu-
late the controversy and see what iesson, philosophic lesson to
be sure, may we derive from this controversy.
Ontological problems 349
lAbhidharmakoéa.
Chap. HI, Verses 19d, 20 : (Ed. Dwarikadas Sastri)
"ity anâdi bhavacakrakam /19
sa pratitya-sanwtpädo dvädasängas îrikândakah \
pwrvâparântayor dve dve madhye'sfau paripürinah //" 20
Ôntoiogicat Problenis 359
Vasubandhu describes all the twelve items as "limbs pertain-
ing to some avasthä or state" (cf. ävasthika).1 Yasomitra explains
that these twelve are, in fact, twelve different states of the per-
sonality series (i.e., series of the five personality aggregates).2
Thus, in fact, the third item, consciousness, is said to refer to
the stage of the "five aggregates" just at the time of conception
in the mother's womb.3 The fourth item, "name and visible
form" (näma rüpa) refers to the immediately succeeding stage
of the same five personality-aggregates; "six bases" (sacläyatana)
refers to the next succeeding stage; and "contact" (sparsdy to
the next succeeding stage which precedes the stage called "ex-
perience" (vedanä) where experiences of pleasure and pain are
possible.4
More intriguing is Vasubandhu's classification of the twelve
items into three groups, viz., kiesa (defilement, evil dispositions),
karma (action or motive forces derived as residues from previ-
ous action to generate further action), and vastu (=phala,
"things" or "resulting process").5 Wrong conception, thirst (or
desire), and means of gratification (upädäna) are called klesa
"evil dispositions \ This is obviously reminiscent of the Nyâya
item doça "evil dispositions". Although in NS 1.1.2 "evil disposi-
tion" and "wrong conception" are separately mentioned (ashas
also been done in the Buddhist enumeration, viz., avidyä of the
former birth, and "desire" and "means of gratification" in the
present birth), under NS 1.1.18, Vatsyàyana clearly states that
dosa means the triplet, räga "attachment", dvesa "aversion" and
moha "wrong ideas or conceptions". "Aversion" and "attach-
iFor such answers one may again consult P.V. Kane, History of Dharmaéâ-
stra, Vol. V, Part 2, the chapter on Karma and Transmigration (punar-
janma).
CHAPTER FIVE
INTERACTION OF GRAMMAR
AND PHILOSOPHY
all other causes that are not immediately connected with the I
effect (Phaläyogavyavacchinna-käranam). It follows that a karana
is such that, it being present, the result must necessarily and
immediately follow (karanamcatatyasmin-sati kriyä hhavatyeva)1
To take for example, in the case of felling a tree, the effective
contact between the axe and the tree will be the final cause and,
hence, it is a karana in this view. For this particular type of
contact {vijätiya samyogä) causes the event itself without waiting
for other conditions. Similarly, in the case of a visual perception,
the final sense-object contact is regarded as the karana.
This view takes the karana t o b e the chief cause. There is,
however, one difficulty connected with this view. In popular
language, we take the axe as the karana in felling a tree, and the eye
as the karana of visual perception. According to this view, the axe
or eye cannot be the karana as they are not the most immediate
cause. In logical analysis we see that it is the axe's peculiar con-
tact with the tree that finally causes its felling, and the sense-object
contact that finally reveals an object of visual perception. Scholars
subscribing to this view may come forward to meet this objection
with a modified definition of kararia. It is that which causes the
action denoted by the verb, but not through the operation
(vyäpära) belonging to a case (käraka) other than itself (svabhin-
na).2 Thus, neither the agent (cutter) nor the object (tree) causes
the action directly in this specified sense. The cutter does so
only by making the axe function well, while the tree by making
the function of the axe possible (because without the tree, the
axe cannot function upon it). Only the axe has been directly
(i.e., through its own operation) the cause of the felling of trees
and not through any other means. So it is a karana and, thus,
the popular usages are justified.
A flaw in this argument is not far to seek. The axe cannot be
the karana, according to the above definition.
A relation is conditioned all alike by both the relata. The
vijätlya contact between the axe and the tree is a relation (a
connector) which is also regarded as the operation (vyäpära)
under the present context and, hence, is necessarily conditioned
by the tree also. Thus, the axe becomes the cause through the
iNyâyakosa, p. 149.
zKâraka-Cakra., Bhavânanda p. 40
Interaction of Grammar and Philosophy 375
who calls the doctor, Mr. B happens to be his servant who prepares
the medicine, Mr. C is the brother who administers the medicine,
and Mr. D? the Doctor. While going to thank them he finds the
first 3 related to him in some way or other. Their relations per-
suaded them to do their respective duties. But Mr. D, not related
to him, comes from outside. Thus, he is the proper man to get
thanks. So also our karana gets thanks. This may not hold under
close scrutiny, but this is how our pre-philosophical intuition
singles out one particular item from the 'causal complex' and
gives it a preferential treatment.
that the weight of the one is quite different from that of the
other. What accounts for this difference in weight should be
called substance. In other words, iron and cotton are two different
substances which have different weights. We can distinguish
between the substance of one object and the substance of another
object also with reference to other properties. Thus, one object,
viz. a sword will cut our body if it touches it, while another
object, viz. a cotton garment, does not behave in the same way
under similar conditions. This difference in behaviour should be
ascribed to their difference as substance. Some object (say, a
hammer) can break a body by a single stroke, while another
object (say, cotton string) cannot break it even after a second or
third stroke. Such differences^ are also to be ascribed to their
differences as substance.
The above argument for the existence of substance has many
flaws. It may be asked why the difference in behaviour or even
in properties should be ascribed to the substance-hood of the
objects. It is equally tenable that only sensory qualities or other
qualities of objects are responsible for their different behaviour
under similar conditions. Perhaps, what Patanjali meant by sub-
stance here is what is called svabhäva 'own nature' or inherent
nature of objects—something which is unique to each object and
consequently accounts for its peculiarities. Later commentators
like Kaiyata were deeply influenced by the Vaisesika notion of
substance and hence tried to explain this passage of the Malta-
bhasya by following the Vaisesika définition of substance as a
substratum of quality.1
Patanjali's second attempt to define substance can be stated
as follows : Substance is the unchanging state of objects. Quali-
ties emerge and disappear in order to make room for new quali-
ties. What stays permanent amid ail changes is what is called
substance. It is the tattvaov 'essence' of an entity. Thus, a mango
fruit becomes green at one time and yellow or red at another
time, but it still remains the same mango or, at least, we call it
'the same mango'. What remains unchanged is the mango-sub-
stance. This seems to be a more sophisticated attempt to esta-
blish substance as the permanent core of things. We have already
discussed this notion of substance' in § 4. 1, 4.3.
iSee Kaiyata's Mahäbhäsya-pradipa, commentary on Patanjali's Vyäkarana-
mahâbhasya (Gurukul Jhajjar, Haryana, India) 1963, vol. IV, p. 87.
Interaction of Grammar and Philosophy 385
1
See Tattvadntamani, Edited by Pt. Kamakhyanath Tarkavagisa, Calcutta,
1884-1901, vol. IV, pp. 66 off.
2See Sabdasaktiprakâsikâ, pp. 136-39.
3lbid.,p. 389.
398 Logic, Language and Reality
Sarthaka-kabda
(significant word)
i 1 I
prakrti pratyaya nipäta
word base (affix) invariant word
i
i Krt taddhita dhâtvatpéa vibhakti
i (infix)
I
1 I
sup tin
i dhätu
nâma (verbal base)
(nominal base) i
1
ganokta yaugika sautra
where 'a\ '£,' *c\ 'd9, (e\ and «/' stand respectively for a creeper,
creeperness, a flower, flower-ness, red-colour, and redness i.e.,
red-universal. By manipulating symbols and using the principle
of substiution of elementary logic, (10) can be obtained from
the initial formula:
(il) Qixyf
It is to be noted that, of the elements 6a\ <b\ *c\ *d\ <e9 and </'
some represent qualificands, some represent qualifier and some
both, i.e., a quaiificand in the immediate context and qualifier in
the broader context and vice versa. But the creeper, represented by
*a\ holds a special position. It is simply a quaiificand with respect
to others and never a qualifier. Therefore, it is described as the
chief quaiificand (mukhya-visesya) of cognition (9).
Equivalently, (10) can be represented by constructing the
following diagram2.
iThis concept has been treated as identical with the tâîparya-sakti in the
Later Nyâya school. See also K. Kimjunni Raja, pp. 187, 209, 221.
414 Logic, Language and Reality
lOne might argue that the same root jnä (~"to know")can also take
different conjugational endings with the same noun-subject to indicate
different tenses, moods, etc. But such variation in conjugational suffixes
does not depend upon, and hence, is not determined by, the variation of
the verb's relation with the noun-subject. The point here is this : in
determining case relations the verb can be said to be an important factor
in some sense, but in determining tenses and moods the noun-subject is
not an important factor in the same sense.
416 logic, Language and Reality
cated. The rabbits do hot have horns, and fire is not used to wet
but to dry. Could we argue here, just as it has been argued by
some in another connection, that creatures like unicorns are
possible objects, although they are not actual, that it is possible
for rabbits to grow horns, for that would not take the rabbit-
hood out of a rabbit? In other words, it does not follow from
the definition (or the essence) of a rabbit that it cannot have
horns. Similarly, one may even say that there may be liquid fire
in some possible world where we can wet or sprinkle the ground
with it. But this line of argument would be deplored by Nyàya,
for the two combinations then would not illustrate incompatibi-
lity. And if they are not incompatible, the ideal hearer would
have a knowledge of their 'meanings', for he would be aided
by, among other things, an awareness of their possibility. The
general Nyâya position is, however, that these combinations do
not generate the required knowledge in the ideal hearer, for
they lack yogyatä. Other examples are clearly intended to show
patent (or logical ?) impossibility. Water-fire may still be in the
borderline, but others can be said to be logically impossible
without further ado : motherhood and barrenness, speech and
speechlessness, knowing and not knowing and listening where
listening is impossible. (The last example was a bit enigmatic,
and different interpretations were given by different commenta-
tors. But I forbear to enter into them here.)
It may be surmised from such discussion that for Nyâya there
is no strict distinction between logical impossibility and factual
impossibility. Incoherent and incompatible conbinations are in
the domain of the impossibles.
The Nyäya theory of Sabdabodha obviously allows that the
domain of 'possible' combinations excludes the above-mentioned
impossible combinations, but it would include, besides the
actual or 'true' combinations, a large number of combinations
or word-clusters that would pass the test of physical proximity
(äsatti), that of the said syntactico-grammaticality (on our inter-
pretation of äkähksä), and also that of possibility or compatibi-
lity {yogyatä), but would still fail to generate a true cognition or
knowledge in the ideal hearer. Why ? Predominance of false
sentences uttered by deceitful or ignorant or incompetent persons
is a matter of common experience. Hence, the hearer, no matter
whether or not he is aware of the speaker's intention or his
Interaction of Grammar and Philosophy 425
(Output)
Diagram I
Interaction of Grammar and Philosophy 429
Diagram II
Here the nine regions should be interpreted as follows :
1 TRUE i.e., the set of those that generate knowledge in the
ideal hearer. The speaker is äpta.
2 FALSE i.e., those that generate a (false) awareness. The
speaker is not âpîa.
3 Grammatical (syntactically acceptable) and Possible.
4 Possible and (physically) Proximate.
5 Grammatical (syntactically acceptable) and (physically)
Proximate.
6 Grammatically (syntactically) acceptable.
7 Possible
8 Proximate (physically).
9 Non-proximate combinations, if any.
Circle I is for Proximity, Circle 11 for Grammaticality, and
Circle III for Possibility.
430 Logic, Language and Reality
avayavin (whole) 39, 275 Carnap, R., 94, 101, 114, 131n, 166n,
avidyä 232, 238, 252, 319-32, 356-7, 169n, 171n
361 Cartesian doubt 183, 218, 233
avinäbhäva (vyâpti) 144 Cärväka 14
a-vyabhicaritatva (nondeviation) 130, Causal Theorists 223-4, 228
143, 188 causality 277, 284-94 (Buddhist no-
avyäkrta 'indeterminate' 'neither good tion) 284-5, (Nyäya) 285-90 (mod-
nor bad' 336 ern) 290-94, universality of cau-
avyâpti (under-extension) 172, 186 sation 291, causal chain of Bud-
avyäpyavrtti (non-pervasive property) dhism 340-2, 357-61)
119-122, 135, 144, 150 also called catuskoti (Tetralemma) 146
'partial location' 119 Celèrent (syllogism) 6, 7, 32
avyaya ('invariant' words) 393, 401 n certainty (logical vs. psychological) 73
Ayer, A.J. 154n, 291 Chakrabarti, A. 140n, 389
chala 'equivocation' 13, 15
B change and permanence, paradox of,
270,275, substratum of change 275,
bädha (=kälätita) 26 (defect of hetu), see also 'causality'
204 Chi, R.S.Y. 124, 125
Bambrough, J.B. 8 Chisholm, R. 88n
Bankimcandra 201 Chomsky, N. 427-8
Barbara (syllogism) 6, 7, 125 Church, A. 165n
Barnes, W.H.F. 220 citta-viprayukta-sairiskära 334-5, 336
Basham, A.L. 304n class-abstraction 167,
being vs. non-being 282-3 class-identity 159, 167
Berkeley, G. 234 class-logic 169n,
Bhadrabâhu 5 class-paradox I33n.
Bhagavad-Gitä 368 co-extensiveness 186, 187, see
Bhagiratha 423 samaniyata 188, also
Bhartrhari 215, 3O6n, 378-80, 381-2, equivalence 191, also
386-7, 397, 399n co-location 120, 122, 123
Bhâsarvajrïa 30, 33, 37, 43, 143, 183, cognitive event, analysis of the struc-
184-7, 192,3, 243, 246-7 ture of, 156-7
Bhätta, see also Kumärila, 207 Collingwood, R.G. 29
Bhattacharya, D.C. 165n, 389n concomitance 140-45, see also 'perva-
Bhattacharya, K. 45, 57-8 sion' and vyäpti
Bhaftoji Diksita 305, 323 contradiction, Law of 305, 310-11
bhâva (category) 161, 162 self-contradiction 312
bhävatva 162 co-occurrence 74, 144
Bhavänanda, 374n, 375n cosmogomy (Sat vs. Asat) 270
bhavänga-vijnäna 336-7 co\miQïû.çmonsiv&ï\<m(pratisthapanâ)
Biardeau, M. 165 2, 3, 4
bija 'seed' 338-40 see also vipäka Cratylus 271
Blue Annals, The. 67n
Bechenski, I.M. 165n D
Boolean Algebra 172n
Brentanp, F. 350 Dandin 395
Broad, C D . 217 Danto, A.C. 347, 348
Brough, J. 378n Dasgupta, S. 385n
buddhi (cognition) 207 dausthulya, two types of 'blemishes'
344
deductive reasoning 89-91
'defeat' situation 13, see nigrahasthâna
caitanya (consciousness, pure) 207 definition (laksana) 164-174, 176-202,
Candrakîrti 282n, 316 nominal vs. real def. 1804, elimi-
Caudramati 272 native def. 181n, contextual def.
Candränanda 37n, 141 n 181 n, legislative def. 181, 197,
Cantor 174 definitiod 166
Caraka 2-4, 10-12, 29, 38, 40 delimitors (avacchedaka) 121, 127
Cardona, G. 177 demonstration (sthâpanâ), 2-4
Index 441
Vätsyäyana 5, 12, 15-7, 22-4, 29-30, vyavahära 187, 200, 207, 211;
34-6, 38-9, 43-4, 47-9, 51-4, 56, 64n, vyavahära-siddhi 191
165, 177-8, 192, 210, 218n, 253, vyäpti 125, 130, 141, 167, 188
332,354-5,359,361,417 vyäpya 272
Vedänta 271 Vyäsa 346
Vedânta-sûtra 367 vyävrtti 187, 200
Vedas (sruti) 25, 263, 275, 287, Vyomasiva 273, 286n, 310-11
Vedic 352
Venkataramanam 333 W
Vidyabhusana, S.C. 2, 5n
Vidyânanda 308-10, Warder, AK. 40n, 321, 326n
vigraha, vigrhya sambhäsä 11 Whitehead, A.N. 170n, 176, 180,
Vijfianavâdâ 206-7, 229* 181n, 283
vijnapti 229, 232 'whole' {avayavin) 275
vijnaptimätratä 220, 229, 232, 248 Wittgenstein, L. 197
vikalpa 263
viksepa (evasion) 14
vipâka (maturity of the seed) 248,
337-40 Yâjtiavalkya 10, 364
vipaksa 131-2, 138 Yâska 382
vipaksäsattva 26-7, 71, 75 Yasomitra 329, 33On, 335n, 336n,
viparyaya ('contrapositive') 253 337n, 338, 359n, 360
viruddha-hetu (incoherent reason) 44 yäthärthya (truth) 208
visaya vs. älambana 219; yaukika näma 394-5
visayatä 213-4, 417-8; visesya 408- Yogäcära 103, 226-8, 231, 239-40,
10 248, 334-5, 337-9, 343, 345, 359n
visista-vaisistyävagähin 84 yogarüdha 394
Visvanâtha'405n Yogasütra 346, 348
vitandä 12, 16-7, 21, 105, vâda-v and yogayatä (compatibility) 82, 405-6,
jâlpa-v. 16-7, 19 416, 422-4, 427, 430
von Wright, G.E. 291 Yuktidïpikâ 5
Vrsagana 41
vyabhicära (deviation) 54-5
Vyädi 380, 386 zero occurrences of inflections 401,
vyäpära (operation) 374-5 403