CONFUCIANISM
CONFUCIANISM
CONFUCIANISM
WRITTEN BY:
Tu Weiming
LAST UPDATED: Aug 12, 2019 See Article History
Confucianism, the way of life propagated by Confucius in the 6th–5th century BCE and followed
by the Chinese people for more than two millennia. Although transformed over time, it is still the
substance of learning, the source of values, and the social code of the Chinese. Its influence has
also extended to other countries, particularly Korea, Japan, and Vietnam.
Confucianism, a Western term that has no counterpart in Chinese, is a worldview, a social ethic,
a political ideology, a scholarly tradition, and a way of life. Sometimes viewed as a philosophy and
sometimes as a religion, Confucianism may be understood as an all-encompassing way of thinking
and living that entails ancestor reverence and a profound human-centred religiousness. East Asians
may profess themselves to be Shintōists, Daoists, Buddhists, Muslims, or Christians, but, by
announcing their religious affiliations, seldom do they cease to be Confucians.
Although often grouped with the major historical religions, Confucianism differs from them by not
being an organized religion. Nonetheless, it spread to other East Asian countries under the
influence of Chinese literate culture and has exerted a profound influence on spiritual and political
life. Both the theory and practice of Confucianism have indelibly marked the patterns
of government, society, education, and family of East Asia. Although it is an exaggeration to
characterize traditional Chinese life and culture as Confucian, Confucian ethical values have for
well over 2,000 years served as the source of inspiration as well as the court of appeal for human
interaction between individuals, communities, and nations in the Sinitic world.
The Thought Of Confucius
The story of Confucianism does not begin with Confucius. Nor was Confucius the founder of
Confucianism in the sense that the Buddha was the founder of Buddhism and Jesus Christ the
founder of Christianity. Rather, Confucius considered himself a transmitter who consciously tried
to reanimate the old in order to attain the new. He proposed revitalizing the meaning of the past by
advocating a ritualized life. Confucius’s love of antiquity was motivated by his strong desire to
understand why certain life forms and institutions, such as reverence for ancestors, human-centred
religious practices, and mourning ceremonies, had survived for centuries. His journey into the past
was a search for roots, which he perceived as grounded in humanity’s deepest needs for belonging
and communicating. He had faith in the cumulative power of culture. The fact that traditional ways
had lost vitality did not, for him, diminish their potential for regeneration in the future. In fact,
Confucius’s sense of history was so strong that he saw himself as a conservationist responsible for
the continuity of the cultural values and the social norms that had worked so well for the idealized
civilization of the Western Zhou dynasty.
ConfuciusConfucius, illustration in E.T.C. Werner's Myths and Legends of China, 1922.
Get unlimited access to all of Britannica’s trusted content.Start Your Free Trial Today
Confucianism
Confucius lived in a time of warring Chinese feudal states. His doctrine focused on reestablishing peace and order
through virtue which he hoped would lead to prosperity.
Although Confucius presented the family as the foundation of society, he was divorced from his wife and lived with his
students.
Confucius’s life as a student and teacher exemplified his idea that education was a ceaseless
process of self-realization. When one of his students reportedly had difficulty describing him,
Confucius came to his aid:
Why did you not simply say something to this effect: he is the sort of man who forgets to eat when he engages
himself in vigorous pursuit of learning, who is so full of joy that he forgets his worries, and who does not notice
that old ageis coming on? (7:18)
Confucius was deeply concerned that the culture (wen) he cherished was not being transmitted and
that the learning (xue) he propounded was not being taught. His strong sense of mission, however,
never interfered with his ability to remember what had been imparted to him, to learn without
flagging, and to teach without growing weary. What he demanded of himself was strenuous:
It is these things that cause me concern: failure to cultivate virtue, failure to go deeply into what I have learned,
inability to move up to what I have heard to be right, and inability to reform myself when I have defects. (7:3)
What he demanded of his students was the willingness to learn: “I do not enlighten anyone who is
not eager to learn, nor encourage anyone who is not anxious to put his ideas into words” (7:8).
The community that Confucius created was a scholarly fellowship of like-minded men of different
ages and different backgrounds from different states. They were attracted to Confucius because
they shared his vision and to varying degrees took part in his mission to bring moral order to an
increasingly fragmented world. That mission was difficult and even dangerous. Confucius himself
suffered from joblessness, homelessness, starvation, and occasionally life-threatening violence. Yet
his faith in the survivability of the culture that he cherished and the workability of the approach to
teaching that he propounded was so steadfast that he convinced his followers as well as himself
that heaven was on their side. When Confucius’s life was threatened in Kuang, he said:
Since the death of King Wen [founder of the Zhou dynasty] does not the mission of culture (wen) rest here in
me? If heaven intends this culture to be destroyed, those who come after me will not be able to have any part of
it. If heaven does not intend this culture to be destroyed, then what can the men of Kuang do to me? (9:5)
That expression of self-confidence informed by a powerful sense of mission may give the
impression that there was presumptuousness in Confucius’s self-image. Confucius, however, made
it explicit that he was far from attaining sagehood and that all he really excelled in was “love of
learning” (5:27). To him, learning not only broadened his knowledge and deepened his self-
awareness but also defined who he was. He frankly admitted that he was not born endowed with
knowledge, nor did he belong to the class of men who could transform society without knowledge.
Rather, he reported that he used his ears widely and followed what was good in what he had heard
and used his eyes widely and retained in his mind what he had seen. His learning constituted “a
lower level of knowledge” (7:27), a practical level that was presumably accessible to the majority
of human beings. In that sense Confucius was neither a prophet with privileged access to
the divine nor a philosopher who had already seen the truth but a teacher of humanity who was also
an advanced fellow traveler on the way to self-realization.
As a teacher of humanity, Confucius stated his ambition in terms of concern for human beings: “To
bring comfort to the old, to have trust in friends, and to cherish the young” (5:25). Confucius’s
vision of the way to develop a moral community began with a holistic reflection on the human
condition. Instead of dwelling on abstract speculations such as humanity’s condition in the state of
nature, Confucius sought to understand the actual situation of a given time and to use that as his
point of departure. His aim was to restore trust in government and to transform society into a
flourishing moral community by cultivating a sense of humanity in politics and society. To achieve
that aim, the creation of a scholarly community, the fellowship of junzi (exemplary persons), was
essential. In the words of Confucius’s discipleZengzi, exemplary persons
must be broad-minded and resolute, for their burden is heavy and their road is long. They take humanity as
their burden. Is that not heavy? Only with death does their road come to an end. Is that not long? (8:7)
The fellowship of junzi as moral vanguards of society, however, did not seek to establish a radically
different order. Its mission was to redefine and revitalize those institutions that for centuries were
believed to have maintained social solidarity and enabled people to live in harmony and prosperity.
An obvious example of such an institution was the family.
It is related in the Analects that Confucius, when asked why he did not take part in government,
responded by citing a passage from the ancient Shujing (“Classic of History”), “Simply by being a
good son and friendly to his brothers a man can exert an influence upon government!” to show that
what a person does in the confines of his home is politically significant (2:21). That maxim is based
on the Confucian conviction that cultivation of the self is the root of social order and that social
order is the basis for political stability and enduring peace.
The assertion that family ethics is politically efficacious must be seen in the context of the
Confucian conception of politics as “rectification” (zheng). Rulers should begin by rectifying their
own conduct; that is, they are to be examples who govern by moral leadership and exemplary
teaching rather than by force. Government’s responsibility is not only to provide food and security
but also to educate the people. Law and punishment are the minimum requirements for order; the
higher goal of social harmony, however, can be attained only by virtue expressed through ritual
performance. To perform rituals, then, is to take part in a communal act to promote mutual
understanding.
One of the fundamental Confucian values that ensures the integrity of ritual performance
is xiao (filial piety). Indeed, Confucius saw filial piety as the first step toward moral excellence,
which he believed lay in the attainment of the cardinal virtue, ren (humanity). To learn to embody
the family in the mind and the heart is to become able to move beyond self-centredness or, to
borrow from modern psychology, to transform the enclosed private ego into an open self. Filial
piety, however, does not demand unconditional submissiveness to parental authority but
recognition of and reverence for the source of life. The purpose of filial piety, as the ancient Greeks
expressed it, is to enable both parent and child to flourish. Confucians see it as an essential way of
learning to be human.
Confucians, moreover, are fond of applying the family metaphor to the community, the country,
and the cosmos. They prefer to address the emperor as the son of heaven (tianzi), the king as ruler-
father, and the magistrate as the “father-mother official,” because to them the family-
centred nomenclature implies a political vision. When Confucius said that taking care of family
affairs is itself active participation in politics, he had already made it clear that family ethics is not
merely a private concern; the public good is realized by and through it.
Confucius defined the process of becoming human as being able to “discipline yourself and return
to ritual” (12:1). The dual focus on the transformation of the self (Confucius is said to have freed
himself from four things: “opinionatedness, dogmatism, obstinacy, and egoism” [9:4]) and on
social participation enabled Confucius to be loyal (zhong) to himself and considerate (shu) of others
(4:15). It is easy to understand why the Confucian “golden rule” is “Do not do unto others what you
would not want others to do unto you!” (15:23). Confucius’s legacy, laden with
profound ethicalimplications, is captured by his “plain and real” appreciation that learning to be
human is a communal enterprise:
Persons of humanity, in wishing to establish themselves, also establish others, and in wishing to enlarge
themselves, also enlarge others. The ability to take as analogy what is near at hand can be called the method of
humanity. (6:30)
Mencius is known as the self-styled transmitter of the Confucian Way. Educated first by his mother
and then allegedly by a student of Confucius’sgrandson, Mencius brilliantly performed his role as a
social critic, a moralphilosopher, and a political activist. He argued that cultivating a class of
scholar-officials who would not be directly involved in agriculture, industry, and commerce was
vital to the well-being of the state. In his sophisticated argument against the physiocrats (those who
advocated the supremacy of agriculture), he intelligently employed the idea of the division of
labour to defend those who labour with their minds, observing that service is as important as
productivity. To him Confucians served the vital interests of the state as scholars not by
becoming bureaucratic functionaries but by assuming the responsibility of teaching the ruling
minority humane government (renzheng) and the kingly way (wangdao). In dealing with feudal
lords, Mencius conducted himself not merely as a political adviser but also as a teacher of kings.
Mencius made it explicit that a true person cannot be corrupted by wealth, subdued by power, or
affected by poverty.
READ MORE ON THIS TOPIC
China: Confucianism
Confucianism was perceived by the Mongols as a Chinese religion, and it had mixed fortunes under their rule.
The teachings…
To articulate the relationship between Confucian moral idealism and the concrete social and
political realities of his time, Mencius began by exposing as impractical the
prevailing ideologies of Mozi’s collectivism and Yang Zhu’s individualism. Mozi, a former
Confucian who had become disaffected with rituals that he viewed as too time-consuming to be
practical, promoted a mode of collectivism that rested on the principle of loving everyone (jianai)
without respect to social status or personal relationship. Mencius contended, however, that the
result of the Mohist admonition to treat a stranger as intimately as one’s own father would be to
treat one’s own father as indifferently as one would treat a stranger. Yang Zhu, on the other hand,
advocated the primacy of the self and the nourishment (yang) of one’s nature (xing) rather than
investing one’s time and energy in social concerns and institutions that (Yang suggested) violated
that nature. Yang Zhu gained infamy among Confucians for declaring that he would
not sacrifice one eyelash to save the world. His point was arguably that people all too often waste
their own lives in the service of social arrangements that actually undermine their best interests.
Mencius, however, who as a good Confucian viewed the family as the natural paradigm of social
organization, contended that excessive attention to self-interest would lead to political disorder.
Indeed, Mencius argued, in Mohist collectivism fatherhood becomes a meaningless concept, and so
does kingship in Yang Zhu’s individualism.
Mencius’s strategy for social reform was to change the language of profit, self-interest, wealth, and
power by making it part of a moral discourse, with emphasis on rightness, public-spiritedness,
welfare, and influence. Mencius, however, was not arguing against profit. Rather, he instructed the
feudal lords to look beyond the narrow horizon of their palaces and to cultivate a common bond
with their ministers, officers, clerks, and the seemingly undifferentiated masses. Only then,
Mencius contended, would they be able to preserve their profit, self-interest, wealth, and power. He
encouraged them to extend their benevolence (his interpretation of ren) and warned them that this
was crucial for the protection of their families.
Mencius’s appeal to the common bond among all people as a mechanism of government
was predicated on his strong populist sense that the people are more important than the state and
the state is more important than the king and that the ruler who does not act in accordance with the
kingly way is unfit to rule. Mencius insisted that an unfit ruler should be criticized, rehabilitated, or,
as the last resort, deposed. Since “heaven sees as the people see; heaven hears as the people
hear,” revolution, or literally the change of the mandate (geming), in severe cases is not only
justifiable but is a moral imperative.
Mencius’s populist conception of politics was predicated on his philosophical vision that human
beings can perfect themselves through effort and that human nature (xing) is good. While he
acknowledged the role of biological and environmental factors in shaping the human condition, he
insisted that human beings become moral by willing to be so. According to Mencius, willing entails
the transformative moral act insofar as the propensity of humans to be good is activated whenever
they decide to bring it to their conscious attention.
Mencius taught that all people have the spiritual resources to deepen their self-awareness and
strengthen their bonds with others. Biologic and environmental constraints notwithstanding, people
always have the freedom and the ability to refine and enlarge their heaven-endowed nobility (their
“great body”). The possibility of continuously refining and enlarging the self is vividly illustrated
in Mencius’s description of degrees of excellence:
Those who are admirable are called good (shan). Those who are sincere are called true (xin). Those who are
totally genuine are called beautiful (mei). Those who radiate this genuineness are called great (da). Those
whose greatness transforms are called sagely (sheng). Those whose sageliness is unfathomable are called
spiritual (shen). (VIIB:25)
Furthermore, Mencius asserted that if people fully realize the potential of their hearts, they will
understand their nature; by understanding their nature, they will know heaven. Learning to be fully
human, in this Mencian perspective, entails the cultivation of human sensitivity to embody the
whole cosmos as one’s lived experience:
All myriad things are here in me. There is no greater joy for me than to find, on self-examination, that I am true
to myself. Try your best to treat others as you would wish to be treated yourself, and you will find that this is the
shortest way to humanity. (VIIA:4)
The metaphysical vision, expressed in the Yijing (“Classic of Changes”), combines divinatory art
with numerological technique and ethical insight. According to the philosophy of change, the
cosmos is a great transformation occasioned by the constant interaction of yin and yang, the two
complementary as well as conflicting life forces (qi). The world, which emerges out of that ongoing
transformation, exhibits both organismic unity and dynamism. The exemplary person, inspired by
the harmony and creativity of the cosmos, must emulate that pattern by aiming to realize the
highest ideal of “unity of man and heaven” (tianrenheyi) through ceaseless self-exertion.
The political vision, contained in the Shujing, presents kingship in terms of the ethical foundation
for a humane government. The legendary Three Emperors (Yao, Shun, and Yu) all ruled by virtue.
Their sagacity, xiao (filial piety), and dedication to work enabled them to create a political
culturebased on responsibility and trust. Their exemplary lives taught and encouraged the people to
enter into a covenant with them so that social harmony could be achieved without punishment or
coercion. Even in the Three Dynasties (Xia, Shang, and Zhou) moral authority, as expressed
through ritual, was sufficient to maintain political order. The human continuum, from the
undifferentiated masses to the enlightened people, the nobility, and the sage-king, formed an
organic unity as an integral part of the great cosmic transformation. Politics means moral
persuasion, and the purpose of the government is not only to provide food and maintain order but
also to educate.
The poetic vision, contained in the Shijing, underscores the Confucian valuation of common human
feelings. The majority of verses give voice to emotions and sentiments of communities and persons
from all levels of society expressed on a variety of occasions. The basic theme of that poetic world
is mutual responsiveness. The tone as a whole is honest rather than earnest and evocative rather
than expressive.
The social vision, contained in the Liji, shows society not as an adversarial system based on
contractual relationships but as a community of trust with emphasis on communication. Society
organized by the four functional occupations—the scholar, the farmer, the artisan, and the
merchant—is, in the true sense of the word, a cooperation. As a contributing member of the
cooperation, each person is obligated to recognize the existence of others and to serve the public
good. It is the king’s duty to act kingly and the father’s duty to act fatherly. If kings or fathers fail
to behave properly, they cannot expect their ministers or children to act in accordance with ritual. It
is in that sense that a chapter in the Liji entitled the “Great Learning” (Daxue) specifies, “From the
son of heaven to the commoner, all must regard self-cultivation as the root.”
That pervasive consciousness of duty features prominently in all Confucian literature on ritual.
The historical vision, presented in the Chunqiu (“Spring and Autumn [Annals]”), emphasizes the
significance of collective memory for communal self-identification. Historical consciousness is a
defining characteristic of Confucian thought. By defining himself as a lover of antiquity and a
transmitter of its values, Confucius made it explicit that a sense of history is not only desirable but
necessary for self-knowledge. Confucius’s emphasis on the importance of history was in a way his
reappropriation of the ancient Sinitic wisdom that reanimating the old is the best way to attain the
new. Confucius may not have been the author of the Chunqiu, but it seems likely that he applied
moral judgment to political events in China proper from the 8th to the 5th century BCE. In that
unprecedented procedure he assumed a godlike role in evaluating politics by assigning ultimate
historical praise and blame to the most powerful and influential political actors of the period. Not
only did that practice inspire the innovative style of the grand historian Sima Qian (c. 145–
c. 87 BCE), but it was also widely employed by others writing dynastic histories in imperial China.
Dong Zhongshu: The Confucian visionary
Like Sima Qian, Dong Zhongshu (c. 179–c. 104 BCE) took the Chunqiuabsolutely seriously. His
own work, Chunqiu fanlu (“Luxuriant Dew of the Spring and Autumn Annals”), however, is far
from being a book of historical judgment. It is a metaphysical treatise in the spirit of the Yijing. A
man extraordinarily dedicated to learning (he is said to have been so absorbed in his studies that for
three years he did not even glance at the garden in front of him) and strongly committed to
moral idealism (one of his often-quoted dicta is “rectifying rightness without scheming for
profit; enlightening his Way without calculating efficaciousness”), Dong was instrumental in
developing a characteristically Han interpretation of Confucianism.
Despite Wudi’s pronouncement that Confucianism alone would receive imperial sponsorship,
Daoists, yinyang cosmologists, Legalists, shamanists, practitioners of seances, healers, magicians,
geomancers, and others all contributed to the cosmological thinking of the Han cultural elite.
Indeed, Dong himself was a beneficiary of that intellectual syncretism, for he freely tapped the
spiritual resources of his time in formulating his own worldview: that human actions have cosmic
consequences.
Dong’s inquiries on the meaning of the wuxing, or five phases (metal, wood, water, fire, and earth),
the correspondence of human beings and the numerical categories of heaven, and the sympathetic
activation of things of the same kind, as well as his studies of cardinal Confucian values such as
humanity, rightness, ritual, wisdom, and trustworthiness, enabled him to develop an elaborate
worldview integrating Confucian ethics with naturalistic cosmology. What Dong accomplished was
not merely a theological justification for the emperor as the “son of heaven” (tianzi); rather, his
theory of mutual responsiveness between heaven and humanity provided the Confucian scholars
with a higher law by which to judge the conduct of the ruler.
Despite Dong’s immense popularity, his worldview was not universally accepted by Han
Confucian scholars. A reaction in favour of a more rational and moralistic approach to the
Confucian Classics, known as the Old Text school, had already set in before the fall of the Western
Han. Yang Xiong (c.53 BCE–18 CE) in the Fayan (“Model Sayings”), a collection of
moralistic aphorisms in the style of the Analects, and the Taixuan jing (“Classic of the Supremely
Profound Principle”), a cosmological speculation in the style of the Yijing, presented
an alternative worldview. That school, claiming its own recensions of authentic classical texts
allegedly rediscovered during the Han period and written in an “old” script before the Qin
unification, was widely accepted in the Eastern Han (25–220 CE). As the institutions of
the Erudites and the Imperial University expanded in the Eastern Han, the study of the Classics
became more refined and elaborate. Confucian scholasticism, however, like its counterparts
in Talmudic and biblicalstudies, became too professionalized to remain a vital intellectual force.
Yet Confucian ethics exerted great influence on government, schools, and society at large. Toward
the end of the Han as many as 30,000 students attended the Imperial University. All public schools
throughout the land offered regular sacrifices to Confucius, and he virtually became the patron
saint of education. Many Confucian temples were also built. The imperial courts continued to
honour Confucius from age to age; a Confucian temple eventually stood in every one of the 2,000
counties. As a result, the teacher—together with heaven, earth, the emperor, and parents—became
one of the most-respected authorities in traditional China.
Confucian ethics in the Daoist and Buddhist context
Incompetent rulership, faction-ridden bureaucracy, a mismanaged tax structure, and domination
by eunuchs toward the end of the Eastern Han first prompted widespread protests by the Imperial
University students. The high-handed policy of the court to imprison and kill thousands of them
and their official sympathizers in 169 CE may have put a temporary stop to the intellectual revolt,
but the downward economic spiral made the life of the peasantry unbearable. The peasant rebellion
led by Confucian scholars as well as Daoist religious leaders of faith-healing groups, combined
with open insurrections of the military, brought down the Han dynasty and thus put an end to the
first Chinese empire. As the imperial Han system disintegrated, barbarians invaded from the north.
The plains of northern China were fought over, despoiled, and controlled by rival groups, and a
succession of states were established in the south. That period of disunity, from the early 3rd to the
late 6th century, marked the decline of Confucianism, the upsurge of xuanxue (“Obscure
Learning”; sometimes called neo-Daoism), and the spread of Buddhism.
The prominence of Daoism and Buddhism among the cultural elite and the populace in general,
however, did not mean that the Confucian tradition had disappeared. In fact, Confucian ethics was
by then virtually inseparable from the moral fabric of Chinese society. Confucius continued to be
universally honoured as the paradigmatic sage. The outstanding Daoist thinker Wang Bi (226–249)
argued that Confucius, by not speculating on the nature of the dao, had an experiential
understanding of it superior to Laozi’s. The Confucian Classics remained the foundation of all
literate culture, and sophisticated commentaries were produced throughout the age. Confucian
values continued to dominate in such political institutions as the central bureaucracy, the
recruitment of officials, and local governance. The political forms of life also were distinctively
Confucian. When a barbarian state adopted a sinicization policy, notably the case of the Northern
Wei (386–534/535), it was by and large Confucian in character. In the south systematic attempts
were made to strengthen family ties by establishing clan rules, genealogical trees, and ancestral
rituals based on Confucian ethics.
The reunification of China by the Sui (581–618) and the restoration of lasting peace and prosperity
by the Tang (618–907) gave a powerful stimulus to the revival of Confucian learning. The
publication of a definitive official edition of the Wujing with elaborate commentaries and
subcommentaries and the implementation of Confucian rituals at all levels of governmental
practice, including the compilation of the famous Tang legal code, were two outstanding examples
of Confucianism in practice. An examination system based on literary competence was established.
That system made the mastery of Confucian Classics a prerequisite for political success and was
therefore perhaps the single-most-important institutional innovation in defining elite culture in
Confucian terms.
The Tang dynasty, nevertheless, was dominated by Buddhism and, to a lesser degree, by Daoism.
The philosophical originality of the dynasty was mainly represented by monk-scholars such as
Jizang (549–623), Xuanzang(602–664), and Zhiyi (538–597). An unintended consequence in the
development of Confucian thought in that context was the prominent rise of the metaphysically
significant Confucian texts, notably Zhongyong(“Doctrine of the Mean”) and Yizhuan (“The Great
Commentary of the Classic of Changes”), which appealed to some Buddhist and Daoist thinkers. A
sign of a possible Confucian turn in the Tang was Li Ao’s (died c.844) essay “Returning to Nature”
that foreshadowed features of Song (960–1279) Confucian thought. The most-
influential precursor of a Confucian revival, however, was Han Yu (768–824). He attacked
Buddhism from the perspectives of social ethics and cultural identity and provoked interest in the
question of what actually constitutes the Confucian Way. The issue of Daotong, the transmission of
the Way or the authentic method to repossess the Way, has stimulated much discussion in the
Confucian tradition since the 11th century.
Confucianism
Which of the following neo-Confucian figures was associated with a movement called “Learning of the Mind-
and-Heart” ( xinxue )?
The Song dynasty (960–1279) was militarily weak and much smaller than the Tang, but its cultural
splendour and economic prosperity were unprecedented in Chinese, if not human, history. The
Song’s commercial revolution produced flourishing markets, densely populated urban centres,
elaborate communication networks, theatrical performances, literary groups, and popular
religions—developments that tended to remain unchanged into the 19th century. Technological
advances in agriculture, textiles, lacquer, porcelain, printing, maritime trade, and weaponry
demonstrated that China excelled in the fine arts as well as in the sciences. The decline of
the aristocracy, the widespread availability of printed books, the democratization of education, and
the full implementation of the examination system produced a new social class, the gentry, noted
for its literary proficiency, social consciousness, and political participation. The outstanding
members of that class—such as the classicists Hu Yuan (993–1059) and Sun Fu (992–1057), the
reformers Fan Zhongyan (989–1052) and Wang Anshi (1021–86), the writer-officials Ouyang
Xiu (1007–72) and Su Shi(pen name of Su Dongpo; 1037–1101), and the statesman-historian Sima
Guang (1019–86)—contributed to the revival of Confucianism in education, politics, literature, and
history and collectively to the development of a scholarly official style, a way of life informed by
Confucian ethics.
The Confucian revival, understood in traditional historiography as the establishment of the lineage
of Daoxue (“Learning of the Way”), nevertheless can be traced through a line of neo-Confucian
thinkers from Zhou Dunyi (1017–73) by way of Shao Yong (1011–77), Zhang Zai (1020–77), the
brothers Cheng Hao (1032–85) and Cheng Yi (1033–1107), and the great synthesizer Zhu
Xi (1130–1200). These men developed a comprehensivehumanist vision in which cultivation of the
self was integrated with social ethics and moral metaphysics. In the eyes of the Song literati, this
new philosophy faithfully restored the classical Confucian insights and successfully applied them to
the concerns of their own age.
Zhou Dunyi ingeniously articulated the relationship between the “great transformation” of the
cosmos and the moral development of human beings. In his metaphysics, humanity, as the recipient
of the highest excellence from heaven, is itself a centre of cosmic creativity. He developed this all-
embracing humanism by a thought-provoking interpretation of the Daoist diagram of taiji (“Great
Ultimate”). Shao Yong elaborated on the metaphysical basis of human affairs, insisting that a
disinterested numerological mode of analysis is most appropriate for understanding the “supreme
principles governing the world.” Zhang Zai, on the other hand, focused on the omnipresence of qi,
which is often taken to be the fundamental enlivening force of the universe but to Zhang was also
the constituent material force of everything in the universe. Zhang also advocated the oneness
of li (“principle”; comparable to the idea of natural law) and the multiplicity of its manifestations,
which is created as the principle expresses itself through qi. As an article of faith he pronounced in
the “Western Inscription”:
Heaven is my father and Earth is my mother, and even such a small being as I finds a central abode in their
midst. Therefore that which fills the cosmos I regard as my body and that which directs the cosmos I consider
as my nature. All people are my brothers and sisters, and all things are my companions.
This theme of mutuality between heaven and human beings, consanguinity between one human
being and another, and harmony between humanity and nature was brought to fruition in Cheng
Hao’s definition of humanity as “forming one body with all things.” To him the presence
of tianli (“heavenly principle”) in all things as well as in human nature enables the human mind to
purify itself in a spirit of reverence. Cheng Yi, following his brother’s lead, formulated the famous
dictum, “Self-cultivation requires reverence; the extension of knowledge consists in the
investigation of things.” By making special reference to gewu(“investigation of things”), he raised
doubts about the appropriateness of focusing exclusively on the illumination of the mind in self-
cultivation, as his brother seems to have done. The learning of the mind as advocated by Cheng
Hao and the learning of the principle as advocated by Cheng Yi became two distinct modes of
thought in Song Confucianism.
Zhu Xi, clearly following Cheng Yi’s School of Principle and implicitly rejecting Cheng
Hao’s School of Mind, developed a method of interpreting and transmitting the Confucian Way
that for centuries defined Confucianism not only for the Chinese but for the Koreans and Japanese
as well. If, as quite a few scholars have advocated, Confucianism represents a distinct form of East
Asian spirituality, it is the Confucianism shaped by Zhu Xi. Zhu Xi virtually reconstituted the
Confucian tradition, giving it new structure, new texture, and new meaning. He was more than a
synthesizer; through conscientious appropriation and systematic interpretation, he gave rise to a
new Confucianism, known as neo-Confucianism in the West but often referred to
as lixue (“Learning of the Principle”) in modern China.
Zhu Xi, ink on paper, by an unknown artist; in the National Palace Museum, Taipei.Courtesy of the National Palace Museum, Taiwan,
Republic of China
The Zhongyong and the Daxue, two chapters in the Liji, had become independent treatises and,
together with the Analects and Mencius, had been included in the core curriculum of Confucian
education for centuries before Zhu Xi’s birth. But by putting them into a particular sequence—
the Daxue, the Analects, Mencius, and the Zhongyong—synthesizing their commentaries,
interpreting them as a coherent humanistic vision, and calling them the Four Books (Sishu), Zhu Xi
fundamentally restructured the Confucian scriptural tradition. The Four Books, placed above
the Five Classics, became the central texts for both primary education and civil
service examinations in traditional China from the 14th century. Thus, they have exerted far greater
influence on Chinese life and thought in the past 600 years than any other work.
As an interpreter and transmitter of the Confucian Way, Zhu Xi identified which early Song
masters belonged to the lineage of Confucius and Mencius. His judgment, later widely accepted by
governments in East Asia, was based principally on philosophical insight. Zhou Dunyi, Zhang Zai,
and the Cheng brothers, the select four, were Zhu Xi’s cultural heroes. Shao Yong and Sima Guang
were originally on his list, but Zhu Xi apparently changed his mind, perhaps because of Shao’s
excessive metaphysical speculation and Sima’s obsession with historical facts.
Up until Zhu Xi’s time the Confucian thinking of the Song masters was characterized by a few
fruitfully ambiguous concepts, notably the Great Ultimate (taiji), principle, vital energy, nature,
mind, and humanity. Zhu Xi defined the process of the investigation of things as a
rigorous discipline of the mind to probe the principle in things. He recommended a twofold method
of study: to cultivate a sense of reverence and to pursue knowledge. This combination
of morality and wisdom made his pedagogyan inclusive approach to humanist education. Reading,
sitting quietly, ritualpractice, physical exercise, calligraphy, arithmetic, and empiricalobservation
all had a place in his pedagogical program. Zhu Xi reestablished the White Deer Grotto in present
Jiangxi province as an academy. It became the intellectual centre of his age and provided an
instructional model for all schools in East Asia for generations to come.
Zhu Xi was considered the preeminent Confucian scholar in Song China, but his interpretation of
the Confucian Way was seriously challenged by his contemporary Lu Jiuyuan (Lu Xiangshan,
1139–93). Claiming that he appropriated the true wisdom of Confucian teaching by reading
Mencius, Lu criticized Zhu Xi’s theory of the investigation of things as fragmented and
ineffective empiricism. Instead, he advocated a return to Mencian moral idealism by insisting that
establishing the “great body” (i.e., heaven-endowed nobility) is the primary precondition for self-
realization. To him the learning of the mind as a quest for self-knowledge provided the basis upon
which the investigation of things assumed its proper significance. Lu’s confrontation with Zhu Xi
in the famous meeting at the Goose Lake Temple in 1175 further convinced him that Confucianism
as Zhu Xi had shaped it was not Mencian. Although Lu’s challenge remained a minority position
for some time, his learning of the mind later became a major intellectual force in Ming China
(1368–1644) and Tokugawa Japan (1603–1867).
China: Confucianism
Confucianism was perceived by the Mongols as a Chinese religion, and it had mixed fortunes under their rule. The
teachings of the Neo-Confucian school of Zhu Xi from the Song period were introduced to the Mongol court at
Zhongdu in the late 1230s but…
Nakae Tōju
JAPANESE SCHOLAR
Nakae Tōju
JAPANESE SCHOLAR
WRITTEN BY:
The Editors of Encyclopaedia Britannica
See Article History
Alternative Titles: Mokken, Nakae Gen
Nakae Tōju, original personal name Gen, pseudonym Mokken, (born April 21, 1608, Ōmi
province [modern Shiga prefecture], Japan—died Oct. 11, 1648, Ōmi province), neo-
Confucian scholar who established in Japan the idealist thought of the Chinese
philosopher Wang Yangming.
Nakae was originally a follower of the teachings of the Chinese neo-Confucian
Rationalist Zhu Xi, whose doctrines had become a part of the official ideology of the
Japanese government. In 1634 he asked to be released from the post he held as retainer
to his feudal lord so he could return to his native village and carry out his filial obligations
to his widowed mother. He left despite his lord’s refusal of permission. At home he
devoted himself to teaching and study, eventually abandoning his adherence to the Zhu Xi
school of thought and becoming a propagator of the philosophy of Wang Yangming. His
fame subsequently spread throughout the land. He attracted many
distinguished disciples and became known as the sage of Ōmi province.
Both Wang and Nakae believed that the unifying principle of the universe exists in the
human mind and not in the external world. They taught that the true Way could be
discovered through intuition and self-reflection, rejecting Zhu Xi’s idea that it could be
found through empirical investigation. In his conviction that a concept can be fully
understood only when acted upon, Nakae emphasized practice rather than abstract
learning. This emphasis on individual action made Nakae’s philosophy popular among
the zealous Japanese reformers and patriots of the 19th and 20th centuries. Tōju sensei
zenshū (“The Complete Works of Master Tōju”) was first published in five volumes in
1940.
This article was most recently revised and updated by Matt Stefon, Assistant Editor.
LEARN MORE in these related Britannica articles:
Japan: The Tokugawa status system
Nakae Tōju, often regarded as the father of Japanese Wang Yang-ming studies, was so earnest in
performing virtuous acts that he was called the sage of Ōmi. One of his followers, Kumazawa Banzan,
who criticized the growing autocracy in the politics of his day, transformed…
Zhu Xi
Zhu Xi, Chinese philosopher whose synthesis of neo-Confucian thought long dominated Chinese
intellectual life.…
Wang Yangming
Wang Yangming, Chinese scholar-official whose idealistic interpretation of neo-Confucianism influenced
philosophical thinking in East Asia for centuries. Though his career in government was rather unstable,…
Nakae Tōju
QUICK FACTS
BORN
Wang Chong
CHINESE PHILOSOPHER
ARTICLE
INFOPRINTCITE
FEEDBACK
FEEDBACK
Corrections? Updates? Omissions? Let us know if you have suggestions to improve this article (requires
login).
Select a type (Required)
Select feedback type:
SUBMIT FEEDBACK
SHARE
SHARE
Wang Chong
CHINESE PHILOSOPHER
WRITTEN BY:
The Editors of Encyclopaedia Britannica
See Article History
Alternative Title: Wang Ch’ung
Wang Chong, Wade-Giles romanization Wang Ch’ung, (born 27 CE, Kueiji, China—died
100?, Kueiji), one of the most original and independent Chinese thinkers of the Han period
(206 BCE–220 CE).
A rationalistic naturalist during an age of superstition, Wang dared attack the belief in
omens and portents that had begun to creep into the Confucian doctrines. He helped pave
the way for the critical spirit of the next philosophical period and prepared China for the
advent of neo-Daoism. Born into a poor family and orphaned at an early age, Wang did
much of his reading in a bookstore. He held a few minor government positions, but during
much of his life he taught in his hometown.
Accepting the original doctrines of Confucius, Wang opposed the contemporary,
“debased” Confucianism. Dismissing teleology, he declared that natural things occurred
spontaneously. Further, Wang rejected the notion that natural disasters were a response
by heaven (tian) to human immorality, especially that of the ruler, the “son of heaven”
(tianzi). A bad king, in other words, would not necessarily produce bad weather. He stated
that human beings, though noble and intelligent, had no exceptional position in the
cosmos. A rationalist, he insisted upon the necessity of supporting any theory with
concrete evidence and experimental proof.
Wang has never been greatly popular in China, though in the 20th century the prevailing
critical spirit, scientific method, and revolt against the past attracted new attention to his
ideas. His outstanding work, the trenchant and critical Lunheng (“Disquisitions”), written
about 85 CE, was translated into English by Alfred Forke (2 vol., 1907–11).
Get unlimited access to all of Britannica’s trusted content.Start Your Free Trial Today
This article was most recently revised and updated by Matt Stefon, Assistant Editor.
Religion
Religion, human beings’ relation to that which they regard as holy, sacred, absolute, spiritual, divine, or
worthy of especial reverence. It is also commonly regarded as consisting of the way people deal with
ultimate concerns about their lives and their fate after death. In many traditions, this…
Naturalism
Naturalism, in philosophy, a theory that relates scientific method to philosophy by affirming that all beings
and events in the universe (whatever their inherent character may be) are natural. Consequently, all
knowledge of the universe falls within the pale of scientific investigation. Although…
Wang Chong
QUICK FACTS
BORN
27
Kueiji, China
DIED
100?
Kueiji, China
SUBJECTS OF STUDY
Confucianism
rationalism
naturalism
Ōyōmeigaku
JAPANESE PHILOSOPHY
Ōyōmeigaku
JAPANESE PHILOSOPHY
See Article History
THIS ARTICLE IS A STUB. You can learn more about this topic in the related articles below.
Alternative Title: Wang Yang-ming studies
Neo-Confucianism
Neo-Confucianism, in Japan, the official guiding philosophy of the Tokugawa period (1603–1867). This
philosophy profoundly influenced the thought and behaviour of the educated class. The tradition,
introduced into Japan from China by Zen Buddhists in the medieval period, provided a heavenly sanction
for the existing social order. In the Neo-Confucian…
Japan: The Tokugawa status system
Wang Yang-ming studies (Ōyōmeigaku in Japanese) were characterized by a strong subjective idealism
but, at the same time, were quite practical since they emphasized the unity of thought and deed. Virtue
had to be not only cultivated in the abstract but practiced as well. Nakae Tōju, often regarded…
SIMILAR TOPICS
Kogaku
Shushigaku
Hayashi Razan
JAPANESE SCHOLAR
Hayashi Razan
JAPANESE SCHOLAR
WRITTEN BY:
The Editors of Encyclopaedia Britannica
LAST UPDATED: Jul 28, 2019 See Article History
Alternative Titles: Dōshun, Hayashi Nobukatsu
Zhu Xi
Zhu Xi, Chinese philosopher whose synthesis of neo-Confucian thought long dominated Chinese
intellectual life.…
Japanese philosophy
Japanese philosophy, intellectual discourse developed by Japanese thinkers, scholars, and political and
religious leaders who creatively combined indigenous philosophical and religious traditions with key
concepts adopted and assimilated from nonnative traditions—first from greater East Asia and…
Hayashi Razan
QUICK FACTS
BORN
August 1583
Kyōto, Japan
DIED
Yan Yuan
CHINESE PHILOSOPHER
Yan Yuan
CHINESE PHILOSOPHER
WRITTEN BY:
The Editors of Encyclopaedia Britannica
See Article History
Alternative Titles: Yan Xijai, Yen Yüan
Yan Yuan, Wade-Giles romanization Yen Yüan, literary name Yan Xijai, (born April 27,
1635, Zhili[now Hubei] province, China—died Sept. 30, 1704, Zhili province), Chinese
founder of a pragmatic empirical school of Confucianism opposed to the speculative neo-
Confucian philosophy that had dominated China since the 11th century.
Yan’s father was abducted into the Manchu army when Yan was three. He never returned,
and the family lived in poverty. As a young man, Yan became interested in Confucianism
and studied to pass his civil-service examinations, which would have given him entrance
into the bureaucracy. But after failing the examination several times he decided to devote
himself to teaching.
His revolt against neo-Confucian metaphysics stemmed initially from his aversion to the
newly established Manchu rule of the Qing dynasty (1644–1911/12). He believed that the
Manchu conquest was made possible by faulty government and education, which had
rendered China easy prey to alien conquerors. He urged that people return to the study of
the ancient Confucian Classics instead of the neo-Confucian interpretations of them. He
advocated implementation of the ancient “well-field” plan of the Confucian sage Mencius,
in which eight families lived on a patch of land that was equally divided into nine squares.
Each family would cultivate its own piece of land, and all eight families would jointly
cultivate the remaining central square for the government. Yan felt that this system, by
providing for an equal distribution of the land, would ensure a livelihood for all. Similarly he
urged a revival of compulsory military service to make each citizen a competent defender
of his country. He believed that useful knowledge and education come only from practical
experience: as long as scholars buried themselves in books and in abstruse discourse,
shunning physical activity and despising soldiery, China would continue to be weak.
Yan put his educational theory into practice when he became director of the Zhangnan
Academy in 1696. His curriculum included mathematics, geography, military tactics and
strategy, archery, and wrestling, in addition to history and the Confucian Classics. Yan’s
writings, together with those of his most eminent student, Li Gong (1659–1733), became
the major works of a new philosophical movement known as the Yan-Li school. A short-
lived society to study and disseminate its doctrines was formed in 1920 in Beijing. Yan’s
major works were reprinted in the late 19th century as the Yan-Li yishu (“Works of Yan
and Li”).
Get unlimited access to all of Britannica’s trusted content.Start Your Free Trial Today
This article was most recently revised and updated by Matt Stefon, Assistant Editor.
LEARN MORE in these related Britannica articles:
Confucianism
Confucianism, the way of life propagated by Confucius in the 6th–5th century bce and followed by the
Chinese people for more than two millennia. Although transformed over time, it is still the substance of
learning, the source of values, and the social code of the Chinese. Its influence has also…
well-field system
Well-field system, the communal land organization supposedly in effect throughout China early in the
Zhou dynasty (c. 1046–256 bce). The well-field system was first mentioned in the literature of the late
Zhou dynasty (c. 4th century bce), especially in the writings of the…
Chinese philosophy
Chinese philosophy, the thought of Chinese culture, from earliest times to the present. The keynote in
Chinese philosophy is humanism: man and his society have occupied, if not monopolized, the attention of
Chinese philosophers throughout the ages. Ethical and political discussions have…
Yan Yuan
QUICK FACTS
BORN
Shushigaku
JAPANESE PHILOSOPHY
Shushigaku
JAPANESE PHILOSOPHY
.
Shushigaku, (Japanese: “Chu Hsi school”), most influential of the Neo-Confucian schools
that developed in Japan during the Tokugawa period (1603–1867). See Neo-
Confucianism
Neo-Confucianism
Neo-Confucianism, in Japan, the official guiding philosophy of the Tokugawa period (1603–1867). This
philosophy profoundly influenced the thought and behaviour of the educated class. The tradition,
introduced into Japan from China by Zen Buddhists in the medieval period, provided a heavenly sanction
for the existing social order. In the Neo-Confucian…
Japan: The Tokugawa status system
…dynasty Chu Hsi school (Shushigaku)—which had been well-known to political and ethical thinkers
since the 13th century—provided an intellectual rationalization for the status-oriented social structure of
the bakuhan system. Shushigaku appealed especially to the feudal rulers because, among the various
schools of Confucianism, it was the most systematic doctrine.…
Kogaku
Ōyōmeigaku
Mohism
CHINESE PHILOSOPHY
Mohism
CHINESE PHILOSOPHY
Mohism, also spelled Moism, school of Chinese philosophy founded by Mozi (q.v.) in the
5th century BCE. This philosophy challenged the dominant Confucian ideology until about
the 3rd century BCE. Mozi taught the necessity for individual piety and submission to the
will of heaven, or Shangdi (the Lord on High), and deplored the Confucian emphasis on
rites and ceremonies as a waste of government funds.
In contrast to the Confucian moral ideal of ren (“humanity” or “benevolence”),
which differentiated the special love for one’s parents and family from the general love
shown to fellow men, the Mohists advocated the practice of love without distinctions
(jianai). The Confucians, in particular Mencius, bitterly attacked the Mohist concept of
undifferentiated love because it challenged the basis of Confucian family harmony, which
was in fact and theory the foundation for the social harmony of the Confucian state.
This article was most recently revised and updated by Matt Stefon, Assistant Editor.
LEARN MORE in these related Britannica articles:
Mozi
…a socioreligious movement known as Mohism.…
Confucianism
Confucianism, the way of life propagated by Confucius in the 6th–5th century bce and followed by the
Chinese people for more than two millennia. Although transformed over time, it is still the substance of
learning, the source of values, and the social code of the Chinese. Its influence has also…
ren
Ren, (Chinese: “humanity,” “humaneness,” “goodness,” “benevolence,” or “love”) the foundational virtue of
Confucianism. It characterizes the bearing and behaviour that a paradigmatic human being exhibits in
order to promote a flourishing human community.…
Mohism
Zisi
CHINESE PHILOSOPHER
Zisi
CHINESE PHILOSOPHER
WRITTEN BY:
Matt Stefon
See Article History
Alternative Titles: K’ung Chi, Kong Ji, Tzu Ssu, Zi Si
Zisi, Wade-Giles romanization Tzu Ssu, also called Kong Ji, (born 483—died 402 BCE),
Chinese philosopher and grandson of Confucius (551–479 BCE). Varying traditional
accounts state that Zisi, who studied under Confucius’s pupil Zengzi, taught
either Mencius (Mengzi)—the “second sage” of Confucianism—or Mencius’s teacher.
Texts dating to about the 2nd and the 4th centuries BCE, discovered at archaeological
sites in Mawangdui (1973) and Guodian (1993), respectively, suggest evidence for a
“school of Zisi.”
According to tradition, Zisi composed the Zhongyong, which was incorporated as a
chapter of the Liji (“Record of Rites”) during the Han dynasty (206 BCE–220 CE). The
great Song dynasty(960–1279) neo-Confucian philosopher Zhu Xi (1130–1200) later
included the Zhongyong among the Four Books, the texts foundational to the orthodox
Confucian Way. The Zhongyong, which draws its title from words that individually denote
“equilibrium” (zhong) and the “common” or “practical” (yong), illumines the proper way
(dao) for exemplary persons (junzi) to act in the world.
Zisi is also credited with developing the theory of wuxing, the five modes (xing)
of moral action through which exemplary persons comport themselves.
The Wuxingpian (“Five Modes of Proper Conduct”), a previously lost document found
during the Mawangdui and Guodian excavations and attributed by many scholars to Zisi’s
school, presents these modes as benevolence (ren), righteousness (yi), ritual propriety (li),
wisdom (zhi), and sagacity (sheng). Mencius adapted the first four as the “four sprouts”
(siduan) of virtue in the human heart-and-mind. Wuxing theory gained popularity and
influence after the alchemist Zou Yan (340–260? BCE), perhaps independently of Zisi’s
school, developed the theory as the Five Phases of cosmic generation and transformation:
wood (mu), fire (huo), earth (tu), metal (jin), and water (shui). The neo-Confucian
philosopher Zhou Dunyi (1017–73) reconnected this cosmological scheme to a moral
vision when he associated the Five Phases with five virtues: the first four of the virtues
recognized by Zisi and Mencius, together with fidelity (xin).
Matt Stefon
Zhongyong
…Five Classics of antiquity) to Zisi (Kong Ji), a grandson of Confucius.…
s
Confucius
Confucius, China’s most famous teacher, philosopher, and political theorist, whose ideas have influenced
the civilization of East Asia. Confucius’s life, in contrast…
Zengzi
Zengzi, Chinese philosopher, disciple of Confucius, traditionally believed to be the author of
the Daxue (“Great Learning”). In this classic, which became a part of the Liji (“Collection of Rituals”) and
one of the Four Books during the Song dynasty, he…
Zisi
QUICK FACTS
BORN
483 BCE
DIED
402 BCE
NOTABLE WORKS
“Zhongyong”
SUBJECTS OF STUDY
Confucianism
wuxing
Han Yu
CHINESE AUTHOR
Han Yu, Wade-Giles romanization Han Yü, also called Han Changli or Han
Wengong, courtesy name (zi) Tuizhi, (born 768, Heyang [now
Mengxian], Henan province, China—died 824, Chang’an [now Xi’an], Shaanxi province),
master of Chinese prose, outstanding poet, and the first proponent of what later came to
be known as Neo-Confucianism, which had wide influence in China and Japan.
An orphan, Han initially failed his civil service exams because the examiners refused to
accept his unconventional prose style, but he eventually entered the bureaucracy and
served in several high government posts. At a time when the popularity of Confucian
doctrine had greatly declined, Han began a defense of it. He attacked Daoism and
Buddhism, which were then at the height of their influence. So outspoken was he that
he castigated the emperor for paying respect to the supposed finger bone of the Buddha;
this act of criticism almost cost Han his life and caused him to be banished to South China
for a year. In defending Confucianism, Han quoted extensively from the Mencius,
the Daxue (“Great Learning”), the Zhongyong (“Doctrine of the Mean”), and
the Yijing (“Classic of Changes”; known to many as I-Ching), works that hitherto had been
somewhat neglected by Confucians. In so doing, he laid the foundations for later Neo-
Confucianists who took their basic ideas from these books.
Han advocated the adoption of guwen, the free, simple prose of these early philosophers,
a style unencumbered by the mannerisms and elaborate verselike regularity of
the pianwen(“parallel prose”) style that was prevalent in Han’s time. His own essays (e.g.,
“On the Way,” “On Man,” and “On Spirits”) are among the most beautiful ever written in
Chinese, and they became the most famous models of the prose style he espoused. In
his poetry also, Han tried to break out of the existing literary forms, but many of his efforts
at literary reform failed. He is considered the first of the renowned “Eight Masters of the
Tang and Song.” At his death the title of president of the ministry of rites was conferred
upon him, as well as the epithet “Master of Letters,” both great honours.
LEARN MORE in these related Britannica articles:
Han Yu
QUICK FACTS
BORN
768
Hechuan, China
DIED
Li Ao
CHINESE SCHOLAR
Li Ao
CHINESE SCHOLAR
WRITTEN BY:
The Editors of Encyclopaedia Britannica
See Article History
Li Ao, Wade-Giles romanization Li Ao, (born 772, Longxi [now in Gansu province],
China—died 841, China), Chinese scholar, poet, and official who helped
reestablish Confucianism at a time when it was being severely challenged
by Buddhism and Daoism. Li helped lay the groundwork for the later Neo-Confucianists of
the Song dynasty (960–1279), who systematically reformulated Confucian doctrine.
Although Li was a high official of the Tang dynasty (618–907), little is known of his
personal life. He was apparently friends with or a disciple of the great Confucian stylist
and thinker Han Yu, with whom he is usually linked. Unlike Han, however, who was
vehemently opposed to Buddhism, Li was much influenced by it, helping to integrate many
Buddhist ideas into Confucianism and beginning the development of
a metaphysical framework to justify Confucian ethical thinking. Li is especially known for
his insistence that the questions of human nature and human destiny were central to
Confucianism, ideas that became the core of later Neo-Confucianism. Moreover, his
quotations from the Daxue (“Great Learning”), the Zhongyong (“Doctrine of the Mean”),
and the Yijing (“Classic of Changes”) helped bring recognition to these previously obscure
works and led to their eventual enshrinement as part of the great body of Confucian
Classics. Finally, for later Neo-Confucians, Li helped establish Mencius as almost the
equal of Confucius.
This article was most recently revised and updated by Kathleen Kuiper, Senior Editor.
LEARN MORE in these related Britannica articles
Confucianism: Confucian ethics in the Daoist and Buddhist context
…turn in the Tang was Li Ao’s (died c. 844) essay “Returning to Nature” that foreshadowed features of
Song (960–1279) Confucian thought. The most-influential precursor of a Confucian revival, however, was
Han Yu (768–824). He attacked Buddhism from the perspectives of social ethics and cultural identity and
provoked interest in…
Han Yu
Han Yu, master of Chinese prose, outstanding poet, and the first proponent of what later came to be
known as Neo-Confucianism,…
Philosophy
Philosophy, (from Greek, by way of Latin, philosophia, “love of wisdom”) the rational, abstract, and
methodical consideration of reality as a whole or of fundamental dimensions of human existence and
experience. Philosophical inquiry is a central element in the intellectual history of many…
Li Ao
QUICK FACTS
BORN
772
Longxi, China
DIED
Mencius, detail, ink and colour on silk; in the National Palace Museum, TaipeiCourtesy of the National Palace Museum, Taipei,
Taiwan, Republic of China
Non-Confucian Critiques
Ren became a distinctly Confucian virtue. As classical Chinese philosophydeveloped
during the Warring States period (475–221 BCE), the concept was criticized by thinkers
from other intellectual movements. One of the main charges was essentially that the
concept depended upon a vision of society modeled on the family and rooted in
hierarchical and even elitist relationships. Although Confucianism was far from being a
static economy of relationships in which each person knew his “place,” it did regard filial
piety (xiao) and showing respect (ti) for elders (and other people of rank) as ideal
behaviours. One of the major formulations of this critique came from the utopian and
quasi-utilitarian thinker Mozi (470?–391? BCE), who rejected what he saw as
the implicit hierarchy in ren and opted instead for “universal love” (jianai). Despite the
meaning of its name, jianai was not an overflowing of goodness or benevolence directed
toward all but rather a starkly practical approach to other human beings, all of whom were
to be treated as equals. Each person, even one’s own father or mother, was merely
another brother or sister who was worthy of respect but due no special consideration.
The philosophical and religious movement subsequently known as Daoism(daojia), whose
thinkers gradually distinguished themselves from the Confucians, launched the second
great critique of ren in the Daodejing, a philosophical and spiritual text composed about
300 BCE and traditionally attributed to the mythical sage Laozi. Confucius and Mencius
connected ren with the order of heaven (tian), offering a worldview within which humans
were more important than other creatures. By contrast, the Daodejing stated that heaven
was buren, literally “no special lover of humanity,” and in fact it compared humans to the
straw dogs that are sacrificed (in place of real dogs) and discarded once the ritual has
been completed. This did not, of course, imply misanthropy on the part of Daoists. Rather,
Daoists held that humans were only one class of things among many others. Thus, any
purported virtue that placed them above all other aspects of the world would in fact be
the antithesis of virtue.
LaoziLaozi, sculpture located north of Quanzhou, Fujian province, China.ThanatoMatt Stefon
junzi
…person whose humane conduct (ren) makes him a moral exemplar.…
Ren
QUICK FACTS
View Media Page
KEY PEOPLE
Mencius
Confucius
Xiong Shili
Zhang Zai
RELATED TOPICS
Confucianism
Contents
Bahāʾī Faith
Bahāʾī Faith
WRITTEN BY:
The Editors of Encyclopaedia Britannica
See Article History
Bahāʾī Faith, religion founded in Iran in the mid-19th century by Mīrzā Ḥosayn ʿAlī Nūrī,
who is known as Bahāʾ Allāh (Arabic: “Glory of God”). The cornerstone of Bahāʾī belief is
the conviction that Bahāʾ Allāh and his forerunner, who was known as the Bāb (Persian:
“Gateway”), were manifestations of God, who in his essence is unknowable. The principal
Bahāʾī tenets are the essential unity of all religions and the unity of humanity. Bahāʾīs
believe that all the founders of the world’s great religions have been manifestations of God
and agents of a progressive divine plan for the education of the human race. Despite their
apparent differences, the world’s great religions, according to the Bahāʾīs, teach an
identical truth. Bahāʾ Allāh’s peculiar function was to overcome the disunity of religions
and establish a universal faith. Bahāʾīs believe in the oneness of humanity and devote
themselves to the abolition of racial, class, and religious prejudices. The great bulk of
Bahāʾī teachings is concerned with social ethics; the faith has no priesthood and does not
observe ritual forms in its worship.
History
The Bahāʾī religion originally grew out of the Bābī faith, or sect, which was founded in
1844 by Mīrzā ʿAlī Moḥammad of Shīrāz in Iran. He proclaimed a spiritual doctrine
emphasizing the forthcoming appearance of a new prophet or messenger of God who
would overturn old beliefs and customs and usher in a new era. Though new, these beliefs
originated in ShīʿiteIslam, which believed in the forthcoming return of the 12th imam
(successor of Muhammad), who would renew religion and guide the faithful. Mīrzā
ʿAlī Moḥammad first proclaimed his beliefs in 1844 and assumed the title of the Bāb. Soon
the Bāb’s teachings spread throughout Iran, provoking strong opposition from both the
Shīʿite Muslim clergy and the government. The Bāb was arrested and, after several years
of incarceration, was executed in 1850. Large-scale persecutions of his adherents, the
Bābīs, followed and ultimately cost 20,000 people their lives.
One of the Bāb’s earliest disciples and strongest exponents was Mīrzā Ḥosayn ʿAlī Nūrī,
who had assumed the name Bahāʾ Allāh when he renounced his social standing and
joined the Bābīs. Bahāʾ Allāh was arrested in 1852 and jailed in Tehrān, where he
became aware that he was the prophet and messenger of God whose coming had been
predicted by the Bāb. He was released in 1853 and exiled to Baghdad, where his
leadership revived the Bābī community. In 1863, shortly before being moved by
the Ottoman government to Constantinople (now Istanbul), Bahāʾ Allāh declared to his
fellow Bābīs that he was the messenger of God foretold by the Bāb. An overwhelming
majority of Bābīs acknowledged his claim and thenceforth became known as Bahāʾīs.
Bahāʾ Allāh was subsequently confined by the Ottomans in Adrianople (now Edirne,
Turkey) and then in Acre in Palestine (now ʿAkko, Israel).
ʿAbd ol-Bahā, left, and his grandson, Shogi Effendi Rabbānī, Haifa, Israel, 1919.© Bahá'i International Community
Before Bahāʾ Allāh died in 1892, he appointed his eldest son, ʿAbd al-Bahāʾ(1844–1921),
to be the leader of the Bahāʾi community and the authorized interpreter of his teachings.
ʿAbd al-Bahāʾ actively administered the movement’s affairs and spread the faith to North
America, Europe, and other continents. He appointed his eldest grandson, Shoghi Effendi
Rabbānī (1897–1957), his successor.
Get unlimited access to all of Britannica’s trusted content.Start Your Free Trial Today
The Bahāʾi Faith underwent a rapid expansion beginning in the 1960s, and by the early
21st century it had more than 180 national spiritual assemblies (national governing
bodies) and several thousand local spiritual assemblies. After Islamic fundamentalists
came to power in Iran in 1979, the 300,000 Bahāʾīs there were persecuted by the
government.
Practices
The writings and spoken words of the Bāb, Bahāʾ Allāh, and ʿAbd al-Bahāʾ form
the sacred literature of the Bahāʾī Faith. Membership in the Bahāʾī community is open to
all who profess faith in Bahāʾ Allāh and accept his teachings. There are no initiation
ceremonies, no sacraments, and no clergy. Every Bahāʾī, however, is under the spiritual
obligation to pray daily; to abstain totally from narcotics, alcohol, or any substances that
affect the mind; to practice monogamy; to obtain the consent of parents to marriage; and
to attend the Nineteen Day Feast on the first day of each month of the Bahāʾī calendar. If
capable, those between the ages of 15 and 70 are required to fast 19 days a year, going
without food or drink from sunrise to sunset. The Nineteen Day Feast, originally instituted
by the Bāb, brings together the Bahāʾīs of a given locality for prayer, the reading
of scriptures, the discussion of community activities, and the enjoyment of one another’s
company. The feasts are designed to ensure universal participation in the affairs of the
community and the cultivation of the spirit of brotherhood and fellowship.
In the early 21st century there were nine Bahāʾī houses of worship: in Australia,
Cambodia, Chile, Germany, India, Panama, Samoa, the United States, and Uganda. In
the temples there is no preaching; services consist of recitation of the scriptures of all
religions.
The Bahāʾīs use a calendar established by the Bāb and confirmed by Bahāʾ Allāh, in
which the year is divided into 19 months of 19 days each, with the addition of 4 intercalary
days (5 in leap years). The year begins on the first day of spring, March 21, which is one
of several holy days in the Bahāʾī calendar.
Organization
The Bahāʾī community is governed according to general principles proclaimed by Bahāʾ
Allāh and through institutions created by him that were elaborated and expanded by ʿAbd
al-Bahāʾ. The governance of the Bahāʾī community begins on the local level with the
election of a local spiritual assembly. The electoral process excludes parties or factions,
nominations, and campaigning for office. The local spiritual assembly has jurisdiction over
all local affairs of the Bahāʾī community. On the national scale, each year Bahāʾīs elect
delegates to a national convention that elects a national spiritual assembly with jurisdiction
over Bahāʾī’s throughout an entire country. All national spiritual assemblies of the world
periodically constitute themselves an international convention and elect a supreme
governing body known as the Universal House of Justice. This body applies the
laws promulgated by Bahāʾ Allāh and legislates on matters not covered in the sacred
texts. The seat of the Universal House of Justice is in Haifa, Israel, in the immediate
vicinity of the shrines of the Bāb and ʿAbd al-Bahāʾ, and near the Shrine of Bahāʾ Allāh at
Bahjī near ʿAkko.
The Seat of the Universal House of Justice, Mount Carmel, Haifa, Israel.© Baha'i International Community
There also exist in the Bahāʾī Faith appointive institutions, such as the Hands of the
Cause of God and the continental counselors. The members of the Hands of the Cause of
God were appointed by Bahāʾ Allāh and Shoghi Effendi. The continental counselors are
appointed by the Universal House of Justice. The primary functions of both groups are
to propagate the Bahāʾī Faith and protect the community.
This article was most recently revised and updated by Brian Duignan.
LEARN MORE in these related Britannica articles:
India: Religions
Those practicing the Bahāʾī faith, formerly too few to be treated by the census, have dramatically
increased in number as a result of active proselytization. Zoroastrians (the Parsis), largely concentrated in
Mumbai and in coastal Gujarat, wield influence out of all proportion to their small numbers because of…
Iran: Religious minorities
Among these, members of the Bahāʾī faith—a religion founded in Iran—were the victims of the greatest
persecution. The Jewish population, which had been significant before 1979, emigrated in great numbers
after the revolution.…
Bahāʾī Faith
Long
CHINESE MYTHOLOGY
Long
CHINESE MYTHOLOGY
WRITTEN BY:
The Editors of Encyclopaedia Britannica
See Article History
Alternative Title: lung
dragon
Dragon, legendary monster usually conceived as a huge, bat-winged, fire-breathing, scaly lizard or snake
with a barbed tail. The belief in these creatures apparently arose without the slightest knowledge on the
part of the ancients of the gigantic, prehistoric, dragon-like reptiles. In Greece the word drakōn, from
which the English…
pottery: China
” The dragon generally is a mild and beneficent creature. It is a symbol of the emperor, just as the
immortal fenghuang symbolizes the empress.…
Chinese painting: Song (960–1279), Liao (907–1125), and Jin (1115–1234) dynasties
…who specialized in painting the dragon, a symbol both of the emperor and of the mysterious all-
pervading force of the Dao. Chen Rong’s paintings show these fabulous creatures emerging from amid
rocks and clouds. They were painted in a variety of strange techniques, including rubbing the ink on with
a…
Long
QUICK FACTS
RELATED TOPICS
Dragon
Fuzanglong
Dilong
Longwang
Chinese mythology
Shenlong
Tianlong
Chinese religion
Junzi
CHINESE PHILOSOPHY
Junzi
CHINESE PHILOSOPHY
WRITTEN BY:
Matt Stefon
See Article History
Alternative Title: chün-tzu