Alexandre Kojève (1902-1968) - Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Alexandre Kojève (1902-1968) - Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Alexandre Kojève (1902-1968) - Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Alexandre Kojève was responsible for the serious introduction of Hegel into 20th
Century French philosophy, influencing many leading French intellectuals who
attended his seminar on The Phenomenology of Spirit in Paris in the 30s. He focused
on Hegel’s philosophy of history and is best known for his theory of ‘the end of
history’ and for initiating ‘existential Marxism.’ Kojève arrives at what is generally
considered a truly original interpretation by reading Hegel through the twin lenses of
Marx’s materialism and Heidegger’s temporalised ontology.
For Hegel, human history is the history of ‘thought’ as it attempts to understand itself
and its relation to the world. He postulates that history began with unity, but into
which man, a questioning ‘I’, emerges introducing dualism and splits. Man attempts
to heal these sequences of ‘alienations’ dialectically, and drives history forwards, but
in so doing causes new divisions which must then be overcome. Hegel sees the
possibility of ‘historical reconciliation’ lying in the rational realization of underlying
unity – the manifestation of an absolute spirit or ‘geist’ – leading to humanity living
according to a unified, shared morality: the end of history.
Kojève takes these ideas of universal historical process and the reconciliation
towards unity, and synthesizes them with theories of Marx and Heidegger:
This article examines the Hegelian context of Kojève’s work, and analyses how Marx
and Heidegger contribute to his theory. It also outlines Kojève’s vision of the
culmination of history; how this fits into 20th Century politics; and the profound
influence he had on French intellectuals including Sartre, Lacan and Breton, and on
America intellectuals including Leo Strauss, Alan Bloom and Francis Fukuyama.
Table of Contents
1
1. Chronology of Life and Works
He later settled in Paris, where he taught at the Ecole Pratique des Hautes Ētudes.
Taking over from Alexandre Koyré, he taught a seminar on Hegel from 1933 till 1939.
Along with Jean Hyppolite, he was responsible for the serious introduction of Hegel
into French thought. His lectures exerted a profound influence (both direct and
indirect) over many leading French philosophers and intellectuals - amongst them
Sartre, Merleau-Ponty, Lacan, Bataille, Althusser, Queneau, Aron, and Breton.
Via his friend Leo Strauss, Kojève's thought also exerted influence in America, most
especially over Allan Bloom and, later, Francis Fukuyama.
His lectures on Hegel were published in 1947 under the title Introduction à la lecture
de Hegel, appearing in English as Introduction to the Reading of Hegel (1969). After
the Second World War Kojève worked in the French Ministry of Economic Affairs,
until his death in 1968. Here he exercised a profound, mandarin influence over
French policy, including a role as one of the leading architects of the EEC and GATT.
He continued to write philosophy over these years, including works on the pre-
Socratics, Kant, the concept of right, the temporal dimensions of philosophical
wisdom, the relationship between Christianity and both Western science and
communism, and the development of capitalism. Many of these works were only
published posthumously.
2
2. The Hegelian Context
Perhaps the core of Hegel's philosophy is the idea that human history is the history of
thought as it attempts to understand itself and its relation to its world. History is the
history of reason, as it grapples with its own nature and its relation to that with which
it is confronted (other beings, nature, the eternal). The historical movement of this
reason is one of a sequence of alienations (Entfremdungen) or splits, and the
subsequent attempt to reconcile these divisions through a restoration of unity. Thus,
for example, Hegel sees the world of the Athenian Greeks as one in which people
lived in a harmonious relation to their community and the world about, the basis of
this harmony being provided by a pre-reflective commitment to shared customs,
conventions and habits of thought and action. With the beginnings of Socratic
philosophy, however, division and separation is introduced into thought - customary
answers to questions of truth, morality, and reality are brought under suspicion. A
questioning 'I' emerges, one that experiences itself as distinct and apart from other
beings, from customary rules, and from a natural world that becomes an 'object' for it.
This introduces into experience a set of 'dualisms' - between subject and object, man
and nature, desire and duty, the human and the divine, the individual and the
collectivity. For Hegel, the historical movement of thought is a 'dialectical' process
wherein these divisions are put through processes of reconciliation, producing in turn
new divisions, which thought in turn attempts to reconcile. Historically, this task of
reconciliation has been embodied in many forms - in art, in religion, and in
philosophy. Enlightenment philosophy, the philosophy of Hegel's own time, is the
latest and most sophisticated attempt to reconcile these divisions through reason
alone, to freely find man's place amongst others and the universe as a whole. This,
for Hegel, is only to be achieved through the overcoming (Aufhebung) of false
divisions, by grasping that underlying apparent schisms (such as that between
subject and object) there is a unity, with all elements being manifestations of an
Absolute Spirit (Geist). Thus Hegel sees the key to historical reconciliation lying in the
rational realisation of underlying unity, a unity that can, in time, come to connect
individuals with each other and with the world in which they live. Universal history is
the product of reason, leading (potentially) to a reconciled humanity, at one with
itself, living according to a shared morality that is the outcome of rational reflection.
3
3. The Influence of Marx
However, Kojève reworks Hegel in number of crucial (and, amongst Hegel scholars,
controversial) ways. The first of these may be identified with the influence of Marx,
especially the writings of the so-called '1848 manuscripts'.
4
which a shared human nature (comprising the desires and inclinations that define
humanity as such) would find its satisfaction.
How and why is this realisation of mutuality and equality to come about? Kojève
follows Hegel's famous presentation of the 'master-slave’ dialectic in order to deduce
the necessary overcoming of inequality, division and subordination. The relation of
'master' and ‘slave’ is one in which the satisfaction of a dominant group's or class’
needs (the 'masters’) is met through the subordination of others (the 'slaves' or
‘bondsmen’). The ‘slave’ exists only to affirm the superiority and humanity of the
'master', and to furnish the 'master's’ needs by surrendering up his labor. However,
this relation is doomed to failure, for two fundamental reasons:
- Firstly, the 'master' desires the recognition and affirmation of his full humanity
and value, and uses the subordinated 'slave' for that end. This means that the
'master', perversely, is dependent upon the ‘slave’, thus inverting the relation
of domination.
- Moreover, this forced relation of recognition remains thoroughly incomplete,
since the 'slave' is not in a position to grant affirmation freely, but is compelled
to do so due to his subordination. Affirmation or recognition that is not freely
given counts for nothing. As Kojève puts it:
The relation between Master and Slave... is not recognition properly so-
called... The Master is not the only one to consider himself Master. The
Slave, also, considers him as such. Hence, he is recognized in his human
reality and dignity. But this recognition is one-sided, for he does not
recognize in turn the Slave's human reality and dignity. Hence, he is
recognized by someone whom he does not recognize. And this is what is
insufficient - what is tragic - in his situation... For he can be satisfied only
by recognition from one whom he recognizes as worthy of recognizing him.
This establishes the constitutive need for mutual recognition and formal equality, if
recognition of value is to be established. It is only when there is mutuality and
recognition of all, that the recognition of any one becomes fully possible.
Secondly, for Kojève (as for Marx) it is the laboring 'slave' who is the key to historical
progress. It is the ‘slave’ who works, and consequently it is he and not the 'master'
who exercises his ‘negativity’ in transforming the world in line with human wants and
desires. So, on the material level, the slave possesses the key to his own liberation,
namely his active mastery of nature. Moreover, the 'master' has no desire to
transform the world, whereas the 'slave', unsatisfied with his condition, imagines and
attempts to realise a world of freedom in which his value will finally be recognised
and his own desires satisfied. The slave's ideological struggle is to overcome his own
fear of death and take-up struggle against the 'master', demanding the recognition of
his value and freedom. The coincidence of material and ideological conditions of
liberation were already made manifest, for Kojève, by the revolutions of the 18 th, 19th
and 20th centuries; these struggles set the conditions for the completion of history in
the form of universal society.
5
4. The Influence of Heidegger
If Marx furnishes one central resource for Kojève's rereading of Hegel, Heidegger
provides the other. From Heidegger, Kojève takes the insight that humankind is
distinguished from nature through its distinctive ontological self-relation. Man's being
is conditioned by its radically temporal character, its understanding of its being in
time, with finitude or death as its ultimate horizon. Kojève's ontology is, pace
Heidegger’s analysis of Dasein in Being & Time, first and foremost experiential and
existential. By bringing together Hegel with Heidegger, Kojève attempts to radically
historicise existentialism, while simultaneously giving Hegelian historicity a radically
existential twist, wherein man's existential freedom defines his being. Freedom is
understood as the ontological relation of 'negativity', the incompleteness of human
being, its constitutive ‘lack’. It is precisely because of this lack of a fully constituted
being that man experiences (or, more properly is nothing other than) desire. The
negativity of being, manifest as desire, makes possible man's self-making, the
process of 'becoming'. This position can be seen to draw inspiration from Heidegger's
critique of the transcendental preoccupations of Western thought, which, he claims,
set reified, metaphysically assured figurations of Being over and above the
processes of Becoming (wherein the 'Being of Beings', das Sein des Seieinden, is
variously revealed within the horizon of temporality). The disavowal of such
metaphysically anchored and ultimately timeless configurations of human being frees
man from determinism and 'throws' him into his existential freedom. In Kojève's
thinking, man’s struggle is to exercise this freedom in order to produce a world in
which his desires are satisfied, in the course of which he comes to accept his own
freedom, ridding himself of the illusions of religion and superstition, 'heroically'
claiming his own finitude or mortality.
We can see, then, how Kojève attempts to synthesise Hegel, Marx and Heidegger:
- From Hegel he takes the notion of a universal historical process within which
reconciliation unfolds through an intersubjective dialectic, resulting in unity.
- From Marx he takes a secularised, de-theologised, and productivist
philosophical anthropology, one that places the transformative activity of a
desiring being centre stage in the historical process.
- From Heidegger, he takes the existentialist interpretation of human being as
free, negative, and radically temporal.
6
Pulling the three together, he presents a vision of human history in which man grasps
his freedom to produce himself and his world in pursuit of his desires, and in doing so
drives history toward its end (understood both as culmination or exhaustion, and its
goal or completion).
For Kojève, historical reconciliation will culminate in the equal recognition of all
individuals. This recognition will remove the rationale for war and struggle, and so will
usher in peace. In this way, history, politically speaking, culminates in a universal
(global) order which is without classes or distinctions - in Hegelian terms, there are
no longer any 'masters' and ‘slaves’, only free human beings who mutually recognise
and affirm each others' freedom. This political moment takes the form of law, which
confers universal recognition upon all individuals, thereby satisfying the particular
individual's desire to be affirmed as an equal amongst others.
7
would end in the triumph of the capitalist West, achieved through economic rather
than military means.
- On the one hand, he follows Marx by seeing in idyllic terms the post-historical world,
one of universal freedom, emancipation from war and want, leaving space for "art,
love, play, and so forth; in short, everything that makes Man happy".
8
6. Kojève's Influence
The influence of Kojève's thought has been profound, both within France and
beyond. It is possible to trace many connections within French philosophy that owe
varying degrees of debt to Kojève, given that his distinctive reinterpretation of Hegel
was key for the French reception of Hegel's thought. However, there are also a
number of important philosophers for whom Kojève's Hegelianism provided direct
insights that were taken-up and in-turn used to found distinctive philosophical
positions.
Another eminent thinker for whom Kojève proved decisive was Jacques Lacan.
Lacan's account of psycho-social formation was developed through a synthesis of
Freud and structuralism, read through Kojève's ontologised version of the 'master-
slave' dialectic. For Lacan, following Kojève, human subjectivity is defined first and
foremost by desire. It is the experience of lack, the twin of the experience of desire,
that provides the ontological condition of subject formation; it is only through the lack-
desire dyad that a being comes into the awareness of its own separation from the
world in which it is, at first, thoroughly immersed. Moreover, Lacan's account of the
childhood development of self-consciousness, captured through his analysis of the
'mirror-stage', replays the intersubjective mediation of consciousness that Kojève
presented to his French students (Lacan amongst them) in the Hegel lectures.
Kojève also profoundly influenced the likes of Georges Bataille and Raymond
Queneau, both through the lectures they attended, and through the friendships he
maintained with them for many years after.
9
Queneau is often associated with Andre Breton and the surrealists (with whom he
broke in 1929), but his novels present a vision of the world that is profoundly
indebted to Kojève. Many of his most famous books depict life at the end of history;
there is no more historical movement, progress or transformation to come, and his
characters live in a kind of 'eternal present' attending to the activities of everyday
enjoyment. History recurs as something that can only be enjoyed as a tourist
attraction, or as a reverie of the past, viewed from the vantage point of its demise.
The influence of Kojève outside France has probably been most pronounced in the
United States. His ideas achieved a new salience and exposure with the publication
of Francis Fukayama's The End of History and the Last Man (1992), in the wake of
the Cold War. Fukayama was a student of Allan Bloom's, who in turn was a 'disciple'
of the 'esoteric' émigré political philosopher Leo Strauss. It was Strauss who
introduced a generation of his students to Kojève's thought, and in Bloom’s case,
arranged for him to study with Kojève in Paris in the 1960s. The book, an
international bestseller, presents nothing less than a triumphal vindication of Kojève's
supposedly prescient thesis that history has found its end in the global triumph of
capitalism and liberal democracy. With the final demise of Soviet Marxism, and the
global hegemony of capitalism, we have finally reached the end of history. There are
no more battles to be fought, no more experiments in social engineering to be
attempted; the world has arrived at a homogenised state in which the combination of
capitalism and liberal democracy will reign supreme, and all other cultural and
ideological systems will be consigned irretrievably to the past. Fukayama follows
Kojève in tying the triumph of capitalism to the satisfaction of material human needs.
Moreover, he sees it as the primary mechanism for the provision of recognition and
value. Consumerism and the commodity form, for Fukayama, present the means by
which recognition is mediated. Humans desire to be valued by others, and the means
of appropriating that valuation is the appropriation of the things that others
themselves value; hence lifestyle and fashion become the mechanisms of mutual
esteem in a post-historical world governed by the logic of capitalist individualism.
10
7. References and Further Reading
11