The Cambridge Foucault Lexicon - Transgression
The Cambridge Foucault Lexicon - Transgression
The Cambridge Foucault Lexicon - Transgression
TRANSGRESSION
509
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Helsinki University Library, on 16 Dec 2019 at 14:20:53, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139022309.089
510 / Allan Stoekl
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Helsinki University Library, on 16 Dec 2019 at 14:20:53, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139022309.089
Transgression / 511
its limitlessness is itself founded on the necessity of the limit. Transgression is con-
tained in, and contains, the limits set by interdiction, and yet the very movement of
social life, the very thing that makes life worth living and makes it something other
than animal life, lies in the passage over those limits.
With all this said, one should note that Bataille’s theory is one of society. It
attempts to explain social phenomena: the ultimate workings, and meaning, of reli-
gion. It is therefore in a sense also a religious theory: it justiies and afirms the
“experience” of the sacred and provides meaning only in the more profound mean-
inglessness of transgression (unbridled sexuality, play, spending without return,
uncontrolled artistic and ludic activity). Bataille is concerned with telling us why we
live and what our ultimate motivations are, whether we recognize them (or can rec-
ognize them, since they operate against limits) or not. He is, in other words, at least
in his arguments on the sacred, a social commentator.
Foucault, in “Preface to Transgression,” is up to something else. His concerns
ultimately turn on textuality and the role of language in it. In his presentation/revi-
sion of Bataille, Foucault asserts that sexuality, like God, is no longer capable of
setting the outer limits of humanity or the limits of the individual. Sexuality for
Foucault appears to be something like what Bataille called eroticism; since God has
died, sexuality “points to nothing beyond itself” (ELCP, 30). (Although Foucault
uses the term “sexuality,” “eroticism” in Bataille’s sense would probably be prefer-
able, since Bataille is not discussing the phenomenon of sexuality examined by the
contemporary medical or social sciences, which clearly have little concern for trans-
gression or interdiction.)
As conveyed by the writings of the Marquis de Sade, sexuality now is a prof-
anation that “links, for its own ends, an overcoming of limits to the death of God”
(ELCP, 33). Through the endless permutations of Sade’s novels, written in the mode
of blasphemy, directed precisely against a God who does not exist, we come to rec-
ognize that sexuality, rather than something outside us (as biological or cultural
imperative), setting our personal limits, even authorized by theology (in its repro-
duction-afirming mode), instead “marks the limit within ourselves and designates us
as limit” (ELCP, 30). Endlessly written sexuality is now internal, referring back to no
animal (“natural”) state; it cannot be incorporated in a benign reproduction under
the aegis of an ininite, and ininitely limiting, God. Rather, it turns on itself, always
generating new permutations, new senseless variants: “Not that it [sexuality] proffers
any new content for our age-old acts; rather, it permits a profanation without object,
a profanation that is empty and turned inward upon itself and whose instruments are
brought to bear on nothing but each other” (ELCP, 30).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Helsinki University Library, on 16 Dec 2019 at 14:20:53, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139022309.089
512 / Allan Stoekl
One has the sense, nevertheless, that there is something positive in all this.
Perhaps in a Heideggerian mode (iltered through Blanchot), Foucault argues for a
transgression that “contains nothing negative, but afirms limited being – afirms the
limitlessness into which it leaps as it opens this zone to existence for the irst time”
(ELCP, 35) (on Foucault on Blanchot, see EFB). What is this afirmation? “Perhaps
it is simply an afirmation of division, but only insofar as division is not understood
to mean a cutting gesture, or the establishment of a separation or the measuring of
a distance, only retaining that in it which may designate the existence of difference”
(ELCP, 36).
Transgression is an afirmative movement, opening the possibility of difference,
but only in and at the limit, not outside; it does not provide a stabilizing boundary,
even in the ininite. It is not scandalous; there is nothing “demonic” about it (ELCP,
37). Transgressive difference is instead the movement not of a productive negativity
making possible revolutionary action, but only an “afirmation that afirms nothing,
a radical break of transitivity” (ELCP, 36) – what Blanchot calls “contestation.”
Division “is” the nonorigin of difference, the “existence of difference” as afir-
mation not afirming any “thing.” Heideggerian Being here morphs into a proto-
Derridean différance, with the difference being that Foucault can still write of the
“existence” of difference. And that difference with Derrida is, I think, signiicant. The
paradox of Foucault’s transgression is that, in the end, its difference from Hegelian
contradiction is not really transgressive in Foucault’s own terms. After all, it exists,
through the difference it afirms. . . . What then is the status of this existence? How
can it be transgressive?
Foucault’s larger goal in his essay on transgression is to dispute the primacy
of the authorial subject and, from there, the role of a constructive or constitutive
negativity. The “experience” is that of the space where experience’s language fails,
“from precisely the place where words escape it, where the subject who speaks has
just vanished” (ELCP, 40). With transgression in and against the internal limit, ini-
tude is lodged in, and transgresses, the space of the absent autonomous subject. Once
again, a Heideggerian note, but the result is quite un-Heideggerian, and indeed un-
Bataillean: transgression entails the sheer proliferation of language, language repeat-
ing and transgressing itself “to ininity,” inding its “uninterrupted domain” (ELCP,
48), permuting endlessly in the void of an authorial, and authoritative, subjectivity
(“transgressing the one who speaks” [ELCP, 44]). This language doubling and dif-
fering from itself, autotransgressing, is a movement that, in Foucault’s view, renders
obsolete the earlier model of Hegelian (and Kojèvian) negation (for a Derridean
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Helsinki University Library, on 16 Dec 2019 at 14:20:53, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139022309.089
Transgression / 513
critique of this endless mirroring and replication, see Gasché 1986). The dialectic
proposed a productive negativity, the uptake of destruction in the creative elabora-
tion of spirit, ending in, literally, the end, a steady-state of Spirit at the close of history
(this was Kojève’s rewriting of Hegel, which had an enormous inluence in France
between the wars, as well as after World War II; see Kojève 1947). But by 1963
the dialectic, especially as espoused in the version put forward by French Marxist
intellectuals (including Sartre), not to mention the French Communist Party, was
starting to show its age. The problem was in the question of replacement. Foucault
poses the rhetorical question: “[Must we] ind a language for the transgressive which
would be what dialectics was, in an earlier time, for contradiction?” (ELCP, 40). He
seems to want it both ways: no to a simple replacement of dialectical-philosophical
discourse, but yes to some other model of philosophy as transgressive discourse. But
is “some other model” not merely a version of replacement?
That is the central problem: is contradiction to be replaced by another philo-
sophical discourse? Are we really that far from negation, and from the Aufhebung?
The answer is not at all clear: philosophy only “regains its speech and inds itself
again only in the marginal region which borders its limits” (ELCP, 43), coming from
the impossible space between “a puriied metalanguage” and “the thickness of words
enclosed by their darkness” (ibid.). A philosophy will appear, in other words, that
transgresses the space between a coherent technical discourse and the madness of
proliferating language.
The answer to the question of replacement, then, is both yes and no. Foucault’s
transgressive duality (the line and its crossing) seems to anticipate much of the later
Tel Quel project – the paradoxical effort to establish a rigorous theory of a prelog-
ical “chora sémiotique,” as Kristeva called it (Kristeva 1984) – and therefore there
could be no simple replacement of Hegelian dialectics but only a repetition, with a
difference, the endless turning of philosophical discourse around its internal limit,
the necessary but unassimilable space of transgression. But the important thing to
note here is that Foucault is nevertheless attempting to work out the logic of a
philosophical discourse that would come after, in one way or another, the coherent
philosophical language of dialectics. It seems, then, that he wants it both ways: on
the one hand, transgressive discourse is an ininite murmuring, a differential afir-
mation, reminiscent of Sade’s endless permutations or Borges’s library of Babel. This
avant-garde ideal is doubled by the suggestion (posed as a question) that dialectics
(contradiction) will ind its successor in a transgressive language that would, we can
easily conclude, destroy the legitimacy of dialectical philosophies, not least Marxism,
and lead to some sort of (rigorously marginal) philosophical discourse, founded not
on contradiction but on transgressive language (which is in fact yet to be found, and
perhaps cannot be found: “must we ind?”). Discrediting Hegelianism (read, in the
1963 French context: Marxism) and putting forward some conjunction of Bataille/
Nietzsche would thus ultimately have to be seen as a political gesture, as well as a
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Helsinki University Library, on 16 Dec 2019 at 14:20:53, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139022309.089
514 / Allan Stoekl
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Helsinki University Library, on 16 Dec 2019 at 14:20:53, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139022309.089
Transgression / 515
Allan Stoekl
See Also
Contestation
Difference
Marxism
Space
Georges Bataille
Maurice Blanchot
Jacques Derrida
Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel
Martin Heidegger
Suggested Reading
Bataille, Georges. 1987. Death and Sensuality, trans. Mary Dalwood. London: Marion Boyars.
1988. Inner Experience, trans. Leslie Anne Boldt. Albany: The SUNY Press.
Deleuze, Gilles. 1983. Nietzsche and Philosophy, trans. Hugh Tomlinson. New York: Columbia
University Press.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Helsinki University Library, on 16 Dec 2019 at 14:20:53, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139022309.089
516 / Allan Stoekl
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Helsinki University Library, on 16 Dec 2019 at 14:20:53, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available at
https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139022309.089