Closing The Gap
Closing The Gap
Closing The Gap
TOBIAS ROSEFELDT
1 Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason is cited as ‘CPR’, with page references to the 1781 and
1787 editions, given as a and b respectively. Other works by Kant are cited by volume and
page number in the Akademie edition (‘Ak.’). See the References section for details.
4 Kant had sent Jakob his own short reply to Mendelsohn’s Morgenstunden (Ak. viii:152–
5); this text was then included in Jakob’s book under the title ‘Einige Bemerkungen von
Herrn Professor Kant’ (Jakob 1786, pp. xlix–lx).
raised by some of his early critics, namely, that his restriction of our
knowledge to appearances commits him to an extreme and self-
refuting form of idealism that turns everything into ‘mere illusion’.5
Kant answers this objection by distancing his own distinction be-
tween appearances and things in themselves from a certain extremely
idealist misunderstanding of it. What I want to show in the following
paper is that, given his own positive account of this distinction, it in-
deed follows that if space and time are properties of appearances,
they cannot also be properties of things in themselves, and that
Jakob’s blunt claim that predicates applicable to phenomena are in
5 See the review of the Critique of Pure Reason by Feder and Garve from 1782 (Sassen 2000,
pp. 53–8) and Pistorius’s reviews of Schulze’s Erl€ auterungen über des Herrn Professor Kant
Critik der reinen Vernunft, which appeared in 1786 (Gesang 2007, pp. 3–25; Sassen 2000,
pp. 93–105). In this review, as well as in his review of Jakob’s book from 1788 (Gesang 2007,
pp. 39–71), Pistorius also raised a version of the neglected alternative objection. Pistorius ac-
cuses Kant of having neglected the third of the following three possible alternative views one
might have about our representation of space and time, namely, ‘that they are merely subjec-
tive, or merely objective, or both subjective and objective at the same time’ (Gesang 2007,
pp. 42f.). Contrary to Jakob, Pistorius did not assume that the neglected third alternative is
one in which space and time are forms of intuition and properties of things in themselves, but
characterized it as one in which the spatio-temporal structure of our experience is partially
grounded in an analogous structure of the mind-independent world, so that we are able to ex-
perience a ‘real plurality’ and a ‘real alterability of the represented things in themselves’
(Gesang 2007, p. 9). He also explains why his version of the neglected alternative objection is
superior to the one mentioned by Jakob and not refuted by the kind of reply that Jakob gives
(Gesang 2007, pp. 44ff.). It is an interesting question whether Pistorius’s version of the ‘ne-
glected alternative’ objection can be refuted by means of the strategy presented in this paper. I
will leave answering it for some other occasion.
time are forms of our intuition, it does indeed follow that they can-
not also be properties of things in themselves.
II
6 For the following, see Willaschek (1997) and Allais (2015, ch. 8, §v).
intuition. However, given that the factors that are in fact responsible
for our pure intuition of space and time are not extra-mental things
in themselves, but rather features of our own mind, the above princi-
ple excludes that pure intuition could represent extra-mental things
in themselves. So, in the end, both Willaschek and Allais conclude
that it follows from Kant’s account of intuition that the objects of
pure intuition cannot be extra-mental things in themselves, and
hence, since space and time are the objects of pure intuition, that
space and time are not things in themselves.
I think that this an ingenious and very attractive attempt to defend
(na*) (i) Space and time are forms of our intuition, and the space
and the time of which we have a priori intuitions are not
things in themselves; (ii) there is another space and another
time, of which we do not have any intuition, that do exist
in themselves.
Both Allais and Willaschek are aware of this kind of worry. Here is
how Allais responds to it:
[I]t is important to notice that the claim that things in themselves are
not spatio-temporal is not exactly what Kant asserts in the Aesthetic
(although he does provide argument for it in the Antinomies). Rather,
he says that space and time represent no property of things in them-
selves or relations between things in themselves (‘Der Raum stellet gar
keine Eigenschaft irgend einiger Dinge an sich, oder sie in ihrem
Verh€altnis auf einander vor’ a26/b42). He says that we have represen-
tations of space and time that play a fundamental role in our experi-
with a thing in itself, but he claims that time is nothing that exists in
itself or pertains to objects as an objective determination (a31/ b49).
And there are also other passages where he makes the stronger claim
about space (see a39f./ b56f.).
Now, some parts of what Allais writes also allow for a stronger
reading. When she says that ‘if there were something like space and
time in mind-independent reality, this something would not be that
of which our representation of space is a representation’, then this
could be understood as an objection to the effect that I have some-
how misdescribed the neglected scenario (na*) as one in which
Genau das gilt nach Kant nun auch für den Raum: Selbst wenn es
unabh€angig von unserem ‘Gemüt’ etwas geben sollte, auf das alle allge-
meinen Merkmale des Raumes zutreffen (Dreidimensionalit€at,
Homegeneit€at, Unendlichkeit, etc.), es w€are nicht der Raum, sofern wir
darunter den Gegenstand unserer Raumvorstellung verstehen. Damit
es sich bei einem Gegenstand . . . tats€achlich um den Raum handelt,
muß er dem externalistischen Anschauungsbegriff zufolge die Ursache
unserer Raumvorstellung sein. Wenn diese also eine Anschauuug a pri-
ori ist, kann ihre Ursache kein von uns unabh€angiger Gegenstand . . .
sein. (Willaschek 1997, p. 555)
7 Kant distinguishes between these two scenarios in his ‘Schlüsse aus obigen Begriffen’ more
carefully with respect to time (a32f./b49) than with respect to space (a26/b42).
8 Independently of this argument, Kant seems to have thought that the Newtonian concep-
tion of space and time is metaphysically so absurd that it is not a serious contender anyway
(see a39/b56 and b70f.).
III
9 See the review by Feder and Garve (Sassen 2000, pp. 53–8).
10See H. A. Pistorius’s reviews of Schulze’s Erl€
auterungen über des Herrn Professor Kant
Critik der reinen Vernunft (Gesang 2007, pp. 4f.).
The first thing to note about this passage is that it contains one of the
most explicit and unambiguous statements of the view that the dis-
tinction between appearances and things in themselves is one between
two different aspects of the same object rather than one between two
different kinds of object.12 As Kant makes clear he does not want to
distinguish between appearances on the one hand and numerically
distinct things in themselves on the other, but it is rather the ‘object as
appearance [that] is to be distinguished from itself as object in itself’
(my emphasis). This clarification implies that the claim that material
objects are appearances does not diminish them to ‘mere illusions’, a
11 The passage corresponds to ‘Note iii’ in the section on the Aesthetic in the Prolegomena
(Ak. iv:290ff.).
12 See also the corresponding passage of the Prolegomena (Ak. iv:292–3). For a general de-
fence of the ontological version of the two-aspect reading proposed in the following, see
Rosefeldt (2007), and also Allais (2007, 2015). The following proposal for how to deal
with the ‘neglected alternative’-objection is a modified and enlarged version of the ideas
presented in Rosefeldt (2013).
13 ‘Property’ here is my translation of the German term ‘Beschaffenheit’, which Kant uses in
the passage quoted above. ‘Beschaffenheit’ is a very general and non-terminological expres-
sion to speak about what objects are like, and it is metaphysically less loaded than expres-
sions such as ‘Akzidenz’ or ‘Realit€
at’.
(forthcoming).
15 Or more accurately: it is independent of the particular response by which ‘being poison-
ous’ is defined, that is, independent of the symptoms of intoxication. Understanding proper-
ties that things have in themselves as properties that they have independently of our mental
reaction to them does not commit us to assuming that these properties are intrinsic or non-
relational in every respect.
them because they bring about certain mental effects in us. In the
case of colours, the effect is a certain colour sensation, and colour
properties themselves can be understood as the higher-order proper-
ties of being such as to elicit such-and-such colour sensations in us.
This property is one that an object has only ‘in relation to a subject’,
and is dependent on the mental constitution of that subject, because
objects would not have it if we did not react to them by having the
respective sensations. Now, Kant seems to think that a similar analy-
sis can be given with respect to traditional primary spatio-temporal
properties. Given what he says about space and time as the forms of
16 In a94, Kant calls this structuring of sensations by the a priori forms of intuition the ‘syn-
opsis of the sense’. It is important to note that this synopsis does not yet yield a mental state
that represents a determinate spatial form or a particular temporal determination. As Kant
makes clear here and in many other passages, this only happens when an additional process
of sensible synthesis is performed by the imagination. A characterization of the mental effect
in non-representational terms is important in order to avoid certain circularity worries with
respect to response-dependent properties (see Rosefeldt forthcoming).
17 Vaihinger writes about the footnote, ‘Die Fussnote, vermuthlich erst nachtr€ aglich und
flüchtig hinzugesetzt, . . . bringt nun in die bis jetzt gewonnenen klaren Ergebnisse eine pein-
liche, ja widerw€artige Verwirrung hinein, welche Kant sich und seinen Lesern durch strenge
Gedankenführung wohl h€ atte ersparen können. Anstatt, wie seine Absicht war, den Text zu
erl€autern, hat Kant ihn nur verdunkelt’ (Vaihinger 1892, p. 488). I could not agree less. The
only slightly unfortunate aspect about the footnote is one further example for an illusion
(namely the illusion that Saturn has two handles), which is disanalogous to the other two
examples. Whereas in this case we can distinguish between the property of appearing to
have two handles and the property of having two handles, Kant’s view in the case of colours
and of spatio-temporal properties is precisely not that objects only appear to have these
properties, but rather that having these properties just is a way of appearing to subjects of a
certain kind. For this reason I am also sceptical about an alternative reading of the passage
b69f. which Andrew Huddleston has suggested to me, and according to which it is not the
spatio-temporal properties themselves that are response-dependent, but only their exempli-
fication by empirical objects. The only possible sense I can make of the idea of a response-
dependent form of exemplification would be to assume that for an object to exemplify a
certain property in this sense does not mean that the object really has the property, but
rather that it only appears, or seems, to have it. This kind of ‘exemplification’ would indeed
be response-dependent. However, it would result in exactly the understanding of Kant’s ide-
alism that he himself explicitly rules out when he writes, ‘I do not say that bodies merely
seem to exist outside me . . . if I assert that the quality of space . . . lies in my kind of intuition
and not in these objects in themselves’ (CPR, b69).
IV
References
Allais, Lucy 2007: ‘Kant’s Idealism and the Secondary Quality Analogy’.
Journal of the History of Philosophy, 45(3), pp. 459–84.
2010: ‘Kant’s Argument for Transcendental Idealism in the Transcen-
dental Aesthetics’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 90(1),
pp. 47–75.
2015: Manifest Reality: Kant’s Idealism and His Realism. Oxford: Ox-
ford University Press.