Moore Behaviorism 2011
Moore Behaviorism 2011
Moore Behaviorism 2011
net/publication/299100427
Behaviorism
CITATIONS READS
11 16,047
1 author:
Jay Moore
University of Wisconsin - Milwaukee
77 PUBLICATIONS 1,101 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:
All content following this page was uploaded by Jay Moore on 07 March 2016.
Sketch
Behaviorism
J. Moore
University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee
Early forms of psychology assumed that mental life was the appropri-
ate subject matter for psychology, and introspection was an appropriate
method to engage that subject matter. In 1913, John B. Watson proposed
an alternative: classical S–R behaviorism. According to Watson, behav-
ior was a subject matter in its own right, to be studied by the obser-
vational methods common to all sciences. Unfortunately, by around
1930, Watson’s behaviorism had proved inadequate. Many researchers
and theorists then adopted a view in which various organismic entities
were inferred to mediate the relation between S and R: mediational
S–O–R neobehaviorism. This general view has remained influential,
although the details of the various versions have differed over the
years. The behavior analysis of B. F. Skinner took an entirely differ-
ent approach. Particularly important was the study of verbal behavior.
Although behaviorism is often conventionally defined as an approach
that seeks to explain behavior without directly appealing to mental
or cognitive processes, this definition needs considerable clarification,
especially as it pertains to Skinner’s behavior analysis and his view of
behaviorism as a philosophy of science.
Key words: behaviorism, cognitive psychology, mentalism, methodological
behaviorism, operationism, hypothetico-deductive method
I thank Marshall Dermer for helpful comments on an earlier version of this article.
Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to J. Moore, PhD, Dept of Psychology,
University of Wisconsin–Milwaukee, Milwaukee, WI 53201 (e-mail: jcm@uwm.edu).
450 Moore
variables are those that have become significant during the lifetime of the
species, or have been experienced during the lifetime of the organism, in-
cluding its social-cultural environment. Part of the environment is enclosed
within the skin. We determine functional relations by varying environmen-
tal conditions and seeing if behavior varies accordingly, through the ex-
perimental method. In special situations it is appropriate to consider “doing
nothing” or “standing still” as instances of behavior. Thus, not all instances
of movement are behavior, and not all instances of behavior entail move-
ment. Some instances of behavior occur because an eliciting stimulus has
been presented to the organism, either unconditioned or conditioned. Other
instances occur because in the past, the behavior has produced a particular
consequence in the presence of a particular set of antecedent circumstances,
and those antecedent circumstances are again present. This latter case is
described as a three-term contingency of reinforcement: In the presence of
(a) a discriminative stimulus, (b) a response characteristically produces (c) a
reinforcing consequence. To be sure, a theoretically oriented behavioral neu-
roscience is clearly a legitimate discipline. There is a sense in which a behav-
ioral account of an event has two gaps. One gap is within the event, from the
time an organism encounters some environmental circumstance to the time
it responds. A second gap is between events, from the time the subject has
a given experience to the time the effects of that experience are reflected in
its behavior. There are physiological phenomena associated with these gaps
that neuroscience can know about and that will increase our ability to pre-
dict and control behavior, for example, if information about an organism’s
behavioral history is lacking. In any case, behavior is not studied because it
provides evidence that validates theoretical or explanatory inferences about
causes of behavior (e.g., acts, states, mechanisms, processes, entities) from
another dimension (e.g., neural, mental, cognitive, psychic, conceptual). The
bulk of traditional psychology embraces the second perspective, however
implicitly.
2. Analytic concepts: Functional, relational, and generic. Definitions of
concepts are functional and relational. For example, a reinforcer is defined
in terms of its function. It is a consequence of a response that increases
the probability of the response. Furthermore, it is defined by its relation to
the response in question. Readers may note that something with sugar in it
may well function as a reinforcer when it is presented as a consequence of
a response. However, we define it as a reinforcer because of its effect on be-
havior, not by how much sugar it has in it. Finally, stimuli and responses are
generic concepts—they belong to classes, and the functional relations (such
as reinforcement) obtain between classes. Class boundaries are sometimes
determined by experience, and sometimes they are innate.
3. Behavior: Public and private. Although many behavioral events are
publicly observable, not all are. Some behavioral events are “private,” in the
sense that they are accessible to only the person who is behaving. Private
behavioral events are determined by the tools or characteristics of an ob-
server, rather than by anything pertaining to the nature of the event itself
(Donahoe & Palmer, 1994). Typically, these private behavioral events gain
their functional significance through public relations. Consequently, there
is no appeal to autonomous private entities from another dimensional sys-
tem as causes of behavior. Behavioral principles are developed through the
analysis of public behavior and then used in interpretations of private forms.
458 Moore
References
Boring, E. G. (1950). A history of experimental psychology. New York, NY:
Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Carnap, R. (1936). Testability and meaning. Philosophy of Science, 3, 419–471.
Carnap, R. (1937). Testability and meaning—continued. Philosophy of
Science, 4, 1–40.
Catania, A. C., & Harnad, S. (Eds.). (1988). The selection of behavior: The
operant behaviorism of B. F. Skinner: Comments and controversies.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Donahoe, J., & Palmer, D. (1994). Learning and complex behavior. Needham
Heights, MA: Allyn and Bacon.
Hempel, C. G., & Oppenheim, P. (1948). Studies in the logic of explanation.
Philosophy of Science, 115, 135–175.
Kantor, J. R. (1938). The operational principle in the physical and
psychological sciences. The Psychological Record, 2, 332.
Kimble, G. (1985). Conditioning and learning. In S. Koch & D. E. Leary (Eds.),
A century of psychology as science (pp. 284-320). New York, NY:
McGraw-Hill.
MacCorquodale, K., & Meehl, P. (1948). On a distinction between
hypothetical constructs and intervening variables. Psychological Review,
55, 95–107.
Moore, J. (1999). On the principles of behaviorism. In B. A. Thyer (Ed.),
The philosophical foundations of behaviorism (pp. 41–68). Dordrecht, NL:
Kluwer.
Moore, J. (2008). Conceptual foundations of radical behaviorism. Cornwall-
on-Hudson, NY: Sloan.
Skinner, B. F. (1945). The operational analysis of psychological terms.
Psychological Review, 52, 270-277, 291–294.
Skinner, B. F. (1989). Recent issues in the analysis of behavior. Columbus,
OH: Merrill.
Tolman, E. C. (1949). Discussion: Interrelationships between perception
and personality: A symposium. Journal of Personality, 18, 48–50.
Watson, J. B. (1913). Psychology as the behaviorist views it. Psychological
Review, 20, 158–177.
BEHAVIORISM 463
Study Questions