This Content Downloaded From 24.179.216.56 On Mon, 22 Jun 2020 22:04:07 UTC
This Content Downloaded From 24.179.216.56 On Mon, 22 Jun 2020 22:04:07 UTC
This Content Downloaded From 24.179.216.56 On Mon, 22 Jun 2020 22:04:07 UTC
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to Journal of Political Economy
George J. Stigler
University (ft( Chicago
The lecture focuses on the reasons that new ideas are accepted or
rejected by a science. A distinction is drawn between prescientific
and scientific stages of a discipline. The diverse fates of new ideas are
illustrated by a variety of episodes in the history of economics, in-
cluding the economics of information and the theory of economic
regulation.
Nobel Lecture presented December 8, 1982, Stockholm. I wish to thank Gary Becker,
Aaron Director, Milton Friedman, and Stephen Stigler for helpful comments.
529
We will find it useful to spend a short time with the large body of
writing called mercantilism. This literature ranges over several cen-
turies, and over England and western Europe. The literature com-
prises hundreds of pamphlets and books and includes participants of
the stature of John Locke and William Petty. I must confess at once
that I have little direct knowledge of that literature, for I have concen-
trated my historical work upon the period which followed. However,
three major studies of mercantilism are reassuringly agreed upon the
characteristics I wish to discuss. The studies are Edgar Furniss's book,
The Position of the Laborer in a System of Nationalism (1920), Jacob Vin
er's famous essay, "English Theories of Foreign Trade before Adam
Smith" (1930), and Eli Heckscher's masterly treatise, Mercantilism
(1935).
A first characteristic of all three surveys of mercantilism is that they
almost totally lack a time dimension. Furniss will document a state-
ment by references to two tracts written more than a century apart.
The process of analysis simply was not cumulative: there was little
advantage in studying foreign trade if one were born in 1680 instead
of 1580.
I am now prepared to come to the rescue of an economist who
needs little rescuing: Adam Smith. A considerable number of econo-
mists, and a few considerable economists, have emphasized the fact
that Smith had many gifted predecessors and almost all or perhaps
exactly all of his ideas are to be found expressed, and sometimes well
expressed, by these predecessors. Some economists therefore wish to
give the title of founder of economics to earlier writers such as Cantil-
lon. This line of argument, in my view, misses the point.
what will be produced and in what quantities, how the resources will
be employed in producing the menu of outputs, and how the re-
sources will be valued. Without a theory of value the economist can
have no theory of international trade nor, possibly, a theory of
money. This central problem of value does not change in its essential
content if one seeks to explain values in rural or urban societies, or in
agricultural or industrial societies. Indeed, if the problem of value
were so chameleon-like as to alter its nature whenever the economic
or political system altered, each epoch in economic life would require
its own theory, and short epochs would get short-lived theories.
If an empirical science requires for its very existence a set of funda-
mental and persistent phenomena, that is not the only kind of phe-
nomena with which it will deal. It will continuously be confronted
with new circumstances which call for more than a routine application
of standard knowledge. Thus the energy crisis of the 1970s has pro-
vided much employment to economists, but it has not called for im-
portant changes in economic science.
An empirical science has a second, and vastly more important, in-
terest in and responsiveness to contemporary problems: its received
theory will at times be incapable of dealing with these problems.
When England began the long-term importation of grain at the time
of the Napoleonic wars and pressed hard upon its domestic produc-
tion capacities, the economists introduced the law of diminishing re-
turns in dealing with the price of grain. It would be difficult to deny a
role to the environment in the appearance of this law. So much for
the origin of that theory: it would not help us one whit in understand-
ing Edgeworth's famous analysis of this law in 1911 to look at his
economic environment. The important place that diminishing re-
turns has achieved in economics is due precisely to the fact that its
usefulness was not limited to Ricardo's analysis of agriculture in Great
Britain.
The responsiveness of economics to environmental problems will
naturally be more complete and more prompt, the more urgent the
problems of the day. The response will also be more complete, the less
developed the relevant body of economic analysis. The respon-
siveness of macroeconomics to contemporary events is notorious.
Keynes's conquest in the 1930s was due to the fact that the neoclas-
sical theory could not account for the persistent unemployment of
that decade. A generation later, persistent inflation even with less
than full employment was equally decisive in ending Keynes's su-
premacy. If and when macroeconomics produces a good theory of the
business cycle, its responsiveness to environmental changes will di-
minish sharply.
A viable and healthy science requires both the persistent and almost
"Nature does not move in jumps," says the proverb, and a science also
progresses through time without making large jumps. This continuity
is often illustrated by two kinds of evidence.
One evidence of scientific continuity that has been adduced by
Robert Merton is the existence of multiple and nearly simultaneous
independent discoveries of a theory by several scientists. The popular
examples in economics are the discovery of the theory of rent by
Edward West and Thomas Robert Malthus in 1815 and the publica-
tion of the theory of utility in the early 1870s by Jevons, Menger, and
Walras. In each case, the new idea was presumably appropriate to the
development of economics at the time: the rent theory allowed the
construction of a theory of the distribution of income; and the utility
theory led naturally to the marginal productivity theory and the
generalization of the theory of utility-maximizing behavior.'
This continuity is also used to explain the not uncommon phenom-
enon of the failure of a man of genius to get acceptance of his ideas
from his contemporaries, even though later generations will applaud
the performance. Augustin Cournot, for example, was an important
scholar in one of the leading intellectual centers of Europe, but he
could not persuade economists in 1838 that the mathematical theory
of maxima and minima was a useful tool for economic analysis.
I would find it more persuasive to establish the continuity of
scientific development by a close examination of the evolution of im-
portant concepts in economics, but that route does not seem appro-
priate to the occasion.2 Candor compels me to note that the route of
close historical study would not be easy to follow because it would
Economists have always known that the extent and accuracy of the
knowledge of the economic actor had influence, and often a decisive
influence, on his behavior and therefore on the behavior of markets.
One striking example of this critical role of information is provided
by the theory of oligopoly. The first formulation of the problem of
oligopoly as a specific problem in economic theory was made by Cour-
not, whose long failure to get acceptance I have already mentioned. It
was essential, in explaining how each of two rivals in a market would
behave, to attribute to each some belief about the behavioral pattern
of the other. Cournot made the assumption that each assumed that
the rival did nothing in response to his own actions. The later theories
of oligopoly all rest upon different assumptions concerning patterns
' I once made such a direct confrontation of the theory of the kinked oligopoly
demand curve and more traditional theories, finding no evidence to support the exis-
tence of a kink. The theory has disappeared from professional work but lives in every
textbook (see Stigler 1978).
test the fertility of the theories (or at least the intellectual fertility of
economists), and the varied applications are partial empirical tests of
the theories. Gradually a consensus emerges among the economists
working on the subject: the theory becomes a part of the standard
analytical corpus or it dies of neglect.
V. Conclusion
References