Logic Dictionary
Logic Dictionary
Keith Burgess-Jackson
12 August 2017
affirmo. Latin for “I affirm.” In categorical logic, the letter names “A” and “I”
come from the first two vowels of the word “affirmo.” The “A” proposition is uni-
versal affirmative; the “I” proposition is particular affirmative. See (1) “A” proposi-
tion, (2) nego, and (3) “I” proposition.
“all.” The universal affirmative quantifier, as in ‘All S are P’. See (1) “no” and (2)
“some.”
1
that follows the word “if,” or, in the case of a symbolized expression, precedes the
horseshoe. Example: In the conditional “If this is an even-numbered year, then
there are Congressional elections this year,” the antecedent is “this is an even-num-
bered year.” In the symbolized expression ‘q ﬤp,’ the antecedent is ‘q’. See (1) con-
ditional and (2) consequent.
“all.” The universal affirmative quantifier, as in ‘All S are P’. See (1) “no” and (2)
“some.”
argument form. Any array of symbols containing propositional variables (‘p’, ‘q’,
‘r’, ‘s’, and so forth) but no propositions, such that when propositions are substi-
tuted for the propositional variables—the same proposition being substituted for
the same propositional variable throughout—the result is an argument. See (1) ar-
gument and (2) substitution instance.
2
Aristotelian interpretation of standard-form categorical propositions.
See (1) Aristotle and (2) square of opposition.
association (Assoc). In propositional logic, two replacement rules. The first says
that three disjuncts may be reassociated with one another (i.e., that parentheses
may be relocated). Formally, ‘p Ú (q Ú r)’ :: ‘(p Ú q) Ú r’. The second says that three
conjuncts may be reassociated with one another. Formally, ‘p • (q • r)’ :: ‘(p • q) • r’.
The four quantification rules (EG, EI, UG, and UI) that apply to syllogisms are
applicable here as well. The finite-universe method of proving invalidity that ap-
plies to syllogisms is applicable here as well. See syllogism.
3
asymmetry. A relation such that if one thing has that relation to a second, then
the second cannot have that relation to the first. Symbolically: (x)(y)(Rxy ~ ﬤRyx).
Examples: “is the father of,” “is north of,” “is older than,” “weighs more than,” “is a
child of.” See (1) nonsymmetry, (2) relation, and (3) symmetry.
1. All M are P.
2. All S are M.
Therefore,
3. All S are P.
binary (dyadic) relation. A relation that holds (obtains) between two individu-
als, i.e., a two-place relation. For example, “Ron is married to Nancy,” “Dallas is
north of Houston,” and “Cain was brother to Abel.” See relation.
bivalence, law (principle) of. The law of classical logic that every proposition
is either true or false. That is, there are just two values a proposition may take: ‘true’
4
and ‘false’. Another way to put this is that the truth values ‘true’ and ‘false’ are
jointly exhaustive; i.e., there is no third or middle possibility. The law of bivalence
is not to be confused with the law of excluded middle, which asserts that every
proposition is either true or not true.
bound variable. In predicate logic, a variable that is bound by a quantifier. See (1)
free variable and (2) quantifier.
5
devised to determine whether particular categorical syllogisms are valid. See (1) Ar-
istotle, (2) predicate logic, and (3) propositional logic.
chain argument. A series of two or more arguments, with the conclusion of the
first argument serving as a premise of a second argument, the conclusion of the
second argument serving as a premise of a third argument, and so on, for as many
arguments as there are. Like a physical chain, a chain argument is no stronger than
its weakest link. See argument.
• ‘(x)Øx’ :: ‘~(Ǝx)~Øx’
• ‘(Ǝx)Øx’ :: ‘~(x)~Øx’
• ‘(x)~Øx’ :: ‘~(Ǝx)Øx’
• ‘(Ǝx)~Øx’ :: ‘~(x)Øx’
Note that double negation is silently employed. See (1) double negation and (2)
quantifier.
6
class. A collection (group, aggregate) of individuals (objects) that have some spec-
ified characteristic (property) in common, the characteristic being known as the
class-defining characteristic.
7
compound proposition. In propositional logic, a proposition that (1) contains
another proposition as a component and (2) remains meaningful when the compo-
nent is replaced with any other proposition. The components themselves may be
compound propositions. See (1) component and (2) simple proposition.
conclusion indicator. A word or phrase that indicates (but does not guarantee)
that what follows it is the conclusion of an argument. Examples: “therefore,”
“hence,” “thus,” “so,” “it follows that,” “consequently.” See (1) argument, (2) conclu-
sion, and (3) premise indicator.
condition. See (1) necessary condition, (2) necessary and sufficient condition, and
(3) sufficient condition.
conditional proof. A method of proof that consists of (1) assuming the anteced-
ent of a required conditional on the first line of an indented sequence, (2) deriving
the consequent of the required conditional on a subsequent line, using only valid
rules of inference, and (3) discharging the indented sequence in a conditional that
exactly replicates the one to be obtained. See (1) conditional and (2) proof.
8
that (i.e., if and only if) at least one member of a given class exists. See (1) uncondi-
tional validity and (2) validity.
conjunction.
consistency.
9
forms (or propositions). Propositional form X is consistent with proposi-
tional form Y (i.e., X and Y are consistent [with one another]) if and only
if it is logically possible for both X and Y to be true. Colloquially, X and Y
can both be true. Example: ‘p • q’ is consistent with ‘p Ú q’, since, in the
case in which both ‘p’ and ‘q’ are true, both compound propositions are
true. One may also speak of a set of propositional forms (or propositions)
being consistent or inconsistent. See inconsistency.
2. A property of (some) deductive systems. A deductive system is consistent
if and only if only valid arguments are provable in it. See (1) compactness
and (2) completeness.
constant. In predicate logic, a symbol (lowercase “a” through “w”) that names (de-
notes, refers to, picks out) an individual. Examples: “a” denotes Alice; “b” denotes
Boston; “c” denotes Colorado. See (1) individual and (2) variable.
contingent propositional form. A propositional form that has both true and
false substitution instances. A propositional form that is neither necessarily true
nor necessarily false. In other words, a propositional form that is both possibly false
and possibly true. Example: ‘p • q’. See (1) contingency, (2) contingent proposition,
(3) propositional form, (4) self-consistent propositional form, (5) self-contradictory
propositional form, and (6) tautologous propositional form.
10
contingent truth. A proposition that is true, but not necessarily so. Examples:
“Abraham Lincoln was the 16th president”; “the Boston Red Sox won the 2013
World Series”; “some bachelors are bald.” See necessary truth.
Premise Contrapositive
All S are P All nonP are nonS
No S are P No nonP are nonS
Some S are P Some nonP are nonS
Some S are not P Some nonP are not nonS
11
‘Some nonP are not nonS’ (by contraposition). See (1) contraposition, (2) conversion
per accidens, and (3) immediate inference.
contraries. Two propositional forms (or propositions) are contraries (of one an-
other) if and only if they stand in the logical relation of contrariety to one another.
In categorical logic, “A” and “E” propositions are contraries on the traditional (Ar-
istotelian) interpretation but not on the modern (Boolean) interpretation. See (1)
contrariety and (2) subcontraries.
converse.
Convertend Converse
All S are P All P are S
No S are P No P are S
Some S are P Some P are S
Some S are not P Some P are not S
12
conversion per accidens (a.k.a. conversion by limitation). In categorical
logic, an immediate inference in which one converts an “A” proposition. From ‘All
S are P’, one infers ‘Some P are S’. The inference is valid only on the traditional
(Aristotelian) interpretation of categorical propositions. The inference is logically
equivalent to subalternation and conversion, in that order. Thus, ‘All S are P’ be-
comes ‘Some S are P’ (by subalternation), which becomes ‘Some P are S’ (by con-
version). See (1) contraposition per accidens, (2) conversion, and (3) immediate infer-
ence.
copula. Some form of the verb “to be.” The copula connects (joins) the subject
and predicate terms of a standard-form categorical proposition. (Note: In this
course, for the sake of uniformity, we use “are” and “are not” as copulas, rather
than, say, “is” and “is not.”) See standard-form categorical proposition (SFCP).
Many One
Many “is a creditor of” “is the son of”
One “is the father of” “is greater by one than”
13
dilemma whose conclusion is opposed (either as contrary or as contradictory) to
the conclusion of the original. If the premises of the second (counter) dilemma are
true, then the original dilemma has at least one false premise. See constructive di-
lemma (CD).
definition. A procedure for giving the meaning of a word or phrase. See (1) defin-
iendum and (2) definiens.
14
definition symbol (“=df”). An abbreviation for “equals (i.e., means) by defini-
tion.” Example: “puppy” =df “young dog.” This may be read as “The word ‘puppy’
means, by definition, ‘young dog.’ ” See definition.
denying the antecedent (DA), fallacy of. In propositional logic, an invalid syl-
logism (i.e., a formal fallacy) in which the first premise is a conditional, the second
premise the denial of the antecedent of that conditional, and the conclusion the
denial of the consequent of that conditional. The name derives from the fact that
the second premise denies the antecedent of the first premise. Formally, ‘p ﬤq’; ‘~p’;
therefore, ‘~q’. See (1) affirming the consequent (AC), fallacy of and (2) Modus Tol-
lens.
direct truth table. Another name for a full (as opposed to a partial) truth table.
See (1) partial truth table and (2) truth table.
15
disjuncts (a.k.a. alternatives, alternants, and alternates). The proposi-
tions (simple or compound) that make up a disjunction. In “Joe is tired or Phil ate
Wheaties,” the disjuncts are “Joe is tired” and “Phil ate Wheaties.” Disjuncts can
be referred to as “left” and “right” or as “first” and “second.” Thus, “Joe is tired” is
the first or left disjunct of the disjunction, while “Phil ate Wheaties” is the second
or right disjunct. See disjunction.
distribution.
16
first rule says that a proposition and a dot may be either distributed to or
collected from each disjunct of a disjunction. Formally, ‘p • (q Ú r)’ :: ‘(p • q)
Ú (p • r)’. The second rule says that a proposition and a wedge may be either
distributed to or collected from each conjunct of a conjunction. Formally,
‘p Ú (q • r)’ :: ‘(p Ú q) • (p Ú r)’. See replacement rules.
dot. In propositional logic, the symbol (“•”) for conjunction. See conjunction 1.
double colon (“::”). The symbol for logical equivalence. For example, ‘p’ :: ‘~~p’
means that the propositional form ‘p’ is logically equivalent to the propositional
form ‘~~p’. The double colon has a different logical status from symbols such as
“~,” “•,” “Ú,” “ﬤ,” and “º.” The latter are logical (i.e., truth-functional) operators on
propositions (or propositional forms); the double colon, by contrast, is a metalogi-
cal symbol about propositions (or propositional forms). See logical equivalence.
end term. In categorical logic, a term that appears in the conclusion of a syllogism
but not in either of its premises. Contrasted with “middle term.” The major term
and the minor term are end terms.
Terms
End Middle
Major Minor
1 2 3
17
See (1) major term, (2) middle term, and (3) minor term.
equivalence. Let “X” and “Y” be propositional forms. The following diagram dis-
plays (among other things) the difference between material equivalence and logical
equivalence:
Implication Equivalence
As a matter of fact, the follow- As a matter of fact, neither of
ing state of affairs does not ob- the following states of affairs
tain: X is true and Y is false. obtains: X is true and Y is
Material false; Y is true and X is
X materially implies Y. false.1
‘X º Y’ is true.
Logically, the following state of Logically, neither of the fol-
affairs cannot obtain: X is true lowing states of affairs can ob-
and Y is false. tain: X is true and Y is false;
Logical Y is true and X is false.2
1
Put differently, “As a matter of fact, X and Y have the same truth value.”
2
Put differently, “Logically, X and Y have the same truth value.”
18
‘X ﬤY’ is a tautology. ‘X º Y’ is a tautology.
See (1) logical equivalence, (2) material equivalence, and (3) tautology.
equivocation, fallacy of. An informal fallacy that occurs when a term is used in
different senses (equivocally, rather than univocally) in the same argument. Exam-
ple:
1. Knowledge is power.
2. All power corrupts.
Therefore,
3. Knowledge corrupts.
The word “power” is being used in different senses. In premise 1, it means “power
to (do something).” In premise 2, it means “power over (others).” In the first sense,
premise 1 is true but premise 2 is false. In the second sense, premise 2 is true but
premise 1 is false. Therefore, whichever sense is chosen, the argument is unsound.
See (1) fallacy, (2) informal fallacy, and (3) unsoundness.
excluded middle, law (principle) of (a.k.a. tertium non datur). One of the
three laws (principles) of thought. It asserts that every object either has or lacks a
19
given property. Formally, (x)(Øx Ú ~Øx). It follows from this law that every propo-
sition either has or lacks the property of truth, i.e., that every proposition is either
true or not true, i.e., that every proposition of the form ‘p Ú ~p’ is true. The law of
excluded middle is not to be confused with the law of bivalence, which asserts that
every proposition is either true or false.
Law of excluded middle Every proposition is either true or not true (this
is an instance of the more general law that every
object either has or lacks a given property).
Law of bivalence Every proposition is either true or false.
See (1) bivalence, law (principle) of, (2) identity, law (principle) of, (3) laws (princi-
ples) of thought, and (4) noncontradiction, law (principle) of.
existential assumption, fallacy of. The fallacy of assuming that a class has
members if it is not asserted explicitly that it does. See fallacy.
20
have existential import. See (1) square of opposition and (2) standard-form categor-
ical proposition (SFCP).
existential name. The name given to the individual that is claimed to exist by an
existentially quantified proposition. Existential instantiation (EI) consists of infer-
ring ‘Øa’ from ‘(Ǝx)Øx’ (read as “Something is Ø, so let ‘a’ be its name”). The exis-
tential name in this case is “a.” See (1) existential instantiation (EI) and (2) instantial
letter.
fallacy. An argument (or argument form) that appears to be correct but is not. An
argument (or argument form) that is psychologically attractive (plausible, alluring),
and therefore commonly made, but which is logically infirm. An error or mistake
in reasoning other than the employment of false premises. Fallacy is not the same
as sophistry, which is the deliberate use of unsound reasoning for some ulterior
purpose, such as deception, “winning” an argument, or undermining proper discus-
sion. Every fallacy is either formal or informal, depending on whether it can be
detected merely through an examination of the form or structure of the argument.
If it can be so detected, then it is a formal fallacy; if it cannot be so detected, but
requires attention to content or context, then it is an informal fallacy. See (1) formal
21
fallacy, (2) informal fallacy, and (3) paralogism.
fallacy of affirming the consequent (AC). See affirming the consequent (AC),
fallacy of.
fallacy of denying the antecedent (DA). See denying the antecedent (DA), fal-
lacy of.
fallacy of illicit process of the major term (a.k.a. illicit major). See illicit
process of the major term, fallacy of.
fallacy of illicit process of the minor term (a.k.a. illicit minor). See illicit
process of the minor term, fallacy of.
1. The middle term is the subject term of the major premise and the predi-
cate term of the minor premise.
2. The middle term is the predicate term of both premises.
3. The middle term is the subject term of both premises.
4. The middle term is the predicate term of the major premise and the sub-
ject term of the minor premise.
Figure
1 2 3 4
----- M ----- P ----- P ----- M ----- M ----- P ----- P ----- M
----- S ----- M ----- S ----- M ----- M ----- S ----- M ----- S
----- S ----- P ----- S ----- P ----- S ----- P ----- S ----- P
Each of the 64 moods (AAA through OOO) can occur with each of the four figures
22
(1 through 4), which gives a total of 256 distinct standard-form categorical syllo-
gisms. Example: AIO-3:
1. All M are P.
2. Some M are S.
Therefore,
3. Some S are not P.
Only 24 of the 256 standard-form categorical syllogisms (9.3%) are valid: 15 of them
unconditionally and nine conditionally (the condition being the existence of mem-
bers of one of the three classes). See (1) mood and (2) standard-form categorical syl-
logism (SFCS).
formal fallacy. A fallacy that can be detected merely by examination of the form
or structure of the argument. See (1) fallacy and (2) informal fallacy.
formal logic. The type of logic in which the reasoning being studied is expressed
in artificial (as opposed to natural) language. See (1) artificial symbolic language, (2)
informal logic, (3) logic, and (4) natural language.
formal proof (of validity). A formal proof that a given argument (or argument
form) is valid is a sequence of propositions each of which is either a premise of that
argument or follows from preceding propositions of the sequence by an elementary
valid argument, and the last proposition in the sequence is the conclusion of the
argument whose validity is being proved. A formal proof of validity is effective in
the sense that it can be mechanically decided of any given sequence whether it is a
proof. Constructing a formal proof, by contrast, is not an effective procedure, for
there is no guarantee that one will be able to “figure out” how to derive the con-
clusion from the premise(s), given the rules of inference. In this respect, formal
23
proof is unlike truth tables, which are completely mechanical. See (1) proof, (2) truth
table, and (3) validity.
free variable. In predicate logic, a variable that is not bound by a quantifier. See
(1) bound variable and (2) quantifier.
full truth table. Another name for a truth table (contrasted with a partial truth
table). See (1) partial truth table and (2) truth table.
general proposition. A quantified proposition, such as ‘All S are P’, ‘No S are P’,
‘Some S are P’, and ‘Some S are not P’. See singular proposition.
Greek letters “Ø” (phi) and “Ψ” (psi). In predicate logic, symbols that repre-
sent predicates or attributes. Just as “x,” “y,” and “z” are variables for objects, “Ø”
and “Ψ” are variables for attributes. The propositional function ‘Øx’ may be read
as “x is Ø.” If “x” is replaced with “a,” the name for, say, Allen Buchanan, and “Ø”
24
is replaced with “P,” for the attribute “is a philosopher,” then we have the propo-
sition ‘Pa,’ which says that Allen Buchanan is a philosopher (i.e., has the property
of being a philosopher). Propositions, unlike propositional functions, are either
true or false. (Propositional functions are neither true nor false; they lack truth
value.) It is true that Allen Buchanan (one of my teachers at the University of Ari-
zona during the 1980s) is a philosopher. See (1) attribute and (2) variable.
horseshoe. In propositional logic, the symbol (“ )”ﬤfor material implication. See
material implication 1.
identity. A relation that holds (obtains) only between an object and itself. To say
that x and y are identical is to say that they are the same thing. Everything is iden-
tical with itself and with nothing else. Examples: Cicero is identical with (i.e., is the
same thing as) Tully (symbolized as “Cicero = Tully”); the longest river in South
America = the Amazon; Whitman = the author of Leaves of Grass; 13 = the sixth
prime number. The relation of identity is transitive, symmetrical, and reflexive:
See (1) reflexivity, (2) relation, (3) symmetry, and (4) transitivity.
identity, law (principle) of. One of the three laws (principles) of thought. It
asserts that every object that has a given property has that property. Formally,
(x)(Øx ﬤØx). It follows from this law that every proposition that has the property
of truth has the property of truth, i.e., that every proposition that is true is true,
i.e., that every proposition of the form ‘p ﬤp’ is true, i.e., that every proposition
materially implies itself. See (1) excluded middle, law (principle) of, (2) laws (princi-
25
ples) of thought, (3), material implication 1, and (4) noncontradiction, law (princi-
ple) of.
illicit contrariety. A fallacy that occurs when the conclusion of an argument de-
pends on an incorrect application of the contrary relation.
• Suppose S’s exist. Then “A” and “E” propositions are contraries, for, while
it is possible for both propositions to be false, it is not possible for both
propositions to be true. It follows that (1) if the “A” proposition is true,
then the corresponding “E” proposition is false; and (2) if the “E” proposi-
tion is true, then the corresponding “A” proposition is false. This is a cor-
rect (i.e., nonfallacious) application of the contrary relation.
• Suppose S’s do not exist. Then “A” and “E” propositions are not contraries,
for it is possible for both propositions to be true (indeed, both are true).
To infer the falsity of one from the truth of the other is to commit the
fallacy of illicit contrariety.
illicit conversion. A formal fallacy that occurs when the conclusion of an argu-
ment depends on the conversion of an “A” or an “O” proposition:
26
Here are counterexamples (i.e., refutations by logical analogy):
• All dogs are animals (true); therefore, all animals are dogs (false).
• Some vegetables are not carrots (true); therefore, some carrots are not veg-
etables (false).
illicit major. See illicit process of the major term, fallacy of.
illicit minor. See illicit process of the minor term, fallacy of.
illicit process of the major term, fallacy of. In a valid standard-form categor-
ical syllogism, if an end term is distributed in the conclusion, then it must be dis-
tributed in the premises. Any syllogism in which the major term is distributed in
the conclusion but not in the major premise commits the (formal) fallacy of illicit
process of the major term (or, more briefly, illicit major). See (1) end term, (2) fallacy,
(3) formal fallacy, (4) major term, and (5) standard-form categorical syllogism
(SFCS).
illicit process of the minor term, fallacy of. In a valid standard-form categor-
ical syllogism, if an end term is distributed in the conclusion, then it must be dis-
tributed in the premises. Any syllogism in which the minor term is distributed in
the conclusion but not in the minor premise commits the (formal) fallacy of illicit
process of the minor term (or, more briefly, illicit minor). See (1) end term, (2) fal-
lacy, (3) formal fallacy, (4) minor term, and (5) standard-form categorical syllogism
(SFCS).
• Suppose S’s exist. Then (1) the “A” proposition is the superaltern of the
corresponding “I” proposition, for (a) it is not possible for the “A” propo-
sition to be true while the corresponding “I” proposition is false and (b) it
is possible for the “I” proposition to be true while the corresponding “A”
proposition is false; and (2) the “E” proposition is the superaltern of the
corresponding “O” proposition, for (a) it is not possible for the “E” propo-
sition to be true while the corresponding “O” proposition is false and (b) it
is possible for the “O” proposition to be true while the corresponding “E”
proposition is false. It follows that (1) if the “I” proposition is false, then
27
the corresponding “A” proposition is false and (2) if the “O” proposition is
false, then the corresponding “E” proposition is false. This is a correct (i.e.,
nonfallacious) application of the subalternation relation.
• Suppose S’s do not exist. Then (1) the “A” proposition is not the superal-
tern of the corresponding “I” proposition, for it is possible for the “A”
proposition to be true while the corresponding “I” proposition is false (in-
deed, the “A” proposition is true and the corresponding “I” proposition is
false); and (2) the “E” proposition is not the superaltern of the correspond-
ing “O” proposition, for it is possible for the “E” proposition to be true
while the corresponding “O” proposition is false (indeed, the “E” proposi-
tion is true and the corresponding “O” proposition is false). To infer the
truth of the “I” proposition from the truth of the corresponding “A” prop-
osition, or the truth of the “O” proposition from the truth of the corre-
sponding “E” proposition, is to commit the fallacy of illicit subalternation.
• Suppose S’s exist. Then “I” and “O” propositions are subcontraries, for,
while it is possible for both propositions to be true, it is not possible for
both propositions to be false. It follows that (1) if the “I” proposition is
false, then the corresponding “O” proposition is true; and (2) if the “O”
proposition is false, then the corresponding “I” proposition is true. This is
a correct (i.e., nonfallacious) application of the subcontrary relation.
• Suppose S’s do not exist. Then “I” and “O” propositions are not subcon-
traries, for it is possible for both propositions to be false (indeed, both are
false). To infer the truth of one from the falsity of the other is to commit
the fallacy of illicit subcontrariety.
implication. Let “X” and “Y” be propositional forms. The following diagram dis-
plays (among other things) the difference between material implication and logical
implication:
28
Implication Equivalence
As a matter of fact, the follow- As a matter of fact, neither of
ing state of affairs does not ob- the following states of affairs
tain: X is true and Y is false. obtains: X is true and Y is
Material false; Y is true and X is
X materially implies Y. false.3
‘X º Y’ is true.
Logically, the following state of Logically, neither of the fol-
affairs cannot obtain: X is true lowing states of affairs can ob-
and Y is false. tain: X is true and Y is false;
Logical Y is true and X is false.4
See (1) logical implication, (2) material implication, and (3) tautology.
implication rules. In propositional logic, eight rules (Modus Ponens, Modus Tol-
lens, Hypothetical Syllogism, Disjunctive Syllogism, Constructive Dilemma, Sim-
plification, Conjunction, and Addition) that allow a particular propositional form
to be inferred from one or more other specified propositional forms. In each case,
the conjunction of the premises logically implies the conclusion (but not con-
versely). The rules (i.e., elementary valid argument forms) are applicable only to
whole lines of a proof. See (1) elementary valid argument form, (2) inference, rules
of, (3) logical implication, and (4) replacement rules.
3
Put differently, “As a matter of fact, X and Y have the same truth value.”
4
Put differently, “Logically, X and Y have the same truth value.”
29
inconsistency (a.k.a. joint unsatisfiability). A logical relation between
(among) propositional forms (or propositions). Propositional form X is incon-
sistent with propositional form Y (i.e., X and Y are inconsistent [with one an-
other]) if and only if it is logically impossible for both X and Y to be true, i.e., if
and only if at least one of the propositional forms (X or Y) is false. Colloquially, X
and Y can’t both be true. Example: ‘p ﬤq’ is inconsistent with ‘p • ~q’. One may
also speak of a set of propositional forms (or propositions) being consistent or in-
consistent. See consistency.
indirect truth table. Another name for a partial truth table. The contrast is with
a direct (full) truth table. See (1) partial truth table and (2) truth table.
30
induction. See inductive argument.
inference, rules of. In propositional logic, a set of rules consisting of eight im-
plication rules (i.e., elementary valid argument forms) and 10 replacement rules, for
a total of 18 rules. The rules provide the means by which the conclusion of an ar-
gument may be derived from its premises. See (1) implication rules and (2) replace-
ment rules.
informal logic. The type of logic in which the reasoning being studied is ex-
pressed in natural (as opposed to artificial) language. See (1) artificial symbolic lan-
guage, (2) formal logic, (3) logic, and (4) natural language.
31
propositions ‘Ja’ (“Allen is a jaywalker”), ‘Jb’ (“Billy Bob is a jaywalker”), and ‘Jc’
(“Carl is a jaywalker”). See (1) constant, (2) propositional function, and (3) variable.
intransitivity. A relation in which, if one thing has that relation to a second and
the second has that relation to a third, then the first cannot have that relation to
the third. Symbolically: (x)(y)(z)[(Rxy • Ryz) ~ ﬤRxz]. Examples: “is the mother of,”
“is the father of,” “is a child of,” “weighs exactly two pounds more than.” See (1)
nontransitivity, (2) relation, and (3) transitivity.
law (principle) of excluded middle. See excluded middle, law (principle) of.
32
is logically equivalent to “Everything is Ø and everything is Ψ.”)
• ‘(Ǝx)(Øx v Ψx)’ :: ‘(Ǝx)Øx v (Ǝx)Ψx’. (Translation: “Something is either Ø or
Ψ” is logically equivalent to “Either something is Ø or something is Ψ.”)
The first rule says (in effect) that a universal quantifier may be either distributed
to or collected from each of two conjuncts. The second rule says that an existential
quantifier may be either distributed to or collected from each of two disjuncts. See
replacement rules.
laws (principles) of thought. Three fundamental laws (principles) that are be-
lieved to be necessary and sufficient for “correct” or rational thinking. These laws
(principles) are the Law of Identity, the Law of Noncontradiction, and the Law of
Excluded Middle. See (1) excluded middle, law (principle) of, (2) identity, law (prin-
ciple) of, and (3) noncontradiction, law (principle) of.
lens. In categorical logic, the part of a Venn diagram that is shaded by an “E”
proposition. The term comes from geometry. See (1) “E” proposition, (2) lune, and
(3) Venn diagram.
logic. From the Greek word “logos,” which could mean any of the following, de-
pending on the context: statement, principle, law, reason, proportion, speech,
thought, word, meaning, or explanation. “Logic” is defined variously as (1) the sci-
ence (study) of logical implication, or valid inference; (2) the science (study) of the
methods and principles used to distinguish good (correct) from bad (incorrect) rea-
soning; (3) the science (study) that evaluates arguments or argument forms; and (4)
the normative study of reasoning. Based on this final definition, logic is concerned
with categories 3 and 4 in the following diagram:
Types of Reasoning
Theoretical Practical
(Issues in (Issues in
Belief) Action)
Empirical (Descriptive/Explana-
Types of tory) (The Real) (What Is) 1 2
Study of Normative (Prescriptive/Justifica-
Reasoning tory) (The Ideal) (What Ought to 3 4
Be)
33
logical equivalence (a.k.a. equivalence, mutual logical implication, mu-
tual strict implication, mutual entailment, and mutual logical conse-
quence). A logical relation between two propositional forms (or propositions).
Propositional form X is logically equivalent to propositional form Y (i.e., X and Y
are logically equivalent [to one another]) if and only if (1) it is logically impossible
for X to be true while Y is false and (2) it is logically impossible for Y to be true
while X is false. In other words, (1) X logically implies Y and (2) Y logically implies
X. In other words, X and Y necessarily have the same truth value. Colloquially, X
can’t be true while Y is false; Y can’t be true while X is false. Example: ‘p ﬤq’ is
logically equivalent to ‘~p Ú q’. See (1) logical implication, (2) replacement rules, and
(3) material equivalence.
lune. In categorical logic, the part of a Venn diagram that is shaded by an “A”
proposition. The term comes from geometry. See (1) “A” proposition, (2) lens, and
(3) Venn diagram.
34
major premise. In categorical logic, the premise that contains the major term.
See (1) major term and (2) minor premise.
major term. In categorical logic, the term that occurs as the predicate of the
conclusion. See (1) end term, (2) major premise, (3) middle term, and (4) minor term.
material equivalence.
material implication.
35
‘~p Ú q’. See replacement rules.
material implication, paradoxes of. The horseshoe symbol (“ )”ﬤis defined as
a material conditional, so ‘p ﬤq’ means nothing more (or less) than ‘~(p • ~q)’. All
this says is that, as a matter of fact, it is not the case that the antecedent is true while
the consequent is false. There are two paradoxical implications of this definition:
middle term. In categorical logic, the term that appears in both premises but not
in the conclusion. Contrasted with “end term.” See (1) end term, (2) major term, and
(3) minor term.
minor premise. In categorical logic, the premise that contains the minor term.
See (1) major premise and (2) minor term.
minor term. In categorical logic, the term that occurs as the subject of the con-
clusion. See (1) end term, (2) major term, (3) middle term, and (4) minor premise.
36
medieval logicians introduced for the valid syllogisms. See Barbara.
modus ponens (MP) (a.k.a. modus ponendo ponens, affirming the anteced-
ent, and mixed hypothetical syllogism). In propositional logic, a rule of infer-
ence (i.e., an elementary valid argument form) in which the first premise is a con-
ditional, the second premise the antecedent of that conditional, and the conclusion
the consequent of that conditional. Formally, ‘p ﬤq’; ‘p’; therefore, ‘q’. Modus Ponens
can be thought of as asserting the following: “Anything materially implied by a
truth is true.” See (1) elementary valid argument form and (2) inference, rules of.
modus tollens (MT) (a.k.a. modus tollendo Tollens, denying the conse-
quent, and mixed hypothetical syllogism). In propositional logic, a rule of
inference (i.e., an elementary valid argument form) in which the first premise is a
conditional, the second premise the denial of the consequent of that conditional,
and the conclusion the denial of the antecedent of that conditional. Formally, ‘p ﬤ
q’; ‘~q’; therefore, ‘~p’. Modus Tollens can be thought of as asserting the following:
“Anything that materially implies a falsehood is false.” See (1) elementary valid ar-
gument form and (2) inference, rules of.
37
among n individuals, i.e., an n-place relation. See relation.
38
class membership. If the claim is one of totality, then the proposition is universal
(‘No S are P’). If the claim is one of partiality, then the proposition is particular
(‘Some S are not P’). See (1) affirmative proposition, (2) “E” proposition, and (3) “O”
proposition.
nego. Latin for “I deny.” In categorical logic, the letter names “E” and “O” come
from the two vowels of the word “nego.” The “E” proposition is universal negative;
the “O” proposition is particular negative. See (1) affirmo, (2) “E” proposition, and
(3) “O” proposition.
“no.” The universal negative quantifier, as in ‘No S are P’. See (1) “all” and (2)
“some.”
39
(Ǝx)(Fx • Gx) (x)(~Fx Ú ~~Gx)
Obvertend Obverse
All S are P No S are nonP
No S are P All S are nonP
Some S are P Some S are not nonP
Some S are not P Some S are nonP
See (1) complement, (2) immediate inference, (3) predicate term, and (4) quality.
40
the triple bar (tribar). See connective, truth-functional.
overlapping quantifiers. Quantifiers that lie within the scope of one another.
Examples:
paralogism. Any fallacious reasoning. See (1) fallacy and (2) reasoning.
41
• For validity/invalidity, the method consists of assuming that the argument
is invalid by assigning the truth value true to each premise and the truth
value false to the conclusion. If this necessarily leads to a contradiction,
then the assumption (of invalidity) is false, which means that the argument
is valid. If it does not necessarily lead to a contradiction, then the argument
is invalid (for it will have been shown that it is possible for the premises to
be true while the conclusion is false).
• For consistency/inconsistency, the method consists of assuming that the
set of propositions is consistent by assigning the truth value true to each
proposition in the set. If this necessarily leads to a contradiction, then the
assumption (of consistency) is false, which means that the set of proposi-
tions is inconsistent. If it does not necessarily lead to a contradiction, then
the set of propositions is consistent (for it will have been shown that it is
possible for all the propositions to be true).
Peirce’s Law. The tautologous propositional form ‘[(p ﬤq) ﬤp] ﬤp’. See (1)
Peirce, Charles Sanders and (2) tautologous propositional form.
42
practical reasoning. Reasoning that culminates in action (as opposed to belief).
The reasoning is designed to help the reasoner decide what to do. See (1) reasoning
and (2) theoretical reasoning.
premise.
premise indicator. A word or phrase that indicates (but does not guarantee) that
what follows it is the premise of an argument. Examples: “since,” “because,” “for,”
“as,” “for the reason that,” “inasmuch as.” See (1) conclusion indicator and (2) prem-
ise.
proof. Demonstration of validity (in the case of arguments) or truth (in the case
of propositions). With regard to validity, a proof that a given argument is valid is a
sequence of propositions each of which is either a premise of that argument or
follows from preceding propositions of the sequence by an elementary valid argu-
ment form, and the final proposition in the sequence is the conclusion of the argu-
ment whose validity is being proved. See (1) indirect proof and (2) validity.
43
proposition. That which is asserted or denied by a declarative sentence. An ob-
ject of belief (“I believe that aliens exist”), nonbelief (“I do not believe that aliens
exist”), or disbelief (“I believe that aliens do not exist”). The meaning of a declarative
sentence. The bearer of truth value. Every proposition is either true or false, and
no proposition is both true and false. We may not know, in a particular case, which
truth value a proposition has; for example, it is unknown whether Abraham Lin-
coln thought about his son Tad just moments before he (Lincoln) was shot, though
it is either true or false that he did so. Synonym: statement. See sentence.
propositional calculus. The logical calculus (i.e., calculating machine) whose ex-
pressions are letters representing propositions, and special symbols representing
operations on those propositions, to produce propositions of greater complexity.
The operations are negation (symbolized by “~”), conjunction (“•”), disjunction
(“Ú”), material implication (“)”ﬤ, and material equivalence (“º”). See propositional
logic.
44
and ‘q’ are propositional variables. To avoid confusion, we use lowercase letters
from the middle part of the alphabet: ‘p’, ‘q’, ‘r’, ‘s’, and so forth. See proposition.
punctuation. In propositional logic, parentheses (“(. . .)”), brackets (“[. . .]”), and
braces (“{. . .}”) are used to disambiguate (i.e., eliminate the ambiguity of) ambiguous
expressions. For example, ‘p • q Ú r’ is ambiguous; it might mean a conjunction
whose right conjunct is a disjunction (i.e., ‘p • (q Ú r))’, or it might mean a disjunc-
tion whose left disjunct is a conjunction (i.e., ‘(p • q) Ú r)’). See (1) conjunction and
(2) disjunction.
quantifier. In categorical logic, the words “all, “no,” and “some.” In predicate
logic, the symbols “(x)” (universal quantifier) and “(Ǝx)” (existential quantifier). See
(1) “all,” (2) existential quantifier, (3) “no,” (4) “some,” and (5) universal quantifier.
45
quantity. A property of categorical propositions. The quantity of a categorical
proposition is either universal or particular, depending on whether the proposition
refers to all members or only some members of the class designated by its subject
term. If the proposition refers to all members, it is universal. If the proposition
refers to only some members, it is particular. See quality.
reflexivity. A relation that a thing must have to itself. Symbolically: (x)Rxx. Ex-
amples: “is the same age as,” “is equal to,” “is congruent to,” “is as intelligent as,”
“has the same color hair as,” “is a contemporary of,” “is a member of the same fam-
ily as,” “is identical with.” See (1) irreflexivity, (2) nonreflexivity, and (3) relation.
46
relation. A way in which two or more things (objects) stand to one another. (The
contrast is with objects having properties.) Here are nine important properties
(characteristics) of binary (dyadic) relations:
47
• Ryz) ﬤ and z, if x is is intransi-
~Rxz] the mother of tive.
y and y is the
mother of z,
then x is not
the mother of
z.
Nontransitivity ----- x is a friend ----- Friendship is
of y nontransi-
tive. (Sup-
pose x is a
friend of y
and y is a
friend of z; x
may or may
not be a
friend of z.)
Reflexivity (x)Rxx x is the Everybody is Sameness of
same age as the same age age is reflex-
y as himself or ive.
herself.
Irreflexivity (x)~Rxx x is the par- Nobody is the Parenthood
ent of y parent of him- is irreflexive.
self or herself.
Nonreflexivity ----- x loves y ----- Love is non-
reflexive.
(Some peo-
ple love
themselves
and some do
not.)
See the entry for each listed term (e.g., symmetry) for elaboration and additional
examples. See binary (dyadic) relation.
replacement, axiom of. An axiom (first principle) to the effect that logically
equivalent expressions may replace (be substituted for) one another wherever they
occur in a proof sequence. See (1) logical equivalence, (2) proof, and (3) replacement
rules.
48
replacement rules. In propositional logic, 10 rules (De Morgan’s theorems,
Commutation, Association, Distribution, Double Negation, Transposition, Mate-
rial Implication, Material Equivalence, Exportation, and Tautology) that allow re-
placement of one propositional form with another form that is logically equivalent
to it. The replacement may occur on a whole line or on any part of a line. See (1)
implication rules, (2) inference, rules of, (3) logical equivalence, and (4) replacement,
axiom of.
rules and fallacies for syllogisms. See syllogistic rules and fallacies.
scope. That to which a quantifier applies (or ranges over). For example, in “(x)Øx
• (Ǝx)Ψx,” the scope of the universal quantifier is “Øx.” In “(x)(Øx ﬤΨx),” the scope
of the universal quantifier is “(Øx ﬤΨx).” The universal quantifier has small scope
in the first example and large scope in the second example. See (1) existential quan-
tifier and (2) universal quantifier.
49
See (1) self-consistency and (2) self-consistent propositional form.
50
and some false substitution instances, each of which is an affirmative singular prop-
osition. See (1) predicate and (2) propositional function.
specific form.
51
1. The specific form of a given argument is the argument form that results
when each different proposition of the argument is replaced with a differ-
ent propositional variable. For example, the specific form of the argument
‘B ﬤG’; ‘G’; therefore, ‘B’ is ‘p ﬤq’; ‘q’; therefore, ‘p’, not ‘p’; ‘q’; therefore,
‘r’. For any given argument, there is a unique argument form that is the
specific form of that argument. An argument is valid if and only if the spe-
cific form of that argument is a valid argument form. To prove that a given
argument is invalid, therefore, one must prove that the specific form of
that argument is invalid. See (1) validity and (2) variable.
2. The specific form of a given proposition is the propositional form that re-
sults when each different component of the proposition is replaced with a
different propositional variable. For example, the specific form of the
proposition “The blind prisoner has a red hat or the blind prisoner has a
white hat” is ‘p Ú q’. See (1) component and (2) variable.
See (1) Aristotle, (2) Boole, George, (3) opposition, and (4) standard-form categorical
proposition (SFCP).
52
are P’ (known as an “E” proposition); ‘Some S are P’ (known as an “I” proposition);
and ‘Some S are not P’ (known as an “O” proposition). See (1) “A” proposition, (2)
categorical proposition, (3) “E” proposition, (4) “I” proposition, and (5) “O” propo-
sition.
Figure
1 2 3 4
AAA AEE AAIM AAIP
See (1) categorical syllogism, (2) figure, (3) mood, and (4) standard-form categorical
53
proposition (SFCP).
Inductive Arguments
Strong Weak
It is improbable that the premises are It is probable that the premises are
true and the conclusion false (or: It is true and the conclusion false (or: It is
improbable that the conclusion is probable that the conclusion is false,
false, given that the premises are true). given that the premises are true).
The conclusion follows probably from The conclusion does not follow prob-
the premises. ably from the premises.
Strength is the inductive analogue of deductive validity (and weakness the induc-
tive analogue of deductive invalidity). With respect to inductive arguments, the
terms “strong” and “weak” are (1) jointly exhaustive (meaning that every inductive
argument is either strong or weak); and (2) mutually exclusive (meaning that no
inductive argument is both strong and weak). Strength is a matter of degree; unlike
deductive validity, it is not all or nothing. Therefore, it makes sense to say, of an
inductive argument, that it is “almost strong” (implying that it is not strong), “very
strong” (implying that it is strong), or “somewhat strong” (implying that it is
strong). It also makes sense to say that one inductive argument is “stronger” than
another inductive argument (implying that both are strong). Strength is not a sub-
jective matter, in the sense of being dependent on what some or many people be-
lieve; it is an objective feature of an inductive argument, independent of what any-
one believes. It is about how the premises are related (objectively) to the conclu-
sion. See (1) cogency and (2) validity.
54
propositional form Y if and only if (1) it is logically impossible for X to be true
while Y is false and (2) it is logically possible for Y to be true while X is false. In
other words, (1) X logically implies Y and (2) Y does not logically imply X. Collo-
quially, X can’t be true while Y is false; Y can be true while X is false. Example: ‘p
• q’ is the superaltern of ‘p Ú q’. On the traditional (Aristotelian) interpretation of
standard-form categorical propositions, but not on the modern (Boolean) interpre-
tation, (1) the “A” proposition is the superaltern and the corresponding “I” propo-
sition its subaltern, and (2) the “E” proposition is the superaltern and the corre-
sponding “O” proposition its subaltern. See (1) logical implication and (2) standard-
form categorical proposition (SFCP).
substitution instance.
1. Any argument that results from the substitution of propositions for prop-
ositional variables in an argument form. See argument form.
2. Any proposition that results from the substitution of propositions for
propositional variables in a propositional form. See propositional form.
55
superaltern (a.k.a. principal and superimplicant). See subalternation.
syllogistic rules and fallacies (a.k.a. the rules of the syllogism). In categor-
ical logic, a set of three rules that enable the reasoner/arguer to avoid (formal) fal-
lacies. A set of higher-order statements laying down the conditions to which a
given syllogistic inference-pattern must conform if it is to be valid. What follows
are the rules for the modern (Boolean) interpretation of standard-form categorical
propositions (according to which only “I” and “O” propositions have existential
import):
symmetry. A relation such that if one thing has that relation to a second, then
the second must have that relation to the first. Symbolically: (x)(y)(Rxy ﬤRyx). Ex-
amples: “is a sibling of,” “exists at the same time as,” “equals,” “is next to,” “is mar-
ried to,” “has the same weight as,” “is a member of the same family as.” See (1) asym-
metry, (2) nonsymmetry, and (3) relation.
56
tautologousness (a.k.a. validity, logical truth, and analyticity). A logical
property of propositional forms (or propositions). Propositional form X is tautol-
ogous (i.e., X is a tautology) if and only if it is logically impossible for X to be false.
In other words, X is necessarily true. Example: ‘p Ú ~p’ is tautologous. See (1) tau-
tologous propositional form and (2) tautology 1.
tautologous propositional form. A propositional form that has only true sub-
stitution instances. A propositional form that is necessarily true, logically true, for-
mally true, or true by virtue of its form alone. In other words, a propositional form
that cannot be false. Example: ‘p ﬤp’. See (1) contingent propositional form, (2)
propositional form, (3) self-consistent propositional form, (4) self-contradictory
propositional form, (5) tautologousness, and (6) tautology 1.
tautology.
Any argument with inconsistent premises, while valid, is unsound, for sound argu-
ments, by definition, have true premises, and inconsistent premises, by definition,
57
cannot all be true. Any argument with a tautologous conclusion, while valid, is un-
informative, for the conclusion, being a tautology, is trivially true (e.g., “Either it’s
raining here and now or it’s not raining here and now”). See (1) contradictoriness,
(2) contrariety, (3) inconsistency, (4) self-contradictoriness, (5) soundness, (6) tau-
tologousness, and (7) trivial truth.
tilde. In propositional logic, the symbol (“~”) for negation. It appears immediately
before that which is being denied. See negation.
transitivity. A relation such that if one thing has that relation to a second and
the second has that relation to a third, then the first must have that relation to the
third. Symbolically: (x)(y)(z)[(Rxy • Ryz) ﬤRxz]. Examples: “is older than,” “is north
of, “is an ancestor of,” “is a descendant of,” “weighs the same as.” See (1) intransitiv-
ity, (2) nontransitivity, and (3) relation.
58
a tilde is added to each or (2) a tilde is subtracted from each. Formally, ‘p ﬤq’ :: ‘~q
~ ﬤp’. See (1) conditional and (2) replacement rules.
triple bar (a.k.a. tribar). In propositional logic, the symbol (“º”) for material
equivalence. See material equivalence 1.
trivial truth (a.k.a. vacuous truth). A proposition that is true by virtue of its
form (e.g., “All dogs are dogs”) rather than by virtue of its content, matter, or sub-
stance (e.g., “All dogs are animals”). See truth.
59
Squiggly (Contra- case that; constituent
Line dictory, it is false proposition
Denial) that is false.
•, &, Ù p•q p and q Dot Con- and; also; A conjunc-
junction moreover; tion is true
but iff both its
constituent
propositions
are true.
(The constit-
uent propo-
sitions are
known as
conjuncts.)
Ú pÚq p or q Wedge, Disjunc- or; either- A disjunc-
Vee tion (Al- or; unless; tion is true
terna- if not iff at least
tion) one of its
constituent
propositions
is true. (The
constituent
propositions
are known as
disjuncts.)
ﬤ, ® pﬤq if p Horse- Material if-then; A material
then q shoe, Implica- only if; conditional
Hook tion necessary is true iff it
(Condi- condition is not the
tional) (reading case both
from right that the first
to left); of its con-
sufficient stituent
condition propositions
(reading is true and
from left the second
to right); false. (The
not p un- first constit-
less q; ei- uent propo-
ther not p sition is
or q; mate- known as
60
rially im- the anteced-
plies ent; the se-
cond con-
stituent
proposition
is known as
the conse-
quent.)
º, « pºq p if and Triple Material if and only A material
only if q Bar, Tri- Equiva- if (iff); nec- bicondi-
bar lence essary and tional is true
(Bicon- sufficient iff its con-
ditional) condition; stituent
just in propositions
case; is are either
materially both true or
equivalent both false.
to
truth table (a.k.a. full truth table and direct truth table). An array (arrange-
ment) of truth values that shows in every possible case how the truth value of a
compound proposition is determined by the truth values of its simple components.
Truth tables have multiple uses:
61
• To classify propositions as tautologous, self-contradictory, &c.
• To compare two or more propositions as logically equivalent, contradic-
tory, &c.
• To test certain deductive arguments for validity.
See (1) compound proposition, (2) partial truth table, and (3) truth value.
truth value. The attribute by which a proposition is either true or false. Every
proposition, by definition, has a truth value. The truth value of a true proposition
is true and the truth value of a false proposition is false. See (1) proposition and (2)
truth.
unit class. A class with exactly one member. To every individual object there cor-
responds a unique unit class whose only member is that object itself. Socrates, for
example, is the sole member of the class “things identical to Socrates.” See class.
62
arbitrarily selected individual) is Ø; therefore, everything is Ø.” This may seem
sneaky, but think of it this way. If it were true that anything one reached out and
grabbed (with eyes closed) were a Ø, then it has to be the case that everything is
Ø. In other words, the only way the premise could be true is if the conclusion were
true as well. See (1) elementary valid argument form and (2) universal quantifier.
63
is unsound if and only if (1) it is invalid, (2) it has a false premise, or (3) it is invalid
and has a false premise. See (1) deductive argument and (2) soundness.
vagueness. A property of (some) terms. A term is vague when there exist “bor-
derline cases” such that it cannot be determined whether the term applies to them.
Examples: “democracy,” “obscenity,” “death.” It may be that most terms in a nat-
ural language (such as English) are vague. One motive for creating an artificial sym-
bolic language is to avoid the vagueness of terms in natural language. See (1) ambi-
guity, (2) artificial symbolic language, and (3) natural language.
Deductive Arguments
Valid Invalid
It is logically impossible for the prem- It is logically possible for the premises
ises to be true while the conclusion is to be true while the conclusion is false
false (or: It is logically impossible for (or: It is logically possible for the con-
the conclusion to be false given that clusion to be false given that the
the premises are true). premises are true).
The truth of the premises is incon- The truth of the premises is con-
sistent with the falsity of the conclu- sistent with the falsity of the conclu-
sion. sion.
The conclusion follows necessarily The conclusion does not follow neces-
(logically) from the premises. sarily (logically) from the premises.
The premises, if true, provide conclu- The premises, even if true, do not
sive grounds for the truth of the con- provide conclusive grounds for the
clusion. conclusion.
The premises are related to the con- The premises are not related to the
clusion in such a way that the conclu- conclusion in such a way that the con-
sion must be true if the premises are clusion must be true if the premises
true. are true.
The premises logically imply the con- The premises do not logically imply
clusion (i.e., the conclusion is logically the conclusion (i.e., the conclusion is
implied by the premises). not logically implied by the premises).
The argument preserves truth. The argument does not preserve
truth.
64
The conditional consisting of the con- The conditional consisting of the con-
junction of the premises as its ante- junction of the premises as its ante-
cedent and the conclusion as its con- cedent and the conclusion as its con-
sequent is a tautology. sequent is either a self-contradiction
or a contingent proposition.
The conclusion is implicit in the The conclusion is not implicit in the
premises. premises.
variable. In predicate logic, a symbol (lowercase “x” through “z”) that serves as a
place marker, serving to indicate where the various letters “a” through “w” (con-
stants) may be written for singular propositions to result. See (1) constant and (2)
singular proposition.
65
weakness. See strength.
wedge. In propositional logic, the symbol (“Ú”) for disjunction. See disjunction.
5
Strictly speaking, this proposition is ambiguous (and therefore in need of punctuation). On
one interpretation, it is a disjunction, the left disjunct of which is ‘p Ú q’ and the right disjunct of
which is ‘r’. On another interpretation, it is a disjunction, the left disjunct of which is ‘p’ and the right
disjunct of which is ‘q Ú r’. That the two interpretations have the same truth conditions does not mean
that there is no ambiguity. In any event, we will treat this proposition as a non-WFF.
66