Currie, Gregory - Image and Mind PDF
Currie, Gregory - Image and Mind PDF
Currie, Gregory - Image and Mind PDF
GREGORY CURRIE
A catalog record for this book is available from the British Library.
Preface page xi
Acknowledgements xxi
Film, 1895-1995 xxiii
Part II Imagination
Chapter 5 Imagination, the general theory 141
5.1 Perspective shifts 142
5.2 Simulation 144
5·3 Fiction and two kinds of simulation 152
viii
Contents
ix
Contents
In conclusion 281
Named propositions
Bibliography
Index
X
Preface
Hard is his lot, that here by fortune placed,
Must watch the wild vicissitudes of taste,
With every meteor of caprice must play,
And chase the new-blown bubbles of the day.
Dr Johnson
' See Noel Carroll, Mystifying Movies. See also George Wilson's Narration in
Light, for fascinating studies of particular films in which Wilson rejects the
tired categories of realism and illusionism usually trotted out to analyse "the
Hollywood Film". Some deficiencies in the methodology of contemporary
film theory are explored in depth, especially as they apply to the production
of particular film interpretations, in David Bordwell, Making Meaning.
xiii
Preface
new one that I have emphasized the connections between film
and other things; a framework for film that bore no interesting
relations to other arts and representational forms, and could not
claim explanatory success in other areas, would have little to
recommend it. But a framework of any merit must also help in
understanding film itself. The framework I offer does so. It en-
ables us to answer a number of specifically filmic questions:
What are cinematic images? What is the nature of our imagi-
native involvement with film? What is the truth in the claims of
so-called cinema-realism? How is time represented in film, and
what are the limits of this representation? What strategies does
the viewer use to interpret a film, and how do they relate to the
strategies we employ to understand verbal fiction?
For those familiar with contemporary film theory, some of the
answers I give will have an air of wilful implausibility. But our
judgements of plausibility are determined largely by our frame-
work of background assumptions; implausible theories can be
cogent, highly explanatory, even true, and background assump-
tions hopelessly false. I'll say something about how my as-
sumptions differ from those of film theory as recently practised.
The first assumption I reject is a conjunction: that psycho-
analysis, or some version of it, is correct, and that it is capable of
illuminating our experience of film. I happen not to believe this,
since I believe that psychoanalysis is false, not just in the sense of
getting a few things wrong, as relativity theory probably does,
but in the sense of being wildly, deeply and unrescuably false, as
Aristotle's physics is. And even if I believed psychoanalysis or
some version of it to be true, I would be sceptical of recent appli-
cations of it to our experience of the cinema. Of course the expe-
rience of cinema, like that of anything else, is a matter for
psychological investigation, and cannot be understood in a priori
philosophical terms. But the psychology we need is not psychoa-
nalysis - particularly not in the version of Lacan, about which I
shall say a little in a moment. Contemporary empirical psycholo-
gists and philosophers of language and mind have found a way
to pool their resources in the project called cognitive science. The
aim is to build plausible models of the mind and its functions
more detailed and specific than philosophers on their own could
xiv
Preface
devise, and more flexible and abstract than neuropsychology
alone could deliver. In contrast with the psychoanalytic program,
cognitive science combines rigorous and clear argument with a
commitment to the most demanding standards of empirical test-
2
ability we can devise.
Cognitive science is not a doctrine. While its practitioners
share broad assumptions, there is no one theory of mind which
all or a majority of cognitive scientists accept. The view of the
mind which I adopt here as a working hypothesis has certain
features I can lay out very briefly: it treats the mind as a hier-
archically organized structure with levels of more or less intel-
ligent decision making going on in it; it regards some of the
systems of the mind - visual perception, for example - as op-
erating in relative isolation from other systems and consequently
unable to benefit from certain information sources; it regards the
mind's knowledge of other minds as resulting not (or not only)
from the possession and deployment of a theory of mind, but
from the ability to make empathetic contact, an ability I shall
explain in terms of mental simulation. The components of this
view will receive appropriate elaboration as the steps in the ar-
gument require.
One particularly damaging consequence of the psychoanalytic
paradigm has been the tendency to think of film as an essentially
illusory medium, capable of causing the viewer temporarily to
think of the film world as real, and of himself as occupying a
place of observation within that world. Thus film theorists have
expended a great deal of effort in trying to show that the point of
view of the camera is usually understood to represent that of a
perceiving agent- that of a character, a supposed narrator or the
spectator, who is assumed to occupy the camera's position
through a process of identification.3 I shall argue in Part I that
, The contrast I see here between Freudian theory and cognitive science is not
accepted by everyone. See, e.g., Clark Glymore, "Freud's Androids".
3 See, e.g., Kaja Silverman, The Subject of Semiotics, p. 202: "The gaze which
directs our look seems to belong to a fictional character rather than to the
camera." See also Jacques Aumont, "The Point of View", p. 2: "The frame in
narrative cinema is always more or less the representation of a gaze, the
auteur's or the character's."
XV
Preface
films are not standardly illusionistic, and in Part II that it is sim-
ply false that the spectator identifies with the camera.
The second assumption of traditional theorizing about film is
the semiotic assumption: that there is a fundamental common-
ality between pictures and language. This is a belief that goes
along with the rejection of the hopelessly old-fashioned view
that, while words operate by convention, pictures operate by
similarity. On the semiotic view, all representation is conven-
tional, and the idea that pictures might in some sense be like
the things they picture is part of a benighted ideology of realism.
This assumption, unlike the psychoanalytic assumption, has
broad support across the intellectual community. A version of
it has been argued for by Nelson Goodman, and there are hints
of it in the work of the art historian Ernst Gombrich and the
perceptual psychologist Richard Gregory, whose views are con-
nected to Karl Popper's idea that perceptions are "hypotheses".4
The semiotic assumption has seen hard times, as people have
come up against awkward dissimilarities between the structure
of language and the structure of visual images.5 Yet it has shown
a remarkable tendency to persist, particularly in film studies.
Christian Metz, for example, recognized fairly early on that
there is nothing in the cinema corresponding to "a language-
system's characteristics and internal organization" .6 But he has
continued to apply the categories, or at least the terminology, of
linguistic analysis to film; he says, for example, that photo-
graphs lack the "syntactic components of discourse so numerous
in cinema", and he describes optical effects as "clauses of
speech" .7 And while the emphasis in film theory has moved
4
Popper is a self-proclaimed realist, but his views on perception seem to me
to undermine realism.
5
Gombrich, for example, has recently distanced himself from the semiotic rel-
ativism of Nelson Goodman's LAnguages of Art. But Gombrich's view that
pictures can be genuine likenesses sits uncomfortably with his insistence that
pictures are conventional. See his "Image and Code: Scope and Limits of
Conventionalism in Pictorial Representation", p. 12.
• Christian Metz, "On the Notion of Cinematographic Language".
7
Christian Metz, "Trucage and the Film", pp. 158 and 165. See also Jacques
Aumont et al., Aesthetics of Film, chapter 4·
xvi
Preface
away from the straightforwardly linguistic to the psychoana-
lytic, the impetus for this move seems to have come not from a
rejection of the linguistic model, but from the thought that psy-
choanalytic models are themselves language-like. Thus one of
the ideas that seems to put the psychoanalytic thinker Lacan in
favour with the film theorists is his claim that the unconscious
is "structured like a language".
I am of the contrary opinion: that pictures and language are
fundamentally distinct, that there is a sense in which pictures
are able to represent by means of likeness rather than conven-
tion. But it is important not to create a false dichotomy here
between those who think that works in pictorial media are
wholly understandable in terms of perceptual skills universal
across humankind and those who think that pictures require an
act of interpretation which by no means guarantees the same
outcome for everyone.8 If pictures appeal to basic perceptual
skills which are widely shared across communities and, as I be-
lieve, to some extent across species, there is still a good deal of
interpretive work left to be done once perceptual skills are de-
ployed. I take up issues of interpretation in the final part of this
book, where I argue for some fundamental commonalities be-
tween the interpretation of linguistically encoded works and the
interpretation of film and other pictorial media, despite the ex-
istence of the nature/ convention gulf which divides them.
So film theorists have misunderstood the relation between the
symbolic and the pictorial orders, and they have failed to pro-
duce a plausible psychology of the experience of cinema.9 But
the failures of film theory are more than failures of doctrine.
8
As do Norman Bryson et al., in their editorial introduction to Visual Theory.
9
This failure and the ones I discuss later are not exemplified everywhere in
theoretical writing on film, though the better kind of writing tends to be
critical rather than constructive. See, e.g., Brian Henderson, "Two Types of
Film Theory". There is also some spirited resistance to the Lacanian model,
as with Raymond Durgnat: "Film watching is no more phallic, self- (mirror)
centered, or voyeuristic than any other self forgetful activity, like reading or
listening to music" ("Theory of Theory -and Bufiuel the Joker", pp. 32-44).
In a review of Metz's Psychoanalysis and Cinema, Durgnat notes that Metz
"swallows Lacan bones, feathers, fur and all" (p. 6o).
xvii
Preface
They are also failures of style and of method. The failures of
doctrine cannot be fully understood in isolation from these other
difficulties.
It is frequently and truly said that writing in film theory has
a tendency to be obscure. There is also a great deal of unex-
plained jargon which is then used in so unsystematic a way that
no clear meaning for it can be inferred from its use. This failure
10
•o Others see the issue of clarity differently: Vivian Sobchack speaks of the
"sloppy liberal humanism that retrospectively characterized cinema studies
before it was informed by the scientific methods and technically precise vo-
cabularies of structuralism and semiotics"; Sobchack, The Address of the Eye,
p. xiv.
" See also Anne Friedberg's exploration of the relations between cinema and
shopping ("Les Fl4neurs du Mal(l): Cinema and the Postmodem Condition",
pp. 419-431).
,. Gilles Deleuze, Cinema 2: The Time-Image, p. 129. See also the discussion of a
"gravity-free world" in Rick Altman, General introduction to Sound Theory,
Sound Practice, pp. 3-4.
xviii
Preface
Out of context of course, and a translation too, but at least a
prima facie example of wheels idly turning. Not that we should
retreat to a narrow formalism, or insist that nothing useful can
be gained by comparing cinema with other things. But we must
pick our analogies with care and attend to the details of their
justification. We can learn a great deal about cinema, I shall
argue, by comparing the interpretation of cinema with that of
language and of intentional behaviour. But these comparisons
cannot be implemented at the level of vague likenesses that are
really nothing more than metaphors. Metaphors are useful for
certain purposes; they can also be extremely misleading. That is
especially likely when it is forgotten that they are, after all, meta-
phors, or when the investigator has lost a sense of the distinction
between the literal and the metaphorical.
Perhaps the most significant failure of method in film theory
has been the habit of appealing uncritically to controversial, and
sometimes poorly corroborated, theories from other disciplines.
This is evident in the move to connect film with psychoanalysis.
It is standard for film theorists to appeal casually to Lacan's idea
of the "mirror stage" as support for some theory about the
relation between film and the viewer, remarking simply that
Lacan "has shown" that such and such is the case.' 3 When some-
one appeals to a theory as if it were established fact it's natural
to suppose that there is a substantial body of evidence in sup-
port of the theory in question, and that this evidence is so much
a part of our common knowledge that it would be tedious to
explain or even to refer to it. But there is no such well-known
body of evidence in the case of Lacan' s claims about the mirror
stage. So far as I have been able to gather, there is no evidence
for them at all.' 4
' See, e.g., Laura Mulvey: "Jacques Lacan has described how the moment
3
when a child recognizes its own image in the mirror is crucial for the con-
stitution of the ego" ("Visual Pleasure and Narrative Cinema", p. 8o7). See
also Daniel Dayan, "The Tutor-Code of Classical Cinema", p. 441; and Chris-
tian Metz, The Imaginary Signifier, p. 6.
'• Jacques Aumont put it mildly: 'The metapsychological model elaborated by
Metz, Baudry and others around 1975 is not easily supported by empirical
evidence" ("The Point of View", p. 19).
xix
Preface
XX
Acknowledgements
The pleasures of writing this book have been many, and some
of them have to do with people and places. A draft was written
in 1991 during a year's sabbatical from the University of Otago.
It began at the Research School of Social Sciences at the Austra-
lian National University in Canberra; I doubt if there is a better
environment for philosophical research anywhere. The philos-
ophers there who helped straighten out my early ideas on the
subject I thank later. Here I thank Professor Tom Campbell, for
the use of his delightful house and exciting car. The writing
continued in Washington, D.C., and at the nearby College Park
campus of the University of Maryland, where teaching the phi-
losophy of film and talking to the excellent and friendly philos-
ophers helped to give the idea of this book a workable shape.
A first draft was completed in Cambridge, where the staff and
fellows of Clare Hall made us welcome. My special thanks go
to the president, Anthony Low, and to the bursar, John Garrod.
Through that year and on subsequent occasions I gave talks,
based on draft chapters of the book, at institutions as far apart
as Tromse and Sydney, San Diego and Sussex. A great many
people made important contributions to the discussions that fol-
lowed, and I have tried to incorporate their suggestions and to
shore up my position against their criticisms in this book.
Among those whose contributions I recall are John Bigelow, An-
drew Brennan, Neil Cooper, George Couvalis, Martin Davies,
John Haldane, Jane Heal, David Hills, Robert Hopkins, Ian
xxi
Acknowledgements
cognitive science, and very little to Freud and his followers. But
the strongest influence on this work is that almost obsessional
concern with realism so distinctive of the best in Australian phi-
losophy.
xxiv
Image and mind
Introduction: the essence of cinema
' Oaims about the aesthetics of film based on some supposed essence of the
media are still made. Sometimes they are very strained. Thus Stanley Cavell:
'The most significant films ... will be found to be those that most signifi-
cantly discover and declare the nature of the medium of film ... a feature of
the medium of film ... is film's power of metamorphosis or transfiguration.
In remarriage comedy, this feature ... is expressed as the woman's suffering
creation, which cinematically means the transfiguration of flesh-and-blood
women into projections of themselves on the screen. Hence the obligation in
those films to find some narrative occasion for revealing ... the woman's
body" ("Ugly Duckling, Funny Butterfly", pp. 222-223).
1
Introduction
I. 1 FILM AS REPRESENTATION
• I have no interest in distinguishing movies and films here, and I use those
terms interchangeably, always to refer to particular works, specified or un-
specified, within the medium of cinema. But a distinction can be made, and
might be useful in other, more aesthetically conscious contexts. See, e.g., Ger-
ald Mast, Film/Cinema/Movie.
3
Attempts to identify the essential features of cinema have not been very suc-
cessful. Gerald Mast's idea that projection is the essential feature of the cine-
matic medium is especially off the mark. Television's failure to achieve the
clarity, luminosity and size of the cinema screen is, as Mast concedes (ibid., p.
267), likely to be a temporary restriction that future technology will overcome
without resorting to projection. Nor is it true that projection ensures the past-
ness of the events we are watching (p. 266). And while projection may empha-
size the artificiality of cinema (p. 270), so would many other salient pieces of
technology devised to deliver an image; see text immediately following.
3
Introduction
a device you load film into, then plug directly into your brain
to give you visual sensations exactly like those you would get
if you were watching a conventionally projected film. Isn't that
cinema without the projection of an apparently moving image
on a surface? If so, what is essential to cinema is the visual
experience, irrespective of how it is delivered. Difficulties also
arise when we try to specify the more distant causes of the ex-
perience- the existence of animated film shows that the cause
need not be photographic.4 What, anyway, constitutes a photo-
graphic method? Creation of a series of images by exposure to
light? Expectant parents can testify to the cinematic, or at least
televisual, quality of images produced by ultrasound. What is
so special about light rays?5
But we need not get involved in a debate about what, exactly,
constitutes allowable methods of production and delivery for
the cinema in the ordinary sense of the term. Instead we can
shape a concept of our own to suit our theoretical purpose.
There is a group of artefacts, interesting and worthy of study
because of the problems to which they give rise, which we may
characterize in the following way. They are produced by pho-
tographic means and delivered onto a surface so as to produce,
or be capable of producing, an apparently moving image. Things
of that kind I am going to call movies, films or works of cinema.
As long as it is remembered that the expressions "movie",
"film" and "cinema" have here this quasi-stipulative use, we
can concentrate on the class of entities they name when so used,
and forget verbal issues. What I shall say about cinema in this
sense will be applicable in some degree to the plug-in, sonic,
and other nonstandard forms, as well as to real-life relatives of
film like television; but I leave it to others or another occasion
to work out precisely what degree that is.
Cinema as I define it is an essentially visual medium. Movies
may or may not present audible speech and other sounds as
well as visual representations, and such auditory accompani-
ments may or may not constitute part of the fictional content
4
The essence of cinema
the movie presents (sound, where it occurs, may be "intra-" or
"extradiegetic", in the favoured lingo). The auditory, as well as
the olfactory and the rest, are optional. Where these things do
accompany the visual component we have a work that is more
than purely cinematic; it has the features a thing must have to
be a cinematic work, and it has others besides.
The claim that the auditory is optional needs careful han-
dling; it is not the claim that we could delete sound from films
that possess it without loss to our understanding or appreciation
of them: an obviously false proposition. Nor is it the claim that
the sound possessed by a given film is inessential to it; we need
to distinguish what is optional for the medium and what is
optional for any particular work in the medium. Thus I take
it to be an essential (that is, an obligatory) feature of a film
with diegetic sound that it has diegetic sound; to run Lawrence
of Arabia without the sound would be to fail, in some degree,
to give access to that film. My claim concerns the medium it-
self, not any particular work that exemplifies it. That's just one
example of the difference between what is essential to a thing
which happens to belong to a kind, and what is essential for
belonging to that kind of thing. On one view, a person's origin
is essential to his or her identity; no one lacking the par-
ents Albert had could be Albert. But having Albert's par-
ents is not a condition for membership in the kind human
being.
I am not claiming that we would make better films if sound
were not available, or that films of the very best kind would not
employ sound because "being of the very best kind" means be-
ing an example of pure cinema, which in tum means having no
optional elements. Nor, finally, am I claiming that visual prop-
erties always or usually contribute more to the value of partic-
ular films than do auditory properties (a somewhat more
plausible claim than the others, but still controversial). Those
are all aesthetic claims, and mine is not of that kind; it is the
claim that a work without visual properties would fail, for that
reason, to count as a cinematic work of whatever value. Audi-
tory properties are not like that; they are optional so far as the
medium is concerned.
5
Introduction
6
The meaning of "determinate of a determinable'' should be clear from the
context. Another example: red is a determinate of the determinable colour.
6
The essence of cinema
7
Introduction
7
Sometimes the characters of fiction are real things, as Hitler is a character in
The Last Days of Hitler. There the cinematic images represent (in fact misrep-
resent) him pictorially. But this is not the typical case. There are also cases
hard to classify. Is Erich von Stroheim a character in Sunset Boulevard, played
by himself, a character of whom it is fictional that (among other things) his
name is Max von Mayerling?
8
This problem is not peculiar to film. In any medium that represents pictori-
ally, there are fictional representations: pictures and sculptures of imaginary
beings, plays that tell us about people who never lived and events that never
happened.
• For reasons, see my Nature of Fiction, chapter 4·
10
The essence of cinema
fiction, various things are fictional, and different fictions are dis-
tinguished, partly, by the different things that are fictional in
them. One difference between The Third Man and, say, Stagecoach
is that in the former but not in the latter, it is fictional that there
is a man whose name is "Harry Lime" who is engaged in var-
ious criminal projects, who has a certain appearance, who moves
in a certain way and who stands in a certain setting on a certain
occasion. How he looks, moves and stands are among his visible
features - or, more precisely, they are among the visible features
concerning which it is fictional that someone has them in this
film. How do we come to know that they are among these fea-
tures? We know that by looking at the screen, and recognizing
there an image of a man (Orson Welles) who looks, moves and
stands in that way. And the recognitional capacity we exercise
in order to do this is just the recognitional capacity we would
exercise if we saw a man in front of us who looked, moved and
stood that way. That, long-windedly, is the story about how our
knowledge that certain things are fictional in the film depends
upon the visual capacities we have to recognize the visible fea-
tures of things when we see them. And that is what it is for the
film's images to function pictorially in their representation of
the story."
'
0
On being fictional (what is sometimes called "being true in fiction") see ibid.,
chapter 2.
" For a somewhat more precise account of picturing, see this volume, Chapter
3, Section 3.1.
11
Introduction
This does not mean that the image is a pictorial representa-
tion; that would require it to be a pictorial representation of
2
something, which it isn't.' It is not, in particular, a pictorial
representation of fictional characters and things. And it is not a
pictorial representation of the fiction itself. A fiction does not
have the kinds of properties - shape, size, colour - that could
be represented pictorially. Saying that cinematic and other im-
ages function pictorially to present fictions is as close as we can
get to saying that they are pictorial representations without say-
ing something false. That is close enough for our purposes. It
will enable us to make all the distinctions we want to make -
especially that between functioning pictorially to present fiction
and functioning linguistically, which is how literature functions.
This will tum out to be a very significant distinction, as I argue
in Chapter 4·
Despite my scepticism about the idea that cinematic images
are pictorial depictions of fictional things, it will be convenient
to speak as if they are, and hence to blur the distinction between
being a pictorial representation of fictional things and function-
ing pictorially to present fictions. From now on I shall simply
speak as if an image represents Harry Lime, and represents him
pictorially as well as visually. Instead of speaking like that, I
could say that the image functions pictorially to present a fiction
in which a man called "Harry Lime" does such and such. But
that would be tedious.
12
The essence of cinema
are two representing functions that cinematic images can per-
form: the photographic and the fictional. Documentary films
perform only the first while fiction films perform both. A fiction
film, like a documentary, is a record of what happened in front
of the camera at the time the film was exposed. But with the
fiction film and not with the documentary, that record is in-
tended for the further purpose of presenting a fictional story. A
rough way to indicate the distinction would be to say that a
documentary has as its primary purpose the representation of
the real, whereas the fiction film uses representations of the real
to represent the unreal or the fictional. What the movie really
represents is determined by the causal processes which result in
the exposure of cinematic film, and not by intention.' 3 A film
may (really) represent something quite other than what its mak-
ers intended it to represent, as when we find evidence concern-
ing crimes or unsuspected historical information in casual
holiday footage. But however hard we look at a film, we shall
not find unsuspected fictional stories represented there; it is fic-
tional - presents a fictional story - only if it was intended to be
fictional.
What intention might a film maker have in giving us repre-
sentations of the unreal? The more or less traditional view is
that we are intended to "suspend disbelief" in the presence of
cinematic (and other) fictions. It has never been very clear what
the suspension of disbelief is supposed to be, but one result of
the use of this phrase has been that writers on cinema have been
able to claim that, in various ways and to various degrees, the
viewer comes to believe in the reality of these fictional events.
In Chapter 5, I argue that this is wrong, and that what is dis-
tinctive of the experience of cinematic and other fictions is not
belief but what I shall call imagining. In general, what is pre-
sented as fictional is what we are intended to imagine, and we
engage in the appropriate way with the fiction when what is
fictional and what we imagine coincide. ' 4
3
' For more on the role of causation in photographic representation, see this
volume, Chapter 2, Section 2.4.
'4 See Currie, Nature of Fiction, chapters 1 and 2; and Kendall Walton, Mimesis
as Make-Believe, chapters 1 and 2.
13
Introduction
15
Introduction
erature allows only two possibilities. In cinema we may have
events and characters presented not as fact but as the material
for make-believe, we may have actors and sets artfully contrived
to inform us of actual events or we may have straightforward
documentary film. Within the realm of the literary, we have dis-
tinctions corresponding to only the first two of these three.
16
Part I
Representation in film
F
ILM is said to be in various ways a realistic medium
of representation. I distinguish three kinds of realism
that might be attributed to film. Only one of them, I
shall argue, is correctly attributable. I also examine, and find
wanting, the idea that filmic representation is language-like
in structure.
Chapter 1
Arnheim is just one of many, now as in his own day, who say
that film creates illusion. Like others, he qualifies the claim, say-
ing the illusion is partial. I say film does no such thing; it creates
no illusion, partial or otherwise. Film has considerable powers
to engage and to persuade, but these powers are not accounted
for in terms of illusion. I'll argue in Part II that they are ac-
counted for in terms of imagination. In this chapter we shall see
that there are different kinds of illusions, and that claims that
film engenders illusion can be more or less plausible depending
on what kind of illusion is in question. I'll distinguish two kinds
of illusions film might be said to engender, concluding that it
engenders neither of them. Before I get to that, I need to distin-
guish claims about the illusory nature of film from other claims
which are sometimes made.
20
The myth of illusion
There is another kind of realism about film which has been his-
torically important and which I shall not discuss: the view that
films can be placed along a dimension of realism according to
whether and to what extent they represent deeply significant
social relations. 3 A fictional film might be said to be realistic in
this sense because it portrays fictional characters as standing in
social relations important for determining the outcomes of in-
terpersonal interactions in real life, and portrays the outcomes
of the characters' interactions as (largely) determined by their
3
Here I am grateful to George Couvalis.
21
Representation in film
standing in those relations. This seems to me a perfectly intel-
ligible sense of realism. The question of whether there are such
relations and, if so, what they are, is an important- perhaps the
most important- question of social theory. I leave that question
to be settled by social theorists, whose skills and knowledge are
quite different from those typical of film theorists and philoso-
phers.
22
The myth of illusion
23
Representation in film
I do not deny that it is possible for film to engender this sort
of an illusion on the part of a viewer. On a liberal enough view
of possibility, it is possible for anything to create an illusion of
anything else. But this mere possibility is not at issue when peo-
ple claim that film is illusionistic; rather, they claim that the
standard mechanism by which film engages the audience is il-
lusionistic, that the creation of an illusion of reality is a standard
feature of the transaction between film and viewer. That is what
I deny.
There are two serious objections to the idea that film induces
the illusion that fictional events are real and that the viewer is
directly witnessing them. The first is that film viewers simply
do not react in the way that people would react who believed
in the reality of the fictional events the film depicts? You have
only to reflect for a moment on how you would react if you
saw, or thought you saw, a threatening monster, or if you
thought yourself alone in a house with an axe murderer, or if
you thought you were watching someone about to be attacked
by an axe murderer, to see that your behaviour in the cinema is
quite unlike that of someone who really did believe in the reality
of the fiction presented.
There are celebrated cases of viewers reacting to a movie as
if they were in the presence of the thing it depicts, though
whether these cases belong to the history or merely to the folk-
lore of cinema I do not know. It is said, for example, that in 1895
a Parisian audience fled in terror during the showing of a film
by the Lumiere brothers which depicted the arrival of a train. 8
If it really happened, this is to be explained in terms of the
unfamiliarity of the medium to that audience; it sheds no light
on our standard and intended response to cinematic fictions.
viewer does not behave like one who merely suspects, or be-
lieves to some degree, that he or anyone else is in mortal danger,
or like one within whom belief is in tension with simultaneous
disbelief. If I even vaguely suspected there was a monster on
the loose I would leave the theatre immediately and call the
9
"[The viewer] certainly has to identify ... if he did not the film would be-
come incomprehensible" (Metz, Imaginary Signifier, p. 46). See also Nick
Browne, The Rhetoric of Filmic Narration, chapter 1.
•o For more on this see Chapter 7, Section 7.2.
" Christian Metz, for example, discusses how film creates "a certain degree of
belief in the reality of an imaginary world". He also says that "somewhere
in oneself one believes that [the events of the fiction] are genuinely true"
(Imaginary Signifier, pp. 118 and 72, emphasis in the original). Jean Comolli
says that "we want ... to be both fooled and not fooled [by cinema]" ("Ma-
chines of the Visible", p. 759).
The myth of illusion
" Thus Sally Flitterman: 'The look ... is an integral part of filmic structure.
The cinematic apparatus is designed to produce the look and to create in the
spectator the sensation that it is she/he who is producing the look, dreaming
these images which appear on the screen" ("Woman, Desire, and the Look:
Feminism and the Enunciative Apparatus in Cinema", p. 24 J). Christian Metz
emphasizes a number of differences between film and dream, but concludes
that "among the different regimes of waking, the filmic state is one of those
least unlike sleep and dreaming, dreamful sleep" (Imaginary Signifier, p. 128).
Representation in film
leave the theatre. Another disanalogy: in dreams the central
character is typically the self, whose acts and sufferings are of
central concern. But film watching is notable for its capacity to
suppress consciousness of the self in favour of the fiction, and
even those who claim that film "puts us in the space of the
action" would not, I suppose, claim that we imagine ourselves
to be active participants in the events portrayed. That both
dreaming and film watching frequently take place in the dark
is another irrelevant consideration; darkness is not typically part
of the experience of dreaming, though it does typically accom-
pany the experience of film watching. Besides, if people were
reduced to the condition of dreamers by film, they would not
be the noisy conversationalists I often find so irritating.
Perhaps in some way film watching is like dreaming; perhaps
everything is in some way like everything else. There does not
seem to be any substantial, systematic likeness between film ex-
perience and dreaming that holds out promise of serious ex-
planatory gains.
lengths. You are then suffering a cognitive illusion. But not all
illusions are cognitive. You may know the two lines are of equal
length and still be subject to the Muller-Lyre illusion: the lines
just look as if they are of different lengths. It is a common feature
of the many kinds of visual illusions that they are, in Zenon
Pylyshyn's phrase, "cognitively impenetrable": belief doesn't
make any difference to the way the illusory phenomenon
looks. 13
An illusion of this kind, which is what I am going to call a
perceptual illusion, occurs when experience represents the world
as being a certain way, when in fact it is not that way and the
subject does not believe it to be that way. My experience of the
two lines may represent the two lines as being of unequal
length, even though I know this experience misrepresents the
relation between the lines.' 4
Someone might claim that cinema is illusionistic in this per-
ceptual sense and not in the cognitive sense I have been consid-
ering up until now. My arguments so far presented against
Illusionism are ineffective against Perceptual Illusionism be-
cause they are designed to show we lack the beliefs necessary
to underwrite the claim of Cognitive Illusionism. I need different
arguments if I am going to oppose Perceptual Illusionism. I shall
'
3
See Zenon Pylyshyn, "Computation and Cognition: Issues in the Foundations
of Cognitive Science", pp. 111-132. See also Jerry Fodor, "Observation Re-
considered". This way of setting up the debate over illusion in film- in terms
of a distinction between cognitive and perceptual illusions - will do for our
purposes. Some writers are sceptical about the distinction, claiming that our
perceptual systems are cognitively penetrable all the way down to the sen-
sory periphery (see, e.g., Paul M. Churchland, "Perceptual Plasticity and The-
oretical Neutrality: A Reply to Jerry Fodor", especially pp. t83-185). The
most such arguments show, I believe, is that there is a continuum between
highly cognitive mental systems within which beliefs are formed on the basis
of other beliefs, and only marginally cognitive systems over which beliefs
can exert some slight influence. What I am here calling the cognitive and
perceptual illusions supposedly created by film would then correspond to
opposite extremes of this spectrum. The arguments I am considering here
are robust under shifts of framework from the dichotomy model to the con-
tinuum model. The continuum model is well argued in W. M. Davies, Ex-
perience and Content: Consequences of a Continuum Theory.
'
4
See Christopher Peacocke, Sense and Content, pp. 5-6.
29
Representation in film
5
' See, e.g., Jean-Louis Baudry, "Ideological Effects of the Basic Cinemato-
graphic Apparatus".
30
The myth of illusion
is a disparity between qualities of the physical material - the
strip of celluloid that passes through the projector - and the
qualities we perceive when watching the movie. In cinema we
watch images. But these images are not the strips of celluloid
themselves. Someone might say, "The celluloid and all the rest
of the apparatus is real, but the image is not; it is a product of
the mind." I want to argue that this dichotomy is false. There is
a sense in which the image we see on the screen is a product of
the mind, but that is not a sense which would justify our saying
that the image is unreal. What we see when we view a film is
a pattern of colour on a surface, usually a screen. That pattern
of colour is, I claim, really there. (For present purposes, I con-
sider black, white and shades of grey to be colours.)
Some philosophers think generally that colours are "not really
there" on a surface, and that when our experience represents an
object or surface as having a certain colour we are thereby sub-
ject to an illusion, because there are no colours to be there.' 6 It
would be a distraction to get deeply involved in this dispute
here; we are after all trying to see whether there are special prob-
lems associated with the idea of cinematic images. We could
proceed simply by ignoring ontological issues about colour al-
together and simply assume that colours, whatever they are, are
real things. However, it will be useful to say something general
about the nature of colour, for what I say about that will be
helpful when we consider the nature of cinematic movement. I
shall argue that cinematic images are real in just the sense col-
ours are real, so we had better establish what this sense is.
I take colours to be properties of surfaces, but properties those
surfaces have in virtue of their being a standard or normal pat-
tern of response to those surfaces on the part of sentient observ-
ers. Colours are, in Mark Johnston's phrase, response-dependent
properties, and in this they differ from properties like being
square, being tall, and being ten miles from Cambridge.' 7 These
6
' See Paul A. Boghossian and J. David Velleman, "Colour as a Secondary Qual-
ity". See also C. L. Hardin, "Color Subjectivism".
'
7
See Mark Johnston, "Dispositional Theories of Value". See also Philip Pettit,
"Realism and Response-Dependence". I am especially indebted to Pettit's
discussion.
31
Representation in film
last three properties are not response dependent because they
are not possessed by an object in virtue of that object's capacity
to elicit a certain psychological response. Of these three prop-
erties, the first is an intrinsic property: to tell whether something
is square you need look no further than at the thing itself. The
last two are extrinsic: whether you are tall depends on the height
of things other than yourself, and how far you are from Cam-
bridge cannot be discerned without taking Cambridge into ac-
count. All response-dependent properties are extrinsic but the
converse is not true, since being tall and being ten miles from
Cambridge are not response-dependent properties, though they
are extrinsic. Being funny is a response-dependent concept and
it is, consequently, extrinsic; things are funny according to how
people react to them, though it is not easy to say exactly what
reactions count as grounds for saying the thing reacted to is
funny.
We can now see how colour properties are different from
many other kinds of properties, while admitting them as real
properties of things. There is some tendency to express the pe-
culiarity of colours by saying they are less real than other prop-
erties, but I find it difficult to make sense of the idea that reality
admits of degrees. Better to put it in terms of a difference be-
tween that which is intrinsic and that which is in various ways
extrinsic. If people grow I shall no longer be tall, though my
height does not change; and if a comet affects our organs of sight
so that things look differently coloured to all of us, they will be
differently coloured though they do not change internally. Being
tall and being red are extrinsic properties of things, whereas
being six feet tall, and having such and such a constitution of
molecules on your surface, are intrinsic properties; changing
those properties would involve a change in you. But extrinsic
properties can be as real as intrinsic ones.
In order to establish the reality of cinematic images, it is not
sufficient to establish the reality of colours in general, for cine-
matic images might constitute a special case where there appear
to be colours but really are not. And there does seem to be a
difference between the image on the cinema screen and that on
32
The myth of illusion
33
Representation in film
able and nonacceptable conditions. My claim is just that, when
those peculiar conditions necessary to display the film hold, the
film image is really there.
34
The myth of illusion
of movement, perhaps that of a crowd of people running about.
Take away the movement and what is left that could constitute
a real image? If there isn't any motion, the real image must be
static. But what then is it an image of? Nothing, we will assume,
was stationary in the photographed scene. The image can hardly
be of people not moving. Is the image an undifferentiated blank,
with no representational features? Then it is not an image. You
might claim that, when there isn't even any apparent movement
in the image (a fixed closeup of a static object, for example),
then the image is real. But it is hardly credible that when I look
at a static cinematic image I am not subject to an illusion, but
become subject to one as soon as movement appears. Also, since
as a matter of fact few cinematic images are static, there would
be little comfort for the realist in the claim that static cinematic
images are real. To be a realist about cinematic images, you have
to be a realist about cinematic movement.
I am taking the view that cinematic motion is illusory to be
a version of the view that cinema involves a perceptual rather
than a cognitive illusion. Someone might argue that this sup-
posed illusion of cinematic motion is a cognitive, and not merely
a perceptual illusion, because most people who watch films ac-
tually believe they are watching moving images; it is only when
you reflect on the technical mechanisms of cinema that you re-
alize this is not the case. That may be true, but the fact is that
the appearance of cinematic motion does not go away for those
people who convince themselves that it is, indeed, an illusion.
If cinematic motion is illusory, then it is essentially a perceptual
illusion and only incidentally a cognitive one. That is why I shall
treat it simply as a (putative) perceptual illusion.
Before I consider the arguments about the reality of move-
ment in cinematic images, I had better clarify exactly what I
mean when I speak of "moving images". Strictly speaking, the
cinematic image is the whole area of illumination on the screen
during projection. We all agree, I take it, that this does not move,
unless, due to some mechanical failure, the projection equip-
ment starts to shift around. What moves when there is move-
ment of an image is a part or parts of this image; if we are
watching a shot of a man walking along a street, the part of the
35
Representation in film
image which represents the man will move from one side of the
screen to the other. Movement of this kind, which is what I am
concerned with here, needs to be distinguished from the move-
ment which occurs as a result of a continuous change in the
position of the camera during a single shot; the man might be
stationary relative to the background while the camera moves
with respect to him. This latter kind of movement introduces
somewhat complex considerations which I shall not attempt to
deal with here. Also, the movement with which I am concerned
here is not the radically discontinuous movement which might
be said to occur across shots, for example, when we see the
image of the man in one place on the screen in one shot, and in
another place on the screen in the next shot. All I am claiming
here is that there really is movement within a single shot taken
from a fixed perspective. That, obviously, is enough to contra-
dict the claim that movement in film is an illusion produced by
the juxtaposition of static images.
I had also better say a word on metaphysical background.
Arguments about motion, and about change generally,
sometimes raise deep questions about what motion and change
actually are. There are two basic and mutually incompatible
views about this. One, which I shall call three dimensionalism,
says that change takes place when a thing has a property at one
time which it, that very same thing, lacks at another. The other
view, four dimensionalism, says that change occurs when a cer-
tain temporal stage possesses a property and another temporal
stage lacks it, where those stages constitute temporal stages of
the same object. I don't believe there is anything in our common
belief about change which decides one way or the other between
these two theories, and nothing I shall say about cinematic
movement here is intended to prejudge which view is correcC 1
time, and the view that there are distinct but suitably related
temporal parts in different places. Both constructs I take to be
inconsistent with the view that there is, literally, no movement
of an image on the screen.
One way to argue that there is real movement of cinematic
images would be to adopt very liberal criteria of reality. In par-
ticular, if we could persuade ourselves that there is no clear
distinction between what it is useful to say and what it is true
to say, it would be easy to establish the reality of cinematic
movement. There is, after all, utility in describing a film by ref-
erence to the movement of the images it presents us with. Daniel
Dennett has recently advocated a kinder, gentler realism that
allows us to say that all sorts of things are real on account of
their usefulness. In Dennett's example, Smith and Jones claim
22
22
Daniel Dennett, "Real Patterns", pp. 27-51. I am grateful to Jerrold Levinson
for drawing my attention to this work, and for valuable discussion of the
topic of this chapter.
37
Representation in film
3
' This point emerged during discussion with Graham Nerlich.
The myth of illusion
unreality of cinematic movement. After all, when we listen to a
tape recording, there is no sound on the tape itself, but just a
pattern of selective magnetization. We would not conclude from
this that when we listen to a tape recording of music we are
subject to an auditory illusion. The claim of Perceptual Illusion-
ism is that there is no movement on the screen; for this, after all,
is where we seem to see movement.
An argument which might seem to favour Perceptual Illu-
sionism is the following: the supposed movement on the screen
is the product of our perceptual system, and cannot be thought
to exist independently of it. Suppose you described the events
on the screen from the kind of objective viewpoint we try to
occupy in physical science: you exhaustively describe the impact
of particles or waves of light on the screen, and you thereby
describe all the relevant physical events at that surface. But you
do not describe any movement of the kind we claim to observe
there; you do not describe any object as moving from one place
on the screen to another. So there simply isn't any movement,
since the objective description comprehends all the relevant
physical facts but describes no movement. It is only when you
take a subjective point of view and include in the description
the viewer's subjective experience of the screen that movement
enters your story.
This is a poor argument. It is parallel to a class of other ar-
guments that would establish the illusory nature of all our ex-
perience of what are called secondary qualities. Consider again
the case of colour; we describe the object from a physical point
of view exhaustively, including everything about the spectral-
reflectance profile of its surface, but we say nothing about the
way it looks; colour enters our vocabulary only when we include
the observer's subjective point of view in the story. So there are
not really any colours. There are those who welcome this con-
clusion, and say the experience of colour is indeed illusory; ex-
perience represents things as having colour properties when in
fact they do not have them."" But on the whole philosophers
resist such starkly revisionist conclusions, and I go along with
39
Representation in film
them. What a realist about colour should say is what I have
already said: colours and other secondary properties are real,
response-dependent properties of things. And so it is, I claim,
with the "apparent motion" of projected film; this is real, re-
sponse-dependent motion.
Perhaps the greatest source of resistance to the idea that cin-
ematic images are real is the idea that the apparent motion of
the image is not "tracked'' by any comparable motion of a phys-
ical object. As I have said, no particle or wave, or any physical
thing, moves across the screen as the image of Cary Grant
(seems to) move across it. But normally, when we say that
something moves, we can identify a correlated moving physical
object - or at least we have good reason to believe there is one.
If a person moves, then his body does also; if a car moves, there
is a mass of molecules out of which the car is constructed which
moves. Moreover, the movement of the person or the car su-
pervenes on the movement of the underlying physical object; a
person's movement logically requires the movement of his body
- similarly with the car and its constituent molecules. The move-
ment I have claimed for cinematic images is not like that. But
this is explained in terms of the basic difference between persons
and cars, on the one hand, and cinematic images on the other.
Cars and persons have relatively stable physical constituents,
while images do not. The movement of the image supervenes
on the pattern of light particles striking the screen. But the image
has qualities not possessed by any of the physical things and
events to which we appeal in explaining it: in particular, it has
movement. In just the same way, the colours on a surface are
explainable in terms of the physical properties of those surfaces,
and ultimately in terms of their subatomic constituents. But the
colour has qualities not possessed by any such constituent; the
greenness of the colour is not to be found in any greenness of
its subatomic parts.
So I say that part of the content of cinematic experience is that
there is movement of images, and there really is such move-
ment. We see the cinematic image of a man, and we see that it
is in one place on the screen, and we later see that it is in an-
other; indeed, we see that image move from one place to another
The myth of illusion
•s Remember that this question is to be taken as neutral between three and four
dimensionalism.
Representation in film
again, as with colour, the concept we appeal to is response de-
pendent. Identity between images is itself a response-dependent
concept, because questions about how to reidentify images
across time are answered by appeal to facts about the psycho-
logical responses of the viewer to those images. But just as with
colours, this response dependence is compatible with the reality
of the images concerned.
'
7
The McCullough effect produces an illusion of green or red stripes where
there actually are white stripes. Which colour it seems to produce depends
on the orientation of the bars (horizontal or vertical) on the cards presented
prior to the induction of the illusion. It is therefore called "an orientation-
specific color aftereffect".
28
See Richard Holton, "Intentions, Response-Dependence and Immunity from
Error".
43
Representation in film
sustained only at the cost of reducing, almost to nothing, the
class of phenomena that count as illusory. It is worth seeing that
this is not so.
Someone might claim that, by an argument parallel to the one
I have given for the reality of cinematic motion, we can establish
that the experience induced by the Muller-Lyre phenomenon is
veridical. In those cases of experience singled out as exempli-
fying the Muller-Lyre illusion, we are to say that what experi-
ence represents is the holding, between two lines, of the relation
being longer* than, where length* is not the metrical property of
objects we measure with rigid rods, but rather a response-
dependent length: a length which stands to metrical length as
the response-dependent movement I have been advocating for
cinematic images stands to the movement we measure by track-
ing physical objects across space. In that case there is no illusion
involved in the Muller-Lyre phenomenon, but merely the verid-
ical experience of one line being "longer* than" another.
This objection fails. Our experience of the Muller-Lyre illu-
sion represents the lines as standing in the relation "longer
than", not the relation "longer* than". The visible appearance
of the lines suggests that, were one to measure them in the con-
ventional way, the result would be that one was measurably
longer than the other. That is why this is genuinely a case of an
illusion, rather than a veridical experience of a response-
dependent property. With the experience of screen watching,
however, it is doubtful whether the movement our experience
represents as taking place is of a kind that would be undermined
by independent checks analogous to the measuring check we
can carry out in the case of the Miiller-Lyre illusion. Our ex-
perience of screen watching does not have this as its represen-
tational content: "there are reidentifiable physical objects
moving in front of our eyes" (a content the falsity of which
could be established by independent checks). Rather, its content
is: "there are images of reidentifiable physical objects moving in
front of our eyes." In this respect the experience of cinematic
motion seems not to be undercut by information from other
sources, and therefore to be crucially different from that induced
by the Miiller-Lyre setup.
44
The myth of illusion
'9 See Stuart Anstis, "Motion Perception in the Frontal Plane: Sensory Aspects".
45
Representation in film
would establish. But these cases are unlike that of cinematic mo-
tion. There are even kinds of motion which cinema sometimes
gives us and which are, or can be, illusory rather than real. For
example, films in 3-D display an illusion of depth; our experi-
ence of watching 3-D is such that objects are perceived as mov-
ing towards or away from the viewer when this is not the case.
The cinematic motion I claim to be real is not of that kind; it
belongs to the kind which psychologists call "motion in the fron-
tal plane".
But even within this restricted class of motion phenomena I
can make distinctions, for not all motion in the frontal plane will
count as real by my lights. It is well known, for example, that
if one looks at a point of light in an otherwise darkened envi-
ronment, the point will seem to shift around when in fact it
remains steady. The explanation seems to be that the appearance
of movement is produced by random eye movements which are
uncompensated for because the viewer has no visible frame of
reference other than the light source itself. 30 Now suppose that,
instead of looking directly at the light source, the viewer looks
at the image of it projected on a screen. Then the projected image
will seem to move around, just as the light source itself would.
And this, I claim, is a case of illusory rather than of real motion
on the screen. For the following is a necessary condition for
there to be genuine movement of an image: that at each place
on the screen occupied by the image as it moves, there should
be illumination at that place (and at the relevant time) on the
screen. But in the case we are considering, there will be only
one fixed and unchanging place on the screen illuminated, and
at many places on the screen where the image seems to be, there
will be no illumination. So here we seem to see movement of
an image where no movement exists. But in the case of what is
conventionally called the moving image of film, at the places to
JO I am grateful here to Sue Feagin and Dan Gilman for helping me to see the
significance of this phenomenon to my theory, and to Michael White, who
explained the details to me. The illusion described is called "autokinetic
movement". See E. L. Brown and K. Deffenbacher, Perception and the Senses,
pp. 412-415·
The myth of illusion
Cinematic images are unlike those of, say, painting; they are
temporary, response dependent and extrinsic in ways the im-
ages of painting are not. Still, cinematic images are real objects,
reidentifiable across time and occupying different positions at
different times during the viewing of the shot. Or, for those who
insist on a tripartite distinction between the real, the apparent
and the illusory, they are apparent, nonillusory objects. The ba-
sic mechanism of cinema is not, after all, based on illusion. Nor
do I believe there is any other substantial, interesting sense in
which cinema is a medium which creates illusions. Certainly, it
does not typically function to produce the cognitive illusion that
what is represented onscreen is real and present to the viewer.
Realism is a notion film theorists have been uncomfortable with
for a while. I shall argue in Chapter 3 that it has been misun-
derstood, and that it is an indispensable tool for understanding
the nature of film. Illusion, on the other hand, is something we
can well do without.
The conclusions of this chapter go beyond film theory to em-
brace general metaphysics. It is traditional to regard motion as
a paradigmatically primary quality, to be contrasted with those
secondary qualities which are in some sense observer depend-
ent, like colour. If what I have said here about cinematic motion
is correct, we shall have to acknowledge a kind of motion which
takes its place among the secondary qualities.
47
Chapter 2
There are people who say that the photographic method gives
the cinema the power not merely to represent the world, but to
present it. Exactly what this means may not be clear; I shall try
to make it clear. But note that this claim (I'll call it the Presen-
tation Thesis) and the argument it has engendered predates the
cinema, having arisen first in connection with still photography.
I'll begin by considering the claim just for the case of still pho-
tography. Later, I shall ask whether the claim is more plausible
when applied to the moving images of cinema. Most people who
argue for the Presentation Thesis restrict their claim to photo-
graphic images which have not been subject to substantial ma-
nipulation after exposure. I shall follow them in this.
One source of confusion has to be cleared up right away. In
the Introduction I pointed to the representational duality of film.
When we ask what is represented onscreen, there are two pos-
sible kinds of answers: "Ingrid Bergman and Cary Grant acting
on a set" or "two spies trying to foil a Nazi plot". The claim
that cinematography presents rather than represents the world
must be understood as the claim that it presents the real world
of actors, props, sets and locations, not the unreal world of fic-
tional characters. If the thesis is right, film presents us with In-
grid Bergman and Cary Grant, not with the characters they play
in the movie, for these characters do not exist. Photography may
have special powers, but it does not have the power to turn
nonbeing into being.
The imprint of nature
thing, paintings can be "of" things that do not and never did
' Andre Bazin, What Is Cinema? vol. 1, p. 97· See also Stanley Cavell, The World
Viewed. For remarks critical of the tradition see Joel Snyder, "Photography
and Ontology".
' "With the assistance of the camera, we can see not only around comers and
what is distant or small; we can also see into the past. We see long-deceased
ancestors when we look at dusty snapshots of them" (Walton, "Transparent
Pictures", p. 251). For similar arguments, see Roger Scruton, "Photography
and Representation". But Scruton, whose concern is mostly with the aesthetics
of photography, does not offer so precise an account of the difference between
photography and painting. See later in this chapter for an analysis of some
of Scruton's arguments. For an examination of the history of this problem,
see Patrick Maynard, "Drawing and Shooting: Causality in Depiction".
The imprint of nature
exist. You can see a painting of a dragon, but you cannot see a
dragon. Nor can you see a photograph of a dragon.
While Walton's thesis is straightforward, his argument for it
is subtle and depends on some technical notions in philosophy.
Accordingly, I shall spend some time in laying out the argument
and explaining the technical notions. The effort will be worth it;
the argument is a good and an instructive one, even if, as I
believe, it fails to establish its conclusion.
Walton's thesis is not Bazin's, if we take Bazin at his literal
word. Walton's thesis is not that a photograph of X is, or is
part of, X. It is not that, when we are in the presence of a
photograph of X, we are in the presence of X. It is just that
when we see a photograph of X we see X. Photographs are,
Walton says, "Transparent"; we see through them to the
things they are of (I'll call this the Transparency Thesis and
sometimes just "Transparency''). I shall argue that the Trans-
parency Thesis is not susceptible to many of the criticisms lev-
elled against other versions of the Presentation Thesis. But I
shall also argue that Walton has failed to establish a case for
Transparency, and that what is correct in his argument can be
accommodated by the view that photographs are representa-
tional, that seeing a photograph of X is a matter of seeing a
representation of X rather than of seeing X itself. The repre-
sentations photographs give us are certainly very different in
kind from those we get by drawing and painting, and these
differences are the product of differences between the ways
photographs and hand-made images are produced. But a pho-
tographic image is a representation.
A remark on terminology: to avoid lengthy formulations I
shall use certain expressions in a special way. I shall contrast
"ordinary seeing" with "seeing photographs", and sometimes
with "seeing paintings". In literal fact there is no contrast here,
because we see photographs and paintings in just the same way
we see other things - by looking at them. The intended contrast
is between seeing an object or scene in the ordinary way, when
the object is before your eyes, and seeing a photograph or paint-
ing of the object or scene.
51
Representation in film
3
"Normal" does not mean "average". Conceivably, a majority of all the pho-
tographs ever taken were so over- or underexposed as to put the relevant
counterfactual connections in doubt. I take "normal conditions" in something
like Ruth Garrett Millikan's sense: a normal condition for photography is a
condition for its proper functioning. (See Millikan, Language, Thought, and
Other Biological Categories.)
• See David Lewis, "Veridical Hallucination and Prosthetic Vision". The con-
dition of counterfactual dependence may not be sufficient for seeing; see Mar-
tin Davies, "Function in Perception".
53
Representation in film
X will display the visible properties of X in such a way that, if
those visible properties were different, the painted image would
be correspondingly different. If the building were differently
shaped the painter would paint a correspondingly different
shape on the canvas. But in the case of the painting, and not in
that of the photograph, counterfactual dependence is mediated
by the beliefs of the artist. The appearance of the painting de-
pends counterfactually on the appearance of the object because
the beliefs of the painter are similarly dependent. If the painter
were having an hallucination, thinking there was a pink ele-
phant in front of him, his painting would display a pink ele-
phant, not the actual scene before his eyes. With the photograph
things are different. Because of the "mechanical" way photo-
graphs are made, it does not matter what the photographer
thinks the object in front of the lens looks like; once the camera
is set up and the film exposed, the camera records the scene
before it. Imagine the same scene successively photographed
and sketched. Now imagine that the scene had looked different
in some way; in that case the photograph and the sketch would
both look different. Now imagine that the scene had looked dif-
ferent and the artist's beliefs about the scene's appearance remained
the same. In that case only the photograph would be different.
Both the photograph and the sketch depend for their appear-
ances on the appearance of the scene, but in the sketch and not
in the photograph, that dependence is mediated by the artist's
beliefs and other mental states.
We can extend this counterfactual dependence between scene
and photograph/sketch to a similar dependence between the
scene and my visual experience of the photograph/ sketch. Had
the scene been different my visual experience on looking at the
photograph/ sketch would have been different. But if the scene
had been different and the artist's mental states the same, my
experience of looking at the photograph would have been dif-
ferent, while my experience of seeing the sketch would have
been the same. In the case of the photograph, the counterfactual
dependence between the scene and the observer's visual expe-
rience is, we may say, independent of belief, but in the case of
the sketch it is not. That is why we might find, in the photo-
54
The imprint of nature
55
Representation in film
I shall look at this argument in some detail. Before that, I shall
briefly note one other argument for Transparency - and some
arguments against it. These latter arguments are prevalent, but
not persuasive.
57
Representation in film
graph is the result of a deliberate exposure at a scene chosen,
framed and focused on in a certain way, perhaps with the ar-
rangement of objects and the lighting organized for the occasion.
If the scene had not looked the way it did to the photographer,
she would not have chosen to take the shot. Again, this is no
objection to Transparency. For in this sense, ordinary seeing de-
pends as much on intention. That I organize the furnishing and
lighting in my study, together with the fact that I am so aes-
thetically sensitive that I refuse to look at anything disorganized
or badly lit, does not show that I do not really see my study
and its contents when I choose to look at it. Once I focus my
eyes in a given direction it is not, from this point on, up to me
what I see. The same holds for the photograph; once the shutter
is opened and the film exposed, it is not up to me what appears
on the negative.
We can see from this that the argument for Transparency is
not that photography is an entirely mechanical activity. So it is
irrelevant to point out against Transparency that most artistic
human activities are mechanical after a certain point, as with
piano playing: once you have hit the key, everything else in the
sound-making process is done mechanically. 12 The advocate of
Transparency need not be saying that photography is uncrea-
tive.
People who dispute the similarity between seeing photo-
graphs and ordinary seeing sometimes emphasize the relation
between seeing and the path of an uninterrupted light ray.
When we see in the ordinary way, even with the aid of lenses
and mirrors, light emitted by or reflected from the object seen
passes into our eyes. The lens or the mirror merely collects or
deflects the light rays. And when we see those stars that no
longer exist, the light from the stars enters our eyes. But with a
photograph, things are different. The light reflected from the
surface of the photograph into my eye is not the light that trav-
elled from the object to the photographic plate. Should we give
this as a reason for saying that seeing photographs and ordinary
" See Ted Cohen, "What's Special About Photography?" See also Jarvie, Phi-
losophy of the Film, p. 109.
The imprint of nature
seeing are not much alike? No. First of all, light is not essential
to seeing. It is true that, for our organs of sight to function
unaided, light rays must be reflected from an object into our
eyes. But there could be seeing in which light rays play no part.
Richard Dawkins raises the possibility that bats might have vi-
sual experiences qualitatively similar to our own, but caused by
their very different perceptual systems, which depend on bounc-
ing sound waves off solid objects.'3 I understand this is not likely
to be true of real bats/4 but we can imagine batlike creatures
complex enough for this to be a plausible story. Their visual
sensations, if they exist, are caused by sound waves instead of
by light - an odd idea, but not a confused one. Sonar is capable
of giving information about objects in a creature's local environ-
ment which is sufficiently detailed and up-to-the-minute for the
creature to build up a complex mental representation of its en-
vironment. This representation is informative in the way our
visual representation of the environment is. Super bat sonar is
not functionally dissimilar from our organs of sight; whether the
representations it gives are qualitatively like our visual ones we
cannot know, but there is no reason in principle why they could
not be. Perhaps we shall invent a device which emits high-
frequency sound waves, which can be fitted to humans as a
prosthesis and which gives us visual sensations as a result. Then
the blind would have their sight restored; they would "see" by
means of sound waves.' 5
You may respond that, while seeing need not involve light
rays, it must involve the uninterrupted transmission of
something functionally equivalent (modulo the purposes of see-
ing) to a light wave, and sound waves might do the job. It is
59
Representation in film
the idea of uninterrupted transmission that is important, not the
particular thing that does the transmitting. That normal seeing
and seeing through lenses and mirrors involves an uninter-
rupted light wave seems important because it is responsible for
some of the informational features of seeing I have described in
connection with bats and to which I shall return: the features of
seeing which enable us to place ourselves in spatiotemporal re-
lations to the things seen. That kind of information is obtained
from sight because the light ray is uninterrupted (though there
are other factors that contribute to this as well). And it is the
maintenance of uninterrupted light transmission which enables
us to track objects over time.
But what is responsible for an essential or quasi-essential
property of X need not itself be an essential property of X: recall
the functionalist's point that neural activity is not essential for
a sentient creature; it is merely what realizes, in us, those func-
tions required for sentience, functions which might be realized
in other ways. So perhaps something other than uninterrupted
transmission could give us the kind of information we normally
get from sight- a simple transducer for instance. Suppose there
is a screen which registers a pattern of light on one side and
emits a qualitatively identical pattern of light from the other-
all this done more or less instantaneously. Looking at the screen
would be just like looking through a window at an object be-
yond. The screen interrupts the light ray, but I think we would
say that when we look at it we see the object on the other side
(assuming the mechanism preserves counterfactual dependence
between our visual sensations and the appearance of the object
beyond). That our way of seeing involves the passage of unin-
terrupted light does not imply that all ways of seeing must.
What is important is that some mechanism make the required
connections. Light propagation (uninterrupted or otherwise) is
one such mechanism; there may be others.
So the fact that there is interruption of the light ray between
the object and my eye when I see a photograph of the object is
not itself an argument against the claim that I see the object
when I see the photograph. However, interruption raises com-
plex issues which will be dealt with later.
6o
The imprint of nature
6
' Walton, "Transparent Pictures", p. 265.
7
' Perhaps it makes a difference to your intuitions about this case whether you
assume the surgeon gives Helen visual experiences corresponding to what
he (the surgeon) sees, or whether you assume he gives her visual experiences
corresponding to what she would see if her eyes were functioning normally.
As Walton describes the case, the surgeon gives Helen visual experiences
"corresponding to what he [the surgeon] sees" ("Transparent Pictures", p.
265), and I admit at least some doubt about whether Helen could properly
61
Representation in film
If you say Helen is not really seeing in this situation, that
may be because it is difficult to imagine how the surgeon could
control the process to ensure the appropriate degree of counter-
factual dependence. Another case, designed to screen out that
factor, will make my point more clearly. Suppose Malebranche
was right and there are no genuine causal powers in natural
objects. God mediates between the scene and our visual expe-
riences, acting, in his benevolence, to maintain counterfactual
dependence. Under this supposition, we would, as Malebranche
put it, "see all things in God" - but we would still see. We
would see by a process which exhibits intentional dependence.
(If God's omnipotence seems to you a barrier to ascribing to him
actions and intentions in the way we ascribe them to mortals,
think of God as just very powerful, but not as omnipotent.) So
natural dependence is not necessary for perception.
Is natural dependence sufficient for perception? Walton
points out that it is not.' 8 A machine which mechanically gen-
erates descriptions of objects does not enable me to perceive
those objects, even though there is natural dependence between
features of the object and the descriptions generated.'9 So what
makes seeing photographs a way of perceiving objects but read-
ing mechanically generated descriptions not a way of doing so?
Perhaps it is a matter of similarities between investigating things
by examining pictures of them (either photographs or drawings)
20
and investigating them by looking at them directly. As Walton
notes, the discriminations we find it difficult to make in cases
of ordinary seeing and seeing photographs are quite different
from those we find difficult in examining a written description.
A house can easily be mistaken for a bam, and a photograph of
be said to see in that case. But if Helen is given visual experiences corre-
sponding to what she would see if her eyes were functioning, it is much
clearer that she does genuinely see, and under conditions of intentional de-
pendence.
8
' Walton, "Transparent Pictures", p. 271: "A process of discrimination counts
as perceptual only if its structure is thus analogous to the structure of the
world" (my italics).
9
' Ibid., p. 270.
"'Ibid.
62
The imprint of nature
a house can easily be mistaken for a photograph of a bam. But
it is easier to mistake "house" for "hearse" than for "bam". The
errors of ordinary seeing and seeing photographs are explaina-
ble by real similarities between things, but the errors of reading
21
are not: a house is really more like a bam than like a hearse.
It is these differences between pictures and descriptions which
allow photographs, but not mechanically generated descrip-
22
tions, to give us perceptual access to thingS.
We can now summarize the argument for Transparency. A
mode of access to information about things counts as perceptual
if and only if it (i) exhibits natural dependence and (ii) preserves
real similarity relations. Painting fails to satisfy (i), and the me-
chanically generated description fails to satisfy (ii), so neither is
a perceptual mode of access. Photography satisfies both, so it is
a perceptual mode of access. Seeing photographs enables us to
see the things the photographs are of. So photography is trans-
parent.
I have already argued that (i) is no necessary condition for
perceptual access (recall Malebranchean seeing). Nor are (i) and
(ii) jointly sufficient for it. The length of the mercury column in
a thermometer depends naturally on the amount of ambient
heat. And because small variations in the level of heat corre-
spond to small variations in the length of the column, the dis-
criminatory errors we make when looking at a thermometer are
similar to those we make when we perceive how hot something
is by feeling it on the skin; it is hard to make very small tem-
perature discriminations either by feel or by sight. So thermom-
eters don't "scramble the real similarity relations" between
temperatures. 23 If feeling (a degree of) warmth is a way of per-
" "Descriptions scramble the real similarity relations" between things, while
visual experience, either direct or by means of photographs, preserves them
(ibid., p. 271).
"' Ibid., p. 273.
3
' Most thermometers are gradated, and we judge temperature by matching the
length of the column with a numerical mark. In such cases, reading a ther-
mometer is much like reading a description. But if the gradations on my
thermometer have worn away and I have to judge temperature by height
estimation, we would hardly say that I perceive heat when I see the mercury
column.
Representation in film
24
I don't say we could not perceive heat in any way other than via the heat
receptors at the skin. If our eyes were so constructed that we had mono-
chromatic vision, and things looked darker the hotter they were, then per-
haps we would see heat (see Paul M. Churchland, Scientific Realism and the
Plasticity of Mind). Snakes, apparently, see heat (as Marty Davies pointed out
to me; see Peacocke, Sense and Content, p. 90n; and E. Newman and P. Hart-
line, "The Infrared 'Vision' of Snakes". I say only that we do perceive heat
through our skin, and not by looking at thermometers.
The imprint of nature
66
The imprint of nature
slice. But the egocentric information available in ordinary seeing is not ob-
tained by inference from the visual experience together with other informa-
tion. Clearly, there are all sorts of inferential paths to egocentric information
which do not count as perceptual paths.
3
' Photographs - particularly a series of photographs - can serve to inform us
about temporal change, when we combine them with information from other
sources. But as with egocentric information, the inferential paths are not per-
ceptual paths.
3
' It is instructive to compare the case of prosthetic vision via the surgeon
(Section 2.6) with the following case. The surgeon gives me visual experi-
ences, but he does not ensure a match between my visual experiences and
the scene before my eyes. Rather, he gives me visual experiences correspond-
ing to a collection of photographs he has taken at various times and places,
quite unrelated to the time and place I now occupy. I have no inclination to
say that in this case my sight has been restored.
Representation in film
68
The imprint of nature
34
They are natural representations because the processes by which they func-
tion exhibit natural dependence. They are representations because they are
used as such by us. I am not suggesting that something can be regarded as
a representation (natural or otherwise) without reference to human intention.
Representation in film
37
Ibid., p. 115.
38
"Should" in the sense of "having reason to be".
73
Representation in film
subject. But if, as I think we should, we reject the Transparency
Thesis, we undercut the motivation for this move. Someone who
holds Scruton's view ought to ask: apart from the claim that
photography is transparent, is there any reason to insist that the
expressive quality of a photographic image is dependent on its
subject in a way that the expressive quality of a painting is not?
One answer might be that the photographer I cinematographer
lacks control over her medium by comparison with the painter,
and that this lack of control is a barrier to expression. Indeed,
Scruton says that a photographer who aims for aesthetically sig-
nificant representation must also aim to control detail; but detail
is hard to control in a photograph, and if it is controlled there
are "few ways in which such intentions can be revealed in the
photograph" .39 The point seems to be that an audience cannot
tell, in looking at a photograph, which elements of detail were
determined by intention, which by accident. Again, this simply
is not true of all photographs and certainly not of all cinematic
images. A photographer can, under certain circumstances, con-
trol detail very finely, and can make it clear that the detail was
controlled. All that can be said is that detail is easier to control
in painting, where each brush stroke is, ideally, the product of
intention, and that, in painting, the intention to control is easier
to signal. But such an argument cannot establish that photog-
raphy is not a representational art: at most it establishes that it
is less rich in its representational possibilities than painting is.
Perhaps it doesn't even establish that. There are aesthetically
relevant features of works of art that depend for their effect
partly upon our recognition that they are difficult to achieve. In
examples of Chinese calligraphy, we admire the elegance and
smoothness of the brushwork, and we do so partly because we
realize how difficult it is to achieve elegance and smoothness in
a medium that requires the artist to work very fast - any hesi-
tation will result in a blotch of ink. It would be a misunderstand-
ing of aesthetic value to suggest that calligraphy would be a
better art if it employed a medium in which a greater degree of
control could be exercised in the production of a character; it
39
Scruton, "Photography and Representation", p. 117.
74
The imprint of nature
75
Representation in film
My opponent might grant this, and still insist there is an
asymmetry here: as I use the expression "of", being of, and rep-
resenting are relations that come apart in painting, but not in
photography. A painting can represent something other than
what it is of in my sense; and a painting can represent something
without being of (in my sense) anything. But a photograph must
be of something and what it is of is what it represents. A pho-
tograph cannot represent a unicorn, and if I dress someone up
to look like Saint Anne and photograph her, I do not end up
with a representation of Saint Anne, but a representation of (in
other words a photograph of) the model so dressed up; I end
up with a representation of a representation.
Consider the photograph of the model dressed as Saint Anne.
I think it is merely prejudice to say this cannot be a represen-
tation of Saint Anne. An exactly similar prejudice might have
been evident at the time people started using models to paint
pictures of biblical characters; a prejudice that would have
showed itself in the insistence that the painting represents the
model and not Saint Anne. We've now lost that prejudice (if we
ever had it) in painting, through habituation to the conventions
of the medium. The only argument I can think of in the case of
photography is that the relation of natural dependence between
model and photograph somehow precludes the photograph rep-
resenting anything other than the model. But consider an anal-
ogous case: the craft of hand shadows. By setting my hands in
a certain way and having their shadow appear on a wall, I pro-
duce a representation of Abraham Lincoln. 4 ' Here there is
natural dependence, just as in photography, between the
disposition of my hands and the shape of the shadow on the
wall. 42 Following the logic of the argument just given, we should
say that it is merely my hands that are represented, and not
Lincoln at all. That is not very plausible. Nor is it plausible to
deny that in cinema we have representations of the story's char-
acters. Natural dependence ought not to preclude a photograph
4
' I take the example of shadow play from Maynard, "Drawing and Shooting".
42
That is, if we keep fixed the beliefs of the shadow maker, the appearance of
the shadow will depend counterfactually on the disposition of my hands.
The imprint of nature
3.1 DEPICTIONS
Though philosophers have denied it, certain pictures do seem
to be like their subjects; not so like them as to be indistinguish-
able, except under very peculiar circumstances, but like them
nonetheless. Indeed, the denials of philosophers in this regard
have an air of paradox. The likeness we think there is between
some pictures and the things they are of is, of course, a matter
of likeness of appearance; no one is (or should be) claiming that
people and pictures of people belong to the same natural kind,
or have the same essence. So what is claimed is that certain
pictures and their subjects appear alike: that the experience of
looking at the picture is in certain respects like that of looking
at the subject. But how could philosophers be better placed than
ordinary folk when it comes to judging what experiences are
like others? Denying that pictures and their subjects can be alike
in this sense seems well beyond the competence of a philoso-
pher.
The sense in which pictures (or, as I shall sometimes say,
depictions) can be like their subjects is not merely a matter of
being "true to" the subjects. A description of a man can be ac-
curate, without the experience of reading the description being
anything like the experience of looking at the man. There can
be accuracy without likeness, as a description can be accurate
without being like its subject. When we read a description, we
may recognize what is being described, and when we look at a
depiction we may recognize what it depicts, but we do these
things in fundamentally different ways. To comprehend the de-
scription I deploy my linguistic capacities, my understanding of
the semantics and syntax of the language. To see that the picture
is a picture of a horse, I deploy my horse-recognition capacities.
That is, I use the same capacity to recognize the picture of a
horse that I use to recognize a horse.'
We recognize objects when we see them by recognizing cer-
' I think Noel Carroll was the first person to give this characterization of re-
alism; see his "Power of Movies". See also Flint Schier, Deeper into Pictures. I
follow Schier's talk of "triggering recognitional capacities".
So
Realism
81
Representation in film
3
I am indebted here, as elsewhere in this chapter, to the work of Flint Schier.
See his Deeper into Pictures, especially section 9·3·
Representation in film
has gone. We know that severing important connections be-
tween the two halves of the brain can lead to strange situations
in which one half "knows" something which the other half does
not. More and more, philosophers and cognitive scientists are
coming to the view that the mind is a complex system of hier-
archically organized subsystems, where information may regu-
larly fail to pass from one subsystem to the other. Crucially, the
subject herself may know very little about the overall architec-
ture of the mind or about what is going on in it. Indeed, we can
think of the person as constituted by a hierarchy (or complex of
hierarchies) of intelligent creatures or homunculi. The farther
down the hierarchy you go, the less intelligent is the homun-
culus carrying out the operations at that level, until we reach
the ground floor, where intelligence bottoms out into straight-
forward causal interactions where notions of information, rea-
son, evidence and inference play no role, and where everything
that happens is driven by brute causal powers in accordance
with natural law. The person or agent himself occupies the top
level of the hierarchy and is more intelligent than any of the
homunculi that operate at subpersonal levels. Many operations
of the mind are conducted by the person himself; judging that
there is a horse in front of me, or that there is a picture of a
horse in front of me, is something that I do. But a great deal of
mental processing can be thought of as conducted at a level
below that of the person or agent. The primary insight of the
homuncular or hierarchical view is that, when an operation is
conducted below the personal level, we are not driven to de-
scribe that operation in purely causal, nomological terms. We
can describe it as a task carried out for a certain purpose, em-
ploying information of certain kinds, and conducted within cer-
tain constraints of efficiency, reliability and so forth. That way,
we describe it as a task performed by a subpersonal homuncu-
lus.4
Back to horses, and to pictures of horses. When I judge that
there is a horse in front of me, I take into account a great deal
4
See, e.g., Daniel Dennett, Brainstorms; John Haugeland, "The Nature and Plau-
sibility of Cognitivism"; and W. G. Lycan, "Form, Function, and Feel".
Realism
5
Jerry Fodor, "Precis of The Modularity of Mind", p. 4· For modularity in per-
ception, see also Marr, Vision.
Representation in film
were evolving our present perceptual mechanisms, and we often
could not afford to wait for the slow, deliberative processes
which issue in such judgements as "There's a horse (lion, etc.)
around here".
Perhaps this view of picture recognition constitutes a sort of
illusionism about pictures. Taking seriously the homuncular
model of the mind, it suggests that there is a not-very-intelligent
homunculus in my visual system who is charged with the task
of matching the visual input with a series of stored models of
known objects and who is fairly easy to fool into thinking that
the visual input derives from a horse, or whatever object is the
best match he can find for the input. 6 But this is an illusionism
we can live with. It allows, exactly, that the person seeing can
recognize a picture as representing a horse without him sup-
posing he is actually looking at one. That way, we can be realists
about cinematic and other images, seeing recognition of the con-
tents of images and recognition of the objects they are images
of as fundamentally similar, without being illusionists about
such images?
In basing my account of depiction on the idea of capacities
for object recognition, I do not mean to suggest that recognition
of depictions depends on having a prior visual experience of the
things depicted. Sometimes it is the other way about; if I have
the capacity visually to recognize echidnas, that's because of my
exposure to depictions of them, since I have never seen an
echidna in the flesh. My claim is not that the capacity to rec-
ognize depictions of Fs is a capacity developed in response to
visually presented Fs. It is the claim that my capacity to recog-
nize depictions of Fs and my capacity to recognize Fs are one
and the same capacity, however acquired. But note that this
claim (call it the claim of capacity identity) is compatible with a
6
For more on this process of object recognition, see Chapter 4, Section 4.8.
7
As Daniel Gilman puts it, "If our perception of form, space and pattern is
largely fixed by these fast, automatic early neurological processes, there
is ... no need for illusion here; we typically have a variety of submechanisms
at play and the organism need not be fooled about what it is seeing just
because some of its mechanisms respond alike to picture and subject" (''Pic-
tures in Cognition").
86
Realism
weak version of the idea that really seeing things has what we
might call "recognitional primacy" over seeing depictions of
them. The weak thesis is this: that it is not possible to acquire
the capacity to see something in a picture unless you already
have the capacity to see something else in the picture, and ex-
ercise that latter capacity in coming to acquire the former one.
Let us say that when an F-recognitional capacity is acquired by
looking at pictures of Fs, it is acquired pictorially. Then, com-
bining the capacity-identity claim and the weak thesis, we say:
For every F, it is possible that the F-recognitional capacity is
acquired pictorially, but it is not possible for every F-recogni-
tional capacity to be acquired pictorially.
It is also a consequence of my explanation of depiction that
you cannot tell for certain whether something is a depiction just
by looking at it; something is a picture if it functions in a certain
way, and not otherwise, whatever its appearance. Thus we
might devise a hieroglyphic version of English in which little
icons replace names, thus: ~~~ is tall," where the icon ~ replaces
the name "Fred". The icon may look like Fred, or as much like
Fred as any picture looks like its subject. It may trigger your
Fred-recognition capacity in virtue of its likeness to Fred. But
the icon is not, in this context, a picture; it serves merely to refer
to Fred, and not to make any claim about him - the claim is
made by the sentence in which the icon occurs. And what is
claimed in this sentence about Fred depends not at all on the
spatial properties of the icon, but merely on its being a referring
device. 8
By explaining depiction in terms of visual capacities to rec-
ognize objects, I have confined the notion of depiction to vi-
sual media. That is certainly in line with our common
understanding of the idea of depiction. But having explained
depiction that way, there is a natural generalization of the no-
tion to other media. Thus, to consider a somewhat artificial ex-
ample, we can conceive an art of olfactory representation in
which smells are represented. How are they to be represented?
8
See Jerry Fodor, The Language of Thought, chapter 2. See also Zenon Pylyshyn,
"Imagery and Artificial Intelligence", p. 179.
Representation in film
All sorts of ways are possible, of course, but one natural way
would be simply to rely on the odour-recognition capacities of
the audience; when the artist wants us to recognize that odour
X is represented, he or she gives us a representation with
odour properties which trigger our odour-X recognitional ca-
pacities. That, roughly, is the function of the scratch cards
handed out to members of the audience at some showings of
John Waters's Pink Flamingos. Such a device is of questionable
usefulness or aesthetic merit. But film commonly and profita-
bly uses depictive representation, in my now-generalized
sense, along another dimension of perception: diegetic sound.
When the film represents, by means of diegetic sound, the
character speaking, we recognize what the character is de-
picted as saying by using our capacity to understand the
speech of others when we hear it. So film is realistic along (at
least) two dimensions: visual images and diegetic sound. By
contrast, the use of subtitles ·is not, in my sense, a realistic
mode of representation, a point I made briefly in the Introduc-
tion. When the film represents a character as speaking by
means of subtitles we recognize what is said not by our ca-
pacity to understand speech but by our capacity to read.
9
The term is due to Flint Schier. For a detailed and illuminating discussion see
his Deeper into Pictures. See also Richard Wollheim, Painting as an Art, p. 77;
and Crispin Sartwell, "Natural Generativity and Imitation".
88
Realism
,. See the excellent discussion in Jerrold Levinson and Philip Alperson, What
Is a Temporal Art?
92
Realism
'
3
We can order textual elements temporally if we want to, for example, by
time of composition. But neither that nor any other temporal order we could
impose would tell us anything constitutive about the work.
93
Representation in film
in this sense may have (one-place) temporal properties of du-
ration; the incidents that go to make up the fiction occupy a
definite amount of time. When specifying what is constitutive
of the work we may need to specify these temporal properties
and relations in precise or in imprecise terms. It is constitutive
of a certain movie that each shot lasts exactly a certain time.
Specifications of duration for a play are vaguer because theatre
is a performance art, and the duration of speech and incident is
to some extent determinable by the makers of each performance
- though in any actual performance each action or speech lasts
a precise amount of time.
We get the second of this trio of kinds of temporality in art
if we look, not for temporal relations within the work itself, but
for a temporal ordering of the observer's experience of the work.
I said that the constitutive elements of the novel are not tem-
porally ordered. Sometimes this is denied; but what people seem
to have in mind when they say that the text is temporally or-
dered is that the ordering of elements- nontemporal as it hap-
pens- induces a temporal ordering in the reader's experience of
the novel.' 4 And it is not just any old ordering of experience,
because the layout of the text, together with the standard direc-
tion of reading, imposes a specific temporal ordering. So it is
with at least some paintings, in that they require a temporally
ordered looking, with certain elements to be looked at before
others. They differ from literary works in that the preferred or-
der of experience cannot simply be read off from any order of
the visible elements themselves; those elements do not have an
intrinsic order in the way that words and sentences do.
In this experiential sense, works of any kind can be temporal,
though not all are; some paintings and some static sculptures
are not: for them there is no preferred ordering of experience. If
we are interested in whether a kind of art, rather than just a
particular work of that kind, is temporal, there is a distinction
worth making. Temporality in our first sense- temporality of
4
' As Gerard Genette says, "The narrative text, like every other text, has no
other temporality than what it borrows, metanymically, from its own read-
ing" (Narrative Discourse, p. 34).
94
Realism
5
' On strong and weak inherence see the Introduction.
95
Representation in film
Palace, wherein events earlier in the life of the Virgin are rep-
resented deeper within the picture space; and by special tech-
niques such as blurring and multiple exposure. Music, if it is a
representational art, can surely represent spatial and temporal
relations.
The capacity to represent the temporal- call it "temporality/'
- is one further good sense in which something can be a tem-
poral art. But as the examples just given show, it is a relatively
undiscriminating sense; it is hard to think of an art form capable
of representation which is not temporal in this sense. Note, how-
ever, that it is not so undiscriminating as to make every repre-
sentational work a work of temporal art. Paintings can lack the
kinds of narrative contents and associations that would render
them tempora~; in terms of our earlier taxonomy, temporalityr
inheres only weakly in painting. Later, I shall ask whether it
inheres weakly or strongly in cinema. But certainly it does in-
here in cinema; cinema makes the representation of temporal
relations possible. In fact the vast majority of films do represent
temporal properties and relations.
they describe take time, but the length of the time necessary to read the work,
or part thereof, is not in general a guide to the length of time taken by the
events narrated. Mieke Bal says that narrative writing is "iconic" because it
resembles its content "since both contain a lapse of time" ("Description as
Narration", in On Story-Telling, p. n6). But this iconicity is very weak com-
pared with the rich temporal correspondence possible in film.
97
Representation in film
whether this is so, for perceiver-relative homomorphicity is as
much as we shall need for present purposes.
Automorphic representation is subject to a somewhat differ-
ent relativity. What constitutes automorphic representation on
one occasion need not do so on another. Grant that the redness
of the name represents the redness of the thing named; but if
we don't care about precise shading, we shall not indicate the
precise shading of Fred by the precise shading of the name; it
is understood that having the name coloured some shade of red
represents Fred's being some (possibly other) shade of red. And
if being some colour or other is all that matters to us, then having
the name written in some colour can represent Fred's being
some colour. In that case, if the name is written in green and
Fred is actually red we still have automorphic representation
because it is not being green but being some colour or other that
does the representing, and it represents itself. The lesson: judge-
ments about whether we are dealing with automorphic repre-
sentation are hasty if they are made in ignorance of the level of
specificity at which we are operating.
Consider an ordinary kind of picture. Our picture contains,
let us suppose, a representation of Fred; that representation has
a part coloured red, and its being so represents Fred's tie being
red. So pictures contain parts that represent things, but the pic-
tures themselves represent states of affairs, though they do not
always represent actual states of affairs. The states of affairs they
represent may have temporal properties that are also repre-
sented, and there may be temporal relations between the states
of affairs that are represented. Those temporal properties can be
represented in various ways; that is, various properties of and
relations between the pictures themselves can represent those
temporal properties and relations. I have noted that it is com-
mon with painting for spatial relations between the picture's
elements to represent temporal relations between the events de-
picted, as with the cartoon's progression from left to right,
which denotes the progression of events from earlier to later.
Within the same frame, on the same canvas, and indeed, as parts
of the same picture, we may have several different events de-
picted, to be understood as occurring at different times, where
98
Realism
spatial relations between the depictions denote temporal rela-
tions between the events depicted (as in Filippo Lippi's tondo).
But with painting, temporal properties of events are not repre-
sented by temporal properties of representations, and the reason
is clear: painting is tempora~ but not tempora~, so it does not
have the capacity to be temporalc-
While painting is not a temporalc art, cinema, as I have al-
ready noted, is; temporal properties of cinematic representations
(images) serve to represent temporal properties of the events
represented. It is temporal properties of the cinematic represen-
tation that we mostly observe and rely upon in order to figure
out what temporal properties of the fictional characters and
events are portrayed. Similarly, it is by detecting spatial prop-
erties of the cinematic representation that we determine the spa-
tial relations between characters and things in the fiction
represented. That way, film depicts space and time. Film's rep-
resentation of time by time can be automorphic or merely ho-
momorphic. The represented fight lasts five minutes, and its
lasting that long is represented by the relevant representation
onscreen lasting just that long. It is the default setting for cine-
matic interpretation that the representation of duration in cin-
ema is automorphic; it is the assumption we start with, and from
which we move only when some aspect of the narration, some
clash with real-world belief or some combination of the two sug-
gests we should. In Passolini' s Gospel According to St Matthew
the representation of the Sermon on the Mount lasts a few mo-
ments. But changes in background and lighting suggest that the
whole performance lasted much longer and took place at vari-
ous locations. Here the context of narration and real-world belief
conspire to shift our understanding: the changes of scene were
meant to indicate something, otherwise they would not have
been made; landscape and lighting are, and are commonly
known to be, by and large locally stable; so what is probably
being suggested here is discontinuous shifting of place and
time.'7
7
' You might argue that what is represented here is not the whole sermon, but
just a few parts of it, and thus we can preserve the default setting. But
99
Representation in film
Automorphic representation is standard for duration. Is it
standard also for temporal relations of precedence, like occurring
ten seconds before? It may seem not. In film, ten seconds between
shots cannot usually be taken to imply that it is fictional that
the events represented in the first shot took place ten seconds
before the events represented in the second; jumps in time be-
tween shots are too common in film for that to be a safe infer-
ence. But remember that judgements about automorphism are
sensitive to the intended specificity of description. If what is
intended to be represented is the relation occurring some time
after, then a representation that occurs ten seconds after another
thereby occurs some time after it, and automorphism is pre-
served. Once again, however, the default setting can be aban-
doned, as when context suggests that the event represented next
actually occurs before the event just represented. Then we have
the flashback, about which there is more in Chapter 7·
Film has the capacity to represent the temporal by the tem-
poral, so it is temporaic. But film can represent the temporal in
other ways; one way is to have a character or narrator say that
this occurred twenty years after that, or for the words "twenty
years later" to come up on the screen. Fades and dissolves func-
tion as qualitative representations of temporality, indicating
some significant distance in time between successively narrated
events, where context may or may not tell us roughly how
much. A complication is that all fades and dissolves take place
in time, so there is a temptation to say that what we have here
is the joining together of temporal and other properties of the
representation to represent temporal properties of the events
represented - a kind of watered-down version of my tempor-
alityc condition. This may happen, but it is not generally so, and
it would be a mistake to suppose that it is so simply because all
cinematic effects take place in time. Suppose the dissolve takes
two seconds, and the effect of the dissolve is to signal "some
to insist on this move in all cases would be, in effect, to identify what is
represented with what is displayed, and that identification is hard to sustain.
There is a similar device in Clouzot's Wages of Fear.
100
Realism
time later". The time taken for the dissolve can be considered
to make a contribution to the representation of this temporal
relation only if it can be thought of as operating differentially.
That is, it must be the case that if the dissolve had taken less
time or more time, then the dissolve would have signalled a
correspondingly smaller or greater gap between the represented
events. In certain cases, especially when there are several quick
dissolves in succession, one can understand temporal represen-
tation to be working like that; a dissolve longer than the norm
for this film, or longer than the last one, might indicate a pro-
portionately greater time lapse. But if the sign saying "twenty
years later" had been on the screen a few seconds longer than
it was, that would have made no difference to the fact that there
is twenty years between the represented events, and time con-
sequently plays no representing role here.
So there are three kinds of cases: pure representation of the
temporal by the temporal; pure representation of the temporal
by nontemporal properties; and mixed (and, I believe, unusual)
cases where the temporal and the nontemporal conspire to-
gether to represent the temporal.
Sometimes when an art form is said to be temporal, what is
meant is that the form in question is especially adapted to the
representation of the temporal, that its capacity for representing
the temporal is peculiarly rich and subtle. The temporalityc of
cinema partly explains why this medium is said to be rich and
subtle in its representation of time.'8 Homomorphic and espe-
cially automorphic representations of the temporal make for
ease and flexibility. In film we get precise and detailed infor-
mation about temporal duration and relations, and only in the
most obscure narratives, like Last Year at Marienbad, does the
quality of temporal information become significantly degraded.
Yet even here there is, by comparison with, say, painting or the
novel, a rich structure of temporal information concerning the
8
' Gerald Mast may have had something like this in mind when he said, "The
cinema is the truest time-art of all, since it most closely parallels the operation
of time itself." See Mast, Film/Cinema/Movie, p. 112. Quoted in Levinson and
Alperson, What Is a Temporal Art?
101
Representation in film
duration of a remark, a gesture or a glance. It is relations of
precedence that are the first victims of subversive narration in
film, and they are the main casualties in Last Year.
This account of temporalityc employs only two of our three
basic notions of temporality; it omits consideration of the sec-
ond, the temporality of the viewer's experience (what I called
temporalitye>. In fact temporalitye is implicit in the account I
gave, for I have been assuming that the temporal prope~ties of
the work - shot duration and temporal precedence between
shots - is a guide for the viewer in working out temporal prop-
erties of what is represented. But that will be so only if there is
coincidence between temporal properties of the work and tem-
poral properties of the viewer's experience of the work. And so,
in general, there are. The viewer's experience of the shot lasts
just as long as the shot - assuming an attentive viewer. The
representation of the temporal by the temporal works because
of this coincidence, and if it started to break down in some sys-
tematic way - if cinematic images began to cause viewers to
have brief, unpredictable and unnoticed periods of unconscious-
ness- that kind of representation would be undermined.
Earlier I raised the question: does temporalityc inhere strongly
or only weakly in cinema? Only weakly if it is possible for there
to be a film in which temporal properties of representations do
not represent temporal properties of what is represented; oth-
erwise strongly. (Recall that this discussion is relativized to fic-
tion films, and that abstract filmic compositions are not in
question here.) I say that temporalityc inheres strongly in film.
Try to imagine a film in which the passage of screen time has
no implications for the relations between events represented.
Even if the temporal relations between what is represented in
successive shots is in all cases obscure (Was that a flashback?),
individual shots, so long as they last, must, in virtue of their
own duration, imply something about the duration of events
depicted, though the implications can be utterly trivial. If the
film image focuses steadily on the Empire State Building for a
period of time, we can infer that the building stood fixed and
unchanging during that time. Shooting in slow motion through-
out the duration of the film would avoid any automorphic
102
Realism
film, but clearly not automorphically. How, then, are they rep-
resented?
I think that absolute spatial properties are represented by rel-
ative spatial properties of representations, taken in conjunction
with background assumptions about what is normal by real-
world standards. Thus the relative spatial properties of cine-
matic representations function automorphically to represent the
relative spatial properties of what is represented, and nonauto-
morphically to represent absolute spatial properties.
This discussion should make it clear that the representation
of spatial properties and that of temporal ones in film are dif-
ferently implemented, and that the representation of space is
more difficult than that of time. The representation of temporal
properties is, for cinema, relatively straightforward, for two
reasons. First, time's one-dimensionality means that keeping
track of the duration and succession of onscreen events is rela-
tively simple, whereas the representation of objects in three-
dimensional space on a two-dimensional screen leads inevitably
to a degradation of information. Worse, cinema imposes a double
relativity on spatial properties, for it represents them perspec-
tively; it is relative spatial properties as perceived from a certain
point of view (namely, that of the camera) that are represented.
When the actor advances towards the camera against a fixed
background, the result is a representation of change in the ap-
parent relations of size between character and setting that may
not, and usually does not, represent any such actual change.
Something vaguely like this can, and occasionally does, occur,
for the presentation of time in film; I am thinking of Eisenstein's
"stretching out'' of the time it takes the soldiers to clear the steps
at Odessa in Potemkin. Perhaps this is a representation of the
time those events seemed to take for those participating in them:
a time distinct from that which those events actually took.' 9 But
this capacity of film to represent time in a quasi-perspectival
'
9
Perhaps, but actually I doubt it. In an earlier scene there is a similar, but
very brief, stretching of time, when a sailor breaks a plate. That occurrence
is not plausibly understood as representing the sailor's subjective perception
of the time involved. Rather, it is done for dramatic effect; so, I imagine, is
the scene on the steps.
Realism
"' There can be exceptions, as when the entire action takes place on Mount
Olympus and all the characters are gods.
" See Bordwell, Narration in the Fiction Film, p. 6.
105
Representation in film
scenery achieves something like coordinate-free representation.
(Of course any spectator always sees the action from a certain
perspective, as indeed we always see the real world from a cer-
tain perspective, namely our own. But this is not to be confused
with any supposed intrinsically perspectival nature of the me-
dium itself.) The third difference between film and theatre con-
cerns the mobility of the camera, which thereby provides a rich
source of information about the spatial relations between objects
and compensates somewhat for the limitations of perspective
and failure to represent absolute spatial properties automor-
phically.
.. Edward Branigan argues that the relation between the time of viewing and
the time of the fictional events themselves is conventional, on the grounds
that what one notices during the period of screen time varies across persons
and occasions (Narrative Comprehension and Film, p. 149). But this undoubted
fact has no tendency to undermine the claim that within a shot, the standard
relation between screen time and the time of fictional events is identity, and
its being so relies on no convention whatsoever.
lo6
Realism
It is in this way that the style called long-take, deep1ocus style
- a style which writers like Bazin have argued is inherently re-
alistic - extends the possibilities for realism in film; it enhances
our ability to detect spatial and temporal properties of the fiction
by using the capacity we have to detect those properties of
things in the real world. When discontinuous shots are edited
together, and when depth of field is limited within a shot, our
ability to exercise our visual capacity to detect spatiotemporal
relations between objects themselves is correspondingly limited.
As shot length and depth of field increase, that ability is given
greater scope. (Length of take and depth of focus are independ-
ent of one another, and long take and deep focus do not always
go together, as David Bordwell pointed out to me. But if I am
right about their capacity to enhance perceptual realism in film,
the combination of these two features constitutes something like
a stylistic "natural kind". It certainly explains the close historical
connection between them.)
In montage style, on the other hand, where there is quick
cutting between very distinct spatial (and sometimes temporal)
perspectives, these spatial and temporal properties and rela-
tions have, with greater frequency, to be judged by means of
inference from the overall dramatic structure of the film. Of
course, as my earlier remarks were intended to suggest, this is
a matter of degree; long-take style is more realistic than mon-
tage style, and montage style can itself be said to be more re-
alistic than some other modes of representation - certainly
more so than linguistic description. Unqualified claims that
long-take, deep-focus style is realistic should be taken as im-
plicitly relative to the class of artistic styles with which it is
most naturally compared, namely other cinematic styles, just
as the claim that elephants are large is understood as relative
to the class of mammals.
It is often remarked that deep-focus style is unrealistic in
that it presents us with an image in which objects are simul-
taneously in sharp focus when they are at considerably differ-
ent distances from the camera, whereas objects at compar-
able distances from the eye could not be seen in focus to-
107
Representation in film
gether. 23 But this does not seriously detract from the percep-
tual realism of deep-focus style. Deep focus, particularly when
used in conjunction with wide screen, enables us to concen-
trate our attention on one object, then to shift our attention at
will to another object, just as we are able to do when perceiv-
ing the real world. Since we are usually not very conscious of
refocusing our eyes, the similarities between viewing deep-
focus style and perceiving the real world are more striking
than the differences. With montage and narrow-focus styles,
on the other hand, we are severely limited by shot length and
depth of field in our capacity to shift our attention from one
object to another at will- though as I have said, this feature is
not entirely absent in montage style.
To summarize: film is, in one sense, a realistic medium. It is
capable of representing depictively, and thereby enables us to
use our visual capacities to identify objects in order to know
that those very objects are represented onscreen. Further, it is
capable of representing spatiotemporal relations between objects
in the same way; we use our capacities to identify spatiotem-
poral relations between things in order to know that those re-
lations hold between the things represented onscreen. And
long-take, deep-focus style is more realistic than some other
styles in that it allows for more of this kind of representation of
spatiotemporal relations.
., See, e.g., Patrick Ogle, "Technological and Aesthetic Influences on the De-
velopment of Deep-Focus Cinematography in the United States".
108
Realism
109
Representation in film
A representation R is perceptually realistic in its representa-
tion of feature F for creatures of kind C iff
(i) R represents something as having F;
(ii) Cs have a certain perceptual capacity P to recognize in-
stances ofF;
(iii) Cs recognize that R represents something as having F by
deploying capacity P.
So what is realistic for us need not be realistic for intelligent bats
or for Martians with their strange sensory faculties. Perhaps the
Martians would not, even after a period of familiarization, be
able to understand our cinematic narratives. But this admission
of relativity does not support the claims of Christian Metz and
others that there is a deep conventionality and cultural specific-
ity in our cinematic depictions. 25 We have learned to be sceptical
of those traveller's tales according to which humans from other
cultures find our styles of pictorial representation alien and un-
interpretable.26 Indeed, the existence of substantial cultural bar-
riers to the understanding of depictions would be surprising in
the light of evidence which shows that creatures belonging to
other species are capable of understanding the depictive con-
tents of photographs.27 And the undoubted fact that cinematic
25
"What is called the analogy, the 'resemblance' ... really lies within a whole
group of highly elaborate mental and social organizations ... and the appre-
hension of a resemblance implies an entire construction whose modalities
vary notably down through history, or from one society to another. In this
sense the analogy is, itself, codified" (Metz, "Cinematographic Language",
P· 584).
26
As Wollheim points out, people from other cultures would not be able to
make the mistakes they are said to make about perspective in the Western-
style pictures with which they are presented if they could not recognize
representational features of those pictures (Wollheim, Painting as an Art, p.
53). Work by Hudson which purports to show that black southern Africans
do not readily understand the depictive content of Western perspective has
been severely criticized; seeR. K. Jones and M. A. Hagen, "A Perspective on
Cross-Cultural Picture Perception".
27
In an experiment by Premack and Woodruff, a chimp, Sarah, was shown a
film of an actor trying to reach some bananas suspended above him; she was
then asked to choose from various photographs depicting further possible
moves in the attempt. Sarah chose the picture that showed the actor piling
110
Realism
crates underneath the bananas, thereby displaying her recognition that this
was the correct solution. The central claim of this paper - that chimps have
a theory of mind - must be treated with some scepticism, but the evidence
on which the authors built their theorizing - the ability of chimps to sort
photographs according to whether they represented a solution to the problem
in hand - is not disputed. See D. Premack and G. Woodruff, "Does the
Chimpanzee Have a Theory of Mind?"
211
"The very necessity of depicting a bulky three-dimensional object as a flat,
two-dimensional image testifies to a certain conventionality" (Juri Lotman,
Semiotics of the Cinema, p. 6). A version of this argument can be found in
almost every discussion of film semiotics. See, e.g., Robert Lapsley and Mi-
chael Westlake, Film Theory: An Introduction, p. 45· For more detail on the
notion of a convention, see this volume, Chapter 4·
29
See, e.g., Boghossian and Velleman, "Colour as a Secondary Quality". This
view goes back to Galileo.
111
Representation in film
conceptualize the world in ways that are inconsistent or incom-
mensurable with our own, and there is no rational way of choos-
ing between these rival conceptualizations. But none of these
possibilities- if that is what they are- is in any way inconsistent
with Perceptual Realism. That doctrine need claim only that de-
pictions in general and cinematic images in particular appear to
us as in significant ways the same as the kinds of things and
events they represent, and that it is their so appearing that en-
ables us to identify their representational contents.
112
Chapter 4
Languages of art and languages
of film
... the proper objects of sight are lights and colours,
with their several shades and degrees; all which, be-
ing infinitely diversified and combined, form a lan-
guage wonderfully adapted to suggest and exhibit to
us the distances, figures, situations, dimension, and
various qualities of tangible objects: not by similitude,
nor yet by inference of necessary connection, but by
the arbitrary imposition of providence, just as words
suggest the things signified by them.
George Berkeley
113
Representation in film
these uses may be unexceptionable shorthand: talk of the vo-
cabulary of an architectural style sometimes means just what-
ever devices are typically employed in that style. But sometimes
the usage suggests possession of a linguistic theory that can tum
casual connoisseurship into a powerful technique of analysis.
The suggestion is spurious. Art, architecture, film and the rest
have little in common with any of the uncontroversial examples
of language that have shaped our recent linguistic theorizing. It
is not likely, therefore, that linguistics will help us explain how
it is we use, interpret and appreciate any of these things. So I
claim, and so I shall argue with respect to the case of film.
This much is negative. But there is something important to
learn about film and the comprehension of it by comparing its
communicative aspect with that of language. That will prepare
the way for a theory of the interpretation of film developed in
Part III. So while this chapter rounds off the discussion of cin-
ematic representation with the thought that it is not linguistic,
quasi-linguistic or even remotely linguistic, much of its sig-
nificance will not be apparent until we compare the interpreta-
tion of texts and that of film in Chapter 8.
3
Tzvetan Todorov, The Poetics of Prose, pp. 1o8-1C)9.
• A kind of mirror image to this approach, deriving from the same universal-
izing conception of the mind, is Piaget's theory that linguistic ability is de-
rived from other more primitive and general human competencies, in
particular from "sensorimotor" abilities. For a lively - if partisan - account
of the collapse of Piaget's program under pressure from Chomsky's linguis-
tics, see M. Piattelli-Palmarini, "Ever Since Language and Learning: After-
thoughts on the Piaget--Chomsky Debate".
115
Representation in film
deaf children who employ sign language at just the same time
as in hearing children, with both groups going through a period
of pronoun reversal, confusing "you'' and "I" .5 There just is no
reason - apart from the initial plausibility and simplicity of the
idea- to suppose that mental structures designed to accomplish
one kind of task will be similar in any interesting way to other
such structures, or that a structure used for one purpose will
tum out to be used for others.6
If the view that there is a language of picturing is to be re-
jected, perhaps "there is another hypothesis to be considered: that
film is not to be analysed as a language, but as an example of
the broader category of semiotic systems. In that case cinema
falls within the scope of a more general theory that includes both
natural languages and a great deal else: everything, in fact, that
is a system of signs. If the hypothesis that cinema is a language
is to be rejected, perhaps we should consider the weaker posi-
tion of the semioticists - weaker because the hypothesis that
cinema is a language entails but is not entailed by the hypothesis
that it is a semiotic system. But I shall not confront the semiotic
hypothesis in any detail. One reason is that the generality aimed
for in semiotics has resulted in a great deal of taxonomizing but
little identifiable as theory. It has also never been made clear
what a "code" is supposed to be, though codes are what semi-
oticists are apparently most interested in finding. Nor is it easy
to read off a characterization from the examples offered. Among
cinematic codes there are, we are told, "the complex system
according to which the cinematic equipment (recording camera,
film strip, projector) 'reproduces movement' '',7 and "the rep-
resentational code of linear perspective" .8 It is hard to think of
a definition of code which would cover these two items and not
cover everything else. So a critical assessment of the semiotic
hypothesis would require us to figure out what the hypothesis
is, exactly. Or, if there is no clear hypothesis available, we shall
5
See L. A. Petitto, "On the Autonomy of Language and Gesture: Evidence from
the Acquisition of Pronouns in American Sign Language".
6
For more on Structuralism see Chapter 9, Section 9+
7
Christian Metz, Language and Cinema, p. 191.
8
Comolli, "Machines of the Visible", p. 135·
116
Languages of art and languages of film
have to devise a plausible hypothesis as a target for criticism.
That would be a lengthy undertaking, and I should like to avoid
it.
It is not just the vagueness of semiotics that makes me un-
willing to tackle it head-on. At least some of what I say in re-
lation to the hypothesis that there is a language of cinema will
count against semiotics as well. Semioticists seem committed to
the "conventionality" of the sign systems they investigate; this
assumption makes them hopeful they will discover a unified
theory of signs. 9 And in the course of arguing against the idea
of a language of film I argue that cinematic images are not con-
ventional signs. I have no quarrel with the claim that cinematic
images are signs, if that means simply that they are represen-
tations. But the nonconventionality of cinematic signs means
that talk of a system of cinematic signs is vacuous.
117
Representation in film
what advocates of cinema language would call "the same lan-
guage", for those transformations would impose a change of
meaning; any change in the appearance of what is on the screen
is potentially significant for our decisions about the content of
the story that is thereby presented. But with natural languages
there is nothing special or privileged about any visually specific
way of representing letters and words, as font and handwriting
differences attest. And there are codes in which you can write
English sentences using permutations of our alphabet, other al-
phabets, numerals or whatever.
Perhaps cinema language is so fundamentally different from
natural languages that no significant properties of the one are
attributable to the other. But if cinema language is so unlike
natural language, what is to be gained from treating it as a lan-
guage at all? True, we cannot conclude immediately from the
fact that there are differences between natural languages and
the supposed language of cinema that there is, after all, no such
thing as a language of cinema. There are differences, some of
them very striking, between the various natural languages. Ide-
ally, we would distinguish accidental from essential differences,
and if we found that cinema "language" differs essentially from
natural language we would conclude that the former is not, after
all, a language. But I do not know of any set of characteristics
generally agreed to be essential for a language. We could try
providing some, in the form of a definition, but that wouldn't
settle anything. We don't decide questions about whether this
or that is a cause by appealing to some definition of "cause",
for we are at the stage with the concept of cause where we are
testing definitions against cases, and not the other way around.
So it is with language.
I suggest another method. Whatever disputes there are about
whether this or that is a language, no one, so far as I know, has
denied that English is a language, or that any of the other things
we call "natural languages" are languages. Also, natural lan-
guages like English have been the objects of the most sustained
and systematic theoretical investigation into language. Linguis-
tics, in so far as it is a developed theory, is about these natural
languages. The hope of those who say there is a language of
118
Languages of art and languages of film
cinema is that they will be able to make use of a well-developed
theory - linguistics - in an area which is theoretically under-
developed." In that case the cash value of the claim that there
is a language of cinema depends directly on the similarity be-
tween film and natural language. The less like natural language
the cinema is, the less probable it is that linguistics will help us
understand it, just as the difference between atoms and social
customs makes it unlikely that physics will help us understand
society.
I shall argue that, in crucial respects, film is very unlike a
natural language. This will enable us to sidestep the definitional
question. If someone agrees with my conclusions and still wants
to say there is a language of film, I shall not argue with her
choice of words. All that matters to me will have been conceded:
that there is insufficient similarity between this "language" and
any natural language for us to expect progress to be made in
understanding the cinema by applying to it linguistics or any
theory that adopts the principles and techniques of linguistics.
The question I am raising here is about the transferability of a
theory, not about the appropriateness of a word.
While I shall be sceptical throughout this chapter about the
relevance of linguistics to film theory, I don't want to imply any
comparable hostility to philosophy of language as a useful tool
in this area. Much of what we class as philosophy of language
is concerned with arguments and conclusions that are not, after
all, specific to language, but which apply to linguistic and non-
linguistic forms of communication alike. And while cinema is
not a linguistic medium, it is essentially a mode of communi-
cation between a story-teller and an audience; more on this in
Part III. Philosophy of language is not exhausted by any single
theory, and within it there is fundamental disagreement about
the nature of language and about the possibility of nonlinguistic
thought and communication. My application of philosophy of
" Metz seems to have thought of it that way: "The methods of linguis-
tics ... provide ... a constant and precious aid in establishing units that,
though they are still very approximate, are liable over time ... to become
progressively refined" (Christian Metz, "Some Points in the Semiotics of Cin-
ema", p. 176).
119
Representation in film
language to film will be the application of a particular contest-
able theory. It will be important to bear this in mind in assessing
my conclusions.
One important aspect of the argument to follow is that lan-
guage and meaning are by no means coextensive; there can be
meaning which is not linguistic meaning. The fault of those who
find language everywhere is that they infer the presence of lan-
guage from the presence of meaning.
120
Languages of art and languages of film
'
3
See David K. Lewis, Convention. I have presented Lewis's account of conven-
tion in language as if it were of the conventionality of words. In fact there
are problems in extending his account from whole sentences to sentential
components. But these problems are, I take it, problems of detail rather than
of principle. The best work I know on this is Timothy Irwin's unpublished
M.A. thesis, Meaning and Convention.
121
Representation in film
being learned sentence by sentence, since in a language which
displays productivity, speakers understand sentences to which
they have had no previous exposure. So meanings in our lan-
guage, if they are to be learned at all, must be specified recur-
sively: we start with a set of conventions that assign meanings
to a finite stock of words, and we combine words into further
meaningful units (e.g., sentences) by rules of composition, which
tell us how the meaning of the whole depends on the meanings
of the parts.' 4 Thus our language is molecular: its sentences are
built out of independently meaningful units - what I shall call
meaning atoms- by rules that assign meanings to complexes as
a function of the meanings of the basic parts. Words are our
atoms; they are meaningful, and they contribute to the meanings
of larger units to which they belong, but they themselves have
no meaningful parts.'5
Since the atoms- words in English- are assigned meanings
individually, and since the composition rules make the meaning
of the whole a function of the meanings of the parts, meaning
in our language is acontextual. The meaning of a given word is
determined by its meaning convention- not by the meanings
of other words, and not by anything else- and the meanings of
sentences depend only on the meanings of the words in them.' 6
In sum, our language is productive and conventional, so its
meaning-determining conventions are recursive, so it has mean-
ing atoms, so it is molecular, so it is acontextual. A great deal
in the argument that follows will depend on these entailments.
As I have already stressed, none of this is definitive of Ian-
4
' I don't say we learn our language entirely from the bottom up. No doubt
we start with simple sentences, shake out the word meanings by decompo-
sition, and zigzag back and forth, continually expanding our competence in
a way governed partly by trial and error. What is claimed is simply that if
the meanings of linguistic units could not, in principle, be stated recursively
the language would not be learnable.
'
5
Not every word is an atom, as when a single word has a meaning that is a
function of the meaning of other words and operators, as with "invalid".
6
' This account of meaning in natural language contradicts the structuralist's
claim that linguistic meaning is wholly a matter of a sign's relations to other
signs. That is as it should be; a change in the meaning of one term does not
induce a change in the meanings of all terms.
122
Languages of art and languages of film
guage; there might be languages that are either not productive,
or not conventional, or neither.' 7 But if there is, for cinema, any-
thing that plays a language-like role, it would surely be pro-
ductive; there is an unlimited number of things that can be
conveyed by cinema images. New films do not simply recycle a
fixed stock of images; they present us with new images which,
by and large, we have no special problem understanding.' 8 And
the people who claim that there is a language of film emphasize
the contingency and conventionality of that language, the degree
of its social and cultural determination. (I shall suggest that
there is some confusion on their parts about what this conven-
tionality amounts to.) So advocates of cinema language will hold
to the idea that this language, or any one of the possibly many
cinematic languages, is both productive and conventional. But
that, as I have argued, means that a language of cinema must
also be recursive, molecular and acontextual.
I shall argue that there is nothing in cinema that satisfies all
these requirements, or anything vaguely like them. One objec-
tion no doubt forming already in the minds of cinema-language
advocates is that my account of meaning in natural language is
too narrowly mechanistic to be plausible for the natural Ian-
7
' Perhaps the language of thought, if there is one, is productive and noncon-
ventional. Perhaps Wittgenstein's "block", "pillar'', "slab", "beam" language
described at the beginning of the Investigations is conventional and nonpro-
ductive. Productivity seems to be more important than conventionality for
characterizing what is special about human languages. There is some evi-
dence that chimpanzees can employ rudimentary systems of arbitrary sym-
bols (see, e.g., D. Premack, "Minds with and without Language"; and S.
Savage-Rumbaugh et al., "Spontaneous Symbol Acquisition and Communi-
cative Use by Pigmy Chimpanzees Pan paniscus"), but their use shows little
sign of productivity (seeM. C. Corballis, "On the Evolution of Language and
Generativity"). For an overview, see David Premack, Gavagai! Or the Future
History of the Animal lAnguage Controversy.
8
' If you doubt this, carry out an experiment recommended by Irving Bieder-
man: "Turn on your TV with the sound off. Now change channels with your
eyes closed. At each new channel, blink quickly. As the picture appears, you
will typically experience little effort and delay ... in interpreting the image,
even though it is one you did not expect and even though you have not
previously seen its precise form." "Higher-Level Vision"; page references are
to the partial reprint, here and in note 29, as "Visual Object Recognition".
123
Representation in film
guage case, and so it cannot be the basis for any significant
attack on the idea of cinema language. So I had better try to
dispel at least some of the more obvious objections to the ac-
count of natural language just given.
'
9
Alternatively we can say that in such cases there are two distinct but iden-
tically spelled words, each with its own (unique) meaning convention at-
tached.
125
Representation in film
ticularly discreditable action of Harold's and as part of a con-
versation about Harold's character, might convey the thought
that Harold is given to scheming self-aggrandizement. But the
sentence "Harold is a snake" does not mean that.
But in that case, why postulate literal meanings? Why not be
content with a single category of meaning: the context-
dependent meaning of the utterance? Some literary theorists
have recently taken that option. But it is not a viable one. It is
20
20
See Stanley Fish, Is There a Text in This Class? and Doing What Comes Naturally.
See also my "Text without Context: Some Errors of Stanley Fish".
126
Languages of art and languages of film
it would be a mistake to say that utterance meaning is itself
conventional. It cannot be supposed that we work out the mean-
ing of an utterance by appealing to conventions of the form, "An
utterance of sentence S in context C means M." There is an un-
limited number of values for C, and contexts are not constructed
recursively from a finite set of context constituents. But knowl-
edge of utterance meaning is productive; we understand utter-
ances in contexts we have not previously encountered. How so?
When we figure out utterance meaning we apply the conven-
tions of literal, linguistic meaning, together with nonconven-
tional rules of rationality; we assume the speaker understands
the language and the relevant features of the speech context, and
is able to act appropriately - to choose appropriate words - so
as to get us to realize what it is he intends to get across. The
best hypothesis about that intention gives us the utterance
meaning. This assumption of rationality, and the various specific
subrules to which it gives rise/' are not conventions, because
they are not assumptions to which there is any realistic alter-
native; they are assumptions the world imposes on us rather
than ones we impose on the world. We cannot choose to regard
a speaker as rational and so interpret his utterance one way, or
choose to regard him as irrational and interpret it in another. If
we do not assume him at least minimally rational we cannot
come up with an interpretation - or rather we have no way of
22
deciding among countlessly many of them.
This account of how language functions suggests that the ad-
vocates of cinema language were too optimistic in assessing
what could be achieved for interpretation by way of convention
alone. Literary interpretation is largely a matter of figuring out
utterance meaning; what story the text has to tell is not just a
matter of the literal meanings of the words on the page, which
often have to be taken nonliterally, and even then can sometimes
be thought of only as hinting at the events of the story. Figuring
out the events of the narrative is a matter of figuring out, on the
" On which see Paul Grice, "Logic and Conversation" .
., This is not Davidsonian charity, which would have us regard the speaker's
utterances as (largely) true - clearly a pointless injunction in the case of a
fictional utterance.
127
Representation in film
23
Wilson, Narration in Light, p. 203.
129
Representation in film
""' Virtually the same point is made by Roger Scruton in The Aesthetic Under-
standing, p. 107.
130
Languages of art and languages of film
sentational properties of cinematic images we have never seen
before. Being without meaning atoms, and therefore nonrecur-
sive, and being at the same time productive, the meaning of cin-
ematic images cannot be conventional. It is natural meaning.
With images, productivity is natural generativity, and we explain
that in terms of natural recognitional capacities. As I argued in
Chapter 3, we understand what is depicted onscreen by employ-
ing our visual capacities to recognize the entities depicted. 25
To say that the meaning of a cinematic image is naturally
rather than conventionally determined is not to say that this
meaning has nothing to do with convention. How things are
placed before the camera will be influenced by social institutions
like styles of dress, composition and decor, as well as by con-
siderations of decorum; these things, or some of them, count as
conventions. But this is not grounds for saying the meaning of
the image is itself conventional in the sense that meaning in nat-
ural language is. To be conventional in the way language is there
would have to be a set of conventions governing the meanings
of all the image atoms, and since there are no image atoms there
are no such conventions.
This nice distinction - between what is conventional and
what is influenced by convention - is overlooked by those who
are content to appeal to a vague, impressionistic and all-purpose
notion of convention to support their claims about the conven-
tionality of images. Umberto Eco gives the example of an image
from Fritz Lang's M, in which the girl's balloon is caught in
overhead wires. This image, he says, "stands for" the capture
of the girl by the murderer, but it does so only by convention;
that is, it does so only because in our culture "wires recall ropes,
ropes capture, and so on". 26
The example isn't helpful to Eco's case, since there really are
no conventions associating wire with ropes and ropes with cap-
ture. Wires and ropes are alike in their function and appearance,
which is nothing to do with convention, and it is by no kind of
,, See Section 3.1 in the previous chapter; and Schier, Deeper into Pictures. See
also Sartwell, "Natural Generativity and Imitation", especially pp. 186-187.
26
Eco, "On the Contribution of Film to Semiotics", p. 207.
131
Representation in film
convention that ropes are useful for capturing things. A better
example would be a case where the image of a red traffic light
is a metaphor (not, I grant, a very imaginative or subtle one) for
the end of a love affair. A red traffic light is suggestive of end-
ings because there is a convention which associates the colour
of the light with the instruction to stop. But still, there is no
conventional meaning possessed by this image of the traffic light,
as it appears in our imaginary film. One thing the image can be
said to mean is what it depicts, which is a traffic light. It does
that in virtue of being a cinematic image of a traffic light, and
not by convention. The image might have meaning in virtue of
being a metaphor for, or suggesting, the end of the affair. That
isn't conventional meaning either. An image, like a word or a
sentence, can suggest or be a metaphor for any number of things
depending on context. No convention associates a real red traffic
light with endings of relationships, and no convention associates
the phrase "a red traffic light" with such endings. For that as-
sociation to be conventional, there would have to be a unifor-
mity of practice in the community to use the one as a sign of
the other, or an agreement to use the one for the other if appro-
priate circumstances arose. I'm not sure I have ever seen a traf-
fic-light image used in film in just the way I have described, but
if I had, I think I would have understood its metaphorical sig-
nificance without drawing on, or making an inference to, any
practice of using traffic lights that way, or any agreement to use
them that way. Metaphors don't work by convention; under-
standing them involves understanding intention, and we see the
traffic lights as suggestive of ending when we see that the image
of the traffic lights has been placed in the film just at this point
with the intention of suggesting an ending. 27 Metaphor has to
be explained in terms of utterance meaning, not in terms of lit-
eral (i.e., conventional) meaning.
In another place, Eco has argued for the conventionality of
images generally on the grounds that our images tend to be,
27
See the comments critical of Eco's conception of convention in Gilbert Har-
man, "Eco Location", in the second edition of Film Theory and Criticism. See
also his "Semiotics and the Cinema: Metz and Wollen", in the same volume.
Both are, unfortunately, omitted from subsequent editions.
132
Languages of art and languages of film
and perhaps inevitably are, affected by our social practices: a
picture of a lion was once praised for its lifelikeness; we can
now see how much it owes to the conventions of heraldic rep-
resentation.28 Again, this argument simply conflates two kinds
of conventions, those that facilitate meaning and those that de-
termine it. From the fact that the characteristics of a sign are
affected by convention it doesn't follow that the sign is a con-
ventional sign. A sign is conventional only if there is a conven-
tion which determines its meaning.
An analogy may help. Colonel Smith asks Colonel Jones if
Colonel Jones will kindly have the barracks cleared up after last
night's party. Smith's request depends for its satisfaction on the
giving of certain orders by Jones. But Smith's request is not itself
an order; Smith is not in a position to order Jones to do anything.
In general, what depends on Xs for its fulfilment is not itself
thereby an X.
It may sound as if I am winning this argument by stipulation,
insisting that images are not conventional in a quite idiosyn-
cratic sense. Not so. Although I believe I am using the word
"convention'' in at least one of its ordinary senses, I agree that
there are other senses my usage does not cover, and that in some
of these senses, cinematic and other images may be said to be
conventional. You may use "convention" in any of these other
senses, or give to it any sense you like, but please use it only in
one way, and make sure you have in your vocabulary other
words, one for each distinguishable concept we need in this in-
quiry. One of those concepts is what I have called "convention-
ality'', and it applies to words in English because their meanings
are determined by a coordinated practice based on mutual ex-
pectation. That is the target concept, whatever you choose to
call it, for anyone who wants to argue that cinematic images
have much in common with the items studied by linguistics.
This target concept does not, and could not, apply to the relation
between cinematic images and their meanings, and the whole
argument just given could be restated without using the word
"convention'' at all.
28
Eco, A Theory of Semiotics, p. 205.
133
Representation in film
137
Part II
Imagination
F
ICTIONS,
I present a theory according to which the imagination
is a mental mechanism with certain uses and charac-
teristics which can themselves shed light on the psychology
of fiction. I develop a theory of visual imagining appropriate
to the cinematic case.
Chapter 5
Imagination, the general theory
Imagination, without inducing the experience I imag-
ine, delivers the fruits of experience.
Richard Wollheim
' See, e.g., Richard Wollheim, "Imagination and Identification", especially the
later part. It is noticeable that when occasionally a writer on film seeks a
theoretical alternative to the Lacanian framework, the alternative is still lo-
cated within the realm of theorizing about the psychopathological - as with
Gaylyn Studlar ("Masochism and the Perverse Pleasures of the Cinema"),
who turns to Gilles Deleuze's Masochism: An Interpretation of Coldness and Cru-
elty.
Imagination
sustained if it served no positive purpose. So we need an ac-
count of what is sometimes called the proper functioning of
imagination: a biologically oriented theory that explains the
adaptive benefit we gain from having the capacity to imagine.
But from this point of view, imagination is puzzling. If we think
of the development of mind in evolutionary terms, we might
expect mechanisms of mental representation to be selected ac-
cording to their reliability, and a mechanism that systematically
misrepresents the world, as the imagination surely does, would
seem to have enormous costs and no obvious benefits; for what
we imagine often bears no systematic relation to what actually
is! As we shall see, the capacity for imagining does serve im-
portant cognitive, information-gathering goals. One effect of this
tum towards science will be, I hope, the long-due recognition
that we cannot answer all the philosophically interesting ques-
tions about imagination by a combination of introspection and
a priori analysis. 3
5
See, e.g., S. Baron-Cohen et al., "Does the Autistic Child Have a 'Theory of
Mind'?"; Leslie, "Pretence and Representation"; and S. Stich and S. Nichols,
"Second Thoughts on Simulation". On some views, Leslie's for example, the
theory in question is presumed to be innate. According to others it is learned.
See, e.g., Alison Gopnik, "What Is It if It Isn't a Theory?"
6
Alvin Goldman, "Interpretation Psychologized"; Robert M. Gordon, "Folk
Psychology as Simulation"; Jane Heal, "Replication and Functionalism"; and
the articles in a double issue of Mind and Language, 7, nos. 1-2 (1992) devoted
to simulation theory.
143
Imagination
5.2 SIMULATION
On the knowing-how view, our basic mode of access to the
minds of others works like this: I imagine myself to be in the
other person's position, receiving the sensory information the
other receives. Having thus projected myself imaginatively into
that situation, I then imagine how I would respond to it: what
beliefs and desires I would have, what decisions I would make
and how I would feel having those perceptions, beliefs and de-
sires, and making those decisions. But, crucially, this process of
"imagining how I would respond" is not a matter of my calcu-
lating how I would respond by appeal to rough-and-ready prin-
ciples of mental functioning. Imagining having certain beliefs
and desires is not a matter of considering the proposition that I
have those beliefs and desires, and then deducing, on the basis
of a theory, what I would do as a consequence. Rather, I simply
observe how I do respond in imagination. To imagine having those
beliefs and desires is to take on, temporarily, those beliefs and
desires; they become, temporarily and with other qualifications
I shall describe in a moment, my own beliefs and desires. Being,
thus temporarily, my own, they work their own effects on my
mental economy, having the sorts of impacts on how I feel and
what I decide to do that my ordinary, real beliefs and desires
have. I let my mental processes run as if I really were in that
situation - except that those processes run "off-line", discon-
nected from their normal sensory inputs and behavioural out-
puts. In that way I use my own mind to simulate the mind of
another.
For example, I might start off my imagining by taking on in
this way the beliefs and desires, and also the perceptions, of
someone who sees a lion rushing towards him. These beliefs and
desires then operate on me through their own natural powers;
I start (if my imagining is vivid enough) to feel the visceral
sensations of fear, and I decide to flee. But I don't flee; these
beliefs and desires -let us call them pretend or imaginary beliefs
and desires - differ from my own real beliefs and desires not
just in being temporary and cancellable. Unlike my real beliefs
and desires, they are run off-line, disconnected from their nor-
144
Imagination, the general theory
mal perceptual inputs and behavioural outputs. I start my sim-
ulation without requiring that the causal chain be initiated by
actually seeing a lion, and end it at the point where the decision
is made, but before that decision is translated into action. The
function of the simulation is not to save me from a lion, since I
am not actually threatened by one, but to help me understand
the mental processes of someone so threatened. If my own mind
is a reliable model of the other person's mind, then this process
of mental simulation is a good guide to the mental states of the
other. I can simply note that I formed, in imagination, a certain
belief, desire or decision, then attribute it to the other. Let us
call the hypothesis that we do, at least sometimes, come to a
view about other people's mental states in this way, the Simu-
lation Hypothesis. On this hypothesis, the shift which takes place
when a child is able to comprehend another's belief which is,
by her own lights, false, occurs like this: before the shift, the
child is unable to project herself imaginatively into the position
of the other; the shift occurs when the child becomes able to run
a simulation which takes as initial conditions a perceptual state
different from her own. Prior to that point, that child can attrib-
ute belief only by directly attributing to the other her own belief,
and she is therefore unable to cope with differences of belieF
An analogy may be helpful in understanding what is at stake
between the knowing-that view (what is sometimes called the
"theory theory") and the knowing-how view, which I have
called the Simulation Hypothesis. Suppose you wish to know
whether a bridge will withstand a certain kind of stress. One
way to find out would be to have a theory about the strengths
of materials and the way forces act on them, and to calculate,
7
The problem for the child at three years old is not that she lacks the concept
of a belief different from her own ("false belief", as this is sometimes called
in the literature). For children at this age can, in certain circumstances, exhibit
an understanding of false belief- citing, for example, an agent's false belief
that the cat is in the garage in order to explain the fact that the agent is
searching in the garage instead of under the table, where the cat really is (see
H. Wellman and K. Bartsch, "Young Children's Reasoning about Beliefs'').
The three-year-old's problem seems rather to be that she finds it difficult,
without substantial prompts, to correct for false belief when imaginatively
projecting herself into the agent's position.
145
Imagination
on the basis of the theory, whether the bridge will withstand
the stress. If you don't have such a theory, but instead have a
reliable model of the bridge, you can answer the question by
subjecting the model to just those stresses (assume that there are
no scaling calculations to do). The Simulation Hypothesis says
that we do have a reliable model of the mental processes of
others, namely our own mental processes run off-line. Using the
model, we are able to draw conclusions about other minds with-
out having a theory of how minds, including our own, work.
But what reason is there to think that my own mind is a
reliable model of the minds of others? To be a reliable model it
needs to be similar to the minds of others. How similar are our
minds? Roy Sorensen has argued that if simulation theory is
correct, we may expect agents within a given population to be
mentally similar, because being mentally average will confer a
selective advantage.8 The more like others I am, the more reli-
able will be the process of mental modelling I engage in, the
more I will be able to work out what others believe and desire,
what they believe I believe and desire, and what they desire I
believe and desire. That way, I shall be better able to cooperate
with them when cooperation suits me, and to compete with
them when it does not. That way I have a better chance of sur-
viving and breeding. And as people's minds bunch more closely
around the average, the pressure to be average increases, be-
cause by being average there are more and more people I can
successfully simulate. On this view, we may expect an acceler-
ating tendency towards mental homogeneity.
Sorensen's argument is not in favour of the Simulation Hy-
pothesis. That is, it does not provide a reason for saying that we
are simulators rather than theorists when it comes to under-
standing the mental states of others. Rather, it is a defence of
the Simulation Hypothesis against an objection to it. Sorensen's
point is that, if we are simulationists, we can expect that evo-
lution will have made us mentally similar enough for simula-
tions to be successful a significant proportion of the time, and
8
Roy Sorensen, "Self-Strengthening Empathy", unpublished.
Imagination, the general theory
so it is no objection to the Simulation Hypothesis to say that
simulation would not deliver the desired result because of men-
tal diversity.
I believe that the Simulation Hypothesis is very important for
our understanding, not just of how we comprehend other minds,
but of how we engage with fictions, including cinematic fictions.
I say that fictions are devices which encourage and guide the
imagination; fictions tell stories, and the things which are parts of
the stories they tell are things which those fictions authorize us to
imagine.9 Clouds of Witness authorizes us to imagine that Lord Pe-
ter establishes his brother's innocence, for that is part of the story
it tells; conversely, it prohibits us from imagining that his brother
is hanged for murder, for it is part of the story that he is not han-
ged. (Sometimes, of course, our decisions about what we are au-
thorized to imagine are more complex and controversial.) We
can, of course, improvise our own stories, providing ourselves
with spontaneous fictions that encourage us to imagine ourselves
in interesting and colourful situations. But we often enjoy having
our imaginations guided by an external source - the work of an
author whose skill in story construction may be superior to our
own and whose outcome we can't predict in advance. Such an ex-
ternal source, however encoded and through whatever sensory
channels it is received, is a fiction, in my sense.'o Films are en-
coded in visual and auditory depictions, and are received
through the senses of sight and hearing. Novels, while normally
received through the sense of sight (we normally read with our
eyes) are encoded not in visual depictions, but in linguistic sym-
bols accessible to sight. Both are forms of fiction.
"Imagination" has a number of senses, none of them very
clear. But one kind of imagining is, I believe, the process of
running our mental states off-line. That is the kind of imagining
which takes place when we engage with fictions. So far, I have
described off-line simulation only in the context of our attempts
to comprehend the mental states of another. But that is simply
one function of simulation. Simulation itself occurs when, for
147
Imagination
whatever reason, we run our mental states off-line. One reason
we can run our mental states, in particular our belief-desire sys-
tem, off-line is to engage with a fictional work. That happens
when the fictional story itself provides the inputs to the simu-
lation.
Consider first a nonfictional work: a newspaper article or tel-
evision documentary. If we think the work reliable, we shall
form certain beliefs based on the information the work conveys.
We may also acquire certain desires: documentaries about the
dangers of smoking can make you want to give up, and travel
articles extolling the virtues of an exotic location can make you
want to go there. (So as to simplify things, I'll concentrate on
the case of belief for the moment.)
A fictional work, assuming we know that it's fiction, can have
effects on our mental processes similar in various ways to the
effects of nonfiction. Fictional works can engage our attention,
and they can have what is, on reflection, a surprising capacity
to move us. But we do not acquire from them beliefs in the
straightforward way that we acquire beliefs from nonfiction.
With fictions, our mental processes are engaged off-line, and
what we acquire instead of beliefs is imaginings which simulate
belief. When I work out what Sally believes about the location
of her chocolates, I mentally simulate Sally's mental processes,
her having certain perceptions and thereby acquiring certain be-
liefs. In other words, I imagine being in Sally's situation, re-
sponding as she responds. When I engage with fiction I simulate
the process of acquiring beliefs - the beliefs I would acquire if
I took the work I am engaged with for fact rather than fiction.
Here I imagine myself acquiring factual knowledge. In the Sally
case I imagine being in the situation someone else actually is in;
in the fiction case I imagine being in a situation I could be in
but actually am not in. In the first case the imagining is an in-
strument to a further purpose: to inform me of the mental proc-
esses of someone else. In the second case the imagining has no
such further purpose: the simulation provoked by the fiction I
read is simply something I enjoy."
149
Imagination
belief to the external world via perception and behaviour, they
retain some internal connections. With off-line simulation, states
of imagining function as internal surrogates of beliefs because
they retain belief-like connections to other mental states and to
the body. Imaginings, like beliefs, can lead to decisions, and can
cause certain kinds of bodily sensations. Compare believing that
you are confronted by a dangerous bear with imagining that
you are. Imagining there is a bear in front of me, just like be-
lieving there is one, may cause a decision to flee. But in the
imagining case the decision itself is an imaginary one; it is
something that stands to real decision as imagining stands to
belief. And vividly imagining there is a bear there will cause me
to have some of the unpleasant visceral and other bodily feelings
that believing there is a bear there would, though perhaps less
intensely. Note that in this case what is caused by the imagining
is a real state of feeling and not an imaginary one. Imagining
yourself in danger causes you really to feel disturbed; it does
not merely cause a state of imaginary disturbance. The reason
for that is that feelings are states identified, not in terms of their
function, but in terms of how they feel. A state which feels like
a bodily sensation really is one.
I have been discussing the relation of imagining to belief, and
I said I would bring desire into the picture. If mental simulation
is how we understand the minds of others, there must be states
that stand to desire as imaginings stand to beliefs; for us ade-
quately to simulate the mental states of others, we must simulate
their desires as well as their beliefs. So as well as pretend or
imaginary beliefs- what I have been calling imaginings- we
need pretend or imaginary desires. Fictions provoke imaginary
desires just as they do imaginary beliefs. Reading the story, I
want the hero to succeed. Or do I? After all, I am perfectly aware
there is no hero to be the object of my desire. How can I desire
something for an entity I don't believe in?'3 What's really hap-
pening is that desires are being run off-line, in tandem with
3
' For more on this absence of belief problem, see my Nature of Fiction, chapter
5· See also this chapter, Section 5+
Imagination, the general theory
pretend beliefs. I have a pretend desire that the hero succeed,
backed up by a pretend belief in his existence.
Couldn't we be more economical here, supposing that there
is one unified state of imagining, and that what we might neu-
trally call "pretend beliefs" and "pretend desires" are accounted
for by saying that in the one case we imagine that we believe
something, and in the other that we imagine that we desire it?
That way we get by with three categories - belief, desire and
imagining - instead of my four - belief, desire, pretend belief
and pretend desire. But this admirably economical move has
problems. It would not then be possible simply to imagine (in
the intuitive sense) that some state of affairs occurred; I would
have to imagine that I believed that it occurred. Now consider
the case of imagining that something occurred and that no one
knows anything about it (cases of this kind will recur when I
discuss imagining in response to film). That would require me
to imagine that I believe that it happened and that no one else
believed that it did. The content of my imagining would in that
and similar cases be paradoxical. But it does seem that I can
imagine that something happens that no one knows anything
about, without thereby imagining something impossible. So
imagining something cannot, in general, be equivalent to imag-
ining believing it.'4 In that case we really are going to need re-
course to what I have called "pretend desires" as well as to
pretend beliefs, in order to explain important aspects of mental
processing.
'
4
Also, of course, I can imagine that no one is doing any imagining, but I trust
there is nothing even apparently paradoxical about what I am imagining in
that case.
Imagination
5
' On this see my Nature of Fiction, chapter 2; and Walton, Mimesis as Make-
Believe, chapter 2.
Imagination, the general theory
the story has it that a certain character walked down a dark
street, and we simply imagine that. Then we have primary imag-
ining without the need for secondary imagining. Primary imag-
ining most notably requires secondary imagining in cases where
what we are primarily to imagine is the experience of a char-
acter.'6 If the dark street hides something threatening, the char-
acter who walks it may have thoughts, anxieties, visual and
auditory experiences and bodily sensations that it would be im-
portant for readers to imagine something about. The author may
indicate, to a greater or lesser degree of specificity, what the
character's experience is. But it is notoriously difficult, and in
some cases perhaps impossible, for us to describe people's men-
tal states precisely. Authors who adopt stream of consciousness
and other subjective styles have failed to do it, and so have film
makers like Hitchcock who try to re-create a character's visual
experiences onscreen. Anyway, the attempt at full specificity
and precision in this regard would usually be regarded as a
stylistic vice, leaving, as we significantly say, "nothing to the
imagination". What the author explicitly says, and what can be
inferred therefrom, will constrain our understanding of the char-
acter's mental state. It will set signposts and boundaries. But if
these are all we have to go by in a fiction, it will seem dull and
lifeless. It is when we are able, in imagination, to feel as the
character feels that fictions of character take hold of us. This
process of empathetic reenactment of the character's situation is
what I call secondary imagining. As a result of putting myself,
in imagination, in the character's position, I come to have imag-
inary versions of the thoughts, feelings and attitudes I would
have were I in that situation. Having identified those thoughts,
6
' I am using the term "experience" here in a very broad sense. In my sense,
what a character experiences includes visual, auditory, bodily and other sen-
sations, and also the beliefs, desires and intentions it is fictional that she has,
in so far as they are accessible to her consciousness. Some people argue that
states with propositional content like beliefs and desires are accessible to
consciousness exactly because they have a characteristic feel in the way that
sensations do (see, e.g., Alvin Goldman, "The Psychology of Folk Psychol-
ogy"). But this is very much a minority opinion, and I do not want to judge
this issue one way or the other here.
153
Imagination
feelings and attitudes ostensively, I am then able to imagine that
the character felt that way. That is how secondary imagining is
a guide to primary imagining.'7
Novels with characters into whose mental lives we readily
project ourselves are not works in which we ourselves are char-
acters. While I may simulate the situation of the character, imag-
ining being in his situation, that piece of imagining does not
correspond to anything which the novel makes fiction. It is, ex-
actly, secondary imagining- imagining undertaken because it
will put me in a position where I will be able to imagine
something the novel makes fictional: that the character has cer-
tain thoughts and feelings in response to his situation. It is that
further imagining which is primary.
Being able to construct fictions with characters whose mental
7
' There are times when secondary imagining fails us, because our minds are
not attuned to the task at hand. Robert Gordon drew my attention to the
following passage from Time magazine (May 9, 1994), by John Skow, entitled
"Harold Brodkey's New Novel Is Erotic- But Not to Everybody": "Were-
spond to stories with astonishing versatility of imagination. The three-year-
old listening to his grandmother momentarily becomes Peter Rabbit; the
geezer reading Patrick O'Brian's sea stories feels scared on the quarterdeck
of a storm-blown frigate. But the distinction between what the reader imag-
ines and what he actually experiences remains solid - the geezer does not
actually get seasick. Over the whole range of literature, only erotica functions
differently. If it works, sexual arousal is real, not imaginary. And if it doesn't
work? The most recent example is Harold Brodkey's novel Profane Friendship
(Farrar, Straus & Giroux; 387 pages; $23). The author tells of a long, intensely
erotic affair between the narrator, an American novelist named Nino, and an
Italian named Onni. The names are anagrams of each other- different stir-
rings of the same ingredients, including the same sex. If the drama is to
succeed, the passion must not merely engage the reader intellectually; it must
arouse him. For this heterosexual male, who has imagined himself to be Moll
Flanders and Jonathan Livingston Seagull, the failure is total. Such a state-
ment will surely be called homophobia, but fear and disapproval are not
operating here. In fact, nothing is operating. The reader's reaction is vague
exasperation. His mind simply does not have the software to induce the
intended physiological response to the author's erotic obsessions, and these
are the essence of the book. Such thoughts, of course, must occur regularly
to gays when they read about hetero sex. You don't have to be a rabbit to
enjoy Beatrix Potter, but you may have to be either gay or straight to appre-
ciate gay or straight erotica."
154
Imagination, the general theory
lives readily lend themselves to simulation is not a capacity
every fiction maker possesses or wishes to exploit. Through in-
competence and sometimes through design, the characters of
fiction resist simulation: their responses to situations, their
words and even their thoughts (in so far as the author lets us
know what they are) seem not to be those we would have in
their situations. In these cases, when we engage with the fiction,
trying to guess what will happen, trying to fill in its background
of unstated presuppositions and undescribed events, we may
have to rely more than usual on inferences we make concerning
the author's intentions or about the constraints of form and
genre the work conforms to. A rough guide to the degree of
naturalism in a work of fiction is the extent to which we can let
our own minds model those of the characters. To the extent that
these minds are opaque, not merely in the sense of being un-
derdescribed by the author, but in that of resisting simulation,
we make a work that rejects the standards of naturalism.
Is it just an historical accident that most of our fiction is nat-
uralistic in this sense? Despite frequent calls for, or announce-
ments of, the death of naturalism, I think it unlikely. The drive
to simulate seems to be a very powerful one. And with good
reason; I shall argue in the next section that the disastrous effects
of simulative failure are evident in the aloneness and multiple
incompetencies of autism. The close historical association be-
tween fiction and psychological naturalism suggests that fictions
have thrived exactly because they give us opportunities to ex-
ercise our capacity for simulation. Fiction may not be logically
tied to psychological naturalism any more than painting is log-
ically tied to naturalistic representation, but in both cases the
psychological connection seems to go very deep.
5·4 CONSEQUENCES
Identifying imagination with simulation has interesting conse-
quences; some of these concern features of imagining generally
agreed on, while others require us to attribute to imagining fea-
tures that can seem counterintuitive but which I believe to be
correct. I want to point out some of those features.
155
Imagination
First, given the characteristics of off-line simulation I have
described, we can now explain certain features of our experience
when we are engaged by fictions. While fictions do not cause
us to believe in the reality of the fictional story, they can engage
us to the extent of causing within us the sometimes pleasant
and sometimes unpleasant bodily states we associate with being
emotionally moved by events. If fictions encourage simulations,
and simulated beliefs and desires retain their internal connec-
tions to our bodily states, that is exactly what we would expect.
The anxiety that watching horror movies induces in me does
not cause me to call the police, but it does cause me to feel afraid.
Second, the idea that imagination is simulation explains one
peculiarity of imagining in relation to belief and desire: that
there is no such thing as dispositional imagining. With belief and
desire we have the distinction between dispositional and occur-
rent states. I may believe something I have never thought about
and which plays no role in explaining my past or current be-
haviour. Similarly for desire. In these cases we say that the belief
or desire is dispositional rather than occurrent; the state is pos-
sessed in virtue of the fact that if a relevant situation were to
arise you would be likely to behave in a way that would betray
the belief or the desire. But there is no comparable category of
dispositional imagining, and all imagining is occurrent (though
not necessarily conscious, as I shall argue). And while I may be
disposed to imagine certain things, the possession of such a dis-
position does not constitute my dispositionally imagining them.
But it is easy to see that with simulation there is also no dis-
positional-occurrent distinction to be made. You are either run-
ning a simulation or not, and being disposed to run a certain
simulation does not constitute dispositionally simulating - no
more than being disposed to run a mile means you are dispos-
itionally running one.
Third, in identifying simulation and imagination we vindicate
the intuition that imaginings are somehow secondary or deriv-
ative states. Imagining something may be different from believ-
ing it, but it does seem as if there is an asymmetrical dependence
of imagining on belief. We can imagine a creature which has
beliefs but lacks the capacity to imagine. Indeed, there may ac-
156
Imagination, the general theory
tually be cases of this in our population. People suffering from
autism show a pattern of disabilities strikingly suggestive of the
hypothesis that what they lack is, literally, imagination.'8 The
condition is marked by a considerable degree of inflexibility and
isolation in social relations; there is no spontaneous enthusiasm
for games of imagination and pretence, and there is considerable
difficulty in verbal communication, though high functioning au-
tistic individuals often have functional mastery of language. Suf-
ferers, even those few of high ability who hold responsible jobs,
have difficulty understanding that other people have different
knowledge, beliefs, desires and generally a different mental out-
look on the world from themselves; and autistic children typi-
cally fail tests of understanding of false belief, such as the
''Sally'' test already described.' 9 This inability to understand the
mental states of others may explain why autistic subjects fail to
provide relevant background information in their speech, fail to
notice that others are bored by their own favourite topics of
conversation, fail to understand that their own behaviour has
caused offence. Often they seem to lack the ability to deceive,
or even to understand the concept of deception.
This inability to comprehend mental states, together with the
157
Imagination
lack of interest in pretence and the fictional, when taken in con-
junction with the idea that we understand other people's mental
states by an act of imaginative projection, strongly suggests that
the basic deficiency of autism is a lack of imagination. But un-
doubtedly, autistic people have beliefs and desires. On the other
hand, it is difficult to imagine a being who had the capacity for
imagining, but not for belief. The Simulation Hypothesis ex-
plains this asymmetry. Since simulation runs the belief-desire
system off-line, imagining is parasitic on these other mental
states.
If imagining is simulation, then I think we have an explana-
tion, or the beginnings of one, for a puzzling phenomenon: our
ability to empathize with fictional characters and their situa-
tions. A familiar formulation: how can we pity Anna Karenina
when we know that she does not exist? There are problems here
of different kinds, one of which is logical: if emotions require
certain kinds of beliefs (not merely causally but constitutively)
how can we have emotions directed at fictional characters when
we lack the relevant beliefs? But putting aside the logical prob-
lem which I have discussed elsewhere/ let us concentrate on
0
" See David Lewis, postscript to "Truth in Fiction", Philosophical Papers, vol. 1.
,. See Currie, Nature of Fiction, chapter 2.
159
Imagination
16o
Imagination, the general theory
avoid the conclusion that the child is imagining something, part
of which is true.
Could we explain the behaviour by saying instead that it is
the outcome of a combination of imagining and belief? That is,
the child imagines that these two cups (which as it happens are
empty) are full, and believes that these other two cups are
empty. But what is the explanation of the fact that other beliefs
of the child do not influence the pretend behaviour? The child
believes that all four of the cups are empty, but only treats two
of them as if they were. The simplest and most natural expla-
nation seems to be that the belief that these two are empty does
become part of what the child imagines, while the belief that all
four are empty does not. And there are other cases where pre-
tence seems to coincide almost entirely with belief- as with the
case reported by Vygotsky of two sisters pretending to be sis-
ters.24
One final and rather startling implication of the assimilation
of imagining to simulation is that imagining should not be
thought of as always and automatically a conscious or even an
intentional action, since simulation, if it really does help us to
understand the minds of others, must be done unintentionally,
mostly at a subconscious level. For me that is a welcome result.
If, as I have argued, fictions function to drive imagination, they
do so in ways of which the subject is sometimes unaware, and
over which the subject rarely exerts conscious control. But there
are those who have argued that it is a priori of imaginative
pretence that it is engaged in consciously and intentionally.25
This claim seems to me symptomatic of a residual Cartesianism
that has not yet been dislodged from this underdeveloped part
of the philosophy of mind. If hitching the concept of imagination
to simulation theory helps us to abandon it, so much the better.
24
Alan Leslie discusses the issue of pretending what is believed in his "Pre-
tending and Believing: Issues in the Theory of ToMM". I owe the reference
to Vygotsky to Leslie's paper (see L. S. Vygotsky, "Play and Its Role in the
Mental Development of the Child"). For criticism of Leslie's theoretical ap-
proach to the issue of pretence, see my "Imagination and Simulation".
25
See, e.g., Noel Carroll, The Philosophy of Horror: Paradoxes of the Heart; and
Anders Pettersson, "On Walton's and Currie's Analysis of Fiction".
161
Imagination
' Jean Mitry, quoted approvingly both in Wilson, Narration in Light, p. 55, and
in Charles Affron, Cinema and Sentiment, p. 7· The quotation is from Esthetique
et psychologie du cinema, I: les structures, p. 179.
Imagination
t66
Imagination, personal and impersonal
3
This thesis, or something like it, seems to be implicit in the work of early
theorists like Miinsterberg and Pudovkin.
4
"In cinema it is not possible to speak, in the strict sense, of a narrator. The
film does not narrate, but rather it places the spectator directly without in-
termediaries, in the presence of the facts narrated" (Julio Moreno, "Subjective
Cinema: The Problem of Film in the First Person", p. 354· Quoted in Branigan,
Narrative Comprehension and Film, p. 144).
5
As I noted earlier, viewers of Waters's Pink Flamingos are sometimes provided
Imagination
we can imagine that we see fictional things, presumably we can
imagine that we smell and feel them, that we have sensory con-
tact of all kinds with them. We can imagine other, nonsensuous
modes of contact with them: that we know, like, distrust or ad-
mire them. But I shall confine my remarks to vision: it is perhaps
the most interesting case because of the highly structured and
complex nature of visual experience, and it is naturally the case
most frequently discussed in connection with cinema. What I
say about the case of seeing will be easily applicable to the other
senses.
To repeat: I take it to be a distinctive thesis of classical film
theory that cinema encourages a certain kind of imagining
which I have called imagining seeing: imagining that you are
seeing the fictional events of the film, and seeing them from the
point of view of the camera.
168
Imagination, personal and impersonal
have tended to emphasize the distance - and the barriers - be-
tween the audience and the fiction presented on stage. Haig
Khatchadourian explicitly contrasts plays and movies in this re-
spect: "It is probably true that we cannot experience the action
of a play from 'within' its space time in the way we can in film." 7
Bernard Williams says that the theatrical audience "see what
they may well describe as, say, Othello in front of a certain pal-
ace in Venice.... But they are not themselves at any specifiable
distance from that palace". As members of the audience, they
"are spectators of a world they are not in".8 I assume Williams
means that spectators imagine they see the palace (they can't
really see a palace which isn't there), but they don't imagine
being any particular distance from it. They do not imagine that
they stand in any perspectival relation to the palace.
Later I shall address the question whether this idea of imag-
ined nonperspectival seeing makes sense. For the moment I
want to ask whether the idea of imagining seeing - perspectival
or not - could be the key to identifying a broad class of visual
fictions: a class which would include film, theatre, painting and
certain other forms. The proposal is this: a fiction is visual, or
belongs to a visual medium, if the kind of imagining it makes
appropriate is imagining seeing. Kendall Walton thinks that
painting is a visual medium in this sense. On his view, it is
central to our interpretation of paintings that we engage in var-
ious visual imaginings with respect to them: we recognize the
picture as a picture of a deer, he says, when we notice ourselves
imagining that we are seeing a deer when we look at the pic-
ture.9
Painting, theatre and film certainly are visual :media. The ques-
tion is whether this is because they encourage imagining seeing.
The idea is not implausible. It offers a neat contrast with another
staged to favour a certain viewing position. But this does not give it an in-
trinsic point of view in the strong sense that a movie has one.
7
Haig Khatchadourian, "Space and Time in Film", p. 176. Italics in original.
8
Bernard Williams, "Imagination and the Self", in Problems of the Self: Philo-
sophical Papers, 1956-72, p. 35·
9
Walton, Mimesis as Make-Believe, p. 294. See also Wollheim, Painting as an Art,
chapter 2.
Imagination
mode of fiction of which the novel is the best example, and a con-
sequent elaboration of the showing-telling distinction. With vi-
sual fictions, we have a showing: we imagine that our act of
looking at the film, stage or picture is an act of looking at the fic-
tional events there portrayed. With poetry and its literary succes-
sors we have not a showing but a telling: we imagine that the
events of the fiction occur, but not that our reading the text is an
act of witnessing those events. That way we have two kinds of
media, divided according to the kinds of representations they
employ, and two kinds of imagining; the proposal is that they
pair off neatly: pictorial fictions with imagining seeing, which is a
species of personal imagining, and (predominantly) linguistic fic-
tions with impersonal imagining. All this, I say, is false.
173
Imagination
imagining; it ought to be part of my imagining that the murderer
is, exactly, unseen. This reading gives "imagine" insufficient
scope. The other, wide, reading is: "I imagine that there is an
unseen murderer which I see." This does not have either of the
two deficiencies noted of the first formulation, but it does make
the content of my imagining explicitly contradictory. Perhaps it
is possible to perform the feat of imagining something explicitly
contradictory. But it is implausible to suppose that the audience
on such an occasion as I have just described is called on to do
that.
One other response to my scepticism about imagining seeing
is that while the fiction precludes the imagined presence of a
witness "in the world of the fiction", it does not preclude the
possibility that the viewer, who stands outside that world, is a
witness. 14 But most films which can be thought of as excluding
"internal" observers can, with equal or greater plausibility, be
thought of as excluding external ones as well. Naturalistic fic-
tions do not leave open as to whether someone is watching the
scene from another world: such an idea would be wildly at vari-
ance with their conventions.
The intrinsic point of view possessed by a movie raises an-
other difficulty. Occasionally that point of view is one we are
required to imagine occupied by a character: then we have a
subjective shot. In Hitchcock's Spellbound there is a shot, the in-
trinsic perspective of which is defined by the position occupied
by the character John Ballantine, as he raises a glass of milk to
his lips, eyeing the psychologist Dr Bruloff suspiciously as he
does so. How is the viewer to integrate his supposed imagina-
tive occupation of the camera's point of view with imagining
that this point of view is that of a character? Presumably, by
identifying himself with that character. I had better say some-
thing about the idea of identification.
For some writers, identification is the central concept of their
theory of cinema; it is what makes the understanding of cine-
matic narrative possible, and it is to be explained in psychoan-
174
Imagination, personal and impersonal
alytic terms. 15 I wish to take a somewhat different path. I shall
concentrate on how identification might take its place in a cog-
nitive theory of imagining of the kind I have outlined. On this
view, identification with a character would be a matter of imag-
ining that you are that character. Consider, then, the hypothesis
that the viewer, when he views a subjective shot, imagines that
he is the character whose subjective view is represented there.
What is required in order to engage in that kind of imaginative
identification? At a minimum, the viewer must imagine that
what is (fictionally) happening to that character is happening to
him or her, and that he or she has the most obvious and dra-
matically salient attributes of that character at that time. But
once this is seen to be required as a condition for identification,
it becomes very hard to square the claim of identification with
the experience of watching a subjective shot. In the shot from
Spellbound, salient features of Ballantine are that he is drinking
milk and that his mental state is one of turmoil. Watching this
shot does not incline me in the least to imagine myself doing or
being either of these things. Nor, when watching a celebrated
subjective shot later in the film, in which the murderer points a
gun towards himself and fires, do I imagine that I am killing
myself. Further, identification, if it is a notion with any content
at all, would seem to require the one who identifies to have, or
to imagine having, some concern with and sympathy for the
values and projects of the one with whom she identifies. But, as
Nick Browne has noted in his study of an important scene from
Stagecoach, one of the peculiarities of the setup there is that,
while we see Dallas the prostitute from Lucy's point of view,
we do not, and are not intended to, feel solidarity with Lucy's
attempt to exclude Dallas. 16 That the camera occupies Lucy's
'' " ... [the viewer] certainly has to identify ... if he did not the film would
become incomprehensible." Christian Metz, Psychoanalysis and Cinema, p. 46.
6
' Nick Browne, The Rhetoric of Filmic Narration, chapter 1. So far as I can see,
Browne does not appreciate that identification is the source of the trouble.
He says that we are "asked to see Dallas through Lucy's eyes"; also that we
"identify" with Dallas. Things are made more confusing by Browne's moving
easily between point of view as a literal place of physical observation to point
175
Imagination
point of view has no implications, or only negative ones, for
identification. Nor do subjective shots from the point of view of
a stalking creature or a homicidal maniac make us identify with
the stalker; they typically have the effect of heightening our con-
cern for the potential victim. In all these ways the supposition
of imaginative identification does not square with the experience
of film.
Some of these objections can be made more vivid if we con-
sider an actual film sequence. I have chosen a short scene from
Hitchcock's The Birds, during which Melanie Daniels (Tipi Hed-
ron) crosses Bodega Bay in a hired boat. Compositionally, the
sequence is of some interest, but it does not seem to be an es-
pecially disorienting scene to watch. One can find the repertoire
of shots out of which it is constructed repeated in a great many
scenes in this and other films. The sequence I have in mind
consists of fourteen shots, beginning with three long shots of the
boat: one from behind as it leaves the quay, one from the side,
with the boat travelling across the screen left to right, and one
from more or less front-on. Shot 4 is close in to the boat, and
travels alongside. Shots 5 to 14 constitute a sequence of pairs of
shots, the first of each pair being a point-of-view shot from Me-
lanie's position, and the second a reverse shot to Melanie herself,
with the last shot reversed on her as she ties up the boat and
gets out.
As I say, there is nothing especially remarkable about the ex-
perience of watching this scene. But if the viewer is to imagine
herself seeing the events represented in the sequence from the
position of the camera, the experience of watching it would be
a very peculiar one indeed. The transitions between the first
of view as, in effect, "taking someone's part". This leads to unresolved ox-
ymorons like "identification asks us as spectators to be [sic] two places at
once, where the camera is and "with" the depicted person.... This passage
[from Stagecoach] shows that identification necessarily has a double structure
in the way it implicates the spectator in both the position of the one seeing
and the one seen" (p. 8). Simultaneous identification with distinct and indeed
antagonistic characters is hardly to be credited. But Browne's analysis is more
sophisticated than the inflexible "system of the suture" against which he is
to some extent reacting.
Imagination, personal and impersonal
7
' This objection I owe to Kendall Walton.
177
Imagination
178
Imagination, personal and impersonal
179
Imagination
8
' This shot, like most shots of its kind, is quite unrealistic because it fails to
capture the binocular nature of ordinary vision. Ballantine would have to
have one eye shut to see anything like what is presented on the screen.
9
' The shot may encourage secondary imagining. That is, in order to imagine
appropriately concerning the character's experience, we may have to imagine
having that experience ourselves, thereby engaging in a simulation of the
character's experience (see Section 5.2 on the distinction between primary
and secondary imagining). But this secondary imagining is not a matter of
identifying ourselves with the character.
180
Imagination, personal and impersonal
would not have induced in you different beliefs about the shape
of the thing described.= Nor, with descriptions, do your beliefs
have the kind of bunched, content-specific character we associ-
ate with perceptual beliefs. You can learn about shape from a
description, and learn nothing about colour. And what you can
learn from a description of colour will lack the specificity that
it would have in the case of a perceptual belief. Descriptions
rarely authorize us to believe the eyes of the person described
are exactly that shade of blue. The beliefs we get from descrip-
tions I'll call symbolic beliefs. They contrast, obviously, with per-
ceptual beliefs, but I am not claiming that between them these
two kinds exhaust the field.
This characterization of the difference between perceptual
and symbolic beliefs applies at the level of tokens rather than at
that of types. One cannot, in general, say that a certain belief
type - for example, that this object is round - is perceptual
rather than symbolic. One token of that belief might be percep-
tual and another symbolic. What makes the token perceptual is
the form of its tokening - its tokening within a system of rep-
resentation that gives to the tokens so represented the features
of structure and content I just mentioned. It should, for instance,
be a system in which size, shape and colour come together as a
single unit of representation. Pictures in the head would serve
well in this regard, but I assume we have independent reason
not to believe in them. No matter; other things may do as well,
including connectionist networks with the right kinds of exci-
tatory links. But for purposes of this argument, I am neutral
about what kinds of representations are at work here.
Note that it would not do to characterize perceptual beliefs
by saying that they are the ones you get when you see the thing
itself rather than a description of it. For you can get genuinely
perceptual beliefs, in my sense, by looking at likenesses of
things; likenesses stand in the same or similar relations of coun-
terfactual dependence with your beliefs as do the things of
which they are likenesses, and the beliefs they induce have the
23
See Andre Bazin, Jean Renoir; see also Noel Carroll, Philosophical Problems of
Classical Film Theory, chapter J.
Imagination
we are right there could underlie such an explanation. I answer:
we are notorious transferrers of properties from things repre-
sented to representations. I'm told that oscilloscope watchers say
things like "That's a loud one" (pointing at the wave on the
screen). They mean, "That represents a loud noise." That plau-
sibly is what is going on in our imagined conversation at the
cinema.
2. Consider the perceptual imaginings that cinema promotes.
These are in a certain sense perspectival imaginings. I have said
that with perceptual imagining, what we are to imagine de-
pends on what we see; we see a cinematic image of a man with
a certain appearance, and we are to imagine that the character
played by the man has that appearance. But what we see is seen
from a certain perspective: that of the camera. If we imagine
that the character looks like that, we must be imagining him
looking like that from that perspective. There is no such thing as
the way a person looks from no perspective. That is the sense
in which perceptual imagining is essentially perspectival: a spec-
ification of the content of what we imagine must make reference
to a certain perspective. But once we admit that we are dealing
with perceptual imagining that is perspectival, doesn't this
amount to an admission that we are dealing with imagining, the
content of which is of the form "I am seeing such and such"?24
In order to answer the objection, let us once again compare
the case of imagination with that of belief. The general form of
the argument just given is this: if the content of an attitude is
perspectival, then the content of the attitude is of the form "I cp
that I am seeing (or, more generally, perceiving) that P", where
cp is a variable ranging over attitudes, and P a variable ranging
over propositions. But in the case of belief, this is manifestly not
so. I see a painting of Uncle Albert and on the basis of seeing it
form the belief that his appearance is thus and so.25 Of course
what I believe is that he appears thus and so from a certain
perspective. But I do not believe that I am seeing Uncle Albert,
24
Again, this objection was suggested to me, in conversation, by Kendall
Walton.
•s I assume that the pictures in question are nonphotographic, thereby avoiding
an argument with the advocates of Transparency.
188
Imagination, personal and impersonal
us as less natural than those taken at roughly eye level. But the
best explanation for this sense of unnaturalness might not be
that we find it unnatural to imagine ourselves in the position
from which the shot is taken. A plausible alternative explanation
is simply that we are unfamiliar with the views of people that
such shots present, together with the fact that facial expressions
are usually so important to the narrative that shots which wil-
fully deny us access to them are very noticeable interventions
on the maker's part. And if unnaturalness were a function of
the extent to which the camera's position deviated from the
norm for a human participant, some shots ought to seem very
unnatural which do not seem unnatural at all. Those views of
the Earth from deep space that we see so often in science-fiction
films do not seem especially unnatural.
5· What, in that case, do we make of the venerable distinction
between diegesis and mimesis, between telling and showing? It
seems that on my view fictions of all kinds are diegetic; all are
experienced as something told. They differ only in the means
used for the telling: words in literature, moving images in cin-
ema. This denial of a universally acknowledged distinction
looks like a problem for my theory.
I reply that my theory still allows for the making of important
distinctions. If all fictions are tellings, there are still fictions
which tell by words, spoken and written, and there are fictions
which tell by showing, as cinema and other visual fictions do.
Also, there are fictions in which the telling is foregrounded, and
is therefore a salient part of the audience's unreflective experi-
ence of the fiction, and fictions in which the artifice of telling is
backgrounded, and easily forgotten. This pair of distinctions will
serve us at least as well as the traditional showing/ telling dis-
tinction.
6.8 PSYCHOLOGISM
194
Imagination, personal and impersonal
sumption in favour of psychologism would make plausible.
Take away that presumption and the motivation for suture the-
ory collapses.
These and other artificial and sometimes desperate attempts
to psychologize the cinema are somewhat ironic in light of what
should be a rather obvious fact about the basic cinema appara-
tus: that it is an impoverished and unconvincing vehicle for
subjectivity. Viewing the cinema screen is, I have argued, in im-
portant ways rather like viewing the real world; it is not at all
like viewing someone's subjective visual experience of the real
world (a notion that barely makes sense anyway). It is extremely
difficult to make what appears onscreen correspond in a con-
vincing way to the content of anyone's visual experience; the
sharply defined boundary of the screen is never effectively over-
come by blurring effects, for they never correspond to our own
graduated field of vision. The screen cannot mimic the capacity
of vision to concentrate on detail, and selective focusing by the
camera simply draws attention to the artifice. Nor does deep
focus correspond to the visual field. For that reason, episodes of
recollection which appear onscreen as visual images rather than
as verbal accounts have a tendency to become, unintentionally,
episodes of objective recounting. For what appears on the screen
always surpasses in detail and clarity the possible content of
anyone's memory. Thus it was that Hitchcock was able to con-
fuse the audience in Stage Fright by presenting, in visual images,
events as recounted from the character's point of view; these
events, as it turns out, did not occur but were the fabrication of
the character. Why do we take visual images as more authori-
tative than verbal recountings, which in the context of a mystery
are automatically treated with some scepticism? The answer
seems to be that the camera's capacity for capturing detail, and
its failure to resemble subjective experience, means that it is only
for short periods and with considerable effort that we are able
or willing to regard what is onscreen as subjective and therefore
as representing what someone thinks or claims, rather than what
actually is.
The oddness of psychologizing the cinema is evident when
we compare it to other media. I should be surprised to learn,
1 95
Imagination
for example, that anyone had suggested, with respect to the
presentation of fictions on radio, that we are required to under-
stand each sound as, or as referred to, the content of some char-
acter's auditory experience. Perhaps the reason this has not been
suggested is that there is nothing in radio comparable to editing
in film, and that it is the editing of shots that enables the viewer
to understand the images the screen presents as referred now to
this character and now to that. (A sufficiently stereophonic radio
might do this, but to my knowledge this suggestion has not been
taken up.) But that psychologism has not prevailed with respect
to radio is instructive, because it does seem that listeners to ra-
dio drama are able to orient themselves and to understand the
narrative without psychologizing the auditory information they
receive. Why should it be otherwise with the cinema?
It is time, I suggest, to tum the psychologizing paradigm on
its head, that is, to take as the default setting an interpretation
of the cinematic image as the rendering of events objectively,
and to allow a subjective interpretation only when no plausible
objective interpretation is available.
197
Chapter 7
Travels in narrative time
I had the impression [in Je t'aime, Je t'aime] of a sort
of eternal present. The hero relives his past, but when
he relives it we are with him, the film always takes
place in the present. There are absolutely no flash-
backs or anything like them.
Alain Resnais'
7. 1 TENSE IN FILM
One class of philosophically interesting and controversial tem-
poral properties I did not discuss in Chapter 3 is that of tense
properties. This consists of the properties of being past, present
and future. These are properties of events, or so I shall assume
for simplicity's sake. 2 My opening the door is future at one time,
present at a later time and past later still. I have argued that
cinematic representations - moving images - have temporal
properties, and that their temporal properties typically function
to represent temporal properties of the events those images rep-
resent. Can we say tensed properties are among those which
function representationally in this way?
For that to be the case, cinematic images would have to have
tense properties, and, in virtue of possessing those tense prop-
1'}8
Travels in narrative time
3
''Anachrony" is Gerard Genette's term. See his influential Narrative Discourse.
Genette's taxonomy is widely applied to cinema: see, e.g., Brian Henderson,
"Tense, Mood and Voice in Film (Notes after Genette)".
199
Imagination
vant to the question before us, which concerns only the rep-
resentation of the fiction itself. The question is whether the
presentness of the image represents the presentness, to the
viewer, of fictional events. There is nothing eccentric about this
decision to concentrate attention on the fictional: discussions of
tense in cinema normally focus on the relation between thenar-
rative order and the temporal order of the fictional events de-
picted. We do not count it as anachrony when shot Y, which
follows shot X in the intended order of viewing, was filmed
before shot X. Rather, we count it as anachrony when shot Y
represents a fictional event whose fictional time of occurrence is
prior to that of X.
• Balazs, Theory of the Film, p. 120. See also, e.g., Jurij Lotman, Semiotics of the
Cinema, p. 77: "In every art which employs vision and iconic signs there is
only one possible artistic time - the present." Balazs seems to conflate the
view that images have only one tense - the present - with the view that they
''have no tenses" (ibid.). See also R. Stephenson and J. R. Debrix, The Cinema
as Art, p. 115: "Film has no tenses- past, present, or future. When we watch
a film, it is just something that is happening- noul' (emphasis in the original).
Some other advocates of the Claim of Presentness are discussed and criticized
by Jarvie in Philosophy of the Film, pp. 12-19.
5
Introduction to the screenplay of LAst Year at Marienbad, p. 12; quoted in Joan
Dagle, ''Narrative Discourse in Film and Fiction: The Question of the Present
Tense". Similar views are occasionally expressed concerning literature: 'The
reader if he is engrossed in his reading translates all that happens from this
moment of [fictional] time onward into an imaginative present of his own
200
Travels in narrative time
201
Imagination
commonly, flashforwards, in which the image is to be taken to
represent a past or future state of affairs. It is said, by advocates
of the claim, that in these cases the assumption of presentness
is overridden by contextual cues (dissolve, verbal narration or
general considerations of narrative coherence). The default set-
ting is presentness.
In that case cinematic images have two distinct functions for
the audience, depending on whether they present fictional
events anachronously. Where there is no anachrony, we are to
interpret the visual images onscreen by imagining that we ac-
tually see before us the fictional events they represent. In the
case where they present material out of sequence, we are to
interpret them in some other way, for we cannot think of our-
selves as seeing past or future events now. Perhaps we are to
think of those images as signs which provide us with informa-
tion about what happens in the story at some time earlier or
later than the story time we have been involved with up to the
point of the time shift. This is implausible. When I watch a film
that contains anachronous material, I detect no difference be-
tween my experience of the images when they present material
in standard order and when they deviate from that order. The
theory we are considering postulates a functional discontinuity
for which there seems to be no psychological evidence.9
Another way to defend the hypothesis that cinematic images
are present tensed would be to suppose that, with episodes of
anachrony, the viewer imagines herself to be shifted in time
along with the image. When the image dissolves to reveal what
happened twenty, two hundred or two thousand years before,
she imagines herself to be a time traveller, shifted in time by
just that amount. This has the advantage of allowing us to say
that anachronous and temporally standard images function in
the same way for the audience rather than in different ways, as
9
Of course the evidence of my introspection (and that of those to whom I have
spoken on this subject) may not be decisive in this matter. But so far as I
know, the advocates of the Claim of Presentness have never brought forward
evidence to support the idea that there is a functional discontinuity here.
Perhaps that is because they do not realize that their theory commits them to
the existence of such a discontinuity.
202
Travels in narrative time
the previous theory would have it. All images, on this view, are
experienced as representing present events; it is just that what
constitutes the present for the viewer is imagined to change to
compensate for temporal shifts in the narrative. But in other
ways this theory is just as implausible as the last; I don't think
I imagine my own temporal position to shift when I view out-
of-sequence images on the screen. It might be claimed that this
kind of imagined shift takes place unconsciously. Perhaps. I
don't say there never are unconscious imaginings; on the con-
trary, I have emphasized that my identification of imagination
with simulation allows for unconscious imaginings in just the
same way that we allow for unconscious beliefs. But we must
not allow the category of the unconscious to degenerate into an
automatic let-out clause for otherwise falsified psychological
hypotheses. When it comes to the hypothesis that the viewer of
anachrony imagines himself travelling in time, this is not
something that we consciously imagine, nor is it something that
prompting naturally brings to mind as part of our previously
unconscious imagining. The only evidence for these unconscious
imaginings seems to be that they are required in order to save
the Claim of Presentness from refutation.
Yet another way to defend the Claim of Presentness would
be to argue that flashforwards and flashbacks do not change the
presentness of the image: that the content of the image in an
anachronous sequence is always the content of a character's
present memory of, or premonition concerning, an event located
elsewhere in time. In that case there would be no need for us to
imagine ourselves moving around in time, and no sense of un-
ease or dislocation on confronting such a sequence would be
expected.
I might raise awkward questions here about how it is that we
could imagine ourselves to be seeing the subjective mental states
of other people, which is what this proposal requires us to imag-
ine. Let us put these awkward questions aside. This view
amounts, strictly speaking, to the abolition of anachrony, be-
cause it would not allow us to say that any story events are
presented out of their strict chronological order. What we nor-
mally call a flashback could not be said to present the event
203
Imagination
itself, but rather to present, "from the inside", a character's cur-
rent memory or premonition of that event, presenting it in the
correct chronological sequence.'o In that case the view we are
considering imposes a very strong and implausible limitation
on the kinds of film narrative there can be. It says that there can
never be a case where the events of the narrative are presented
out of their correct temporal order, and that all apparent cases
of anachrony are really cases of memory or premonition. But if
a film maker can present scenes which represent a sequence of
fictional occurrences in their correct order, why can't she, simply
by rearranging the order of showing, present them out of se-
quence? Further, it seems wrong to claim that every apparently
anachronous episode in film is in fact one of memory or pre-
monition. It is true that anachronous episodes in film (of which
the majority are flashbacks) are often associated with a charac-
ter's psychological state; the character begins describing the past
event and the image dissolves to the flashback. But at least some
cases of the flashback, and especially the flashforward, are not
associated with any act of memory or premonition on the part
of a character. At least, there is in some films no evidence for
this association, and to insist that the association is there purely
on the grounds that the Claim of Presentness requires it is man-
ifestly ad hoc.
We might, on behalf of the Claim of Presentness, associate the
anachrony with the mind of the narrator, an imaginary being
who the viewer is to think of as the (veridical) source of the
information which the film provides. This being may not appear,
•o Discussions of anachrony in ffim seem often to presuppose that current mem-
ories and premonitions do constitute the material for anachrony. See, e.g.,
Stephenson and Debrix, Cinema as Art, especially p. uS. David Bordwell goes
even farther in this surely mistaken direction. He counts it as a case of the
narrative reordering of story time when a character in the story recounts a
story event, as long as that act of recounting constitutes our source of infor-
mation about the event. See his Narration in the Fiction Film, p. 78. The re-
counting is itself a story event, presented in the narrative in the conventional
temporal order; that it is a recounting of an earlier story event makes for no
disruption of story time - otherwise there would be anachrony every time a
character gave the date of his birth. (Genette makes the same mistake while
analysing a passage from Jean Santeuil, in Narrative Discourse, p. 38.)
204
Travels in narrative time
" Turim, Flashbacks in Film, p. 1. Turim also quotes a similarly tensed account
of the flashback from Leslie Halliwell (The Filmgoer's Companion, 3d ed.), who
calls it "a break in chronological narrative during which we are shown events
of past time which bear on the present situation".
" See J. M. McTaggart, The Nature of Existence, vol. 2, chapter 33· McTaggart
argued, roughly, that the A-series involves a contradiction, that without it
there is no change, and without change there is no time. So there is no time.
2o6
Travels in narrative time
3
' As Robin le Poidevin points out, McTaggart himself wondered whether
the time of fiction might be a time constructed from the B-series alone, al-
though he seems also to have rejected this view (Nature of Existence, vol. 2,
207
Imagination
achrony in terms of B-series relations only, I start with this pro-
posal:
(A) Film F contains anachrony iff F contains representations
of fictional events X and Y, where the representation of
X in viewing time is after that of Y, but it is fictional that
the time of the occurrence of X is before that of Y.
This definition is not quite right. I want to consider a number
of problems that it faces. The first, put to me by David Lewis,
concerns the relation between anachrony in cinematic fiction
and those cinematic narratives which involve time travel. In a
time-travel story the narrative might begin in, say, 1982, during
which plans are made for a journey into the past; later in the
narrative we are presented with events which take place at the
time travelled back to, say 1952. Now it is intuitively wrong to
assimilate cinematic (or other) narratives involving time travel
to anachronous narratives; there seems to be a sense in which,
in the time-travel story I described, the events of the story are
presented in the chronologically correct sequence; after all, the
journey back to 1952 takes place after the events in 1982, which
are presented first - otherwise, how would the events of 1982
constitute a preparation for the journey? But then the objection
to my definition (A) is, exactly, that it conflates anachronous
narratives and narratives involving time travel.' 4 For it is true,
concerning the time-travel story just described, that events oc-
curring in 1952 are shown later in viewing time than events
occurring in 1982.
Lewis was good enough to suggest a way out of the difficulty
for me. The objection shows not that there is an error in defi-
P· 16). See Robin le Poidevin, "Time and Truth in Fiction" for an interesting
discussion of tense and fiction.
'• It is possible for there to be a time-travel story that would not count as
anachronous according to definition (A). That would be a narrative in which
the events "travelled back to" in 1952 are presented first in viewing time
and the events leading up to the journey in 1982 are presented later in view-
ing time. So the objection is not that (A) makes all time-travel stories come
out as anachronous, but rather that it makes some of them so appear - and
in fact all the time-travel narratives I know about would come out as anach-
ronous on the definition.
2o8
Travels in narrative time
nition (A), but rather that there is an ambiguity in its statement.
That is, there is an ambiguity in the expression "the time of the
occurrence of X". Is this supposed to refer to objective time, or
to what is sometimes called personal or subjective time? With
time travel, as it occurs in stories and as it might occur in reality
if it ever does, there is a disparity between objective and per-
sonal time. The traveller travels back to a time earlier in objec-
tive time than the time she left; from 1982 to 1952, as it might
be. But for her, the events she encounters in 1952 are later (say,
an hour later) than the events she previously encountered in
1982. Here the time traveller's journey is thirty years into the
objective past, and one hour into her personal future.' 5
Normally, in stories and in reality, objective time and per-
sonal time run in the same direction and at the same rate, and
there is no need to distinguish between them. Time travel occurs
when they come apart. How is that possible? Perhaps in this
way: that the direction of time is the direction of causation - the
direction from causes to effects. That is why we can remember
the past but not the future, and why, more generally, we are
familiar with traces of the past in the present, but never en-
counter traces of the future in the present (unconfirmed reports
of premonitions aside). But suppose that not all causal processes
move in the same direction- that there is a small minority of
causal processes that swim against the tide. In that case we
could say that the predominant direction of causation is the di-
rection of objective time, and that, given this direction, objects
undergoing reversed causation are travelling back in objective
time. But for those involved, if they are sentient creatures ca-
pable of thought and memory, their journey backwards will end
after it began; for them, the reversing of causal processes will
mean that objectively later states of consciousness will affect ob-
jectively earlier states, and the travellers will remember doing
things in 1982 when they get to 1952; if the journey takes a
significant amount of time, they may end the journey hungrier
than they began it, have fuller beards and longer fingernails.
5
' On the distinction between objective and personal time see, e.g., David Lewis,
'The Paradoxes of Time Travel".
Imagination
The journey ends later in their personal time, and earlier in ob-
jective time.
With this distinction between objective and personal time, we
can solve our problem. In a time-travel story, events that occur
earlier in objective time may be recounted after events that occur
later in objective time. But according to the model of time travel
just proposed, the events occurring earlier in objective time are
occurring later in personal time. So if we take "the time of the
occurrence of X", as that expression occurs in (A), to refer to a
character's personal time, time-travel stories will not count as
anachronous according to that definition. Of course it would be
awkward to interpret "the time of the occurrence of X" in (A)
as sometimes referring to objective time and sometimes to per-
sonal time, according to whether the work in question is a time-
travel story or not. But we need not do that. We may simply
say that "the time of the occurrence of X" always refers to per-
sonal time, which, in the case of a story which involves no time
travel (whether it involves anachrony or not) will automatically
coincide with objective time.
It might be objected to this that what I have said depends
upon a complex and highly unobvious metaphysics of time, and
that we ought not to appeal to such things when we are ex-
plaining the basis of distinctions that ordinary people make, and
make in the same way even though they have no knowledge of
that metaphysics. But while I grant that the metaphysics is dif-
ficult to spell out, I claim that the central distinction it involves
- that between objective time and personal time - must in some
way be grasped by the viewer if he or she is to make sense of
the narrative as one involving time travel rather than anachrony.
It is surely part of our understanding of time-travel narratives
that "in some sense" the events travelled back to by the char-
acters occur later for them than do the events from which they
have travelled back; if that were not perceived to be the case, it
would be hard to explain how film viewers could ever distin-
guish between a time-travel narrative and an anachronous nar-
rative - and the whole basis of the objection to (A) above was
that we do indeed make such a distinction. So while the meta-
210
Travels in narrative time
physics I briefly outlined may be unobvious, its central distinc-
tion I take to be common currency.
The next objection will require some revision of (A), though
only a rather minor one; the need for it was pointed out to me,
again, by David Lewis. Fictions, including cinematic ones,
do frequently give us a good deal of information about the
temporal relations between the events they portray. But in this
area, as in others, they rarely give us complete information.
Sometimes they are unspecific about the temporal relations be-
tween events, even when those events are explicitly represented
onscreen in a determinate order in viewing time. And
sometimes it is not possible to make any reasonable inferences
- either from the order in viewing time or from any other source
- about the temporal relations between these events. Typical of
this phenomenon are those "summarizing" sequences which
might concern the arrival of the Martians: Martians are seen
landing in Paris, then seen landing in Washington, and so on.
But there need not be any implication that the order of showing
corresponds to the order of occurrence; we are simply to infer
that these events occurred at roughly the same time, and to-
gether constitute a sort of collective phenomenon.
In cases such as these we have, as we always do, a determi-
nate order of viewing,' 6 but the order of viewing does not cor-
respond to any order of occurrence in the story. I suggest that
this phenomenon deserves to be classed as a kind of anachrony
- "weak anachrony'' we might call it, since it involves a deter-
minate relation in viewing time but no determinate relation in
fictional time, rather than the strongly anachronous presenta-
tions we have been considering until now, which involve a de-
terminate relation in viewing time and a determinate (but
opposite) relation in fictional time. Our definition of anachrony
ought to cover weak anachrony as well as strong, and it can be
made to do so with a slight alteration:
6
' Devices like the split screen can present material simultaneously, but still the
temporal order is determinate - it is co-occurrence.
211
Imagination
(A*) Film F contains anachrony iff F contains representations
of fictional events X and Y, where the representation of
X in viewing time is after that of Y, but it is not fictional
that the time of the occurrence of X is after that of Y.
This differs from (A) in that the final words "it is fictional that
the time of the occurrence of X is before that of Y" are replaced
by the words "it is not fictional that the time of the occurrence
of X is after that of Y". Any case of strong anachrony as defined
by (A) is also a case of weak anachrony as defined by (A*), but
not vice versa.' 7
There may be further objection to (A) on the grounds that it
does not provide a necessary condition for anachrony, since it
fails to cover the "flashforward ending" exemplified by a film
whose temporal structure we might indicate as 1235.'8 Writers
on narrative have urged that such a structure should be classi-
fied as an ellipsis - a mere passing over in viewing time of rel-
evant story events between points 3 and 5 - rather than as an
anachrony.' 9 If that is right, the (A)/(A*) combination provides
a necessary and sufficient condition for anachrony, the only
possible cases of which are the flashback and the "returned"
flashforward (exemplified in the structure 132), which in my
taxonomy is the only flashforward there is. However, I have
some doubts about the standard treatment of ellipses which I
shall discuss in the appendix to this chapter.
7
' There is an interesting exploitation of the difference between weak and
strong anachrony in Black Widow (Bob Rafelson, 1986), which begins, appar-
ently, with two episodes of wives murdering their husbands. At first I took
this to be weak anachrony: sequential representation of roughly simultaneous
events involving distinct pairs of characters. Soon it turns out that it is the
same woman in both and that the murder represented second in fact oc-
curred considerably before the first.
8
' Here a number's actual value denotes its position in story time, while its
position in the sequence denotes its position in the narrative order.
9
' Describing a flashforward as a leaping ahead "to events subsequent to in-
termediate events", Seymour Chatman goes on, 'These intermediate events
must themselves be recounted at some later point, for otherwise the leap
would simply constitute an ellipsis" (Story and Discourse, p. 64). See also
Genette, Narrative Discourse, p. 43· But further, see the appendix to this chap-
ter.
212
Travels in narrative time
But there is a more serious worry concerning the definitions.
It can be explained most easily by concentrating on (A): while
(A) might be adequate as a condition for the presence of (strong)
anachrony, it is inadequate to specify the direction of the anach-
rony in any particular case. Imagine that X and Y are events of
the fiction satisfying condition (A). The onscreen representation
of Y occurs before the representation of X, but it is fictional that
Y occurs after X. Do we have here a flashback or a flashforward?
It might seem that we have, unambiguously, a flashback; X oc-
curs before Yin the story, but is represented after Yon screen,
so X is represented in a flashback. But this is not necessarily the
case. Y might have been represented in a flashforward, and the
transition to the representation of X is the return which com-
pletes that flashforward. In order to decide whether the transi-
tion in question signifies a flashback or a flashforward we shall
have to look at the representation of some other, suitably related,
story event, and decide whether that belongs to a flashback or
flashforward. If we are not to start on a regress, we shall have
to locate some transition that can be identified as a flashback or
flashforward without reference to another such transition.
Which one will that be?
We might hope to start with the fictional event presented first
in the narration, and anchor the rest of the narrative to it by
discovering a principle according to which the direction of an-
achrony can be judged unambiguously from there. But there is
no such principle. The event first presented may itself be a flash-
back or even a flashforward, and which one it is can depend on
its relation to later representations in the narrative. It is probably
true that there is a tendency to give a certain weight to the
hypothesis that a scene is temporally standard if that scene is
represented first, but that weighting can be overcome. Priority
in narration time offers no Archimedean point from which to
judge the temporal structure of the rest of the narrative.
It is tempting at this point to say that we need to establish
some story event or sequence of events P as present, and then to
judge the direction of anachrony in relation to P. But that would
be to appeal to a notion of tense, which I have said I will
not do.
213
Imagination
So the problem is this: while B-series concepts enable us to
identify an episode of anachrony, they do not enable us to say
what is the correct description of it; they do not enable us to say
whether it is a flashback or a flashforward. But most of the time
we find noncollusive agreement between subjects as to which
description is appropriate in particular cases: flashback or flash-
forward. If B-series notions offer no way of deciding between
the two, that agreement cannot be based on our employment of
B-series concepts alone. So any explication of the direction of
anachrony in terms of the B-series alone must be inadequate.
But I have not claimed that the direction of anachrony could
be explained in terms of the B-series alone. I have claimed that
the concept of anachrony itself could be so explained. It is one
thing to decide what constitutes anachrony, another to decide
how it is directed in particular cases. Of course I must give an
explanation of this direction. I shall do that by describing the
sorts of considerations that incline us to say we are dealing with
a flashback, or alternatively with a flashforward. These consid-
erations are not themselves temporal, and so they have nothing
to do with tense. They have to do with simplicity and the em-
phasizing of nontemporal connections between events in the
story.
Suppose we have an episode that is anachronous. We have
to choose between one description of it and another, and our
choosing is partly dictated by the principle that we should im-
pose as simple and straightforward a narrative structure as is
consistent with the film itself. Of course, the simplest structure
we can arrive at may in fact be rather complicated, and the film
may so defy our narrative expectations that all efforts to impose
on it a consistent structure fail. 20 It is just that we start with the
assumption of simplicity and introduce complexity as needed;
any other path would make narrative interpretation impossibly
difficult. Let us see how, in particular cases, the constraint of
simplicity works to dictate, or at least to suggest, one description
of anachrony rather than another.
"' Resnais's Last Year at Mnrienbad and Deren's Meshes of the Afternoon are often
cited as examples of this.
214
Travels in narrative time
215
Imagination
7 ·3 IS THIS REVISIONISM?
I have argued in this chapter, as in the preceding one, that some
of our common ways of speaking about the cinematic experience
3
' Flashforwards unconnected with premonition occur sometimes in credit se-
quences, for example, in Clayton's The Innocents and Wilder's Double Indem-
nity. The Godfather, Part 2 is notable for its use of objective flashbacks (unless
we are meant to view them as flashbacks within flashbacks, filtered through
the recollection of Vito Corleone, whose death occurs before the beginning
of Part 2; I think there is some evidence for this interpretation).
24
See, e.g., the discussion of They Shoot Horses, Don't They? in Bernard F. Dick,
Anatomy of Film, p. 1]8.
5
' Noel Burch, I think, was making a similar point when he asked, "Are not
jumps forward and backward in time really identical at the formal organic
level of a film?" (Theory of Film Practice, p. 8).
216
Travels in narrative time
are fundamentally wrong. Yet my aim has not really been a
revisionary one; I have not been trying to show that we should
approach the cinema in a new and unfamiliar way. My aim in
this chapter has been largely to rescue our judgements about
time and especially about anachrony in film from what I take to
be a false theory about the basis of those judgements. I have not
tried to argue that people are wrong in any straightforward
sense when they describe this or that movement of the film's
narration as a movement from the present to the past rather than
as one from the present to the future. I say only that we should
not take them literally when they employ words like "past",
"present'' and "future". The Reverend Dr Spooner is said to
have ended a puzzling sermon by saying, after a moment of
reflection, "Whenever I said 'Aristotle', I meant 'Saint Paul' ".
We would do well to believe him. It is sensible to reassign mean-
ings to a speaker's words if in doing so we can interpret him as
saying something significantly closer to the truth. At least, it is
sensible to do this if we can reasonably credit the speaker with
a sensitivity to the concepts that our meaning reassignments in-
troduce, and reasonably explain his utterance as the result of his
sensitivity to those concepts. We go along with Dr Spooner's
plea for reinterpretation because we believe him to have had a
grasp of the concept of Saint Paul, and we find it plausible to
think that what he said in the sermon was the outcome, in part,
of that grasp. We do not reinterpret the speech of witch finders
so as to make them early investigators of epilepsy, because it is
not reasonable to credit them with a sensitivity to that concept
- they would come out, by our lights, as very poor epilepsy
discriminators. But it is perfectly reasonable to assume that com-
petent and alert film watchers have a sensitivity to those con-
cepts in terms of which I explain the phenomenon of cinematic
anachrony: temporal but untensed ones, plus the machinery of
narrative interpretation. So we should treat them as Dr Spooner
would have us treat him.
There is one somewhat surprising consequence of the view I
have advanced. It is that the concept of the direction of anach-
rony is on a quite different footing from the concept of anach-
217
Imagination
rony itself. Anachrony is explainable in terms of temporal
concepts. The direction of anachrony is not; it is fundamentally
a dramatic notion.
218
Travels in narrative time
bothered, could truly and at any time say "I am here now'', just
as we can. So we can say: the space and time of cinematic fiction
is structurally like the space and time of the real world.
222
Part III
Interpretation
I
N
to us courtesy of our capacities for recognizing the objects
depicted. The process of recognizing depictive content
hardly counts as interpretive. But there is more to under-
standing a film than merely recognizing its depictive content.
That is where interpretation starts. In Chapter 8, I develop a
theory of interpretation for literary and filmic narratives. But
there are important differences between the kinds of narra-
tives available to film and to literature. In Chapter 9, I illus-
trate this diversity through the example of narrative unreli-
ability.
Chapter 8
The interpretive problem
Even if we reject the thesis that creative interpretation
aims to discover some actual historical intention, the
concept of intention nevertheless provides the formal
structure for all interpretive claims. I mean that an
interpretation is by nature a report of a purpose.
Ronald Dworkin
229
Interpretation
story's significance, message, or relation to other stories. Con-
versely, an argument about symbols or genres that is not re-
flected in the least disagreement at the level of what is fictional
seems an excellent candidate for being a spurious or at least
unresolvable dispute.
You might hope to explain agreement at the level of narrative
interpretation without appeal to universal principles of inter-
pretation by arguing that genre-specific principles would be suf-
ficient to generate agreement. This cannot be right. Deciding
what genre a work belongs to is itself an interpretive matter/
one of deciding to give certain elements in the work a signifi-
cance that depends on their relations to all the other elements
of the work. There is no checklist of features that determines
whether the work is a screwball comedy or a film noire. But as
with other interpretive judgements, we do find a broad measure
of agreement between agents concerning what genre this or that
work belongs to, and so the argument for their being interpre-
tive principles applies as much here as elsewhere. It sometimes
happens that the viewer knows what genre the work belongs to
by some independent route; it might be advertised in such a
way as to make its genre clear. But this is not how it always is,
and we usually are capable of deciding, in an unprompted way,
on the genre of a work by seeing it.
I am not claiming that there are no local principles to be de-
ployed in a media-, genre-, or style-dependent way. There may
well be such principles, but they are not the only ones. Nor am
I claiming that the interpretive method which I regard as uni-
versal always or even usually enables us to arrive at one single
and uncontroversially correct interpretation of the story. Inter-
pretive principles are never mechanical rules that can be applied
as algorithms, and there is often room for rational disagreement
as to whether the rule has been correctly applied in this case;
such disagreement is one source of the plurality of interpreta-
tions. Another is the fact that the rules, even when there is no
disagreement concerning their application, can sometimes lead
230
The interpretive problem
to a tie between competing interpretations: we shall see that the
rules do not guarantee that one interpretation will always be
preferable to the rest.
Before I develop the theory of interpretation I shall need some
distinctions, and some theses about the relations between the
things thus distinguished. That will occupy the next two sec-
tions.
233
Interpretation
5
Complex dispositions to behave may be constitutive of belief, but that is an-
other matter.
The interpretive problem
237
Interpretation
6
For more on unreliable narrators see Chapter 9·
7
For more on this point see my Nature of Fiction, chapters 2 and 3·
The interpretive problem
states responsible for a person's behaviour. The next section
brings these two projects more closely together.
240
The interpretive problem
241
Interpretation
the author's intention, and the content of his intention is the
content of the story.9
On this view, narrative interpretation turns out to be just a
special case of ordinary, conversational interpretation, the inter-
pretation of the casual remarks of speakers we encounter every
day. We figure out the meaning of a speaker's utterance when
we figure out what the speaker meant by uttering it - when we
figure out, in other words, what intentions the speaker had that
caused him to make that utterance. The difference between the
conversational and the literary case is just a matter of the length
and complexity of the text concerned; of its having, in the lit-
erary case, generally a written rather than a spoken form; and
of the consequent leisure that the relative permanence of writing
affords us for reflection in our interpretive efforts.
In Part II I argued that fictions are things we typically respond
to by engaging in simulations; fictions provide the inputs, or
some of them, for off-line simulations. But in order to know
what inputs are appropriate - should I give myself the pretend
belief that the governess sees ghosts, or the pretend belief that
she is mad?- I need to do some interpreting. A decision about
what the story is determines the contents of my pretend inputs.
But this suggests that fictions may encourage simulation in an-
other way: I need to know what the story is, and to do that I
need to know what story-telling intentions the author most
probably had. The best way to carry out the latter task may be
to do some simulating; I put myself in the author's position,
thinking of myself as the person who produced the text, and
ask myself, ''What story-telling intentions would have led me
to write that text?" If I can run a simulation in which having
those story-telling intentions leads to the (off-line) decision to
write this very text, then I can say that it is at least initially
plausible that the author did have those intentions. That will not
be the end of the matter; reflection on the historical and cultural
differences between the author and myself may convince me
that my simulation did not do enough to correct for differences
Let us call the idea that the interpreter's task is to discover the
author's intended meaning for the text "Real Author Intention-
alism", or RAI. It will soon be apparent why I choose this name.
RAI is scarcely a popular option among theorists of criticism,
and some of the arguments against it are good ones. For one
thing, RAI denies the gap between aspiration and performance,
making it impossible for the author to fail to tell the story he
intends to tell. The story he does tell is, according to RAI, just
the one he intended to tell, and it is consequently the job of the
interpreter to discover what his intentions were. But authors
can, and sometimes do, fail to tell the stories they intend to tell.
The author can think that enough has been said to indicate a
certain development of plot or character, and be mistaken, be-
cause readers cannot reasonably be expected to grasp that de-
velopment on the basis of the text he gives them. In that case
the story he intends to tell is not, in at least some respect, the
story he tells.
Defenders of RAI sometimes claim that the author's inten-
tions to which we may legitimately appeal are not merely pri-
vate mental occurrences, but embodied intentions: intentions
which could be understood by a suitably receptive reader on the
basis of a reading of the text, and without access to information
Interpretation
intended but not embodied will not count, for interpretive pur-
poses, as intended at all. But the problem is not merely how to
exclude interpretations that might have been in the author's
mind but never got into the work- the problem the embodiment
condition is supposed to solve - but how to allow, on realist
grounds, for interpretations which never were in the author's
mind at all. For example, some readers of The Possessed have
found Stepan Trofimovich to be a redeemed character, but Dos-
toyevsky' s notebooks do not indicate that he intended him to
be seen in this light. Yet there are some intuitive grounds for
saying that readers who interpret the story that way are onto
something. How could the intention for us to see Stepan as
11
245
Interpretation
to the story. If we take our goal to be finding the real author's
narrative intentions, we have to acknowledge that authorial er-
ror can make the text not the best guide to what those intentions
are, and interest may shift from the text to psychobiography.
But no amount of deconstructive rhetoric should make us forget
the centrality of the text. In interpretation, we make inferences
to narrative intentions so as to illuminate and render coherent
the text we have before us, not some other text the author might
have written, one perhaps more in tune with her actual inten-
tions. It is possible for an author to be moved by certain nar-
rative intentions, but fail to give proper effect to them in her
text-tokening activity: she can be wrong in thinking that enough
has been said to indicate a development of plot or character,
and a reading made most plausible by her text can be one she
fails to comprehend. When that happens (as in small ways it
commonly does) the path recommended by RAI- to infer, from
her diaries and acquaintances, the narrative intentions the au-
thor actually had - will not, by assumption of authorial error,
illuminate and make coherent the text we have. The interpreter
who takes that path has ceased to be an interpreter of the work,
and his intentional hypothesizing serves rather to interpret an-
other, hypothetical work- the one that would have been written
had the author's narrative intentions gone well. By contrast, IAI
can guarantee the centrality of the text, irrespective of authorial
error. According to IAI, the task is to hypothesize narrative in-
tentions which make as good sense of the text we have as can
be made of it, irrespective of whether they were the real author's
intentions or not.' 5 Since IAI has us look for the interpretation
which makes best sense of the given text regardless of the psy-
chological facts, it gives the text a properly constitutive as well
as an evidential role.
5
' "As can be made of it" because it is not always possible to avoid imputing
some degree of authorial incompetence and textual incoherence. The dis-
crepant reporting of Natasha's age in War and Peace could be reconciled by
assuming Tolstoy intended us to infer that she is a time traveller, but that
would clash with the conclusion, well-supported by other aspects of the
work, that no fantasy or science-fiction elements are intended in this story.
IAI demands only that we maximize coherence.
246
The interpretive problem
Having admitted that the real author's intentions are not deci-
sive for interpretation, why insist that the interpreter's task is to
construct another, this time hypothetical, author? Why not say
instead that the interpretive problem is simply to go from what
is explicit in the text to what is implicit, where what is implicit
might not correspond to anything anyone intended? But there
can be no meaning implicit in the words and sentences of the
text itself; the meaning that there is in the text itself is all explicit,
literal meaning. What we call implicit in the text is what we
think of as intended (perhaps, indeed, unconsciously intended)
by an agent who hopes to convey by his words more than the
words themselves literally mean. A text can encourage in the
reader's mind beliefs about what those intentions were even
when, as a matter of fact, the real author had no such intentions.
IAI says that it is what the text makes it reasonable to believe
was intended, and not what actually was intended, that deter-
mines the content of the story.
There is another reason we can't ignore intention. Narratives
obstruct, mislead and manipulate us by their selective presen-
tation of events. But no text, no sequence of visual images, can
do those things; such things require agency. Most of the ways
we describe narrative make no sense if we cut narrative off from
the agency which produced it. Writers on narrative sometimes
ignore this. Thus David Bordwell, speaking of film:
As for the implied author, this construct adds nothing to our
understanding of filmic narration. No trait we could assign to
an implied author of a film could not more simply be ascribed
to the narration itself: it sometimes suppresses information, it
often restricts our knowledge, it generates curiosity, it creates
a tone, and so on. To give every film a narrator or implied
author is to indulge in an anthropomorphic fiction ....
[Filmic] narration is better understood as the organization of
a set of cues for the construction of a story. This presupposes
a perceiver, but not any sender, of a message.' 6
6
' Bordwell, Narration in the Fiction Film, p. 62
247
Interpretation
Bordwell speaks of a narration which "suppresses information".
There is no literal sense in the idea of an unnarrated narration
which suppresses information. Without recourse to the idea of
intention you can speak of a system that fails to deliver all the
information you want, but not of a system that suppresses infor-
mation. And the idea of suppression (rather than just of infor-
mational incompleteness) is essential to Bordwell's description
of filmic narration and our reaction to it; we feel, in some cases,
that we are being deliberately deprived of information (as when
we see only the hands of the murderer), that we are being de-
prived of it for some dramatic or emotional purpose, that our
expectations are being played with. None of this would make
sense unless we understood the story as told.
If Bordwell's claim has any plausibility for the filmic case, I
believe it derives ultimately from what I have called the Imag-
ined Observer Hypothesis. If we think of the viewer's imagi-
native involvement in the movie as requiring him to imagine
that he is viewing the action from within the space of the film,
then of course it would be out of place for him to suppose that
the images he receives are being presented to him by a control-
ling intelligence that presents them in a certain way and in a
certain order to tell a certain story by their means. But if we
reject this view and think of the viewer's imaginative engage-
ment with the film as characterized by perceptual imagining
rather than by imagining seeing, there is no such objection to
the idea that cinematic fictions are experienced as mediated; in
fact we are then obliged to think of them in that way.
248
The interpretive problem
is whether we should concern ourselves with the real intentions
behind the work, or with the intentions which seem to have
been productive of the work.' 8 I say our concern is with the
latter.
Scripts and Scenes: Aspects of Schema Theory). Such schemata are important for
interpretation, but their importance is primarily in providing us with evi-
dence about how the author would probably have intended the story to be
filled out.
8
' A point made by Ronald Dworkin in Law's Empire. Some of my conclusions
in this essay have been influenced by Dworkin's work on interpretation (see
also his Matter of Principle).
249
Interpretation
(and therefore best) interpretation, it comes out true, since all its
constituents come out true.
" In both cases - the filmic and the linguistic - the order of production can
have consequences for what is implicated, in Grice's sense.
Interpretation
This promising beginning notwithstanding, I want to argue
that photographic meaning cannot play the same kind of evi-
dential role in cinema that the literal meanings of words and
sentences can play in interpreting literary fictions. There are two
reasons for this.
The first is that photographic meaning does not bear on the
story in cinema in the same way that linguistic meaning does
in literature. In literature the text consists of words and sen-
tences which describe events within the fictional world; they can
be thought of as doing that in virtue, partly, of the literal mean-
ings they have. Thus if the text says, "Holmes and Watson spent
the evening at Baker Street", we may decide to take that sen-
tence as a literal description of the activities of the characters on
a particular occasion. We might decide instead to take that state-
ment nonliterally, as metaphor or irony, or even as the words
of an unreliable speaker. In that case we would not take the
literal meaning of the sentence as a reliable guide to what hap-
pened in the fiction. But the literal meaning of the text can be,
and sometimes is, a reliable guide, and we always need to know
what the literal meaning is.
But with cinema it is different. We cannot ever take the pho-
tographic meaning of an image to coincide with what happens
in the story at that point. For the photographic meaning is al-
ways something to do with real people (actors, mostly) perform-
ing real actions in the real world. There cannot be a photograph
of something that does not exist, or of an act no one ever per-
formed. But the characters of the fictional film are, at least typ-
ically, characters that do not exist, and the events of the fictional
story are, at least typically, events that do not occur. There is
always a disparity between photographic meaning and what is
true in the fictional story.
The second reason photographic meaning cannot be regarded
as the evidential analogue of linguistic meaning is that viewers
are sometimes unaware of, or mistaken about, the photographic
meaning of a cinematic image. But their being unaware of it or
mistaken about it does not automatically count as evidence that
they lack some piece of knowledge vital to working out what is
going on in the story. A shot may be a trick shot; it may seem
254
The interpretive problem
to show a man falling a distance that no man involved in the
filming ever did fall. It may seem to show a fantastical creature,
or a man walking on water. Or it may be a shot that seems to
be a distant or blurred view of the main actor but is actually a
cinematic image of a stand-in. In such cases the members of the
audience will sometimes know that there is some trick involved,
but they will seldom have any idea what the trick is; they will
have little idea, that is, about what the camera actually records.
They will, in those cases, therefore have little or no idea about
the photographic meaning of the shot in question. But if there
is a doubt in the minds of the audience about what is happening
in the story - or a disagreement about it - it is implausible to
suppose that it will be resolved by teaching them more about
the cinematographer's tricks of the trade. By learning those
tricks they might learn something about cinema in general, but
they would not be put in a better position to work out what is
happening in the story. In the case of literary interpretation, on
the other hand, it is always true that a reader who lacks knowl-
edge of the literal meaning of a passage in the text will be helped
in forming a reasoned opinion about what is going on in the
story by learning what that literal meaning is. To have the text
and not to know its literal meaning is to be like a monolingual
Chinese reader trying to make sense of a novel in English. So
what I have called the photographic meaning of cinematic im-
ages cannot play the role of evidence for an interpretation in the
way that the literal meaning of words and sentences can.
However, while the photographic meaning of the image may
be unclear to the viewer, it is at least usually possible for the
viewer, given the right background of cultural knowledge, to
say that this image appears to represent a man falling off a build-
ing, or a creature of fantastical appearance, or a man walking
on water; you can make a decision about what the image ap-
pears to represent without knowing a great deal about the con-
text of surrounding images that occur in the film. It may be that
a certain image functions within the diegesis to represent a
dream, a lie or an hallucination, and that it does so can be dis-
covered only by seeing and interpreting the whole film. Still,
one can say of the image, pretty much on the basis of viewing
255
Interpretation
it alone, that it seems to represent a woman running down a
corridor while arms protrude from the walls on either side, or
whatever. It would be possible, if anyone could be bothered to
do it, to establish meaning at this level of "seeming" or appear-
ance for any particular shot by finding a viewer who (i) had no
knowledge of the rest of the film, and (ii) could not identify the
actors in the film and generally knew nothing about its construc-
tion, and then getting this person to describe what the image
represents. The answer given, assuming the viewer is alert and
cooperative, would correspond roughly to what I shall here call
"appearance meaning". There would no doubt be some varia-
tion in the detail of each individual's description, reflecting dif-
ferent levels of attention and visual acuity, but there would in
general be a large measure of agreement between viewers about
what the image appears to represent. It is this possibility of in-
tersubjective agreement that justifies our saying that here we
have another kind of meaning for the image - appearance mean-
ing.
It is appearance meaning, and not photographic meaning,
which plays the role in the interpretation of film that literal
meaning plays in the interpretation of literature. It is the data
to be explained. Appearance meaning is evidence meaning. The
shot shows what appears to be children being attacked by a
flock of birds (though in fact it may be a trick shot that does
not record any such event). The question the interpreter needs
to ask, then, is: why is that shot, with just that appearance, in-
serted in the film just at this point, between these other shots?
The answer will be: because the insertion of that shot was in-
tended to tell us something about what is happening in the
story, and how that event stands in relation to others in the
story. But while appearance meaning is, for film, the analogue
of literary, textual meaning, it should be evident from what
was said in Chapter 4 that appearance meaning is not under-
stood in anything like the way that linguistic meaning is. There
are no atoms of appearance meaning out of which are built
more complex units of meaning, for every visible part of the
image is meaningful. Yet we are able to understand what is
represented in images we have not seen before. Appearance
256
The interpretive problem
meaning displays the natural generativity possessed by all pic-
torial kinds of meaning.
When we see films we are generally not conscious of what I
have called appearance meaning, but this is not grounds for
thinking it plays no role in our interpretive strategies. We are
rarely conscious, after all, of the literal meaning of the text we
read. If we could not identify each shot, as we see it, at least
roughly at the level of appearance meaning, we would find it
impossible to interpret the film: we would not be able to rei-
dentify characters and locations from one shot to another; we
would not be able to say what kind of action was being under-
taken or what kind of event was happening; and we would have
no expectations about what would follow, and so no sense of
the rightness or disparity of succeeding images. To see a film
and not be able to specify its meaning at the level of appearance
would be like looking at the pages of a book written in an un-
known language; in neither case would it be possible to interpret
the work.
Sometimes appearance meaning is unclear. If the scene is very
dark, or if the location or action undertaken is very unfamiliar,
we may not be able to judge the appearance meaning of the shot
as we see it, or we may be heavily dependent on the context of
surrounding shots and the interpretation of them we have so
far built up in order to judge it. For example, the novice viewer
of The Searchers will not immediately understand that the uni-
formly dark screen at the beginning has any appearance mean-
ing at all; it is only when the door opens to reveal an exterior
scene that she will realize that the featureless screen represented
a darkened interior. But the same can happen with a text. We
do not understand every sentence we read, and some texts con-
tain sentences that deliberately challenge or defy understanding.
But this has no tendency to show that textual meaning is irrel-
evant to understanding. If the text entirely lacked meaning, or
belonged to a language you didn't understand, you wouldn't be
able to interpret it. If no image in the film had any appearance
meaning, you wouldn't be able to interpret that either.
So filmic interpretation is like literary interpretation in this: it
takes as input certain data, and gives as output a hypothesis
257
Interpretation
concerning what story a rational agent would most probably
have intended to communicate by means of that data. Filmic
interpretation is subject to the same vaguenesses, ambiguities
and indeterminacies that attend literary interpretations because
in both cases the relation between data, hypotheses and the prin-
ciples that govern inferences to intention are in various ways
vague, ambiguous and indeterminate. But in neither the literary
nor the filmic case is every interpretation as good as every other
one. It is just that there is not always an interpretation which is
uniquely best.
Filmic interpretation differs from literary interpretation both
in the nature of its data inputs and the competencies required
for processing them. In the literary case the data is linguistic
meaning and the required competence is with the syntax and
semantics of the language. In the filmic case the inputs are cin-
ematic images correctly juxtaposed; the required competence is
the ability to understand the appearance meaning of those im-
ages, a competence based on the possession of visual capacities
to recognize objects, their properties and relations.
259
Chapter 9
Narrative and narrators
For films as for novels, we would do well to distin-
guish between a presenter of the story, the narrator
(who is a component of the discourse), and the creator
of both the story and the discourse (including the nar-
rator): that is, the implied author.
Seymour Chatman
I have been arguing that our basic interpretive strategy, for film
as for literature, is to look for an intentional explanation of what
is put before us - image or text. I have said nothing yet about
the role of a narrator in all this. Here we shall find some im-
portant differences between the roles of narrators in literature
and in film; film offers much less scope for the narrator than
does literature. Also, film requires us to acknowledge that there
can be unreliable narration without there being any narrator to
whom we can ascribe the unreliability. This will require a sub-
stantial revision of accepted theory. This chapter will also lend
weight to the claims of Chapter 8 concerning the implied author;
it will specify in some detail how appeal to the implied author
helps us make sense of the text or image. It will also show how
the concept of the implied author is more significant for under-
standing narrative than is that of the narrator.
There is one other issue of general significance on which this
chapter will bear. Recent writing on the theory of literature and
film has tended to focus on ways in which the act of interpre-
tation resembles or exemplifies pathological behaviour. There
have been attempts to characterize the reader's, and sometimes
the writer's, relation to the work as having an obsessive, pos-
sessive, violent and quasi-sexual nature. No doubt these things
find their place in any human activity. But they are very far from
being the whole story when it comes to interpretation. In op-
position to this tendency I hold that interpretation is a largely
26o
Narrative and narrators
rational enterprise governed by the standards of evidence and
probability that apply in other areas. One thing I hope to do
here is to show how this approach can help us understand why
certain kinds of narrative effects are common while others are
not.
Briefly, my argument will be this: standard accounts of nar-
rative unreliability require there to be a narrator - a fictional
being who belongs within the world of the story and who
claims, falsely, to be recounting events of which he or she has
knowledge. But I shall argue that there are narratives which are
unreliable even when there is no narrator. In these cases, unre-
liability is not the product of a disparity between two conflicting
viewpoints, one internal (the narrator's) and one external. Rather
it is the product of a single, external viewpoint which has, as
we shall see, a rather complex structure. This, I say, enables us
to make sense of unreliability in film, without committing us to
implausible claims about the kinds of narrators which films em-
body. Finally I shall show how unreliability in film and other
media connects with another narrative trope- that of ambiguity.
Ambiguity, I shall argue, facilitates unreliability in ways that tell
us something about the scope and limits of narrative itself.
' So the implied author, as I use that notion, is always "extradiegetic" in Ge-
nette's sense (Narrative Discourse).
2
Here I shall ignore a tendency which some writers on narrative have of using
the terms "narrator" and "author'' to refer to things which could not literally
be narrators or authors because they are not persons. Thus, Christian Metz
speaks of the viewer's perception that the film images are organized by a
''grand image-maker'', which Metz then goes on to describe as "the film itself
as linguistic object" (Film Language: A Semiotics of the Cinema, pp. 2o-21). See
also remarks on Seymour Chatman in note 14 to Chapter 8, this volume.
Narrative and narrators
3
A distinction is sometimes made between intradiegetic narrators who are
characters and narrators who are not (cf. Genette's distinction between homo-
diegetic and heterodiegetic narrators in his Narrative Discourse, pp. 244-245).
But this is a distinction without a difference. The narrator is someone who,
within the scope of the story itself, knows of certain events and recounts them
to us (reliably or unreliably). His knowing requires that he belongs to the
world of the fiction, and so he is a character in it, if an unnamed one. Whether
he knows because he took part in the action or because he was told about it
Interpretation
belongs within the world of the story, just as Julius Caesar and
I belong to the same world (the actual world), even though what
I tell you about him I know only through hearsay.
The reader trying to figure out what happens in this story
now has two voices to attend to: the (implied) author's and the
narrator's. The authorial voice may not be explicitly signalled,
but readers are aware of its presence if they know that what
they are reading is fiction, because fictions have to be thought
of as works produced with certain intentions. Sensitive readers
may be able to spot a tension between these two voices, the
authorial and the narratorial. The narrator insists that there are
ghosts. But why has the author made this a story in which no
one else, apparently, sees or has knowledge of them? These and
like clues suggest that, perhaps, the author's intentions concern-
ing the story conflict with the narrator's certainties. But in such
a conflict the author always wins. Author and narrator do not
speak with the same authority. The narrator, within the world
of the story, is a mere reporter of events, and a fallible one like
all such reporters. The author, standing outside the story, is not
conveying to the audience a set of possibly erroneous beliefs
about the story world; the author makes things be true in that
story world (makes things "be fictional", as I say) simply by
decree or stipulation. If we as readers find it reasonable to infer
that the author intended that there not be any ghosts in the
story, then we must conclude that there simply aren't any. So
narrators are unreliable when their claims contradict the inferred
intentions of the author. This view of narrative unreliability, or
something broadly like it, is widely accepted. It is expressed in
a summarizing remark of Wayne Booth's: "I have called a nar-
rator reliable when he speaks for or acts in accordance with the
norms of the work (which is to say, the implied author's norms),
unreliable when he does not." 4 That, roughly, is how it is in
later (or because of the operation of magic, if that's how things are in the
story) is of no moment to his being a character. There is a distinction here,
but it is best understood as that based on epistemic proximity to the action,
and it admits of degrees. It is of no special relevance to our present concerns.
• Booth, Rhetoric of Fiction, pp. 158-159, emphasis in the original. One mislead-
ing feature of this remark is the implication that narrative unreliability is
Narrative and narrators
266
Narrative and narrators
man who has been in trouble with the law and who is subse-
quently and falsely accused of a murder-robbery. Wilson argues
that this natural interpretation of the film is, on closer exami-
nation, not supported by, and is in fact at certain crucial points
undermined by, the film's narration and its studiedly selective
presentation of events. On Wilson's view, a right interpretation
of the film would have us withhold judgement as to Eddie's
guilt or innocence. But that is certainly not what most viewers
" I agree with Christian Metz that "the explicit enunciators in the film are
always embedded" (Metz, "The Impersonal Enunciation", p. 768).
12
Wilson, Narration in Light.
268
Narrative and narrators
of the film have done; generations of critics and lay viewers have
accepted the view that Eddie is an innocent victim. But there
does not seem to be any embedded narrator in the film to whom
unreliability might be described. And, given the film's dramatic
structure, it is not easy to come up with a covert embedded nar-
rator of any plausibility.' 3
I am not entirely convinced by Wilson's interpretation, but it
does mesh well with parts of the film which are otherwise hard
to understand. And if Wilson's interpretation does not apply in
all detail to Lang's film, it is not difficult to imagine a film,
different from Lang's in minor ways, to which it does. So we
may conclude that it is possible for there to be unreliable narra-
tion in film where no embedded narrator is present - and when
it comes to definitions, possible counterexamples are as telling
as actual ones. In that case we really will have to look for an-
other definition of narrative unreliability if we are to accom-
modate You Only Live Once and like cases. Anyway, I shall
assume, for the sake of the argument, that Wilson is right about
the film.
So You Only Live Once is an unreliable narrative without an
unreliable narrator.' 4 What, then, is the source of its unreliability,
if not the tension between author and embedded narrator? Un-
reliability can have its source, I claim, in a certain kind of com-
plex intention on the part of the implied author. Let me explain.
An agent can do something with an intention of the following
complex kind: she creates or presents something which she in-
tends to be taken as evidence of her intentions, and she intends
that a superficial grasp of that evidence will suggest that her
intention was <1>, whereas a better, more reflective grasp of the
' Perhaps you think it analytic that narrative must have a narrator (as does
3
Sarah Kozloff: "Because narrative films are narrative, someone must be nar-
rating"; Invisible Storytellers, p. 115, quoted approvingly in Chatman, Coming
to Terms, p. 133). But then you simply object to my terminology, and I could
avoid the objection by using another term to refer to the vehicle of narrator-
less story-telling. Consider it done.
'• As Cary Groner pointed out, An Occurrence at Owl Creek (1961) seems to be
a case of unreliability without a narrator. But here the unreliability is tem-
porary; that the film's images are largely the imaginings of a character is
made evident at the end.
Interpretation
evidence will suggest that her intention was 'I'. An example:
Freida compliments Fred on his sophisticated sense of humour.
Her flattery seems out of line with what we know of Freida's
acerbic personality. But now we see that it was all ironic and
intended to be recognized, ultimately, as more of the abuse she
usually heaps upon Fred. Freida's performance was unreliable
in my sense, and there may be people, Fred among them, who
didn't get to the second stage, because that took just a little more
calculating than some of us can be relied on to make.
That seems to be what is going on in You Only Live Once; we
take the images and sounds that make up the film as intended
one way. But if we are scrupulous in our examination of those
images, we find peculiarities, incongruities and apparently un-
motivated elements that start to fall into place when we see that
it can be interpreted in another way. Their falling into place
consists in their being seen as intended to suggest that second,
less obvious interpretation. Narratives which are the product of
this kind of two-tier system of intentions constitute a distinctive
and especially challenging class, and I do not think that they are
very well understood. I hope to change that somewhat in the
rest of this chapter.
'
5
In that case we have a "seductive" unreliable narrator. The classic case is
The Tum of the Screw. Where Booth's definition applies and mine does not,
we have an unseductive one. See James Phelan, "Narrative Discourse, Lit-
erary Character and Ideology", in idem, Reading People, Reading Plots, p. 137.
Sometimes cases of unobviously unreliable narratives are described as "am-
biguous" (e.g., by Shlomith Rimmon-Kenan, Narrative Fiction, p. 103), but I
wish to use this term for another purpose. See Section 9-4-
Interpretation
that my characterization of unreliability in terms of a complex
intention - call it "complex unreliability" - is of greater theo-
retical and critical interest than the familiar Boothian character-
ization in terms of a disparity of outlook between the narrator
and the author- call it "Booth unreliability". There are of course
interesting cases of Booth unreliability, but they tend also to be
cases of complex unreliability, that is, cases in which the nar-
rator's unreliability is to some degree intended as unobvious.
We are past the point where a narrator's unreliability is intrin-
sically interesting, because we no longer presume that narrators
will be reliable. Without that presumption, narratorial unrelia-
bility is, of itself, no more significant than the mendacity of a
dramatic speaker - no more significant, that is, from the point
of view of a theory of narrative. But unreliability that is to some
degree hidden is of theoretical interest because its operation de-
pends on delicately balanced inferential strategies that the
reader must undertake. To get a good sense of the nature of
these inferences will require the introduction of another narra-
tive concept, that of an ambiguous narrative.
6
' The film narratives used by Bordwell and Thompson to illustrate ambiguity
(Day of Wrath and Last Year at Marienbad) would count as ambiguous on my
definition. Bordwell and Thompson associate ambiguity closely with causal-
ity (Film Art, p. 250). Their idea seems to be that the work is ambiguous to
the extent that the causes or effects of narrative elements are unclear. Since
most narrative events, like most events in real life, have many distinct partial
causes and many distinct effects, we shall need to distinguish the significant
274
Narrative and narrators
from the nonsignificant causes and effects. My proposal can be read as doing
that.
7
' See my "Interpretation and Objectivity".
275
Interpretation
Note that You Only Live Once is, on Wilson's account, both
ambiguous and unreliable. At first the question "Is Eddie guilty
of murder?" seems to be answered by the narrative. But we see,
on closer inspection, that it is left open by it. That also seems to
me the best case that can be made on behalf of a psychological
interpretation of The Turn of the Screw: reflection doesn't show
that there are no ghosts; at best it shows that another hypothesis
does about as well as the supernatural one when it comes to
explaining the text.' 8 In that case might there be some internal
connection between unreliability and ambiguity?
Complex unreliability does not necessitate ambiguity. But
complex unreliability is an easier effect to achieve when it in-
volves ambiguity than when it does not. The task of the maker
of a complex-unreliable narration is difficult. It is to set clues at
two levels: at level1, where the clues are more obvious but only
superficially persuasive; and at level 2, where they are less ob-
vious but more weighty when reflected upon. But the degree of
difficulty of the task varies from case to case, and one deter-
minant of it is what we might call the epistemic distance between
the two levels: increase the distance and you increase the diffi-
culty. By "distance" I mean the disparity between what you
want to convey at a first impression and what you want the
audience to grasp on further reflection. The greater the distance
in this sense, the greater the subtlety and complexity of the rea-
soning the audience will have to go through to cover the gap,
and the less likely it is that they will succeed. Trying to raise
the probability of success in such a case by reinforcing the clues
at level 2 may simply undermine the whole project by making
the inference to level 2 more obvious and natural than that to
level1.
8
' Jack Clayton's The Innocents, a film version of The Tum of the Screw, is inter-
esting in this regard. One difficulty the film makers had to contend with was
that a significant proportion of the film's audience would bring with them
their knowledge of the unreliability in James's story, which would make it
impossible for the film to achieve the same effect; the audience would be
primed for the discovery of the higher-level clues from the start. As I un-
derstand the film, their solution, intelligently enough, was to forgo any at-
tempt at complex unreliability and to settle for ambiguity.
Narrative and narrators
279
Interpretation
position of unreliability, the narrator a merely conditional one.
That is why there can be narratives which are genuinely unre-
liable - rather than merely ambiguous or misleading - even
when there is no narrator in whom we can locate the source of
the unreliability.
280
In conclusion
281
In conclusion
velop a general theory of interpretation which accounts for both
literature and film. According to this theory, interpretation is
explanation - explanation by reference to intentional causes.
With a novel or a film, the interpreter's task is to formulate
plausible hypotheses about the story-telling intentions produc-
tive of the work. Still, literature and film offer rather different
kinds of narrative possibilities and, in particular, the role for
unreliable narrators is more restricted in film than in literature.
Film shows the need for a category of unreliable but narratorless
narratives.
Named propositions
286
Bibliography
288
Bibliography
Halliwell, Leslie, The Filmgoer's Companion, 3d ed., New York: Hill &
Wang, 1970.
Hardin, C. L., "Color Subjectivism", in A. Goldman (ed.), Readings in
Philosophy and Cognitive Science.
Harman, Gilbert, "Eco Location", in M. Cohen and G. Mast (eds.), Film
Theory and Criticism, 2d ed., New York: Oxford University Press,
1979·
"Semiotics and the Cinema: Metz and Wollen", in M. Cohen and G.
Mast (eds.), Film Theory and Criticism, 2d ed., New York: Oxford
University Press, 1979.
Harvey, Nigel, ''Wishful Thinking Impairs Belief-Desire Reasoning: A
Case of Decoupling Failure in Adults?" Cognition, 45 (1992): 141-
162.
Haugeland, John, "The Nature and Plausibility of Cognitivism", Be-
havioral and Brain Sciences, 2 (1978): 215-26o.
Heal, Jane, "Replication and Functionalism", in J. Butterfield (ed.), Lan-
guage, Mind, and Logic, Cambridge University Press, 1986.
Henderson, B., "Tense, Mood and Voice in Film (Notes after Genette)",
Film Quarterly, 36, no. 4 (1983): 4-17.
"Two Types of Film Theory'', in B. Nichols (ed.), Movies and Methods:
An Anthology, vol. 1, Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of Cal-
ifornia Press, 1985.
Hirsch, E. D., Validity in Interpretation, New Haven, Conn.: Yale Uni-
versity Press, 1967.
Holton, Richard, "Intentions, Response-Dependence and Immunity
from Error", in Peter Menzies (ed.), Response-Dependent Concepts:
Working Papers in Philosophy, no. 1, Canberra: Research School of
Social Sciences, Australian National University, 1991.
Humphreys, Glyn W., and Jane M. Riddoch (eds.), Visual Object Proc-
essing: A Cognitive Neuropsychological Approach, London: Erlbaum,
1987-
Irwin, Timothy, Meaning and Convention, M.A. thesis, Otago University,
1g88.
Jackson, Frank, Perception: A Representative Theory, Cambridge Univer-
sity Press, 1977.
"Metaphysics by Possible Cases", in Brian Garrett and Peter Menzies
(eds.), 1992 ANU Metaphysics Conference, Working Papers in Philos-
ophy, no. 2, Canberra: Research School of Social Sciences, Austra-
lian National University, 1992.
Jackson, Frank and Phillip Pettit, "Functionalism and Broad Content",
Mind, 97 (1g88): 381-400.
Bibliography
Jarvie, Ian, Philosophy of the Film, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul,
1987.
Jeannerod, M. "The Representing Brain: Neural Correlates of Motor
Intention and Imagery'', Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 17 (1994):
187-202.
Johnson, C. N., and PaulL. Harris, ''Magic: Special but Not Excluded",
British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 12 (1994): 35-51.
Johnston, Mark, "Dispositional Theories of Value", Aristotelian Society
Supplementary Volume, 63 (1989): 139-174.
Jones, R. K., and M. A. Hagen, "A Perspective on Cross-Cultural Pic-
ture Perception", in M. A. Hagen (ed.), The Perception of Pictures,
vol. 2, New York: Academic, 1980.
Juhl, P. D., Interpretation: An Essay in the Philosophy of Literary Criticism,
Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 198o.
Kanner, L., "Autistic Disturbances of Affective Contact", Nervous Child,
2 (1943): 217-250.
Khatchadourian, Haig, "Remarks on the 'Cinematic/Uncinematic Dis-
tinction in Film Art'", in Music, Film and Art, New York: Gordon
Breach, 1985.
"Space and Time in Film", British Journal of Aesthetics, 27 (1987): 169-
177·
Kozloff, Sarah, Invisible Storytellers: Voice-Over Narration in American
Fiction Film, Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California
Press, 1988.
Lapsley, Robert, and Michael Westlake, Film Theory: An Introduction,
Manchester University Press, 1988.
le Poidevin, Robin, "Time and Truth in Fiction", British Journal of Aes-
thetics, 28 (1988): 248-258.
Leslie, Alan, "Pretence and Representation: The Origins of 'Theory of
Mind'", Psychological Review, 94, no. 4 (1987): 412-426.
"Pretending and Believing: Issues in the Theory of ToMM", Cogni-
tion, 50 (1994): 211-238.
Leslie, Alan., T. German and F. Happe, "Even a Theory-Theory Needs
Information Processing: ToMM, an Alternative Theory-Theory of
the Child's Theory of Mind", Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 16
(1993): 57·
Levinson, Jerrold, "Seeing, Imaginarily, at the Movies", Philosophical
Quarterly, 43, no. 170 (1993): 7o-78.
Levinson, Jerrold, and Philip Alperson, What Is a Temporal Art? Vol. 16
of Midwest Studies in Philosophy, French et al., ed. Notre Dame
Ind.: Notre Dame University Press, 1991.
Bibliography
293
Bibliography
294
Bibliography
Roth, D., and A. Leslie, "The Recognition of Attitude Conveyed by
Utterance: A Study of Preschool and Autistic Children", British
Journal of Developmental Psychology, 9 (1991): 315-3.30·
Sartwell, Crispin, "Natural Generativity and Imitation", British Journal
of Aesthetics, 31 (1991): 58-67.
Savage-Rumbaugh, S., et al., "Spontaneous Symbol Acquisition and
Communicative Use by Pigmy Chimpanzees Pan paniscus'', Journal
of Experimental Psychology: General, 115 (1986): 211-235·
Schier, Flint, Deeper into Pictures: An Essay on Pictorial Representation,
Cambridge University Press, 1986.
Scruton, Roger, "Photography and Representation", in The Aesthetic
Understanding: Essays in the Philosophy of Art and Culture, London:
Methuen, 1983.
Sesonske, Alexander, "Time and Tense in Cinema", Journal of Aesthetics
and Art Criticism, 38 (1979'-'8<>): 419-426.
Silverman, Kaja, The Subject of Semiotics, New York: Oxford University
Press, 1983.
Skow, John, "Harold Brodkey's New Novel is Erotic- But Not to Ev-
erybody", Time, May 9, 1994.
Snyder, Joel, "Photography and Ontology'', in J. Margolis (ed.), The
Worlds of Art and the World, Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1984.
Sobchack, Vivian, The Address of the Eye: A Phenomenology of Film Ex-
perience, Princeton, N. J.: Princeton University Press, 1992.
Sorensen, Roy, "Self-Strengthening Empathy'', unpublished manu-
script.
Sparshott, Francis, "Basic Film Aesthetics", in G. Mast and M. Cohen
(eds.), Film Theory and Criticism, 3d ed., New York: Oxford Uni-
versity Press, 1985.
Stalnaker, Robert, Inquiry, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1984.
Stampe, Dennis, "Toward a Causal Theory of Linguistic Representa-
tion", Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. 2, Morris: University of
Minnesota Press, 1977·
Stanzel, F. K., A Theory of Narrative, trans. Charlotte Goedsche, Cam-
bridge University Press, 1984.
Stephenson, R., and J. R. Debrix, The Cinema as Art, New York: Penguin,
1976.
Sternberg, Meir, Expositional Modes and Temporal Ordering in Fiction, Bal-
timore, Md.: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1978.
Stich, S., and S. Nichols, "Second Thoughts on Simulation", in M. Da-
vies and T. Stone (eds.), Mental Simulation, forthcoming.
Studlar, Gaylan, "Masochism and the Perverse Pleasures of the Cin-
295
Bibliography
297
Index
cinematic movement: as apparent but film, 1-16; and controlling narrator,
nonillusory, 42-46; the reality of, 34- 266-268; documentary I fiction, 14-16;
42 engendering cognitive illusion, 22-23,
Citizen Kane (Welles), 14, 181, 266 27; engendering perceptual illusion,
Cohen, T., 58n 29-30, 35, 39; and imagining
colour: and cinematic image, 33; and someone's visual experience, 193-
film, 6-7; the reality of, 31-32, 39- 196; and impersonal imagining, 179-
40 18o; and personal imagining, 165-
Comolli, J.-L., 26n, u6n 179;realism, 19-22, 1o6-1o8;and
Constable, J., 52 seeing the world, 48, 69; as spatial
Cooper, N., xxi art, 103-106, 218-219; as temporal
Corballis, M. C., 123n art, 9(), 99-103, 218-219; unlike
Couvalis, G., xxi, 2m language, 114, 117-124, 128-131, 134-
Crossfire (Dmytryk), 205 135; see also photography
Culloden (Weir), 173 Fish, 5., 126n
Flitterman, 5., 2~
Dagle, J., 200n Fodor, J. A., 29n, 8m, 85-86, 8~
Davies, M., xxi-xxii, 53n Ford, F. M., 265, 2j'Sn
Davies, W. M., 29n, 59n, 6~ Freud, 5., xxiv
Dawkins, R., 59 Friedberg, A., xviiin
Dayan, D., xixn, 194
Debrix, J. R., 2oon Galileo, G., 111n
Deffenbacher, K., ~n Genette, G.,~' 199n, 20~, 212n,
Deleuze, G., 141n, 201n; on film and 262n, 263n
physics, xviii-xix Gilman, D., 46n, 86n
Dennett, D., 37-38, 8~ Glymore, C., xvn
Deren, M., 21~ Godfather, The, Part 2 (Coppola), 216n
Descartes, R., 83 Goldman, A. 1., 143n, 153n
Dick, B. F., 216n Gombrich, E., xvi
Dickens, C., 229 Gone with the Wind (Fleming), 14, 273-
Dombey and Son (Dickens), 228 274
Don't Look Now (Roeg), 216 Good Soldier, The (Ford), 265
Dostoyevsky, F., 244-245 Goodman, N., xvi, 12n
Double Indemnity (Wilder), 216n, 266 Gopnik, A., 143n
Durgnat, R., xviin Gordon, R. M., 143n, 154n
Dworkin, R., 225, 249n Gospel According to St. Matthew, The
(Passolini), 99
Eco, u., 11~, 131-133 Grant, C., 23, 38, 40'-41, 48, 189
Eisenstein, 5., 104 Great Expectations (Lean), 181
ellipsis, 212, 215, 220; in literture, 219- Gregory, R., xvi
222 Grice, P., 12~, 215n, 253n
Ellis, J., 22n Groner, C., 59n
300
Index
imagination, 141148, 151-152; and intentions of implied author, 270o-
interpretation, 242-243; and other 272
minds, 144-147
Sirk, D., 259 Velleman, J. D., 31n, 39n, 111n
Skow, J., 15~ Verrnazen, B., 245n
Snyder, J., 50n Vertigo (Hitchcock), 170o-171
Sobchack, V., xviii visual perception, xv; as nonlinguistic,
Sober, E., xxii 136-137
Soli, I., xxii Vygotsky, L. S., 161
Sorensen, R., 146-147
Sparshott, F., 34- 20m Walton, K., xxii, 13n, 24n, 14~, 152n,
Spellbound (Hitchcock), 174-175, 179- 161n, 169n, 17~, 188n; on
tSo transparency, 20, 5o-51, 55n, 56n,
Squires, R., xxii 57n. 61-63, 75n, 173n
Stage Fright (Hitchcock), 195, 267-268 Wages of Fear, The (Clouzot), 1oon
Stagecoach (Ford), 175-176 War and Peace (Tolstoy), 246n
Stalnaker, R., 78n Warburton, N., 66n
Stampe, D., 78n Waters, J., 88, 167
Stanzel, F. K., 266n Weir, P., 173
Sternberg, M., 200n Weiss, P., 23n
Stich, S., 143n Welles, 0., 10
Stokes, J., xxii Wellman, H. M., 145n
structuralism: errors of, 114-116, 122n; Westlake, M., 111n
and narrative intentions, 278-279 Wetherall, P., xxii
Studlar, G., 141n White, M., 46n
Sturgeon, S., xxii Whyte, J., xxii, 149n
Wilder, B., 216n
Taylor, K., xxii Wilensky, R., 113n
They Shoot Horses, Don't They? Williams, B., 169, 178
(Pollack), 216n Williamson, T., xxii
Third Man, The (Reed), 1o-11 Wilson, G., xiiin; on cinematic images
Thompson, K., 27~ as unlike language, 128--130; on
Tingler, The (Castle), 168 imagining seeing, 165n, 166, 171-173,
Todorov, T., 115 178; on unreliability, 268--269, 276,
Tolstoy, L., 246n 278n
Tom Jones (Fielding), 262 Wimmer, H., 142n, 15~
Tooley, M., xxii Wittgenstein, L., 97, 123n, 136
Townsend, A., xxii Wollheim, R., 88, 90, 110n, 141, 169n
Turim, M. C., 22n, 198n, 2o6n Woodruff, G., 110n
Turn of the Screw, The (James), 232, 238, Woolley, J. D., 163n
240, 25o-251,261-262,276-277
Yalowitz, S., xxii
unreliable narrative, 261-262, 265; You Only Live Once (Lang), 268--270,
Booth, 268--270; in terms of complex 275-277
301