Book HandbookOfHumorResearch
Book HandbookOfHumorResearch
Book HandbookOfHumorResearch
HUMOR RESEARCH
Volume I
Volume I
Basic Issues
HANDBOOK OF
HUMOR RESEARCH
Edited by
Springer-Verlag
New York Berlin Heidelberg Tokyo
Paul E. McGhee Jeffrey H. Goldstein
Department of Home and Family Life Division of Social Psychology
Texas Tech University Temple University
Lubbock, Texas 79409, U.S.A. Philadelphia, Pennsylvania 19122, U.S.A.
With 8 Figures
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be translated or reproduced in any form
without written permission from Springer-Verlag, 175 Fifth Avenue, New York, New
York 10010, U.S.A.
The use of general descriptive names, trade names, trademarks, etc., in this publication,
even if the former are not especially identified, is not to be taken as a sign that such
names, as understood by the Trade Marks and Merchandise Marks Act, may
accordingly be used freely by anyone.
9 8 765 432 I
About a decade ago we edited The Psychology ofHumor. Besides the summary
chapter and bibliography of about 400 items, the book contained eleven original
papers that represented the state of knowledge at that time. We confess that it
was not easy to fill that volume with first-rate contributions. In a few instances
we invited contributors only on the basis of having heard through the grapevine
that they were doing interesting work on humor. Our sources proved reliable
and we were pleased with the results. We even made new friends as a result of
these blind invitations. But the fact remains that in the early 1970s there was
only a handful of social scientists studying humor and laughter.
The history of humor research prior to the 1970s can also be characterized in
terms of the short-term commitment to investigating humor among those who
did venture out and try their hand at designing humor studies. For reasons that
remain unclear, many investigators published only one or two humor studies
before abandoning the area in favor of some other research domain. We have
the impression that for decades social scientists have been very intrigued by the
idea of studying humor. Psychologists have suspected for a long time that humor
somehow is very important in the lives of people. We find laughter and humor
occurring almost wherever we find people engaged in social interaction. The
fact that we usually feel better when we laugh suggests that laughter may
somehow be important for our health and well-being. When any of us who are
engaged in humor research describe to others what we are doing, we are
consistently met with reactions of interest and fascination.
Given all the apparent interest in humor, why did it take so long (until the
mid-1970s) for humor research to "catch on"? One reason may be that humor,
like play, remains an elusive concept. There is still no agreement on how humor
vi Preface
·Goldstein, J. H., McGhee, P. E., Smith, J. R.. Chapman, A. J., & Foot, H. C. Humour, laughter
and comedy: A bibliography of empirical and nonempirical analyses in the English language. In
A. J. Chapman & H. C. Foot (Eds.), It's a funny thing humour. Oxford Pergamon Press,
1977.
Preface vii
sociology, linguistics, and anthropology, and several that stem from various
psychological perspectives. If we have learned anything from the study of
humor it is that oversimplified, global explanations are inadequate to the task.
The contributors to the Handbook have avoided such simplistic answers. The
focus on specific issues within the broad area of humor, laughter, and comedy
liberates the theorist and basic researcher from premature and unwarranted
generalizations. By restricting their field of view, students of humor are better
able to deal with the complexity of the phenomenon.
Methodological issues are discussed in several chapters, but they form the
primary concern of Marianne LaFrance's chapter. She directly confronts one of
the key problems in using smiling and laughter as an index of degree of humor
appreciation, namely, that it is difficult to tell the difference between genuine
humorous laughter and social or artificial laughter. She provides a framework
for using Paul Ekman's scoring system for facial expression of affect to
distinguish real from feigned signs of funniness.
Chapter 2 by Paul McGhee examines psycho-physiological research and
issues associated with humor. The first part of the chapter discusses the role of
arousal in humor, summarizes existing data on physiological correlates of
humor, and examines the nature of metacognitive processes involved in making
judgments about funniness. The second half discusses the differential roles of
the right and left hemispheres in humor.
The next two chapters focus on cognitive aspects of humor. Jerry Suls's
chapter reviews theories and research concerned with cognitive processes
involved in humor appreciation, giving special attention to the extension of
incongruity-resolution theory to disparagement humor. William Pepicello and
Robert Weisberg summarize existing findings from linguistic analyses of humor
and draw attention to issues that must be addressed before real progress can be
made in our understanding of linguistic forms of humor. Considerable attention
is given here to develomental changes in children's linguistic humor. Chapter 6
by McGhee is entirely devoted to developmental studies of humor, focusing
primarily on issues that must be addressed in order to investigate humor
development across the life span.
Chapter 5 by Dolf Zillmann reviews theories and research in the area of
disparagement humor. Special attention is given to the "evolution" of these
theories and to attempts to integrate disparagement theory with other attempts
to explain humor.
Chapters 7 and 8 deal with social and sociological aspects of humor. Tony
Chapman discusses the many functions served by laughter and humor in the
context of social interaction. He is critical of many researchers' failure to obtain
measures of laughter in studies of humor and calls for greater rigor in the
conduct of humor research generally. Several pitfalls are discussed that may
interfere with the obtaining of valid findings in studying laughter and humor.
Gary Fine reviews sociological approaches to the study of humor. In discussing
humor and social roles, attention is given to the fool, the clown, the wit and
viii Preface
joker, and the comedian. Studies of the use of humor in context are examined
along with reference group humor and the relationship between humor and
group culture.
Mahadev Apte's chapter discusses methods used by anthropologists to study
humor and also reviews selected areas of anthropological theories and research
related to humor. Specific attention is given to joking relationships, humor in
religion, and trickster studies. Problems in conducting anthropological humor
research are also discussed. Finally, Chapter 10 by Howard Pollio presents a
field theory of humor. This phenomenological theory depicts laughter and
smiling as "embodied social events" and stresses the importance of the feelings
of the laughing or smiling person.
Both volumes of the Handbook of Humor Research are intended for
students, researchers, and practitioners in psychology, sociology, anthropology,
linguistics, mass communications, medicine and nursing, education and human
development, interested in (a) a handy source of information about humor,
laughter, and comedy, (b) a rich source offresh theoretical and research insights
into the nature and functioning of humor, and (c) a guide for the enhancement,
use, and application of humor. With regard to information, the Handbook
summarizes current and classical literature on humor and laughter. Literature
reviews focus on theories of the nature of humor, on the relationship of humor to
language, cognition and social functioning, on biological and physiological
features, and on the presence, use, and effects of humor in a wide variety of
settings. Included also are theoretical integrations, philosophical speculations,
methodological suggestions, and thoughtful analyses of humor and all its
attendant phenomena. Indeed, we hope the Handbook will serve as a fertile
ground for research ideas. Finally, the Handbook ofHumor Research contains
chapters that instruct on the development and enhancement of humor, both in
oneself and in others. As a whole, then, these chapters should help the reader to
further develop his or her own sense of humor as well as to understand the
nature, development, and functions of humor.
Paul E. McGhee
Jeffrey H. Goldstein
Contents
MARIANNE LAFRANCE
This chapter was written while the author was on sabbatical at the Human Interaction Laboratory,
University of California, San Francisco.
2 Marianne LaFrance
examining the relationship between humor and laughing and smiling by looking
at facial expressions of affect. More specifically, research on facial action is
examined for clues as to whether or when laughter and smiling can be taken for
genuine signs of felt funniness.
At first glance, laughing seems to be a superlative dependent variable. As to
its presence or absence, high inter-observer reliability seems assured, and as to
its measurement qualities, a number of objective indices are possible including
timed latency and duration, as well as amplitude and intensity. The same
applies to smiling.
What then seems to be the problem? The problem is one of validity. Although
people laugh when they find something funny, they also laugh when a "joke" is
seen to be anything but funny. Moreover, people can be very straight-faced in a
truly humorous situation, giving little sign of felt mirth. In fact, many would
argue as Tomkins (1980) has that "facial behavior ... is as ambiguous in its
meanings as any other behavior, and we interpret such behavior at its 'face'
value at our peril" (p. 160).
To date these vagaries have not hounded the humor researchers. In contrast
to many psychological phenomena, humor has been operationalized in few and
simple ways that appear obvious and unassailable. Subjects are either asked to
rank-order jokes for funniness (Godkewitsch, 1972) or observers assess the
degree of a subject's response using a scale. For example, the scale might begin
with "no response noted," move to "smile varying in magnitude from a gentle to
a broad smile," next to "laugh varying from one with normal voice sounds to
one involving moderately active head and shoulder movements," and end with
"explosive laugh" (Pollio, Mers, & Lucchesi, 1972).
There are several problems with defining humor as smiling-laughing or self-
reported funniness. First, the operationalizations assume that an isomorphism
exists between degree of felt funniness and degree of visible response. But the
person laughing the loudest may be the least amused, while the person smiling
the least may be suppressing full-flow fun until a more appropriate context can
be found. In both cases, the response is less to the humor present than to the
operating social context. A second problem with these operationalizations of
humor is the constraint they put on what can be considered humorous.
Measurements of laughter amplitude may be a good indicator of the kinds of
things that people laugh at, but not necessarily the range of things that they find
humorous. Finally, regarding the relationship of smiling to laughing as one of
degree rather than kind may blind researchers to the possibility that there are
types of laughter and types of smiles all of which may vary as to their
association with each other.
Progress in understanding humor may proceed when the response to humor is
operationalized more carefully and exhaustively. Work in the field of nonverbal
communication and particularly that being done on the facial expression of
emotion can assist by providing the means for coding faces in well-defined and
highly refined ways. When the face is coded thusly, it becomes the carrier of
Felt versus Feigned Funniness 3
multiple meanings that extend beyond the one or two simple phrases usually
ascribed to it by humor researchers.
To describe a smile seems the height of excess. Smiles and laughter are
recognizable and apparent to anyone. Nevertheless, the task has occupied
scientists for over a century. Darwin (1872) wrote of the smile that:
By drawing backwards and upwards of the corners of the mouth, through the
contraction of the great zygomatic muscles, and by the raising of the upper lip, the
cheeks are drawn upwards. Wrinkles are thus formed under the eyes, and, with old
people, at their outer ends ... As in laughing and broadly smiling the cheeks and
upper lip are much raised, the nose appears to be shortened, and the skin on the bridge
becomes finely wrinkled in transverse lines, with other oblique longitudinal lines on
the sides. The upper front teeth are commonly exposed. A well marked nasa-labial
fold is formed, which runs from the wing of each nostril to the corner of the mouth.
(p. 210)
As to laughter, he wrote:
clonic spasms of the diaphragm in number ordinarily about eighteen perhaps, and
contraction of most of the muscles of the face .... The upper eyelid is elevated, as are
also, to some extent, the brows, the skin over the glabella ... the head in extreme
laughter is thrown backward; the trunk is straightened even to the beginning of bending
backward, until (and this usually happens soon), fatigue-pain in the diaphragm and
accessory abdominal muscles causes a marked proper flexion of the trunk for its relief.
The whole arterial vascular system is dilated ... the eyes often slightly bulge forwards
and the lachrymal gland becomes active. ordinarily to a degree only to cause a
"brightening" of the eyes. (p. 853-854)
zygomatic major (Ekman & Friesen, 1982), but other muscles can also effect a
mouth comer raise such as the zygomatic minor, buccinator, risorious, and
caninus muscles and these result in differential appearances (Ekman, Friesen,
& Ancoli, 1980).
Ethologists have also been interested in describing different forms of smiling.
Grant (1969) lists eight types of smiles and grins based on the degree of mouth
comer pull, the position of the upper and lower lips relative to the teeth, the
unilaterality or bilaterality of the action, and the jaw position. Brannigan and
Humphries (1972) differentiate 10 smiles and grins looking at appearance
changes in the mouth region. McGrew (1972) distinguishes between a "grin
face," "play face," and "smile." Van Hooff (1972) describes the facial,
postural, and vocal features in old-world monkeys and apes that effect two smile
variations, the "silent bared-teeth face" and the "relaxed open-mouth face,"
that he argues are homologous to human smiling and laughing.
At issue in all these descriptions is the opportunity they afford for comparing
and contrasting types of smiles and laughs and for checking which ones are
indicative of genuine humor and which ones suggest feigned expression.
Moreover, such fine-grain descriptions afford the testing of more highly
differentiated hypotheses about the causes or functions of humor. For example,
distinctions could be made between amusement smiles, mocking or superior
smiles, and nervous smiles by reference to specific facial features associated
with happiness, contempt, or fear, respectively.
Most observational coding systems are constructed for particular uses and
hence do not necessarily travel well. In contrast, Ekman and Friesen (1978)
have developed a system that exhaustively describes facial movement in
objective terms-Facial Action Coding System (FACS). Thus, an investigator
trained in FACS can apply it to any question where variation in facial
expression is of interest. Before showing how F ACS could profitably be applied
to humor research, let me describe some of the main features of the system.
In complete form, F ACS includes the coding of all separate, visible, muscle-
based facial changes and their intensity, laterality, temporal location, and
timing. More specifically, F ACS distinguishes among 44 action units. One
such action unit (AU) associated with happiness is AU 12, named the "lip
comer puller." For each AU, the FACS manual describes the muscle involved,
the appearance changes that result from contraction of the relevant muscle, how
to perform the action, and the minimum requirements for scoring it. In the case
of AU 12, the minimum requirements describe three visual changes: a change in
the nasolabial furrow, which is raised up and laterally slightly; a change in the
infraorbital triangle, which is slightly raised and seen by reference to the lifting
and puffing out of the side top comer of the infraorbital triangle; and a change in
the lip comers, which are slightly elongated and angled up.
Felt versus Feigned Funniness 5
Also included in the full scoring are intensity, the strength of the action unit
on a 5-point scale from "barely noticeable" to "maximum intensity"; laterality,
whether the action unit appears equally on both sides of the face, on one side
only, or more on one side than the other; location, the precise time points for the
start and end of the action unit; and timing, elapsed time from onset to apex,
apex duration, and elapsed time from apex to completion. Each discriminable
action unit is comparably scored.
The FACS is objective and exhaustive and chief among its advantages is its
ability to detect distinct facial movements that occur simultaneously. Conse-
quently, expressive blends and mixed affect can be cause for clarification rather
than confusion.
The rationale for such compulsivity is the speculation that variations in one or
more of these scoring features are associated with meaningful psychological
variations. That is to say, other action units that give the appearance of a smile
may be unrelated to amusement and so suggest the presence of a feigned smile
and/or some other reaction. Similarly, variations in intensity, symmetry,
location, and timing may cue the operation of something quite different from
genuine humor.
*For a complete description of these action units see Ekman and Friesen (1978). Information
reprinted by permission of P. Ekman.
to mask negative affect, AUs associated with the negative feeling may be visible
along with the smile. For example, the brows may be drawn down and/or
together implicating anger, or the lips may be pressed together suggesting an
attempt to dampen or suppress the smile. By focusing just on the smile and
neglecting to look elsewhere on the face for additional actions that theoretically
should or should not be there during genuine pleasure, unfounded conclusions
may result.
Smile Location
A recurrent observation from the humor literature is that the act of laughing is
typically set off suddenly, such as by a "punch line" (Hertzler, 1970). It is
possible then to gauge the authenticity of the smile-laugh response by timing its
appearance in reference to this point. Specifically, it has been suggested that a
false smile is one that occurs "too early or too late" (Ekman & Friesen, 1982).
Premature or delayed laughter may thus be a sign that humor is expected rather
than experienced.
Another aspect of location is the occurrence of smiling in the behavioral
sequence, again pointing to the need to code behaviors in addition to the smile
or laugh. For example, Sroufe and Waters (1976) hypothesized that smiling is
likely to occur after the onset of the release of a psychological tension produced
by a process of cognitive evaluation. Consequently, one could look for
behaviors suggestive of build up such as brow knits, eye narrowing, and jaw
drop. One study has provided supportive data. Oster ( 1978) found that prior to
one smile form in very young infants there predictably occurred precursory
brow knits with characteristic appearance and timing, generating a hypothesis
that such a smile expressed cognitive mastery. Given the predominance of
cognitive theories of humor (McGhee, 1979), such a sequence may be worth
exploring. In any case, regularities in the sequence of antecedent and
subsequent acts in the behavior of the smiler/laugher must be looked at for
information regarding the "why" and "what for" of smiling and laughing in
humor.
Timing of Smiling/Laughing
A useful principle in accounting for nonverbal behaviors that are noticed and
that strike a false cord is that the behavior deviates in some way such as in
expected duration or intensity (LaFrance & Mayo, 1978). Tomkins (1980) has
argued with respect to smiling that" a smile that is either faster or slower and/or
more or less wide than an innate smile tells the other that one is really not
amused" (p. 160). Some preliminary data have in fact pointed to the normal
time boundaries of a genuine smile. McGrew (1972) for instance characterized
a "grin face" as "reflexive and fleeting in appearance" (p. 44). Ekman and
8 Marianne LaFrance
Friesen (1982) report that most felt smiles were between two-thirds of a second
and four seconds in length. It would be informative to know whether boundaries
could be determined for laughter as well.
Timing also involves durations to apex, apex length, and offset time. Here
again, Ekman and Friesen (1982) report that false smiles differ from felt ones in
all three aspects: onset time is too short, apex time is too long, and offset is
irregular.
Laterality of a Smile
Prevailing practice has it that the relationship between smiling and laughing is a
matter of degree rather than kind. Darwin (1872) established the precedent by
stating that "a man smiles-and smiling, as we shall see, graduates into
laughter" (p. 196). Current empirical research has followed suit varying only in
the number of positions on the scale (Pollio et aI., 1972). Despite the
obviousness of the relation, there have been disagreements. McDougall (1923)
insisted that smiling and laughing have different origins but Berlyne (1972)
concluded that though they are distinct, the smile and laugh are not inde-
pendent. The matter is far from settled: Duncan and Fiske (1977) report
substantial positive correlations between smiling and laughing in dyadic
Felt versus Feigned Funniness 9
conversations but Pollio et al. (1972) found smile and laugh duration to be
unrelated in response to comedy albums.
This is not the place to resolve the issue but rather to suggest how more fine-
grain coding of nonverbal responses to humor might aid in its resolution.
Smiling and laughing may be separately scalar. The F ACS system (Ekman &
Friesen, 1978) scores each facial action unit on a 5-point intensity scale;
laughter may be similarly scaled. However, it may be that under certain
circumstances smiling intensity is more highly correlated with felt funniness
than laughing intensity.
One of the intriguing aspects of the relationship between humor and laughing is
the repeated observation that laughter can be found at occasions that are
singularly nonhumorous, such as derisive or triumphant occasions. Unfor-
tunately, little comes of the observation save for the recognition that there are
different kinds of laughter. Research in nonverbal communication may provide
the methods for operationalizing these differences. For example, Scherer
(1974) used a Moog synthesizer to systematically vary levels of seven acoustic
cues and measured the impact of these variations on observer inferences about
perceived emotional states. This kind of methodological approach seems a
promising avenue for differentiating types of laughter (including feigned vs. felt
laughter) in conjunction with other objective indices such as amplitude,
frequency, and duration.
With regard to smiling, research is somewhat further along. Using the Facial
Action Scoring System, Ekman & Friesen (1982) have distinguished among
"felt, false, and miserable smiles" and and Ekman (Note 1) adds another 16
kinds to the list. For humor researchers, being able to distinguish between types
of smiles may bring methodological and theoretical clarity. As to the former,
feigned responses to humorous stimuli may be screened out from faithful
responses. As to the latter, more precision may be obtained in testing
hypotheses about the causes or functions of humor. If, for example, one is
interested in testing the notion that humor represents "masked aggression," a
facial expression representing a blend of happiness and anger may be more
evident that one indicating pure happiness. Or if one were investigating whether
surprise were critical to humor appreciation, a facial blend of surprise and
happy components may be more telling than one containing anger or fear. Or if
one were checking the possibility that superiority were a key ingredient in
humor, then faces could be scored for presence of contempt along with
happiness. In sum, the face can be scored not only for differing components and
intensities in the mouth region but also for concurrent or overlapping
components in the other regions of the face. Expansion of the response variable
could presumably effect diminution of possible causal variables.
10 Marianne LaFrance
There may be many reasons to laugh and many kinds of laughter, but the
occasion is nearly always a social one. Bergson (1911) pointed to this in his
classic work on laughter: "However spontaneous it seems, laughter always
implies a kind of secret freemasonry, or even complicity, with other laughters,
real or imaginary" (p. 6), This "complicity" complicates things for humor
researchers who would use laughter as an index of funniness to particular
humorous material. Are people smiling and laughing in response to some funny
input or to the fact that others are smiling and laughing or both?
Within the nonverbal communication literature, it is well recognized that
expressive behavior can be both indicative and communicative (LaFrance &
Mayo, 1978). In other words, facial signs are not only informative about the
expressor's internal state but also have an impact on others who are present.
Smiling and laughing are no exception. Moreover, smiling and laughing can
have a kind of reverberating effect on the individuals involved, stimulating them
to even more response.
The challenge is in being able to link particular responses to particular
stimuli. One possible tack is to bring greater attention to the duration and timing
of smiling and laughing and to do this in reference to other preceding,
concurrent, and subsequent events. It may be that laughter is cyclic in nature; if
so, there are now methods available for handling the resulting data (Gottman,
1979). It may be that laughter in response to felt funniness has a different
duration and/or timing than laughter in response to other laughter.
Another aspect of the context of humor has to do with the social rules for
smiling and laughing. Social situations frequently call for duplicity not
authenticity. Feigned laughter is functional; fabricated smiling is serviceable.
Research in nonverbal communication suggests methods for testing when the
response is feigned or felt. In addition, the issue could be approached head-on
by giving research participants the opportunity to report when their reactions
were indicative or communicative and correlating this with particular facial
and/or vocal configurations.
CONCLUSIONS
The aim of this chapter has been to suggest how humor research might profit
from a little borrowing from research in nonverbal communication and
particularly that from the area of facial expression of emotion. The advantages
of a coding system such as the Facial Action Coding System developed by
Ekman and Friesen (1978) are twofold: methodological and conceptual. As to
the former, measurement of smiling and laughing responses to humor can
achieve greater validity than heretofore; as to the latter, refinement of coding
can lend greater theoretical precision.
Felt versus Feigned Funniness II
There are disadvantages too with the application of a system like the FACS.
It is expensive in terms of training required to implement it-the estimate comes
to around 100 hours of training to reach satisfactory levels of coding reliability
(Ekman & Friesen, 1978). It is expensive in terms of coding hours required-
taking as much as 60 minutes to score 1 minute of data. The question here as in
any empirical research comes down to whether the benefits accruing from usage
are worth the cost of securing them. Nevertheless it does seem apparent that the
understanding of humor is a goal worthy of the effort.
REFERENCE NOTE
I. Ekman, P. Liars and lie catchers. Book in preparation, 1982.
REFERENCES
Bergson H. Laughter: An essay on the meaning ofthe comic. New York: McGraw-Hill,
1911.
Berlyne, D. E. Humor and its kin. In J. H. Goldstein & P. E. McGhee (Eds.), The
psychology of humor. New York: Academic Press, 1972.
Blurton Jones, N. G. Criteria for use in describing facial expressions of children. Human
Biology, 1971,43,365-413.
Brannigan, C. R., & Humphries, D. A. Human non-verbal behavior, a means of
communication. In N. Blurton Jones (Ed.), Ethnological studies of child behavior.
London: Cambridge University Press, 1972.
Darwin, C. The expression of the emotions in man and animals. London: Murray,
1872.
Dearborn, G. V. N. The nature of the smile and the laugh. Science, 1900, 9, 851-856.
Duncan, S., & Fiske, D. W. Face-to-face interaction: Research, methods, and theory.
Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1977.
Ekman, P., & Friesen. W. V. Nonverbal leakage and clues to deception. Psychiatry,
1969,32,88-105.
Ekman, P., & Friesen, W. V. Facial Action Coding System. Palo Alto, Cal.: Consulting
Psychologists Press. 1978.
Ekman, P., & Friesen, W. V. Felt, false and miserable smiles. Journal of Nonverbal
Behavior. 1982, 6, 238-252.
Ekman, P., Friesen, W. V., & Ancoli, S. Facial signs of emotional experience. Journal
of Personality and Social Psychology. 1980, 39, 1125-1134.
Ekman, P., Hager, J. C., & Friesen, W. V. The symmetry of emotional and deliberate
facial actions. Psychophysiology, 1981,18, 101-106.
Godkewitsch, M. The relationship between arousal potential and funniness of jokes. In 1.
H. Goldstein and P. E. McGhee (Eds.), The psychology of humor. New York:
Academic Press, 1972.
12 Marianne LaFrance
PAUL E. MCGHEE
The interdisciplinary focus of these two volumes underscores the fact that
humor can be explained or discussed from many different vantage points. This
diversity is essential to the ultimate achievement of a comprehensive under-
standing of humor. Most attempts to explain humor have focused on cognitive,
social, emotional, linguistic, psychodynamic, sociological, or anthropological
variables, as these two volumes attest. Relatively little attention has been given
to more reductive explanations of humor. The present chapter will focus on
theoretical issues and data related to psychophysiological explanations of
humor.
An enduring popular conception of humor (first advanced over 120 years ago by
Spencer, 1860) suggests that the laughter that accompanies humor serves to
reduce built-up energy or tension. Spencer argued that laughter serves as a form
of "safety valve" for relieving excess energy built up in the nervous system.
Darwin's (1872) "principle of the direct action of the nervous system"
strengthened this view with its claim that "when the sensorium is strongly
excited, nerve force is generated in excess, and is transmitted in certain definite
directions, depending on the connection of the nerve cells and partly on habit."
Freud (1905/1960) also adopted this notion, arguing that laughter is a means of
releasing excessive "psychic energy." The sUbjective feeling of reduced tension
14 Paul E. McGhee
after laughing has probably sustained the belief that there must be a
corresponding physiological energy release.
Contemporary neurophysiological explanations of humor are best exempli-
fied by the views of the late Daniel Berlyne (1960, 1969, 1972). Berlyne (1972)
criticized the energy release hypothesis, noting that:
This kind of hypothesis is not viewed very favorably nowadays, mainly because the
underlying notion of a quantity of pent-up "nerve force," "energy," "excitation," or
"tension" that demands release receives little support from our present knowledge of
how the nervous system works. Nevertheless, laughter seems clearly to be capable of a
cathartic effect. (p. 52)
The key properties of humor stimuli that lead to humor appreciation were
referred to by Berlyne (1960, 1969, 1972) as their "collative properties."
These properties are defined not in terms of the stimulus alone, but in terms of
absolute stimulus qualities as these relate to the individual's knowledge of those
properties. Any arousal changes that occur in connection with a given stimulus
depend on the outcome of comparing one's knowledge about comparable stimuli
experienced in the past with the properties of this particular stimulus. The most
important collative properties of stimuli are novelty, complexity, incongruity,
and, perhaps, redundancy. Berlyne argued that these stimulus properties cause
arousal changes that account for the extent of humor experienced.
Berlyne's (1972) position on humor was derived from a broader base of
research concerned with the relationship between pleasure and arousal change.
As arousal resulting from a stimulus increases, it is presumably associated with
increased pleasure (positive hedonic tone) up to a point, and reduced pleasure
beyond that point. Extremely high levels of arousal were considered to be
experienced as aversive. Berlyne noted that as arousal increases, only the
reward system is initially activated. As arousal continues to increase. an
aversion system becomes activated in addition to the reward system. The extent
of pleasure experienced depends on the relative levels of activation of these two
systems. At extremely high levels of arousal, the relatively greater activation of
the aversion system should interfere with enjoyment of a joke or cartoon.
Anything that reduces this arousal should be welcomed and experienced as
pleasurable. For example, iflaughter at a joke helped lower such high arousal,
hearty laughter would be expected once the punch line occurred.
Berlyne (1960, 1972) suggested that two separate arousal mechanisms
combine with the activation of the reward and aversion systems of the central
nervous system to determine the pleasure experienced in humor. An arousal
"boost" mechanism contributes to enjoyment by elevating arousal to moder-
ately high levels that are themselves enjoyable apart from any subsequent drop
in arousal. The arousal boost mechanism presumably does not involve any
significant activation of the aversion system. In the case of the arousal "jag"
mechanism, pleasure occurs when arousal reaches a very high level and is then
sharply reduced. This reduction is pleasurable because arousal has become high
The Role of Arousal and Hemispheric Lateralization in Humor 15
Investigators studying the relationship between arousal and humor have clearly
shown that humor is associated with increased activity of the sympathetic
nervous system (e.g., Averill, 1969; Levi, 1965; Sternbach, 1962). Similar
activation occurs in very different emotional states, such as sadness and anger
(Averill, 1969; Levi, 1965). The fact that epinephrine secretion occurs in both
anger and humor points to the general importance of sympathetic arousal in
each of these emotional states. Early support for the contribution of such
arousal to funniness of a humor stimulus was provided in Schachter and
Wheeler's (1962) classic siudy. They found that injection of subjects with
epinephrine led to increased laughter while watching a humorous film. Other
studies have shown that the experiencing of humor is associated with increased
heart rate (Averill, 1969; Fry, Note 1; Godkewitsch, 1976; Goldstein,
Harman, McGhee, & Karasik, 1975; Jones & Harris, 1971; Langevin & Day,
1972; Martin, 1905; and Spencer, 1860), increased skin conductance (Averill,
1969; Godkewitsch, 1976; Goldstein et aI., 1975; and Langevin & Day, 1972),
increased muscle tension (Chapman, 1973, 1976; Spencer, 1860), altered
respiratory patterns (Fry, Note I; Fry & Rader, 1977; Fry & Stoft, 1971;
Lloyd, 1938; Spencer, 1860; and Svebak, 1975, 1977), and characteristic EEG
changes (Svebak, 1982). Given this convincing evidence that humor does
increase arousal, the important question is whether the amount or other
properties of arousal experienced during humor is related to the level of
appreciation or funniness experienced.
Heart Rate. Both Godkewitsch (1976) and Langevin and Day (1972) found a
positive linear relationship between funniness ratings given to jokes or cartoons
and the maximum heart rate occurring during their presentation. Langevin and
Day found a similar relationship for amount of heart rate change. In an
especially noteworthy finding, Godkewitsch found a positive relationship
between self-reports of arousal and funniness ratings (if subjects prove to be
reliable in judging their own arousal, future studies could use self-report
The Role of Arousal and Hemispheric Lateralization in Humor 17
GSR. Findings for skin conductance are consistent with the general pattern of
heart rate data, showing a positive relationship between funniness ratings and
GSR (Galvanic Skin Response) amplitude or log GSR across a wide range of
humor stimuli (Averill, 1969; Godkewitsch, 1976; Langevin & Day, 1972). It
should be noted that both Godkewitsch and Langevin and Day found that
extremely unfunny jokes or cartoons can produce greater GSR reactivity than
funny ones. Both the heart rate and GSR data appear to provide stronger
support for Berlyne's arousal boost mechanism than for the arousal jag
mechanism.
Muscle Tension. Spencer (1860) observed over a century ago that humor was
accompanied by an increase in muscle tension. This finding has recently been
confirmed by Chapman (1973, 1976). Chapman (1976) divided subjects into
subgroups who had given high or low funniness ratings to the jokes. Muscle
tension was greater among the high funniness rating group at periods 30, 40, and
50 seconds into the joke, as well as 20 seconds after the joke (measurements
were not taken at the punchline or 10 seconds afterwards because of the
confounding influence ofthe act oflaughing). If muscle tension is considered an
index of arousal, then these findings add further support to the view that humor
stimuli that produce greater levels of arousal are experienced as funnier.
since there is no clear link between amount of arousal and respiratory changes
beyond the fact that laughter is associated with deeper and faster breathing (Fry
& Rader, 1977; Martin, 1905; Spencer, 1860). Fry and Rader (1977) and
Lloyd (1938) found that expiration during laughter is considerably more
prolonged than inspiration. Fry and Stoft (1971) note that there is such a high
imbalance of expiration over inspiration in laughter that a pulmonary gas deficit
usually results, requiring several respiration cycles to return to normal. Fry and
Rader ( 1977) have provided a detailed analysis of both common properties and
individual differences across laughs and laughers.
Only Svebak(1975, 1977) has linked respiratory measures to level of humor
appreciation. In one study ( 1975), he found that greater abdominal inspiration-
expiration trunk circumference change was associated with more frequent and
more enduring laughter among women (but not men). A second study by
Svebak (1977) has clear implications for the role of arousal in humor. Drawing
from the work of Christiansen (1972), he distinguished between three different
respiration patterns. He provides support for the view that one of these,
"sighing," can be used as an index or situationally induced anxiety or tension
(arousal). Subjects who showed the sighing pattern prior to being shown a
humorous television program showed the greatest amount of laughter during the
program. While this arousal was present before the appearance of the humorous
event(s), the findings are consistent with the view that increased arousal leads to
increased funniness.
giving away the exact punch line) may also be conducive to heightened arousal
during the joke body.
One of the greatest puzzles in the study of humor continues to be why the
mental experience of humor should be associated with the motor response of
laughter. While most of us can experience mild amusement without showing
more than a brief smile, extremely funny experiences tend to automatically
trigger laughter. The reason for this may lie in our general tendency to increase
physical activity in states of heightened emotional arousal. In threatening
situations, this activity probably originally took the form of "fight or flight." The
use of energy through physical exertion may aid in the process of returning
arousal to a normal adaptive range, regardless of the particular form taken by
that exertion. Haberman (1955; cited by Fry & Stoft, 1971) noted European
research that showed that vigorous laughter provides an average of over 75%
increase in energy expenditure relative to a resting state. Given the many
muscle systems involved in laughter, it should be an effective means of reducing
arousal or felt tension.
While laughter does appear to (help) reduce the arousal produced by humor
experiences, the timetable and exact nature of arousal change at the punch line
and following it (up to a return to a baseline of arousal) remain unclear. Given
the strong repeated expirations of air during laughter and the accompanying
increased muscular exertion, muscle tension, heart rate, and GSR should all
increase as a direct result of the laughter. It may be, then, that strong laughter
actually adds to humor-induced arousal before eventually reducing it. The real
significance of arousal changes for the subjective experience of funniness will
remain uncertain until arousal changes surrounding the punch line are better
understood.
There is some basis for arguing that laughter serves a general arousal-
reduction function, apart from its connection with humor. In "nervous
laughter," for example, the act of laughing appears to help regulate felt tension.
Also, Nerhardt (1970, 1976) and Deckers (Deckers & Devine, 1981; Deckers
& Kizer, 1975) have found that laughter occurs in weight-lifting experiments
when there is a discrepancy between the weight expected and the weight
actually encountered. This laughter appears to serve to return the arousal
resulting from the expectancy violation back to a base level range. It is probably
the awareness of this arousal reduction that sustained the earlier belief
(discussed above) that laughter actually releases energy from the nervous
system.
Rothbart (1973) and Sroufe (Sroufe & Waters, 1976; Sroufe & Wunsch,
1972) have also put forth arousal-related explanations of laughter, although
these are restricted to infants and young children. Rothbart argued that arousal
changes alone do not determine whether laughter or some other response
The Role of Arousal and Hemispheric Lateralization in Humor 21
occurs; rather, this depends on the child's evaluation of the context surrounding
the arousal. As long as arousal does not increase excessively, an evaluation of
the situation as safe or inconsequential will lead to laughter. But if arousal does
get high, or the stimulus or context is judged to be threatening, laughter will be
replaced by some other (presumably negative) emotional response. Sroufe and
his associates also stress the importance of contextual factors for infant laughter.
They use the term "tension" instead of "arousal" and argue that an increase
followed by a decrease in tension is required for laughter or smiling to occur.
The greater and more rapid the build-up of tension, the greater the probability of
laughter occurring instead of smiling.
Sroufe's position is similar to the more physiologically based view of
Tomkins (1962). Tomkins argued that laughter and other positive affects result
from the changes in neural firing that accompany sudden drops in stimulation.
Tomkins (as did Darwin, 1872, nearly a century earlier) also considered
laughter to be simply an intense form of smiling: "As such it is activated in the
same way as the smile except that the general density of stimulation which is
suddenly reduced begins at a higher level in the case of laughter ... " (p. 370).
Actually, for Tomkins it is the combination of the original degree of intensity of
stimulation and the suddenness of the drop in neural firing that determines
whether laughter or smiling occurs.
Both existing data and theoretical views, then, suggest that the link between
arousal changes and laughter is a very general one that does not necessarily
require a humor experience as a prerequisite. While it is difficult to speculate
about when in human evolutionary history the capacity for humor began to
appear, it seems likely that this general relationship between laughter-smiling
and arousal (in a positive or safe context) developed first. As the cognitive
experience of humor developed out of a more general disposition toward play
(see McGhee, 1979), its associated arousal changes must have been incor-
porated into the general system linking laughter to arousal. While it is
commonly acknowledged (e.g., see Giles & Oxford, 1970) that there are several
forms of nonhumorous as well as humorous laughter, virtually no attempt has
been made to study how these different kinds of laughter differ. It would be of
immense value to the progress of humor research if humorous laughter could be
distinguished either behaviorally or physiologically from other forms of
laughter. (See Chapter I by LaFrance.)
It should be emphasized that the existing data do not yet allow for any firm
conclusions about the relationship between humor, laughter, and arousal. Most
of the data reviewed above are based on funniness ratings provided after the
physiological measures have been obtained. The clearest theoretical link
between arousal and humor appreciation, however, applies to laughter, not
humor. Since laughter and funniness rating measures generally show only a
moderate positive correlation with each other, it is not clear how variations in
findings in different studies relating arousal changes to funniness ratings should
be interpreted. Most investigators have chosen not to measure laughter, perhaps
because of the artifactual influence of the act of laughing upon the arousal
22 Paul E. McGhee
point funniness scale instead of some other rating. While most of us feel
confident about whether something is or is not funny, do we find it funny only
because we notice our laughter or because of cognitions that we monitor
independent of our laughter? Studies of children's humor have demonstrated
that jokes or cartoons that pose some moderate level of effort for comprehension
are judged to be funnier than those that are either very easily understood or
understood only with extreme effort (McGhee, 1976; Zigler, Levine, & Gould,
1966, 1967). It is not clear whether these children (school-aged) were aware of
the difficulty they had in understanding the material presented, but this would
appear to be a good starting point for studying metacognitive determinants of
judgments of funniness.
Research completed in the 1970s by Howard Leventhal and his associates
underscores the importance of initiating the study of metacognitive processes in
humor. Their data suggest that males and females differ in the information (at
least regarding laughter) used to make decisions about funniness. When shown
either a slapstick film or cartoons accompanied by a laugh track, both high
school (Leventhal & Mace, 1970) and college students (Cupchik & Leventhal,
1974) showed increased laughter, relative to a non-laugh-track condition. In
both studies, though, only females also rated the cartoons as funnier in the laugh
track condition. In a second study, Leventhal and Mace (1970) asked first
through fifth graders to either laugh a lot at the film or not laugh at all. Again,
instructions to laugh increased the laughter of both sexes, but only girls also
rated the film to be funnier when they laughed at it more. Women also both
laughed more and rated cartoons as being funnier at an end-of-the-semester beer
party than in a laboratory, while men laughed more at the cartoons at the party
without rating them as funnier in that context (Leventhal & Cupchik, 1975). It
is important to note that women can discount their elevated laughter in making
judgments about funniness if instructed to do so. Panagis, Leventhal, and
Caputo (Note 2) found that when both sexes were asked to pay careful attention
to the nature of the audience reaction and the quality of the cartoon, males and
females gave comparable funniness ratings. Without these instructions, women
again gave higher funniness ratings in the presence of high laughter on a laugh
track.
These findings strongly suggest that different factors enter into making
funniness judgments among males and females. Females seem to monitor their
own laughter more in making this judgment. Leventhal and Mace (1970) argued
that this pattern of findings for funniness is simply one manifestation of a
general trend toward females taking their own expressive reactions into account
in making judgments about events, while males are more likely to keep their
expressive reactions independent of their intellectual judgments.
Godkewitsch's (1976) finding that subjects were quite accurate in estimating
their own arousal during jokes may be especially important for determining the
extent to which the monitoring of one's arousal enters into making funniness
judgments. It may not be sufficient, though, to simply correlate perceived self-
arousal scores with funniness ratings since subjects may become consciously
24 Paul E. McGhee
aware of their arousal during humor only when asked to evaluate it. As in the
case of laughter monitoring, careful attention in studies along these lines should
be given to sex differences and other sources of individual differences.
While the main focus of this chapter has been on the influence of arousal and
laughter on judgments of funniness, serious consideration must also be given to
cognitive evaluations of various aspects of the cartoon or joke itself. The joke
may be judged to be funny because of the clever incongruities represented,
because of allusions to sexual activity, because a member of a disliked group is
put down, and so forth. These are the kinds of dimensions individuals are most
likely to refer to when they are asked to explain why the event was (or was not)
funny. But since information on humor comphrension is typically not obtained
(although this is occasionally done in studies using children), it is difficult in
most studies to be certain that the joke recipient has really understood the
"intended" humor. In this writer's view, since humor is most essentially a
cognitive experience (McGhee, 1979), additional research on the kinds of
cognitive evaluation that occur in connection with humor events should be
especially fruitful in improving our understanding of the determinants of
intellectual judgments about humor. Arousal may prove to interact with
cognitive appraisal dimensions in key ways to determine perceived funniness
or it may be shown to be a mere by-product of cognition. Arousal may also
prove capable of influencing laughter without necessarily influencing judgments
of funniness.
An increasing amount of attention has been given in the past decade to the
differential capacities of the right and left cerebral hemispheres (see Springer &
Deutsch, 1981, and Tucker, 1981, for reviews). Language competence has long
been known to be typically associated with the left hemisphere (at least among
right-handed individuals), and nonverbal functions (e.g., music and visual form
perception) have been assumed to be associated with the right hemisphere (e.g.,
see Kimura, 1973; Milner, 1962). More recent research, however, has
suggested that the critical property that differentiates the two hemispheres may
be processing style, with the left hemisphere being specialized for relational,
sequential, or analytical processing and the right specialized for simultaneous or
holistic processing (Bever, 1980; Das, Kirby, & Jarman, 1979; Tucker, 1981).
Bever (1980) has argued that language is mediated by the left hemisphere
simply because language requires relational or sequential (hereafter used
interchangeably) processing. He also presents data that support the position
The Role of Arousal and Hemispheric Lateralization in Humor 25
that music and form perception may be mediated by the left hemisphere if tasks
in these areas are specifically set up to require relational processing. Thus, it
appears to be the kind of processing required within a modality, and not the
modality itself, that determines the relative involvement of the two hemispheres.
Das, Kirby, and Jarman ( 1975) distinguished between these two processing
styles as follows:
Das, Kirby, and Jarman (1975) note that many complex intellectual tasks
involve elements of both types of processing and probably include fluctuations
back and forth between the two as the cognitive demands of the task change.
Finally, Tucker ( 1981) concluded that
Anatomical Basis for Hemisphere Differences. One recent study has pro-
vided data that suggest that anatomical differences in neuronal organization
may at least partially account for the different processing styles of the two
hemispheres. Gur, Packer, Hungerbuhler, Reivich, Obrist, Amamek, and
Sackheim (1980) used radioisotope techniques and found a greater amount of
white matter in the right than in the left hemisphere, suggesting that the right
hemisphere may be characterized by a greater degree of interconnectedness
among different regions than the left hemisphere. Tucker ( 1981) notes (as Gur
et aI., 1980, had earlier) that this finding
26 Paul E. McGhee
supports the suggestion from earlier clinical observations (Semmes, 1968) that the
receptotopic distribution of information across the cortex is focal and discrete in the
left hemisphere but more diffuse and generalized in the right hemisphere. (p. 38)
Each hemisphere's pattern of organization at a neuronal level may thus be uniquely
suited to its preferred cognitive operations .... The left hemisphere's focal and
discrete layout seems compatible with a tendency toward analytic and cognitive
organization, whereas a more diffuse and global neuronal pattern in the right
hemisphere seems to coincide nicely with holistic cognitive operations. (p. 38)
Howard Gardner and his associates have recently completed a series of studies
with patients who have suffered damage to the right hemisphere (usually as a
result of a stroke). These studies have consistently shown that while right-
hemisphere damage does not affect basic language functions, it does interfere
with comprehension of a number of subtle and complex aspects of language.
Patients with right-hemisphere lesions have been found to show reduced ability
to: (1) determine connotations of common words (Gardner & Denes, 1973), (2)
interpret metaphors (Winner & Gardner, 1977), (3) appreciate antonymic
contrasts (Gardner, Silverman, Wapner, & Zurif, 1978), (4) organize randomly
ordered sentences into coherent narratives (Wapner, Hamby, & Gardner,
1981), and (5) detect bizarre or incongruous elements in a story (Wapner et aI.,
1981). Wapner et aI. found that for both shorter and longer story narratives,
right-hemisphere patients could understand and remember isolated details of a
story, but had difficulty integrating the information into a consistent whole and
in judging the appropriateness or fit of different story elements. They also noted
that
Wapner et aI. (1981) concluded from the overall pattern of their data that
patients with right-hemisphere lesions show an impaired plausibility metric.
That is, they lack the capacity shown by individuals with normal brains to judge
whether a particular stimulus element is appropriate within a particular
context.
Thus, even as a patient may challenge a statement which normal controls consider to
be perfectly plausible, the same patient may accept, or even strive to justify that non-
canonical element which is immediately challenged or ignored by a normal control.
Bereft of a structure into which to place the element, unaware of (or insensitive to) the
rules which generally govern discourse in the area, the patient must make an
The Role of Arousal and Hemispheric Lateralization in Humor 27
assessment based only on the element itself. And so, when a patient's individual
answer or remark is examined without respect to context, it generally seems
appropriate. (p. 27)
Another related, but somewhat more abstract way of characterizing the difficulties of
these patients is to stress their problems in acquiring a sense of overall gestalt of
linguistic entities. Patients seem unable to appreciate the relations among the key
points of the story .... The basic schema-the major episodes organized in an
appropriate manner-seems disturbed, if not totally destroyed, while it may well be
spared even in linguistically compromised left hemisphere patients. (p. 28)
The findings reviewed above strongly suggest that the right hemisphere plays a
central role in the comprehension and appreciation of humor. While caution
must always be exercised in drawing conclusions about normal brain functions
on the basis of data from damaged brains (Springer & Deutsch, 1981), patients
with right-hemisphere lesions show deficits in numerous capacities in a
nonhumor context that should interfere with normal humor appreciation, as
well. These include a reduced ability to: (1) consider connotations of words, (2)
interpret simple metaphors, (3) organize information into coherent sequences,
(4) detect bizarre or incongruous elements, (5) integrate details into a broader
coherent whole, (6) judge plausibility of an event relative to a particular context,
(7) consider interrelationships between parts, and (8) go beyond specific details
to "get the point" of a message. Data from the limited number of humor studies
completed with individuals with right- or left-hemisphere damage are consistent
with the view that it is the right hemisphere that performs the insightful
integration of the key elements of information that must be meaningfully linked
before the humor can be understood and appreciated. If the left hemisphere
must fend for itself, the individual may be surprised by the humor stimulus (see
Brownell et aI., 1982), but will be unable to determine how the surprising event
does meaningfully fit in. A given joke, cartoon, or spontaneous humorous
incident requires simultaneous awareness of several key bits of information
represented in the current stimulus event, along with pertinent context-related
knowledge derived from past experience. The right hemisphere's greater
interconnectedness of neurons makes it better suited to perform this function
than the left hemisphere.
Normally, of course, the two hemispheres do not operate in isolation from
one another. Tucker (1981), for example, noted that "the human brain must be
considered something of a binary system, with two functionally differentiated
information-processing subsystems." How, then, do the two hemispheres
interact in processing humor, and what role is played by the left hemisphere? In
the case of verbally mediated humor, left hemisphere processing should
predominate up to the punch line. That is, language automatically entails
relational or sequential processing because words must follow each other in
time. As one reads or listens to a joke, incoming information is continually
related to what has been said and to what is expected to follow. In the case of
straightforward communications, the left hemisphere is fully competent to
understand statements and respond appropriately. When the unexpected and
incongruous information in a joke is delivered (in the punch line), however, the
left hemisphere appears unable to go beyond registering surprise. It is the right
The Role of Arousal and Hemispheric Lateralization in Humor 31
hemisphere that comes into play at this point and produces the simultaneous
awareness of two meanings (as in a pun) or of diverse elements that must be
brought together in order to appreciate the humor potentially present.
Cartoon humor should be processed in the same fashion, unless the cartoon is
simple enough to be understood with one quick glance. As the individual scans
the surface of the drawing, increasing amounts of information are picked up in
sequential fashion. Eventually incongruous or inconsistent information will be
detected. The cartoon will not be understood until other information available
from either the cartoon or the individual's prior experience is seen to provide a
meaningful and coherent link with the elements forming the incongruity. Again,
this presumably requires right-hemisphere involvement.
Fouts (Note 6) appears to have been the first person to speculate about the
roles of simultaneous and successive processing in humor. He argued (at the
second International Conference on Humor in Los Angeles) that both processes
are involved in humor. Simultaneous processing was first considered to lead
to a global perception of key relationships; the humor recipient then sequentially
compares the pattern just received with the expected pattern-that is, with what
has happened in the past. According to Fouts, it is only after this sequential
process leads to a comparison of the present incongruous event with expected
relationships drawn from one's memory that humor occurs. This position, then,
appears to link the humorous insight most directly to left-hemisphere function-
ing, although both hemispheres clearly contribute in key ways. The position
outlined here differs from that of Fouts in that I have argued that simultaneous
processing in the right hemisphere plays the most important role in the
humorous insight. At some level, the individual is aware of both the expected
relationship and the current incongruous relationship at the same time.
Sequential processing is considered to come into play after the humor has been
perceived, as the individual thinks about why the joke or cartoon is funny or
otherwise reflects about the contents of the punch line or drawing.
SUMMARY
This chapter examines existing research and theory concerning the role of
arousal in humor and discusses issues and data that have implications for the
possible differential operation of the two cerebral hemispheres in humor.
Primary attention is given to Berlyne's (1972) view that an arousal boost and
arousal jag mechanism are both involved in determining the extent of pleasure
derived from humor. Berlyne's position has led to confusion as to whether
arousal change should be related to humor appreciation in a positive linear,
inverted-V, or V-shaped fashion. Since all possible relationships can be
interpreted as being consistent with Berlyne's model, it is concluded that the
model is inherently untestable. Physiological data provide stronger support for
the operation of the arousal boost than the arousal jag mechanism in
contributing to funniness, although this may be due to the failure of investigators
to use humor stimuli that produce very high levels of arousal in subjects. While
extent of humor appreciation does appear to be positively related to amount of
arousal change associated with most jokes or cartoons, the chain of causal
influence operating between arousal change, laughter, and cognitions related to
humor comprehension and appreciation remains unclear.
Existing research and theory pointing to a different style of cognitive
processing by the two cerebral hemispheres are discussed, leading to the
conclusion that the right hemisphere may playa critical role in understanding
and appreciating humor. Studies of patients who have suffered damage to the
right hemisphere ( especially the frontal areas) point to deficits, in comparison to
normals, in comprehension of both metaphors and humor. These patients have
particular difficulty in judging the appropriateness of a given stimulus event
within a specified context; they commonly fail to see the meaningful coherence
of incongruities composing a joke or cartoon. It is proposed that simultaneous
processing associated primarily with the right hemisphere plays the key role of
achieving humorous insights, although sequential processing associated with the
left hemisphere will usually be involved in providing pertinent information
34 Paul E. McGhee
REFERENCE NOTES
1. Fry, W. F. Instinctual and physiologic bases of the humor experience. Paper
presented at the meeting of the Western Psychological Association, Vancouver,
September 1969.
2. Panagis, D. H., Leventhal, H., & Caputo, G. C. Sex differences in integrating focal
and contextual cues. Unpublished manuscript, University of Wisconsin, 1975.
3. Sackheim, H. A., Weiman, A. L., Gur, R. C. Greenberg, M. S., & Hungerbuhler, J.
P. Functional brain asymmetry in the experience of positive and negative emotions:
Lateralization of insult in cases of uncontrollable emotional outbursts. Unpublished
manuscript, 1980.
4. Geschwind, N. An approach to a theory of localization of audition in the human
brain. Paper presented at the International Neuropsychology Symposium, Roc-
Amadour, France, 1976.
5. Brownell, H. H., Michel, D., Powelson, J., & Gardner, H. Surprise and coherence:
Sensitivity to verbal humor in right hemisphere patients. Unpublished manuscript,
1982.
6. Fouts, R. S. Chimpanzee language and humor. Paper presented at meeting of the
Second International Conference on Humor, Los Angeles, August 1979.
7. Caputo, G. C., & Leventhal, H. Sex differences in lateralization effects for holistic-
subjective processing. Unpublished manuscript, University of Wisconsin, 1975.
REFERENCES
Averill, J. R. Autonomic response patterns during sadness and mirth. Psychophysiology,
1969,5,399-414.
Berlyne, D. E. Conflict, arousal and curiosity. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1960.
Berlyne, D. E. Laughter, humor and play. In G. Lindzey & E. Aronson (Eds.),
Handbook of social psychology (2nd ed., Vol. 3). Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley,
1969.
Berlyne, D. E. Humor and its kin. In 1. H. Goldstein & P. E. McGhee (Eds.), The
psychology of humor: Theoretical perspectives and empirical issues. New York:
Academic Press, 1972.
Bever, T. G. Broca and Lashley were right: Cerebral dominance is an accident of
growth. In D. Caplan (Ed.),. Biological studies of mental processes. Cambridge,
Mass.: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press, 1980.
Cantor, J. R., Bryant, J., & Zillmann, D. Enhancement of humor appreciation by
transferred excitation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 1974, 30,
812-821.
The Role of Arousal and Hemispheric Lateralization in Humor 35
Gur, R C., Packer, I. K., Hungerbuhler, J. P., Reivich, M., Obrist, W. D., Amarnek,
W. S., & Sackheim, H. A. Differences in the distribution of gray and white matter in
human cerebral hemispheres. Science, 1980, 207, 1126-1128.
Habermann, G. Physiologie und phonetik des lauthaften Lachens. Leipzig: Barth,
1955.
Jones, J. M., & Harris, P. E. Psychophysiological correlates of cartoon humor
appreciation. Proceedings of the American Psychological Association, 1971, 6,
381-382.
Kimura, D. Functional asymmetry of the human brain. Scientific American, 1973,228,
70-78.
Kutas, M., & Hillyard, S. A. Reading senseless sentences: Brain potentials reflect
semantic incongruity. Science, 1980, 207, 203-204.
Limgevin, R, & Day, H. I. Physiological correlates of humor. In J. H. Goldstein & P. E.
McGhee (Eds.), The psychology of humor: Theoretical perspectives and empirical
issues. New York: Academic Press, 1972.
Leventhal, H., & Cupchik, G. C. The informational and facilitative effects of an
audience upon expression and evaluation of humorous stimuli. Journal of Experi-
mental Social Psychology, 1975, 11, 363-380.
Leventhal, H., & Mace, W. The effect of laughter on evaluation of a slapstick movie.
Journal of Personality, 1970, 38, 16-30.
Leventhal, H., & Safer, M. A. Individual differences, personality and humour
appreciation: Introduction to symposium. In A. J. Chapman & H. C. Foot (Eds.), It's
ajunny thing, humour. Oxford: Pergamon, 1977.
Levi, L. The urinary output of adrenalin and noradrenalin during pleasant and
unpleasant emotional states. Psychosomatic Medicine, 1965,27,80-85.
Lloyd, E. L. The respiratory mechanism in laughter. Journal of General Psychology,
1938,10,179-189.
Martin, L. J. Psychology of aesthetics: Experimental prospecting in the field of the
comic. American Journal of Psychology, 1905, 16,35-116.
McGhee, P. E. Children's appreciation of humor: A test of the cognitive congruency
principle. Child Development, 1976, 47, 420-426.
McGhee, P. E. Humor: Its origin and development. San Francisco: Freeman, 1979.
Milner, B. Laterality effects in audition. In V. B. Mountcastle (Ed.), Interhemispheric
relations and cerebral dominance. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press,
1962.
Nerhardt, G. Humor and inclination to laugh: Emotional reactions to stimuli of different
divergence from a range of expectancy. Scandinavian Journal of Psychology, 1970,
11, 185-195.
Nerhardt, G. Incongruity and funniness: Towards a new descriptive model. In A. J.
Chapman & H. C. Foot (Eds.), Humour and laughter: Theory, research and
applications. London: Wiley, 1976.
Perria, L., Rosadini, G., & Rossi, G. F. Determination of side of cerebral dominance
with Amobarbital. Archives of Neurology, 1961,4,173-181.
Rothbart, M. K. Laughter in young children. Psychological Bulletin, 1973, 80,
247-256.
Rothbart, M. K. Incongruity, problem-solving and laughter. In A. J. Chapman & H. C.
Foot (Eds.), Humor and laughter: Theory, research and applications. London:
Wiley, 1976.
Schachter, S., & Wheeler, L. Epinephrine, chlorpromazine, and amusement. Journal of
Abnormal and Social Psychology, 1962,65, 121-128.
The Role of Arousal and Hemispheric Lateralization in Humor 37
Cognitive Processes in
Humor Appreciation
JERRY SULS
Several early philosophers and essayists looked for an explanation for humor-
why is it funny-and thought they found it in the incongruous or surprising
40 Jerry Suls
Incongruity Theories
One contemporary view follows directly from the observations of Hazlitt, Kant,
and others in positing that incongruity is the necessary and sufficient element
that elicits humor. Nerhardt (1976, 1977) argues that humor is a consequence
of the discrepancy between two mental representations, one of which is an
expectation (presumably derived from, for example, the main body of a joke
preceding the punch line) and the other is some other idea or percept (for
example, as contained in the punch line). According to this account, the greater
the divergence of a stimulus from expectation in one or more dimensions, the
funnier the stimulus. Of course not all surprises are funny. Opening the door to
one's closet and finding a corpse is unlikely to inspire laughter. Recognizing this
problem, Nerhardt (1977) suggests that perception of incongruity must occur in
a safe or nonthreatening environmental to evoke humor.
To test this model Nerhardt (1970) conducted a series of ingenious
experiments in which expectations and divergence from expectation were
manipulated. For example, in one study he had subjects lift a series of weights
under the guise that weight discriminations were being tested. The final weight
in the series was greatly discrepant from the prior weight (either much heavier
or much lighter). Consistent with Nerhardt's thesis, subjects smiled or laughed
more the more discrepant the final weight was from expectation, a result that
has been replicated by Gerber and Routh (1975), Deckers and Kizer (1975),
and Deckers, Jenkins, and Gladfelter (1977). The latter study is especially
interesting because the experimenters had a series of control conditions. In one
condition the subject was led to expect a much heavier weight and had previous
experience with it. In this case humor was low compared to experimental
subjects whose expectations were "rudely" disconfirmed.
Nerhardt's approach argues that incongruity is a necessary and sufficient
condition to produce humor, given that the stimulus receives a safe interpre-
tation. And indeed it seems clear that many instances of real life humorous
experiences and ones devised by comedians and film directors fall under this
category. However, there are forms of verbal and cartoon humor that appear to
involve a more complex process-something beyond mere incongruity.
Incongruity-Resolution Theory
Find rule
that makes
ending follow
from preceding
material
Is rule found? I
l
YES
t
NO
I Laughter II Puzzlement I
Figure 3-1. Incongruity Resolution Model. (From "A Two-Stage Model for the
Appreciation of Jokes and Cartoons" by J. Suls, in J. H. Goldstein and P. E. McGhee,
Eds., Psychology of Humor, New York: Academic Press, 1972. Copyright 1972.
Reprinted by permission of the publisher.)
Cognitive Processes in Humor Appreciation 43
Another way in which humor is different from other problems is that it may
evoke what Berlyne ( 1972) called" arousal jags." This term refers to conditions
that generate an increase in arousal that is then quickly reduced that presumably
brings pleasure. Shultz (1976) has suggested that the incongruity-resolution
model can be incorporated with Berlyne's arousal jag notion if it is assumed that
the perception of joke incongruity increases the subject's level of cognitive
arousal and a successful resolution serves to decrease arousal back to baseline.
However, Shultz also acknowledges that such a conception is purely heuristic
since there is currently no way to assess cognitive arousal in a precise way.
Another problem is that certain kinds of nonhumorous puzzles may also
produce arousal jags but do not instigate laughter. A tentative answer to this
dilemma will be reserved for a later section. The reader is referred to McGhee's
chapter in this volume for a detailed discussion of arousal mechanisms and
humor.
Experimental Evidence
The earliest empirical work to emphasize that some form of problem solving is
implicated in humor came from Zigler, Levine, and Gould (1967). They
suggested that appreciation of humor requires comprehension of the material
and that appreciation should be highest when the material requires a moderate
amount of challenge or effort. Appreciation will be low when the joke material is
too easy or extremely difficult to understand. In one investigation using
cartoons of varying levels of difficulty with children in the second, third, fourth,
and fifth grades, Zigler et al. found some evidence for the so-called cognitive
congruency principle. However, McGhee (1977) observed that neither Zigler et
al. nor McGhee ( 1971) in another investigation had been able to specify a priori
a relative difference in the amount of cognitive effort required by different
children to understand the humor.
A more recent study (McGhee, 1976) provided a better test by employing
children who varied in the degree to which they had acquired conservation and
class inclusion. Jokes were presented to them in which the humor derived from
the violation of the concepts. For example a joke requiring conservation was:
Mr. Jones went into a restaurant and ordered a whole pizza for dinner. When the
waiter asked if he wanted it cut into six or eight pieces, Mr. Jones said: "Oh, you'd
better make it six! I could never eat eight."
Here the humor appears to result from recognizing ,that Mr. Jone's last
statement violates the conservation of mass. McGhee found, consistent with the
cognitive congruency notion, that appreciation of jokes like the one above was
greatest for children who had just recently acquired the requisite concepts, while
reduced appreciation was shown by children who did not yet possess
conservation or had mastered it some years previously.
Cognitive Processes in Humor Appreciation 45
"Doctor, come at once! Our baby swallowed a fountain pen!" "I'll be right over. What
are you doing in the meantime?" "Using a pencil."
The reader will note that in the original "Using a pencil" is incongruous but
follows from the ambiguity of the question that precedes it "What are you doing
in the meantime?" -meaning what are you using as a substitute for the pen. As
Shultz and others have pointed out, linguistic ambiguity is a common way that
humor provides incongruity and potential resolution.
Other children received a resolution-removed version of the joke:
"Doctor, come at once! Our baby swallowed a rubberband!" ''I'll be right over. What
are you doing in the meantime?" "Using a pencil."
"Doctor, come at once! Our baby swallowed a fountain pen!" "I'll be right over. What
are you doing in the meantime?" "We don't know what to do."
Each child was presented via tape recording a series of jokes, one-third of each
type. The child was asked to provide a funniness rating on a scale and the
experimenter also noted the child's overt reaction (smiling or laughing). The
results showed that the 8-, 10-, and 12-year-olds found the original forms
funnier than the resolution-removed jokes and the resolution-removed jokes
funnier than the incongruity-removed jokes. Interestingly, the 6-year-olds
showed no difference between the original and resolution-removed forms, but
both were funnier than forms without incongruity. Shultz has suggested that at
46 Jerry Suls
If a researcher does not retain the same incongruity for both original and resolution-
removed forms, the incongruity alone condition may present a different level of
incongruity than the original version ... (thus) if the original version ... is pre-
ferred ... we do not know whether it is due to appreciation of resolution aspects or to
appreciation of additional incongruities present. (Pien & Rothbart, 1977, p. 212)
They gave, as an example, a cartoon used by Shultz (1972) that in its original
form shows a cow with an "out-of-order" sign and a girl walking angrily away
with an empty pail. In the resolution-removed version, the picture only shows a
cow with the "out-of-order" sign. Pien and Rothbart contend that the original
contains more incongruity (girl's angry expression and the empty pail) than the
altered version. These criticisms are well-taken although they do not apply to all
of the materials used in past studies. One way around the problem is to use the
method of convergent operations (Campbell & Fiske, 1959) and find other
ways to examine the impact of incongruity and resolution.
A study by Wicker, Thorelli, Barron, and Ponder (1981) takes such a
different approach. Wicker et al. had a large group of subjects rate a series of
jokes first for funniness and then on 13 other scales to assess dimensions
suggested by various accounts of humor. Some of the dimensions included
surprise, incongruity, resolution, anxiety, originality, importance, superiority,
and emotional involvement. Subjects' ratings were averaged for each of the
jokes on each of the scales and intercorrelations among scales over joke
averages were computed. These correlations were then subjected to a principal-
components factor analysis that revealed that ratings of surprise, resolution, and
originality correlated strongly with funniness and defined a factor on which
funniness ratings loaded. Ratings of painfulness and anxiety were also positively
correlated with funniness but defined a factor essentially independent of it.
Perhaps of greatest importance, partial correlations showed that painfulness and
Cognitive Processes in Humor Appreciation 47
anxiety scales were related to funniness through their common relationship with
the incongruity and resolution scales. Not only do these data suggest that both
incongruity and resolution are important in the appreciation of humor, they also
suggest that affective elements may influence humor through their effect on
cognitive mechanisms related to resolution. Thus, it appears that painful or
anxious material increases funniness not simply because it allows greater
tension release, but also because it is associated with increases in surprise and
resolution. This is indicated by the fact that
Suls (1972, 1977) and Shultz (1972, 1976) emphasize the importance of
incongruity and resolution for humor (for adults) while Nerhardt (1977)
believes that incongruity is sufficient. Also, Rothbart (1973, 1976) maintains
that incongruity that is perceived as safe is sufficient to evoke humor. Indeed,
the weight discrimination experiments reviewed earlier involve no obvious
resolution so it does appear that even among adults incongruity may in some
cases be sufficient. We submit, though, that most humor, particularly of a verbal
form, has an incongruity-resolution structure. Indeed Shultz (1977) examined
verbal humor from the folklore literature of cultures very different from Western
technological society-Chinese jokes, riddles from nonliterate cultures, and
Japanese riddles and folk-tales. The presence of incongruity and resolution
features was found in the vast majority of the materials (for example, of 242
Chinese jokes examined, 210 possessed incongruity and resolution). The
incidence of incongruity humor is rarer and generally involves nonverbal,
physical gags (Nerhardt's weight study is in essence a physical gag) as in
slapstick or situations where a need to make sense of things may not be urgent,
for example, when a person is intoxicated. But such cases for adults are
probably the exception rather than the rule.
48 Jerry Suls
between these two different kinds of humor is not clear and has been given
virtually no attention. One tentative suggestion is that when the incongruity is
extremely divergent from expectations the respondent assumes that no
resolution is possible and as a result perceives no need to attempt a "fit." But
when the incongruity falls somewhere between the expected and unexpected,
the need for resolution becomes salient and engenders frustration if it is not
found. Unfortunately, these conjectures can only be empirically examined when
we develop the tools to operationalize discrepancy or incongruity; up till now
the scaling of incongruity has received little attention.
should be operative, Leventhal contends that females are more likely to employ
inner feelings about the stimulus (subjective processing), while males are more
likely to make their appraisals on the basis of external features (objective
processing). This argument is based on suppositions that characterize males as
analytical and field independent and females as subjective and field dependent
Consistent with their hypothesis, Leventhal and Cupchik (1975) found that
variables that raise the subject's level of spontaneous expressive behavior (such
as a setting that permits laughter or canned laughter) also raised the level of
perceived funniness, but only for females. Males also laughed more, but ratings
of humor were unaffected. The inference from this and other studies (Cupchik &
Leventhal, 1974) is that males rely more on objective-stimulus based cues while
females rely more on SUbjective-expressive based cues.
Leventhal and Cupchik (1976) suggest that the sex difference occurs because
of differential reliance on the left or right cerebral hemispheres. Presumably,
females' reliance on emotional cues stems from the influence of the right
hemisphere that is a major center for holistic or emotional analysis. In contrast,
males rely more on objective cues because of the greater role played by the left
hemisphere that processes information objectively. Results consistent with their
reasoning were found in a study in which males and females received humorous
material and heard canned laughter through the left ear (right hemisphere) or the
right ear (left hemisphere). If females rely more on right hemisphere processing,
then they should find the material funnier when heard through the left ear. In
contrast, males should rate the material as funnier when heard through the right
ear. The results were as predicted, suggesting some general differences in
hemispheric dominance between males and females in processing of humorous
material.
Of more present relevance is the fact that the dual process model provides a
way to understand how contextual cues (canned laughter or the presence of
others) influence the appreciation of humor quite independent of the structural
properties of humor (e.g., incongruity, resolution). In fact, we might speculate
that audience cues and other facilitators of expressive reactions may be
responsible for some instances of laughter when incongruity or resolution
structures are absent (e.g., the giddy audience that will laugh at anything).
Another aspect of Leventhal's approach may provide insight into the
observation that humor processing appears to be automatic and spontaneous.
Leventhal proposes that the linkage between expressive cues (facial expression)
and evaluative reactions is normally automatic, but is disrupted if the person
deliberately focuses attention on the ongoing response. Thus, it follows that
humor should be lost by self-consciousness and indeed experimental data show
that deliberate attention to one's laughter diminishes enjoyment of the
experience (Cupchik & Leventhal, 1974). Given these considerations, it is not
surprising that the comprehension of joke material must be a spontaneous,
almost automatic process for humor to result It also follows that explaining a
joke will never be as funny as processing it naturally. This point is emphasized
because Rothbart ( I 976) has argued that if incongruity resolution is involved in
Cognitive Processes in Humor Appreciation 51
humor, then subjects should find an incongruous picture funnier when the
incongruity is pointed out and explained than if only the incongruity is pointed
out. Finding that the explanation of the incongruity was not perceived as funny
by her subjects was interpreted by Rothbart as evidence that resolution is not
required and may even detract from humor appreciation. However, in light of
the above comments it should be apparent that by explaining the incongruity
Rothbart disturbed the usual automaticity and disrupted the spontaneous link
between facial expression and evaluative appraisal. For these reasons,
Rothbart's experiment is not a cogent test of the incongruity-resolution
model.
It is hoped that by now the reader can recognize the potential of Leventhal's
scheme for conceptualizing the processing of humorous stimuli and for
providing an explanation of phenomena where the incongruity-resolution model
is not sufficient. As knowledge about the links between expressive cues and
emotional experience and dual processing increases so might our understanding
of the complex set of factors that influence the humorous experience.
Question: If a 1DO-pound student senator and a 200-pound student senator jumped off
a tall building at exactly the same moment, who would come out ahead?
Answer: The rest of the campus. (Taken from Wicker et ai., 1980).
Theories about this kind of humor, such as superiority theory (LaFave, 1972)
or dispositional theory (Zillmann & Cantor, 1976), assume that humor
increases with negative sentiments and decreases with positive sentiments
toward the debased agent. More simply, appreciation should be maximal when
our friends humiliate our enemies and minimal when our enemies manage to get
the upper hand over our friends (Zillmann & Cantor, 1976). The reader is
referred to Chapter 5 by Zillmann for a review of research on this theory.
Suls ( 1977) has suggested that the incongruity-resolution model may be able
to account for disparagement humor if it is recognized that in such humor the
punch line (incongruity) typically involves a surprising misfortune. According
to Suls, a respondent who sympathizes or identifies with the disparaged party is
less likely to make sense of the unexpected misfortune or resolve the joke. That
is, for the sympathetic respondent the incongruity should not fit. On the other
hand, the more hostile or superior we feel toward the disparaged joke character,
52 Jerry Suls
the more the surprising misfortune will seem to fit or "make sense" based on
how we feel about the victim. Thus, for the example above, students with
negative attitudes toward their politically oriented classmates should enjoy the
above joke because there is more resolution.
Is there any evidence to support this approach? In 1977 Suls provided a
review suggesting that the results of past disparagement studies can be
interpreted within the new framework. Since then a study was designed and
conducted to examine whether affective reactions toward joke protagonists
impact on joke resolution.
Wicker, Barron, and Willis (1980) had college students rate written jokes for
funniness and on a series of scales such as surprise ("Did you feel surprised by
the ending?"), resolution ("When over your surprise, did the unexpected thing
in the joke make sense?") and anxiety ("Did the joke refer to a topic about
which you feel anxious?"). The jokes were varied on the degree of equity of
retaliation in an exchange of insults, the status of the two parties in the
exchange, and popularity of the victim of the joke squelch. A major finding of
the study was that jokes with disliked victims were rated as both funnier and
higher in resolution than were jokes with neutral or liked victims. In other
words, when the unfortunate outcome was perceived as "fitting," the joke was
perceived as funnier. Wicker et al. also found that when the misfortune was seen
as overretaliation, rated funniness and resolution decreased. Further, when
perceived resolution was controlled via analysis of covariance, the effect of the
degree of retaliation was nonsignificant. The suggestion of these results is that
disparagement enhances humor only if it is seen· as providing a reasonable
resolution and that feelings toward protagonists influence humor appreciation
via the resolution of incongruity.
and cartoons but do not evoke humor. As noted earlier, one suggestion
emphasizes that humor is occasioned by a set or cue that it be processed as "this
is play" or "not to be taken seriously" (cf. McGhee and Johnson, 1975).
However, one must be careful because this can be reduced to the circular
statement that funniness is what is funny (Leventhal & Safer, 1977). Perhaps
Rothbart's (1973, 1976) assertion that humorous stimuli must be interpreted as
safe or nonthreatening escapes the circularity. Of course, artistic stimuli are
also safe but are not considered humorous. (There are exceptions here too, for
example, the work of Claes Oldenburg). Perhaps the difference is, as Berlyne
(1972) observed, that humor presents extreme divergencies from what is
expected while aesthetic productions use milder deviations. But even this seems
less than satisfactory if one considers recent avant garde art and music that
offer extreme divergencies.
One solution is that humor must possess three critical features: (1) a "play"
cue, (2) extreme divergence, both considered above, and in addition (3) a
certain appropriate time scale for the perception and processing of joke
materials. Timing may be critical for two aspects of humor processing. First, in
oral presentation the joke premise must be told in such a way that the listener
has enough time to generate an (erroneous) expectation and therefore be
surprised by the punch line. Provided with too much time the listener may
anticipate the punch line correctly; provided with too little time no expectation
will be generated. The emphasis on timing frequently mentioned by comedians
suggests this is an important ingredient in producing humor.
There is also another phase in the process where time is of importance-in
the resolution of the incongruity. We submit that resolution must occur quickly
or the humorous experience is minimal. This may be connected to Berlyne's
(1972) contention that fluctuations in arousal must be rapid to be pleasurable.
Presumably, successful incongruity resolution serves to bring arousal provided
by the incongruity back to baseline. Consistent with this suggestion is
Goldstein's (1970) finding that joke appreciation increased as time to
understand the joke decreased. More data are obviously needed as well as new
inventive research techniques to ascertain whether the three elements-play
cue, extreme incongruity, and timing-can satisfactorily distinguish humorous
from nonhumorous stimuli that share some features in common.
SUMMARY
When I came to this country I hadn't a nickel in my pocket. ... Now I have a nickel in
my pocket.
REFERENCES
Beattie, J. Essays. Edinburgh: William Creech, 1776.
Berlyne, D. Humor and its kin. In J. H. Goldstein & P. E. McGhee (Eds.), Psychology
of humor. New York: Academic Press, 1972.
Campbell, D. T., & Fiske, D. W. Convergent and discriminant validation by the
multitrait-multimethod matrix. Psychological Bulletin, 1959,56,81-105.
Chomsky, N. Aspects of a theory of syntax. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1965.
Cupchik, G. c., & Leventhal, H. Consistency between expressive behavior and the
evaluation of humorous stimuli: The role of sex and self-observation. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 1974,30,429-442.
Deckers, L., Jenkins, S., & Gladfelter, E. Incongruity versus tension relief: Hypotheses
of humor. Motivation and Emotion, 1977,1,261-272.
Deckers, L., & Kizer, P. A note on discrepancy and humor. Journal of Psychology,
1975,86,309-312.
Fodor, J., Bever, T., & Garrett, M. Thepsychology of language. New York: McGraw-
Hill, 1974.
Freud, S. Jokes and its relationship to the unconscious. New York: Norton, 1960.
Gerber, W. S., & Routh, D. K. Humor response as related to violation of expectancies
and to stimulus intensity in a weight-judgment task. Perceptual and Motor Skills,
1975,41,673-674.
Goldstein, J. H. Humor appreciation and time to respond. Psychological Reports, 1970,
27, 445-446.
Hazlitt, W. Lectures on the English comic writers. London: Taylor & Hessey, 1819.
Jones, J. M. Cognitive factors in the appreciation of humor: A theoretical and
experimental analysis. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Yale University, 1970.
Kant, I. Kritik der Urteilkra/t. Berlin: Lagarde, 1790.
Koestler, A. The act of creation. London: Hutchinson, 1964.
La Fave, L. Humor judgments as a function of reference group and identification classes.
In J. H. Goldstein & P. E. McGhee (Eds.), Psychology of humor. New York:
Academic Press, 1972.
Leventhal, H. Toward a comprehensive theory of emotion. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.),
Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 12). New York: Academic Press,
1979.
Leventhal, H., & Cupchik, G. C. The informational and facilitative effects of an
audience upon expression and evaluation of humorous stimuli. Journal of Experi-
mental Social Psychology, 1975,11,363-380.
Leventhal, H., & Cupchik, G. C. A process model of humor judgment. Journal of
Communication, 1976,26, 190-204.
56 Jerry Suls
Both psychologists and linguists have discussed the nature of linguistic humor
as distinct from forms of humor based on such cultural categories as politics or
obscenity or on cognitive categories such as the visual stimulus of slapstick.
Linguists have been primarily concerned with manipulations of grammatical
categories in producing humorous effect (Green & Pepicello, 1978; Hockett,
1977; Pepicello, 1980; Scott, 1965, 1969). Psychologists have primarily dealt
with linguistic humor as an extension of the study of incongruity and its
resolution (e.g., Shultz & Robillard, 1980; Suls, 1972). However, both types of
study share a common focus, namely, that much of the linguistic humor that
appears in traditional riddles and jokes is based on ambiguity, that is, on a word
or phrase that has more than one possible meaning.
As an example, consider the humorous question-and-answer sequence
presented by Shultz (1974):
relevant stress and juncture phenomena that distinguish "away for" (;}wey+f;}r)
from "a wafer" (;}+weyf;}r). Such studies focus on the structural aspects of
linguistic humor and describe how phonological, morphological, and syntactic
categories can be manipulated to produce ambiguities that are then employed
humorously through a vehicle such as the question-answer format of riddles.
It seems obvious that these two types of analysis are complementary. That is,
the linguistic analysis serves to explicate the relations among the phonological
strings arising from the two possible interpretations of the joke, the initial or
incongruous interpretation and the final or resolved interpretation. However,
there has been little if any real integration of the two approaches. As we shall
see, understanding of linguistic humor is enhanced through such an integration
since both analyses view language as a structured system of rule-governed
behavior, the playful manipulation of which in certain definable ways is
generally recognized as witty or humorous. Given this common focus of works
dealing with linguistic humor, this chapter will suggest how such studies can be
profitably integrated. Toward this end we shall review the literature from both
fields, showing how the groundwork for integrated studies may be laid. A basic
tenet of our proposed integration will be an initial narrowing of focus for such
studies an issue to which we return below.
We begin with a linguistically based analysis of major genres of linguistic
humor. There has been a problem concerning definitions of major types of
linguistic humor, and we shall attempt to provide a reasonably coherent,
although somewhat limited, framework for classification that is amenable to the
interdisciplinary approach we advocate. In a related issue, we shall address the
problems attendant to the classification of the types of ambiguity involved in
linguistic humor. Once we have defined the generic and structural parameters of
linguistic humor, we shall review the relevant literature from psychology and
suggest how it might be refocused so as to help provide, in combination with the
linguistic analyses we shall review, a more comprehensive treatment of
linguistic humor.
humor. The definition of the riddle (and so the object of riddle study) has varied
greatly in the literature. Taylor (1948) described the "true riddle" as a
description "in terms intended to suggest something entirely different";
Abrahams and Dundes (1972) define the riddle as a question "framed with the
purpose of confusing or testing the wits of those who do not know the answer";
Shultz (1974) views the riddle as "a question followed by a surprising or
incongruous answer." While all of these characterizations are in fact partly
accurate, they do not distinguish riddles from other humorous forms such as
ethnic jokes or riddle parodies such as "Why do elephants paint their toenails
red? So they can hide in cherry trees."
What is in order, then, is an initial narrowing of the focus of linguistic humor
to a set of data that exhibits common characteristics. Toward that end, Green
and Pepicello (1979) define the riddle as a humorous form that is: (1) based on
the question-answer format; (2) potentially solvable from the information
included in the question, if the riddlee is able to determine the witty devices for
confusion employed in the riddle; (3) solvable by virtue of participation in a
cultural system (Le., shared language, world view, and tropes); and (4) placed in
a conventional locus within a particular tradition in a performance context. This
definition immediately eliminates most ethnic jokes or parodies since such
question-answer sequences are not solvable, but rather consist of a setup and a
punch line that must be learned by rote. The elephant joke presented above is an
example of a riddle parody. It has the surface form of a riddle, but the answer is
not derivable from the question.
This definition of the riddle genre provides a starting point for generic
classification of linguistic humor in general. For if we begin with an analysis of a
fairly well-defined set of data, we can then extend or revise the analysis as other
types of linguistic humor are treated. Let us consider next the types of linguistic
strategies that have been discussed in connection with riddles as we have
defined them.
The first attempts at the application of linguistic theory in riddle analysis are
found in Scott (1965, 1969). In his earlier work, Scott proposed a tagmemic
model for riddles. That is, he suggested that the riddle can be viewed as having a
slot-filler structure where various fillers (i.e., content) are inserted into the
appropriate slots (Le., the riddle's question-answer structure). However, Scott
was not concerned in this work with developing a linguistic approach to the
riddle via tagmemics; thus he encouraged others to pursue his suggestions
without developing them himself.
In Scott's later work, we find a more definite linguistic approach to the
characterization of riddles. In dealing with the notion of topic-comment analysis
introduced by Georges and Dundes (1963), Scott contended that it is useless as
an analytical tool for riddles. He considered the following example:
62 William J. Pepicello and Robert W. Weisberg
napkin
is blue
Figure 4-1. Underlying structure of the riddle" A blue napkin full of pears." (Sky full of
clouds).
Linguistics and Humor 63
surface level, is to be equated with topic and that any VP, at any level, is to be
equated with comment. This is simply a misinterpretation of topic-comment
analysis, for topic-comment is a method of analysis carried on at a syntactic
level only at the surface level (see Green & Pepicello, 1979).
More recently, Ben-Amos (1976) offered a brief description of linguistic
ambiguity in riddles. He made reference to two subcategories, "phonetic
ambiguity" and "semantic ambiguity." His example of the former is:
He claimed that the homophony of red and read is purely phonetic. This
characterization missed the important point that the homophony is caused by
the morphology of English in this case since the adjective red is homophonous
with the irregular past participle of the verb read. Thus, the phonological
identity results from two very different derivational histories, making it
necessary to distinguish the two words in question. So the issue here is
morphological not phonological. Similarly, what Ben-Amos referred to as
semantic ambiguity is demonstrated by him in the riddle:
He claimed that one word can refer to several objects. Again, he missed the
point that the real ambiguity here is phonological since eye, in all of its semantic
interpretations, is pronounced the same and is the same part of speech, a noun.
(This example differs from the "red/read all over" version discussed above.)
We might further point out that the term "semantic ambiguity" is vacuous since
all ambiguity is, by definition, semantic; the same is true of the term "phonetic
ambiguity" since ambiguity results from the surface phonological identity of two
different underlying structures (see Green & Pepicello, 1978).
Sutton-Smith (1976) proposed a classification of riddle structure based on
the semantic devices employed by the riddler to confuse the riddlee. These
devices involve for the most part a reclassification of semantic elements or an
unexpected inversion of these elements. This analysis falls short on several
counts. First, although he claimed that his studies based on children's riddles do
not for the most part fit the systems proposed by Georges and Dundes (1963),
nor by Abrahams (1968), his "reclassification" types of riddles are based on
the same kinds of semantic oppositions discussed in those works. Second,
Sutton-Smith misconstrued the term "homonym," apparently confusing it with
"homograph." Specifically, he claimed that the terms hot dog (a warm canine)
and hot dog (a weiner) are homonyms, when in fact the pronunciations of these
two phrases are distinguished in English by their stress patterns. In the latter
case, primary stress is on hot, in the former case, on dog. Thus, while the two
phrases are indeed spelled alike, they are not homonyms. Sutton-Smith's
misinterpretation of homonyms and of their potential for causing ambiguity lead
him to a statement of the semantic relations in the riddle form. His conclusions,
64 William J. Pepicello and Robert W. Weisberg
since they were based on the same sorts of observations made by Scott, echo
Scott's findings.
Perhaps the greatest array of humorous strategies playing on linguistic
structure is found in Hockett (1977), although his analysis ignored generic
distinctions. Hockett dealt with both the external and internal linguistic
structures of humorous genres, although his focus was primarily on the linguistic
strategies employed across genres. His external classification of "jokes" (his
cover term for a variety of humorous vehicles) was based on a bipartite structure
consisting of a buildup and a punch line, for example, "Tough luck," said the
egg in the monastery, "out of the frying pan into the friar." A compound joke
involves a single buildup with two or more punches. An example of a compound
joke would be to add additional egg puns or monastery puns to the previous
examples, such as "What a cruel yolk," or "Such a dangerous habit." Various
combinations of simple and compound jokes may be employed in what Hockett
terms a "complex" joke.
It is Hockett's analysis of the internal linguistic strategies of jokes that is most
instructive, however. Here he distinguished two types, prosaic and poetic jokes.
Prosaic jokes do not involve linguistic manipulation per se, but play rather upon
cultural situations, interactions, and institutions. Poetic jokes, on the other
hand, involve what Hockett called "accidents in the design of English," by
which he meant humor based on grammatical forms and their usage or
misusage. Poetic jokes are for Hockett of two types: puns and non-puns. Puns
may be perfect (involving homophony) or imperfect (involving near homo-
phony). Of the former type we find examples like a sign that reads "Cohen and
Son, Tailor and Attorney. Let Us Press Your Suit." The latter type is
exemplified by our earlier example where friar and fire are contrasted.
Imperfect puns may also involve metathesis, according to Hockett, for example,
"What's the difference between a fisherman and a dunce? One baits hooks, the
other hates books."
Hockett's poetic category also contains what he terms non-puns; for example,
the word-reversal in an example like:
At an army post they put some one-armed bandits into the Officers' Club. The slot
machines were in the Officers' Quarters, and soon the officers' quarters were in the
slot machines.
Finally in this category he included certain jokes that turn on stress and juncture
phenomena, as in the following examples:
What do you do with a stiff neck? (Compare: What do you do with a stiff? Neck?)
What's that rolling down the road ahead? (Compare: What's that rolling down the
road? A head?)
Hockett pointed out that a basic fact that holds true for all poetic jokes is that
they are nontranslatable, since they are dependent upon English-specific
grammatical categories. He also pointed out that many poetic jokes are based
Linguistics and Humor 65
on the types of grammatical structures that result from speech errors, e.g., the
metathesis in spoonerisms such as "Let me sew you to your sheet" for" Let me
show you to your seat."
I. Phonological
A. Lexical What turns but never The French missionaries
moves? Milk moved westward through
the North American
wilderness converting the
Indians, mainly to dust.
B. Minimal What's the difference Sign on the gate of a nudist
pairs between a baby and a coat? club in October: Clothed
One you were, one you for the season.
wear.
C. Metathesis What's the difference A knife that slices through
between a midget witch and four loaves of bread at once
a deer fleeing from hunters? could be advertised as a
One's a stunted hag, the four-loaf cleaver.
other a hunted stag.
D. Stress/ What bird is in lowest Two men were in a bar. One
Juncture spirits? A bluebird. said, glancing at a girl,
"Say, isn't that Hortense?"
The other replied, "She
looks perfectly relaxed to
me."
II. Morphological
A. Based on What's black and white and A woman asked me if I'd
irregular red/read all over? A like to have my palm read,
morphology newspaper. and when I said yes she
painted it.
B. Morphologi- What bow can no one tie? Do you have any sixes
cally A rainbow. you'd like shot or any
analyzed threes you'd like bagged?
C. Exploitation What kind of ears does a I must say you're looking
of bound train have? Engineers. couth, kempt and sheveled
morphemes today.
D. Pseudomor- What's the key to a good The key to the success of
phological dinner? A turkey. the Seagram family has
been whiskey.
III. Syntactic
A. Phrase How is a duck like an icicle? I'd like to look up your
Structure Both grow down. sister some time. Mind if I
borrow your speculum?
B. Transfor- What do you call a man who I can marry anyone I please,
mational marries another man? A Ijust haven't found anyone I
minister. please yet.
Linguistics and Humor 67
C. Idiom What goes most against a If you hit me I'll wax roth,
farmer's grain? His reaper. and then Roth will be all
slippery.
D. Syntax/Mor- Why can you not starve to Knock Knock. Who's there?
phological death in the desert? Because Cantaloupe. Cantaloupe
homophony of the sandwiches (sand who? Can't elope tonight-
which is) there. Dad's got the car.
IV. Other
A. Pre- How many balls of string
supposition does it take to reach the
moon? One, if it's long
enough.
B. Parody Why do elephants paint
their toenails red? So
they can hid in cherry
trees.
Here, two different underlying semantic elements have identical surface form,
turns.
Pepicello (1980) noted several additional linguistic strategies, at the
phonological level. For instance, we also find examples like:
What is the difference between a baby and a coat? One you were, one you wear.
What is the difference between a midget witch and deer fleeing from hunters? One is a
stunted hag. the other is a hunted stag.
What bird is in lowest spirits? A bluebird.
In the first example we find a contrast of the minimal pairs were and wear,
minimal pairs being pairs of words that differ by only one phoneme in
pronunciation. In the second case we find metathesis or sound reversal
employed as a strategy in stunted hag versus hunted stag. Finally, we see stress
and juncture exploited to contrast a sad bird (blue bird) with a specific avian
species (bluebird).
At the morphological level we find four basic ambiguity-producing strategies.
The first is seen in riddles like:
Here the fact that the verb read plus its past participle morpheme is
homophonous with the simple adjective red is exploited. Two closely related
morphological strategies are seen in:
In the first example, one morpheme (here -bow) from a larger morphemic
construction (i.e., a word) is used as ifit were an independent word with which it
is homophonous. In the second example, the independent word ear is
deliberately confused with the bound morpheme -eer, a bound morpheme being
one that cannot stand alone as a word. We find this type of morphological
strategy extended further in examples like:
A second strategy involves ambiguous sequences that arise when two different
underlying structures have an identical surface form as a result of their
respective syntactic derivations (i.e., "transformational ambiguity"), as in:
Here the idiom go against the grain meaning annoy is contrasted with a literal
reading of the same surface sequence.
At the syntactic level we also find riddles based on mixed strategies, like:
Linguistics and Humor 69
Why can you not starve to death in the desert? Because of the sandwiches (sand which
is) there.
Having now outlined a basic linguistic approach to riddles, we can examine the
psychological literature that attempts to deal with the development of, the
sensitivity to, and the appreciation of linguistic ambiguity and humor based on
such ambiguity. While commendable as regards methodology, in general this
literature is unfocused from the perspective of linguistic theory. This problem is
70 William J. Pepicello and Robert W. Weisberg
Lexical Ambiguity
He went lion hunting with a club. He went lion hunting with friends.
No one liked the plant. No one liked the factory.
This restaurant even serves crabs. This restaurant even serves lobster.
He put some gas in the tank. He put some gas in the car.
He often goes to the bank. He often goes to the river.
He did not have enough dough. He did not have enough money.
Phonological Ambiguity
The doctor is out of patience (patients). The doctor has lost his temper.
He stepped over the lion (line). He stepped over the stick.
He bought it because of the sail (sale). He bought it because it was half price.
The baby bear has a big pa (paw). The baby bear has a big daddy.
I have enough for eighty (eight tea) cups. I have enough for eight cups.
He saw three pears (pairs). He saw the fruit.
Sur/ace-Structure Ambiguity
He laughed at the school. He laughed in the classroom.
He sent her kids story books. He sent the children some story books.
He is looking up the street. He is looking down the street.
She helped the boy with the hat. She helped the boy put on his hat.
The fat sailor's wife likes to cook. The sailor's fat wife likes to cook.
He saw a man eating fish. He saw a ferocious fish.
Deep-Structure Ambiguity
The shooting of the Indians was bad. It was bad to shoot the Indians.
The duck is ready to eat. The duck is ready to eat the food.
It is really quite wonderful to see. It is really a wonderful sight.
He did not like disturbing children. He did not like disturbing the children.
The mayor asked the police to stop drinking. The mayor asked the police
to arrest, drunks.
They are visiting sailors. They are visiting Europe.
Linguistics and Humor 71
I have enough for eighty (eight tea) cups. (stress and juncture)
Waiter, what's this?
It's bean soup, Ma'am.
I'm not interested in what it's been, what is it now? (Minimal pairs)
The doctor is out of patience (patients). (morphological)
He saw three pairs (pears). (lexical)
duck is ready to eat are both transformation ally ambiguous, while they would
be treated as separate types in the works being discussed. Failure to distinguish
types of ambiguity, as we shall discuss, may have serious consequences for the
usefulness of these studies.
Similar confusions of levels are found in other works, for example, Fowles
and Glanz (1977), and Hirsch-Pasek, Gleitman, and Gleitman (1978). In the
former work we find that surface ambiguity includes morphological, stress and
juncture, and transformational ambiguities, as seen in the following examples:
Such riddles exploit presuppositions underlying the question in the riddle and
are not dependent upon purely grammatical strategies for their wit.
Hirsch-Pasek et al. (1978) offer the largest proliferation of categories. Here
lexical ambiguity includes only minimal pairs (e.g., quackervs. cracker) that, it
should be noted, are not ambiguous. Further, the surface-structure versus deep-
structure ambiguity distinction postulated by Hirsch-Pasek et al. suffers from
the same type of confusion discussed above with these categories, where man
eating fish is considered to be a surface ambiguity, while Make me a milkshake
is deep structure; in fact, both are transformationally ambiguous. In the former
case, the two underlying constructions contain relative clauses that are then
reduced, namely, fish that eats man and man who was eating fish. In the latter
instance one underlying structure looks much like the surface example, while
the other is roughly Make a milks hake for me that then undergoes a
transformation called Dative Movement that deletes for and moves me into
direct object position.
While Hirsch-Pasek et al. recognized morphemic exploitation in riddles, for
example, engineers versus engine ears, they did not make the distinctions
between types, as we outlined earlier, that we consider necessary and often
included examples that are probably best categorized differently. For example,
Hirsch-Pasek et al. categorized the riddle that exploits sandwiches versus sand
which is as morphological, when it is more appropriately classified as syntactic,
as we have discussed. Hirsch-Pasek et al. categorized the following as
morphological also:
Linguistics and Humor 73
Do you think that if I wash, my face will be clean? Let's soap for the best.
Since this example turns on stress and juncture, it is probably best classed as a
phonological riddle.
A final problem arises in several works (e.g., Fowles & Glanz, 1977; Shultz,
1974) concerning the inclusion of jokes and/or riddles that are not linguistically
based in the data to be analyzed. We touched upon this area briefly in our
discussion of Hirsch-Pasek et al. above. As pointed out by Yalisove (1978), one
needs to distinguish between nongrammatical categories, such as those
exemplified in the following examples:
How many balls of string does it take to reach the moon? One, if it's big enough.
Where can you always find money? In the dictionary.
How do you get six elephants in a VW? three in front, three in back.
In the first example we are dealing with presuppositions about the world and
upsetting normal presuppositions about balls of string for witting effect. In the
second example, which Yalisove calls a "name mention" strategy, much the
same is true. The third example is simply a riddle "parody," as are ethnic jokes,
that is a question-answer sequence designed to allow the questioner to deliver a
punch line that is impossible for the person questioned to guess.
Let us now examine the implications that the lack of focus from the linguistic
perspective has for the psycholinguistic studies we have been discussing and
how a refocusing along the lines suggested above might affect such works.
Mr. Fields, do you believe in clubs for children? Only when kindness fails.
74 William J. Pepicello and Robert W. Weisberg
According to Shultz, this remark is funny because at first Fields's answer makes
no sense to us, which produces incongruity. However, when we realize that
Field's remark makes sense if one interprets "clubs for children" as meaning
"beating children with clubs," we can resolve the incongruity, which results in
our finding the remark humorous instead of merely perplexing. Thus we see that
the basis for the perception of humor in this remark depends on the perplexed
person's ability to detect the ambiguity of the phrase "clubs for children."
Psychological researchers in humor have found linguistic material to be an
important area of study because language seems to provide an ideal arena for
the study of people's ability to detect and resolve incongruities. Language is
seen as a structured system involving rule-governed behavior of several different
sorts. These linguistic rules can be assumed to make explicit the expectancies of
the fluent speaker and so can serve as the criterion for the structural analysis of
a piece of verbal humor (Shultz & Robillard, 1980).
As discussed above, linguistic theory has been taken as providing a formal
analysis of ambiguity, which theoretically can make possible the specification of
the exact sort of incongruity involved in a given piece of verbal humor. Based on
this view, the almost exclusive thrust of psycholinguistic research in humor has
involved assessment of people's sensitivity to various sorts of linguistic
ambiguity since this sensitivity is assumed to be necessary, although not
sufficient, for the perception of verbal humor. A related research aim has been
to measure people's appreciation of verbal humor that allegedly hinges on the
detection and resolution of incongruities based on ambiguities of various
sorts.
An early study in this area was that of Shultz and Pilon (1973). Children in
grades 1, 4, 7, and 10 were presented with ambiguous sentences and were asked
to paraphrase the sentences and to match the sentences with pictures
representing the two possible meanings of each sentence. These methods were
used to determine if the child was sensitive to the two meanings of the
ambiguous sentences.
As mentioned earlier, questions can be raised about the classification system
used by Shultz and his colleagues, especially concerning the sentences
classified as phonologically ambiguous (see Table 4-2). Several of these
sentences do not involve ambiguity at all (e.g., lion vs. line; eighty vs. eight tea;
and perhaps pa vs. paw). Furthermore, the other sentences in this category are
not distinguishable from those called lexically ambiguous, except that the latter
sentences are also spelled identically in both versions, while the phonological
ambiguities involve different spellings. However, since the sentences were
presented auditorally, this distinction seems irrelevant. Therefore, Shultz and
Pilon's (1973) results for these two categories of ambiguities will be grouped
together. We shall refer to these as phonological ambiguities. Also, as
mentioned earlier, the surface structure-deep-structure distinction made in
these studies turns out to involve confabulation of several different sorts of
ambiguities. Therefore, these results will be grouped together and discussed as
syntactic ambiguities.
On both the paraphrase and picture-matching measures, the phonological
ambiguities were more easily detected than the syntactic ambiguities. Further-
more, the first graders were not sensitive to any type of ambiguity, while the
tenth graders did well in detecting phonological ambiguity but were not nearly
perfect in detecting syntactic ambiguity.
Brodzinsky (1977) used Shultz and Pilon's (1973) categorization system to
classify jokes that were presented to fourth-grade children. Comprehension and
appreciation scores were obtained from the children. The results supported
those of Shultz and Pilon (1973). Comprehension and appreciation scores were
76 William J. Pepicello and Robert W. Weisberg
higher for the phonologically based jokes than for the syntactic ambiguities.
Additional support for the finding that phonologically based humor is
appreciated at an earlier age than is syntactically based humor comes from
studies by Shultz (1974) and Shultz and Horibe (1974).
Two studies have raised questions concerning the linguistically based
analysis of verbal humor proposed by Shultz and his colleagues. Fowles and
Glanz (1977) tested a very small sample of children in grades 1-3 and used
riddles involving Shultz's categories of phonological, phrasal, and transforma-
tional ambiguities. In addition, they also examined what they called "meta-
linguistic" riddles such as:
Comprehension and recall scores did not support the developmental trends
found by Shultz and his colleagues. However, the fact that Fowles and Glanz's
classification of riddles was inconsistent, as mentioned earlier, the small sample
size and restricted age range make the Fowles and Glanz study very difficult to
interpret. Be that as it may, since in their opinion the linguistic variables were
not predictive of riddle difficulty, Fowles and Glanz examined a number of
other variables in a post hoc analysis. Again, although the small subject sample
makes all conclusions extremely speculative, Fowles and Glanz found that on
the whole children were better able to retell riddles that were familiar, short,
simple in syntax, and in which the setup did not favor a single intrepretation of
the ambiguous element. Comprehension was easier for riddles that contained
familiar vocabulary and that were concrete in both meanings of the ambiguous
elements. In sum, although the Fowles and Glanz study has some linguistic and
methodological problems, these investigators have pointed out some potentially
relevant variables which should be taken into account in further studies of the
development of appreciation and comprehension of linguistic humor.
As part of a large-scale study of the relationship between linguistic skills and
metalinguistic judgments, Hirsch-Pasek et al. (1978) investigated children's
responses to riddles and jokes. The children, good and poor readers in grades
1-6, were asked to rate the humor in riddles and jokes and to explain why each
was funny. Two aspects of this study are worthy of note. First, as mentioned
earlier, Hirsch-Pasek et al. raise questions about the adequacy of Shultz's
categorization system, although their own system is not without problems.
Second, the Hirsch-Pasek et al. study is unique in this area because it involves a
theoretical rationale for investigating various sorts of riddles. Specifically,
Hirsch-Pasek et al. argue that children should be most sensitive to those riddles
that hinge on "deeper" or more meaningful aspects of language, rather than
surface properties. The basis for this prediction comes from studies that
demonstrate that children can segment a sentence into words much earlier than
they can segment words into syllables. Presumably, segmentation of a sentence
into words depends on meaning, while syllable segmentation of words does
not.
Linguistics and Humor 77
Based on this viewpoint, one would predict that riddles and jokes hinging on
transformational ambiguities should be easier to understand than those based on
phrase-structure ambiguities. Furthermore, Hirsch-Pasek et al. would also seem
to predict that riddles and jokes based on minimal pairs (e.g., If you put three
ducks in a box, what do you have? A box of quackers.) should be hardest to deal
with because the only relation between the punch line and the expected word
(Le., crackers and quackers) is arbitrary and has nothing to do with underlying
meaning. The same should be true of jokes and riddles involving morphological
strategies (e.g., How does a train hear? Through its engine ears.) since in this
case also the surface material must be dealt with directly, without any reliance
on underlying meaning.
Hirsch-Pasek et al. tested these various predictions through detailed analysis
of the children's performance on the various categories of riddles. However,
given our earlier questions about the categorization system used by Hirsch-
Pasek et aI., these comparisons are equivocal. For example, one important
comparison was between phrase structure and transformational ambiguities, but
we saw earlier that both these categories may contain riddles based on
transformational ambiguities, which nullifies any conclusions. Several of the
other categories used by Hirsch- Pasek et al. suffer from similar problems.
Hirsch-Pasek et al. also concluded that the poor readers were uniformly
worse than the good readers in dealing with all categories of material. This
finding may raise a problem, as Hirsch-Pasek et al. note, because from their
viewpoint reading skills should be important only on those categories involving
manipUlation of surface form, but the deficiency of poor readers was found
across all types of materials. However, given the problems with classification of
materials, a potentially interesting set of analyses must, in our opinion, await
more precise classification of stimulus materials.
In conclusion, analysis of several of the most important studies in this area
indicates that little more than the most tentative conclusions can be drawn, due
to problems of classification of stimulus materials.
If, as many have argued, humor depends on resolvable incongruity, then ifeither
the incongruity were removed from a joke or the incongruity were not
resolvable, then that joke should not be funny. Two studies (Shultz, 1974;
Shultz & Horibe, 1974) presented modified riddles and jokes in an attempt to
examine these two predictions from incongruity/resolution theory. As an
example of the modifications, consider the following riddle (Shultz, 1974);
Why did the cookie cry? Because its mother was a wafer so long.
The resolution-removed version of the riddle has as its answer: Because its
mother was a wafer. This revision does not contain all the material needed for
78 William J. Pepicello and Robert W. Weisberg
the ambiguous string and therefore does not allow the riddlee to reinterpret the
string to resolve the incongruity. This should result in mere confusion rather
than humor. The incongruity-removed version of this riddle had as its answer:
Because it was left in the oven too long. This answer follows plausibly from the
question, without incongruity and resolution (assuming that cookies can feel
discomfort and cry), and therefore it too should not be funny.
The subjects in the two studies were children in grades 1, 3, 5, and 7 (ages 6,
8, 10, and 12). The children provided funniness ratings and explanations for the
jokes and riddles, and the experimenter independently rated the child's mirth
response. The results were similar across the two studies. Overall, the original
form of the joke or riddle was judged to be funnier than the two altered forms.
Also, the children's explanations of the jokes and riddles indicated that the
modifications had had the desired effects. For example, when the incongruity
was removed, the children made no mention of it, and little mention was made
of the hidden meaning of the riddle or joke. This is to be expected since
removing the incongruity involves eliminating the ambiguity.
There was also an interaction with age, with the youngest children in the
Shultz and Horibe (1974) joke study finding the original and resolution-
removed forms equally funny, while the older children found the original form
funnier than both the modified forms. Shultz and Horibe interpret this finding to
indicate that there is an initial stage of humor appreciation based on unre-
solvable incongruity, or nonsense, and a second stage based on resolvable
incongruity. However, the riddle study (Shultz, 1974) found that the youngest
children rated all forms equally funny, which raises problems for the
unresolvable incongruity view since the incongruity-removed riddles had no
unresolvable incongruity.
In sum, these two studies are consistent in demonstrating that altering jokes
and riddles in certain ways significantly reduces their humor, in a manner
seemingly consistent with incongruity-resolution theory. Further, given the sorts
of analyses carried out in these studies, problems of stimulus classification do
not arise since all comparisons are within riddle or within joke.
Do you believe in clubs for young people? Only when kindness fails.
Do you believe in social groups for young people? Only when kindness fails.
According to the view that the humorist must first notice an exploitable
ambiguity, it should be easier to produce ajoke from the resolution information
since the ambiguity is present there. This situation thus mirrors what is assumed
to occur in real life. The incongruity information, on the other hand, is only
perplexing, with no obvious basis for humor, and should not be particular
effective as a stimulus. The results of Shultz and Scott (1976) supported this
interpretation, with more good jokes produced by their subjects in response to
resolution information.
In summary, although very few studies of verbal humor production have been
carried out, the results that are available indicate that creation of humorous
material may depend in many cases on the humorist's exploiting a potentially
humorous segment in the speech stream. These segments can involve ambi-
guities, as examined by Shultz and Scott (1976), or speech errors (e.g.,
metathesis, as discussed earlier in this chapter). There are additional sources of
humor in the speech stream, such as a word that differs from another word by
only one phoneme (e.g., crackers vs. quackers), and perhaps further studies of
the sort carried out by McDowell (1979) would shed some light on how these
potentially humorous strings are exploited in real time by humorists.
Redefinition
The first point to emerge from this review is that important theoretical
conclusions in this area are at present premature, due to problems concerning
definitions of relevant stimulus variables. We have seen that investigators differ
so greatly in their linguistic categorizations of jokes and riddles that no detailed
theoretical predictions can be tested. Thus, our first suggestion is that
researchers go back to the beginning and reanalyze stimulus materials in order
to reach a consensus as to how differences among riddles and jokes are to be
analyzed. We have presented the framework in Table 1 as a possible basis for
such a reanalysis, although we realize that it does not provide all the
answers.
Incongruity-Resolution Theory
As mentioned earlier, one area that has received almost no attention from
researchers is the production of linguistic humor. Difficulties in controlling
stimulus materials obviously have contributed to the dearth of production
studies, but Shultz and Scott (1976) carried out a well-designed study of
production of linguistic humor. In addition, McDowell's (1979) field study of
children's riddling sessions, while not allowing direct experimental control of
stimulus conditions, did produce important data concerning factors involved in
children's "real-time" production of riddles. It might be possible to elaborate on
these two designs in order to get further insight into production of linguistic
humor.
In conclusion, the study of linguistic humor is an area that has attracted the
attention of researchers from many disciplines. However, due to a lack of
communication among these various disciplines, a deep understanding of the
factors involved in the production of appreciation of linguistic humor has been
slow in emerging. The present chapter has emphasized critical issues that we
believe will have to be addressed before real progress will be made.
82 William J. Pepiceilo and Robert W. Weisberg
REFERENCE NOTE
1. Weisberg, R. W., & Pepiceilo, W. J. Outline of a model of riddle production.
Unpublished manuscript, Temple University, 1982.
REFERENCES
Abrahams, R. D. Introductory remarks to a rhetorical theory of folklore. Journal of
American Folklore, 1968,81, 143-158.
Abrahams, R. D., & Dundes, A. Riddles. In R. Dorson (Ed.), Folklore andfolklife: An
introduction. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1972.
Ben-Amos, D. Solutions to riddles. Journal ofAmerican Folklore, 1976,89,249-254.
Berlyne, D. E. Humor and its kin. In J. H. Goldstein and P. E. McGhee (Eds.), The
psychology of humor. New York: Academic Press, 1972.
Brodzinsky, D. M. Children's comprehension and appreciation of verbal jokes in relation
to conceptual tempo. Child Development, 1977, 48, 960-967.
Fowles, B., & Glanz, M. E. Competence and talent in verbal riddle comprehension.
Journal of Child Language, 1977,4,433-452.
Georges, R. A., & Dundes, A. Toward a structural definition of the riddle. Journal of
American Folklore, 1963, 76, 111-118.
Green, T. A., & Pepicello, W. J. Wit in riddling: A linguistic perspective. Genre, 1978,
11,1-13.
Green, T. A., & Pepicello, W. J. The folk-riddle: A redefinition of terms. Western
Folklore, 1979,38,3-20.
Hamnett, I. Ambiguity, classification and change: The function of riddles. Man, 1967,
2,379-393.
Haring, L. On knowing the answer. Journal of American Folklore, 1974, 87,
197-207.
Harries, L. The riddle in Africa. Journal of American Folklore, 1971,84, 377-393.
Hirsch-Pasek, K., G1eitman, L. R, & G1eitman, H. What did the brain say to the mind?
A study of the detection and report of ambiguity by young children. In A. Sinclair,
R. J. Jarvella, & W. J. M. Levelt (Eds.), The child's conception of language. Berlin:
Springer-Verlag, 1978.
Hockett, C. The View from Language. Athens, Ga.: University of Georgia Press, 1977.
Maranda, E. K. A tree grows: Transformation of a riddle metaphor. In P. Maranda &
E. K. Maranda, (Eds.), Structural Models in Folklore and Transformational
Essays. The Hague: Mouton, 1971.
McDowell, J. H. Children's riddling. Bloomington, Ind.: Indiana University Press,
1979.
Miller, G. A. Language and speech. San Francisco: Freeman, 1981.
Pepicello, W. J. Linguistic strategies in riddling. Western Folklore, 1980,39, 1-16.
Pepiceilo, W. J., & Green, T. A. New approach to riddle analysis. Columbus, Oh.:
Ohio State University Press, in press.
Scott, C. Persian and Arabic riddles: A language-centered approach to genre
definition. Bloomington, Ind.: Indiana University and Mouton, 1965.
Linguistics and Humor 83
Scott, C. On defining the riddle: The problem of a structural unit. Genre, 1969,2,
129-142.
Shultz, T. R Development of the appreciation of riddles. Child Development, 1974,45,
100-105.
Shultz, T. R A cognitive-developmental analysis of humor. In A. J. Chapman & H. C.
Foot (Eds.), Humor and laughter: Theory, research, and applications. London:
Wiley, 1976.
Shultz, T. R, & Horibe, F. Development of the appreciation of verbal jokes.
Developmental Psychology, 1974,10, 13-20.
Shultz, T. R, & Pilon, R Development of the ability to detect linguistic ambiguity.
Child Development, 1973,44,728-733.
Shultz, T. R, & Robillard, J. The development of linguistic humor in children:
Incongruity through rule violation. In P. McGhee & A. Chapman (Eds.), Children's
humour. Chichester, England: Wiley, 1980.
Shultz, T. R, & Scott. M. B. The creation of verbal humor. Canadian Journal of
Psychology, 1974,28,421-425.
Suls, J. M. A twcrstage model for the appreciation of jokes and cartoons: An
information-processing analysis. In J. H. Goldstein & P. E. McGhee (Eds.) The
psychology of humor. New York: Academic Press, 1972.
Sutton-Smith, B. A developmental structural account of riddles. In B. Kirshenblatt-
Gimblett (Ed.), Speech play: Research and resource for the study of linguistic
creativity. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1976.
Taylor, A. English riddles from oral tradition. Los Angeles: University of California
Press, 1948.
Yalisove, D. The effect of riddle structure on children's comprehension of riddles.
Developmental Psychology, 1978, 14,173-180.
Chapter 5
Disparagement Humor
DOLF ZILLMANN
Much has been said and written about humor that disparages, belittles, debases,
demeans, humiliates, or otherwise victimizes. A myriad of observations and
opinions on the subject eventually found expression in theoretical proposals,
and these proposals have been reviewed in considerable detail (e.g., Berlyne,
1969; Keith-Spiegel, 1972). The research efforts spawned by the proposals,
together with theoretical advances and refinements suggested or demanded by
the findings, also have been detailed and summarized (e.g., La Fave, 1972;
Zillmann & Cantor, 1976). Obviously, there is little merit in restating the
various theoretical views and in rehashing research findings that have been
reported repeatedly already. This chapter, consequently, traces the evolution of
disparagement theory in its essentials only and then focuses on new develop-
ments, both theoretical and empirical, that have occurred since the publication
of the reviews in the early and mid-seventies. More specifically, extensions of
theoretical approaches to disparagement humor are reported and the generality
and specificity of these approaches is assessed. Efforts at integrating disparage-
ment theory with other approaches to humor are reported. New findings
concerning the ontogeny of mirthful reactions to disparagement are discussed.
Finally, the discontent with the "incompleteness" of disparagement-centered
theories of humor is detailed, and recent efforts at removing the apparent
incompleteness of older models in the construction of more integrative theories
are described. Much attention is given to the issue of converting the potential
enjoyment of disparagement into amusement.
86 Dolf Zillmann
1898; Wallis, 1922). All these views, which are typically classified as
superiority theories, build on the idea that laughter is a spontaneous response of
triumph that derives mainly from a favorable comparison of the self to others.
Those others, needless to say, tend to be inept, ugly, dumb, clumsy, weak, poor,
and so forth, and the sudden revelation of these traits in characteristic behaviors
is what is seen as prompting the self-enhancing comparisons that fuel laughter.
Hazlitt (1826/1926) captured the thrust of the argument in his cynical
comment, "We grow tired of every thing but turning others into ridicule, and
congratulating ourselves on their defects" (p. 239). And Baudelaire (1855/
1961) amplified the moral concern with self-glorifying humor that Plato and
Hobbes, among many others, had voiced by characterizing laughter as the most
reliable indication of the satanic spirit in man.
The dispositional approach of Wolff et al. was expanded and refined in the work
of La Fave and his collaborators (e.g., La Fave, 1961, 1972; La Fave, Haddad,
& Maesen, 1976).
La Fave originally offered the formula that something "is humorous to the
extent that it enhances an object of affection and/or disparages an object of
repulsion," and that it "is unhumorous to the extent that it does the opposite"
(1972, p. 198). The dispositional nomenclature was soon abandoned, however,
in favor of specifications in terms of groups and classes. "Object of affection"
was replaced by "positive reference group" and "positive identification class,"
and "object of repulsion" became "negative reference group" and "negative
identification class." But all these substitutions did not alter the proposition as
such: objects toward which positive attitudes were held were placed into the
positive classes, objects toward which attitudes were negative were placed into
Disparagement Humor 89
the negative classes, and-to use La Fave's analogy-seeing the good guys
stick it to the bad guys was deemed to produce merriment, the reverse not
Whether expressed in attitudinal terms or conceptualized in reference groups
or identification classes, the model is based on an assumed dichotomy of
sentiment, and it projects both negative and positive sentiments to control and
influence mirthful reactions to witnessing disparagement. Repulsion, resent-
ment, hate, or simply negativeness are recognized as dispositional forces that
motivate mirth. Obvious as such recognition may seem, it was not well
integrated in earlier formulas for the enjoyment of disparagement humor. Wolff
et aI., for instance, did not stipulate that "unaffiliated" objects be resented-
despite the fact that Murray (1934) had linked the enjoyment of derisive humor
to the respondents' possession of egotistic, hostile, and world-derogatory
sentiments. In their formal model, "unaffiliated" amounted to lack of affiliation
or absence of a positive bond, not negative disposition. La Fave's formula, in
contrast, is specific on negativeness. (The formula is, of course, equally specific
on positiveness. This makes for the confusing projection that witnessing the
enhancement of an object in a positive identification class is a sufficient
condition for amusement. Such a proposal departs from common conceptuali-
zations, as witnessing the benefaction of a friendly party usually is considered
enjoyable but not funny. The emerging conceptual difficulties have been
discussed elsewhere (Zillmann & Cantor, 1976), and suggestions concerning
reactions to the enhancement of some object that is not linked to the debasement
of another receive further attention later in this chapter.)
Although the conceptualization of humorous situations as happenings
between "identification classes" is abstract enough to encompass any entity in
any specifiable situation, the parallel reasoning in terms of reference groups
proved to be confining. The research conducted by La Fave and his
collaborators essentially extended that of Wolff et al. in exploring the
enjoyment of the disparagement of persons from one well-defined social group
at the hands of persons from another well-defined group by members of the
disparaging group as well as by members of the disparaged group. The paradigm
is, of course, that of ethnic humor (e.g., La Fave, 1977). In this realm of
disparagement humor, La Fave and his collaborators have instituted a
methodological improvement: group affiliations that had been taken at
face value were now empirically ascertained. La Fave, McCarthy, and Haddad
(1973), for example, suspected that Americans are not necessarily pro-
American and Canadians not necessarily pro-Canadian, and they determined
the pertinent attitudes in order to identify genuine pro-Americans and genuine
pro-Canadians. The enjoyment that can be derived from seeing, say, a
Canadian disparage an American should, according to their model, be greater
for pro-Canadians than for Canadians; and it certainly should be greater for pro-
Canadians than for pro-Americans. Similarly, witnessing an American dis-
parage a Canadian should be more enjoyed by pro-Americans than by
Americans, Canadians, and pro-Canadians. The findings largely confirmed
these expectations. La Fave, Billinghurst, and Haddad (cited in La Fave,
Haddad, & Maesen, 1976) employed attitudinal assessments analogously to
90 Dolf Zillmann
This disposition theory of humor and mirth (Zillmann & Cantor, 1972, 1976)
transcends reference groups and identification classes. Prediction of the
enjoyment of witnessing disparagement is based on affective dispositions
toward the parties involved, that is, toward the disparaging and the disparaged
entities. These dispositions may be positive (e.g., affection, admiration, love) or
negative (e.g., resentment, condemnation, hate), and they are expected to vary
in intensity. Both the hedonic quality and the intensity of affect are empirically
ascertained, and the likelihood and magnitude of mirth resulting from witnessed
disparagement is projected from this ascertainment. Obviously, the affective
dispositions under consideration may correspond with group affiliations (e.g., a
Jew may feel sympathy toward other Jews and antipathy toward KKK
members), and if so, disposition theory can accomodate reference group theory.
But such correspondence need not exist (e.g., a professor might hold a negative
Disparagement Humor 91
4. The more intense the positive disposition toward the disparaging agent or
entity, the greater the magnitude of mirth.
Mirth, then, is said to vary proportionally with the negativeness of the
affective disposition toward the disparaged party and with the positiveness of
the affective disposition toward the disparaging party, and jointly so. It should
be noticed that all propositions concern disparagement specifically. The
benefaction or enhancement of one party by another is not a condition for
enjoyment in this model of disparagement humor. The mirth-producing event-
namely, disparagement-is thoroughly negative. There is nothing positive about
the critical behavioral exchange. However, the fact that one party succeeds in
debasing another may, of course, be deemed self-enhancing.
Evidence supportive of the disposition theory of humor comes from research
in which the disparagers and/or disparagees were manipulated or selected to
draw reactions of sympathy or antipathy (e. g., Cantor & Zillmann, 1973;
Chapman, Smith, & Foot, 1977; Zillmann & Cantor, 1972). In this context, the
disparagement of an antipathetic agent by a sympathetic one was expected to
produce a maximum of mirth; the reverse a minimum or none at all. In the
investigation conducted by Zillmann and Cantor, for instance, disparagement
occurred between professors and students-among other superior-subordinate
groupings. To the extent that a touch of mutual resentment characterizes such a
superior-subordinate relationship, it may be expected that disparagement is
appreciated and deemed funny when it victimizes those who are resented,
especially when it is delivered by those with whom the respondent shares the
negative disposition. Those who suffered subordination should thus particularly
enjoy seeing superiors disparaged; and those who had cause for discontent with
subordinates should particularly enjoy seeing subordinates disparaged. Figure
5.1 illustrates the two discussed social avenues of disparagement. These
cartoons were actually used in the experiment, among many other stimuli. Either
the upper or the lower version was presented to persons of the subordinate or
superior variety, and the magnitude of humor reactions was found to follow the
predicted pattern. In the subsequent study by Cantor and Zillmann, sympathy
and antipathy toward the disparaged agents were directly measured. Disparage-
ment was brought about by accident, unidentified sources, children, and
animals. All disparagers were rather neutral dispositionally. As predicted, mirth
reactions were the more intense, the more pronounced the negative affective
disposition toward the disparaged object. Figure 5.2 gives an example of the
manipulation. In this instance, the policeman evoked antipathy while the
zookeeper proved sympathetic. The humiliation that is about to happen in the
cartoon produced more enjoyment when the victim was resented than when he
was liked. The investigation by Chapman et al. attests further to the usefulness
of dispositional assessments in predicting mirth reactions; so do investigations of
political disparagement humor by Priest (1966) and by Zillmann, Bryant, &
Cantor, (1974).
An investigation by Zillmann and Bryant (1974) linked the dispositional
reasoning with moral considerations. Apparently, respondents to disparagement
Disparagement Humor 93
(b)
Figure Sol. Example of upward (a) and downward (b) directed disparagement humor.
Persons experienced as superiors enjoyed the cartoon more when disparagement was
downward directed than when it was upward directed. Persons experienced as
subordinates exhibited the reverse preference. (From "Directionality of Transitory
Dominance as a Communication Variable Affecting Humor Appreciation" by
D. Zillmann and J. R. Cantor, Journal ofPersonality and Social Psychology, 1972,24,
191-198. Copyright 1972 by the American Psychological Association. Reprinted by
permission of the publisher.)
94 Dolf Zillmann
Figure 5-2. Humorous disparagement of a disliked (a) versus a liked (b) character.
Persons with negative dispositions toward policemen and positive ones toward zoo
keepers enjoyed version a more than version b. (From "Resentment toward Victimized
Protagonists and Severity of Misfortunes They SutTer as Factors in Humor Appre-
ciation" by J. R. Cantor and D. Zillmann, Journal of Experimental Research in
Personality, 1973, 6, 321-329. Copyright 1973. Reprinted by permission of the
publisher.)
Disparagement Humor 95
The disposition theory of humor has been expanded in order to explain the
enjoyment that audiences and spectators derive from suspenseful drama
(Zillmann, 1980) and from sports events (Zillmann, Bryant, & Sapolsky,
1979). These extensions have received support from numerous experimental
investigations (e.g., Bryant, Brown, Comisky, & Zillmann, 1982; Zillmann &
Cantor, 1977; Zillmann, Hay, & Bryant, 1975). The particular propositions
supported are as follows:
96 Dolf Zillmann
humor. It shows that the theory predicts joy, exultation, euphoria, and their
hedonic inverses-at least, for domains of human conduct in which these
emotional reactions may be freely expressed. And it shows that the unamended
theory is incomplete as a theory of humor.
Such insight is not exactly new. For instance, Hobbes, although insisting that
humor derives mainly from witnessing the infirmities and the disparagement of
others, also noted that "whatsoever it be that moveth laughter, it must be new
and unexpected," and it must amount to "elegant discovering" (1650/1966,
p. 46). The most succinct expression of this view that disparagement alone
(even if dispositionally appropriate) is not a sufficient condition for humor,
comes from Freud (1905/1958), however.
Freud conceived of tendentious humor (i.e., mainly hostile and obscene
humor) as a stimulus condition composed of tendentious and nontendentious
elements. Tendentious elements are those that pertain to vital needs whose
satisfaction is blocked. Nontendentious elements are rather innocuous stimuli
associated with amusement, gaiety, and laughter. These latter elements are
usually subsumed under the heading "joke-work" (Witzarbeit), which refers to
formal techniques of humor such as the "play on words." Berlyne (1969, 1972)
arrived at a distinction similar to that between tendentious and nontendentious
elements, speaking of need- and drive-related ecological factors in contrast to
innocuous collative variables. His collative variables (novelty, surprise,
incongruity, strangeness, complexity, ambiguity, puzzlement, and apparent
contradiction) essentially constitute what Freud called joke-work. But while
Berlyne concerned himself with the arousal properties of the various elements of
humor and pondered the impact of summed arousal on mirth, Freud's reasoning
focused on the necessity of joke-work in the liberation of mirth and, hence, on
the conversion of covert enjoyment into overt amusement.
Freud has often been credited with the idea that the enjoyment of
disparagement humor is due, in large measure, to the camouflage of the hostility
contained in it. Blunt hostilities, this interpretation suggests, are socially
objectionable; any enjoyment that their expression would motivate needs to be
repressed for fear of social repercussions. Hostilities that are camouflaged by
joke-work, in contrast, are not fully recognized for what they are, making them
more acceptable and even enjoyable. Such a view is somewhat counterintuitive.
How, for instance, can persons who are motivated to enjoy someone's disparage-
ment be appreciative of humor in which the hostile, disparaging acts are cleverly
concealed and go unrecognized? Additionally, this view is at variance with
much of the research evidence on the dispositional facilitation of the enjoyment
of hostile humor (cf. Zillmann, 1977). Most importantly, however, it seems to
misrepresent Freud's position. It appears that this misrepresentation is simply
due to translation. Freud used the term "Verkleidung," which indeed translates
into "camouflage." But he also used "Einkieidung," which is translatable as
"embodiment," "investiture," "adornment," or "embellishment." The fact
that he used both terms rather interchangeably would suggest that camouflage in
the sense of disguise or coverup was not the intended meaning. If this
Disparagement Humor 99
makes us burst out in laughter, we can always tell ourselves that we laughed
because of the peculiar way in which the mailbox was deformed, the peculiar
expression on our neighbor's face, the peculiar squeaking noise of the impact, or
a dozen other peculiar things. The important thing is that we do not have to
believe that we are cruel enough to have enjoyed our neighbor's misfortune.
Construing another's inferiority or misfortune as funny thus saves us from a
dilemma and permits us-in our expression of joy-to be malicious without
having to be apprehensive about being reprimanded by anybody, including
ourselves. It permits us, in a way, to be malicious with dignity.
As an alternative to the suggestions by Freud, Suls (1977) has recently
promoted an incongruity-resolution model of disparagement humor that
integrates tendentious and nontendentious elements. Essentially, Suls thought
to bring together the two major, all-too-indepehdent approaches to humor,
namely, those notions that concentrate on disparagement and those that focus
on joke-work. The most characteristic interpretation of the latter approach is
usually referred to as incongruity theory (cf. Berlyne, 1969; Keith-Spiegel,
1972). Truthful to the label, it projects amusement as the result ofthe encounter
of something incongruous; that is, of an aggregate of elements that thwarts
expectations in that it contains some parts that are odd and unfitting. In so-
called "cognitive-perceptual theories" of this approach (e.g., Jones, 1970;
Shultz, 1972; Suls, 1972), the bewildering reaction to incongruity is considered
a first stage only. The resolution of the incongruity is viewed as the essential
second stage, and mirth is said to depend on reaching the second stage.
Experimentation with children lends strong support to this stage model (e.g.,
Shultz, 1972, 1974). Suls proposed that such incongruity resolution is vital to
the enjoyment of disparagement, too; he suggested that amusement from
disparagement humor should be the greater, the less ambiguous and drawn out
the resolution of any incongruity associated with the disparagement. Wicker,
Barron, and Willis (1980) have presented data in support of this proposal. They
have shown, among other things, that amusement in response to disparagement
humor tends to decline with the "sensicalness" of the resolution.
Suls' proposal has merit in that it unites approaches to humor that, as theories
of limited scope, have coexisted in relative isolation. Hopefully it will stimulate
further integrative efforts. However, the proposal does not directly address the
question of why, through the addition of incongruities and their resolution, the
disposition ally motivated enjoyment of disparagement would find expression in
amusement.
the mechanics of this conversion have been formalized and tested only recently
(Zillmann & Bryant, 1980). Specifically, Freud's suggestions concerning the
individual's inability to properly apportion mirth to particular elements of a
complex stimulus situation, as discussed earlier, have been further developed in
an attributional analysis. This analysis, applied to the enjoyment of disparage-
ment humor, yielded the following propositions:
1. Witnessing the intentional or accidental infliction of misfortunes upon
entities toward which negative dispositions are held and/or that are
considered deserving of such treatment motivates positive affective reac-
tions.
2. In social encounters characterized by sincerity, the overt manifestations of
these reactions need to be inhibited. The inhibiton results from the
anticipation of social reproach for violations of the known rules of good
social conduct. However, such inhibition tends to become habitual and to
generalize to nonsocial situations.
3. The presence of innocuous humor cues (Le., nontendentious mirth-evoking
stimuli; stimuli fostering Witzarbeit; collative variables of humor) in the
misfortunes removes the basis for the anticipation of social reproach in that
the overt expression of mirth can be attributed to these humor cues. This
attribution-or more accurately, this misattribution-thus "justifies" and
"legitimizes" the normally censured open enjoyment of the disparagement of
detested entities. As amusement, joy in response to tendentious elements is
virtually liberated by the presence of nontendentious elements of humor.
Clearly, such projections hinge on the assumption that people are poor judges
of what, exactly, makes them laugh. If particular innocuous humor cues were
unmistakably linked to particular amounts of amusement, misconception could
not occur. Only to the extent that the mirth response to such stimuli is highly
variable and its magnitude can not be foretold, can it be expected that the
individual may misconstrue a high-magnitude mirth response that feeds on
witnessing the disparagement of a resented party as a reaction primarily caused
by "the humor" in the situation.
The implications of these presumed attributional processes for the enjoyment
of disparagement humor were determined by an experimental investigation in
which humorous disparagement was decomposed into its component parts;
namely, tendentious and nontendentious elements. There were, consequently,
three pertinent conditions: the first one entailed both disparagement and
innocuous humor cues; the second one featured the raw, unembellished
disparagement; and the third one involved the innocuous humor cues only. As
the proposed liberation of mirth presupposes negative sentiment, these
conditions were cross varied with negative sentiment versus a control in which
no particular sentiment was evoked.
Operationally, both male and female subjects individually interacted with a
female experimenter who treated them either in a condescending, rude manner
or in a neutral fashion. After thus establishing a negative versus a neutral
102 Dolf ZiIImann
Situations
No Mishap. Mishap. No Mishap.
Dispositions Humor Cues Humor Cues Humor Cues
Neutral 15.1 ab 7.P 23.9 bc
Resentment 12.7ab 28.3 c 50.3 d
Note. Means having no letter in their superscripts in common differ atp < .05 by Newman-Keuls'
test.
From "Misattribution Theory of Tendentious Humor" by D. Zillmann and J. Bryant, Journal of
Experimental Social Psychology, 1980,16, 146-160. Copyright 1980. Reprinted by permission of
the publisher.
Disparagement Humor 103
the component parts when the victim was met with indifference; but when the
victim was resented, mirth exceeded this sum significantly. In the critical,
dispositional condition, then, mirth was pronounced and more than the sum of
the reactions to the constituent's parts. If it is assumed-as is done in mis-
attribution theory-that in the absence of mirth-liberating humor cues the
individual is forced to hold back the expression of enjoyment, the moderate
reaction to the pure mishap can be considered subdued and the pronounced
reaction to the embellished mishap minus the reaction to the pure embellish-
ment indicative of the enjoyment motivated by negative sentiment. But
regardless of the reconstruction of the magnitude of motivated mirth, the
findings are entirely consistent with the propositions of the misattribution theory
of tendentious humor, and they support the theory in this sense.
The misattribution theory of humor has the disquieting corollary that disparage-
ment, in and of itself (and regardless of dispositions toward disparager and
disparaged), is not funny. Dependent upon the dispositional conditions
articulated in disposition theory, disparagement may motivate enjoyment-even
evoke overt enjoyment under some circumstances. It will not produce
amusement, however, unless humor cues are part and parcel of any disparage-
ment. Dispositional analyses thus seem to beg the question as to what makes
humor humor (or what makes something funny). Dispositional considerations, it
could be argued, forecast the intensity of mirth reactions, not their particular
euphoric mode or status. Put simply, they project how funny a disparaging event
will be to whom; but they fail to predict whether or not it will befunny in the first
place. Disposition theory proper, then, might be considered a theory of humor
facilitation (or humor impairment) rather than a theory of humor per se. The
disposition theory of humor obviously relies on elements alien to dispositional
considerations to arrive at predictions of amusement an<;l funniness. It relies on
collative variables such as novelty, surprise, incongruity, and the like. Only the
involvement of these variables appears to assure humor, and presumably so
because of particular intrinsic properties of the stimuli they subsume.
It might seem advisable to put forth a general classification of innocuous-
stimulus conditions that are intrinsically funny and that, therefore, are capable
of triggering smiles and laughter in response to disparagement-as long as they
are properly integrated with the disparaging happenings. Moreover, one might
be inclined to acknowledge that searching for the "essence of humor" in
disparaging situations and in the dispositions toward the parties involved is a
moot undertaking, and that the search ought to focus on nontendentious stimuli
as they seem to hold greater promise of being "intrinsically funny." Both
reactions would be rash, however. It turns out that all efforts at classifying
seemingly intrinsically-funny stimulus conditions have failed to differentiate
104 Dolf Zillrnann
between stimuli that consistently produce mirth and those that consistently do
not. Novel, surprising, incongruous, strange, complex, ambiguous, puzzling,
and contradictory stimuli (cf. Berlyne, 1969, 1972) stimulate amusement on
some occasions, but not on others. Situations that contain ample novelty and
surprise, such as seeing the pope get shot, may bewilder us, get us upset, or
leave us indifferent rather than make us laugh-even in the case the dispositions
were favorable to enjoyment. The collative variables thus do not subsume
"intrinsically funny" stimuli, and their presence in disparaging situations might
be considered facilitative of humor but not essential to it. Stimuli of this type do
not necessarily qualify as "humor cues."
Those who have searched for the apparently elusive innocuous stimulus
conditions that consistently evoke smiles and laughter-that assure humor, so to
speak-have come to acknowledge the significance of the context in which
innocuous, potentially mirth-inducing stimuli are presented. McGhee (1972),
for instance, stipulates that cues calling for "fantasy assimilation" be present,
and Rothbart (1973, 1976) similarly insists on the presence of cues that signal
"play" or "fun." For example, children tend to construe riddles in which
incongruities are featured as problems to be resolved in earnest; only when
given a "play" hint do they respond to them in a humored fashion (e.g.,
Rothbart & Pien, 1977).
It would appear, then, that stimuli drawn from the so-called collative
variables and stimuli that signify playfulness (or lack of seriousness) are both
necessary to elicit smiles and laughter. Both types of stimuli, it seems, are
necessary to convert the resentment-motivated enjoyment of disparagement into
amusement. Notwithstanding the significance of this function, little is known
about the stimulus combinations in question. Do certain stimuli have intrinsic
properties that link them to merriment specifically? Is the signification of play
arbitrary and entirely the result of cultural convention? Or do intrinsic
properties combine with conventions in unique ways to signal funniness-and
through such signaling set us free to enjoy disparagements that we otherwise
could not?
REFERENCES
Aristotle. Treatise on poetry. London: Luke Hansard, 1812.
Bain, A. The emotions and the will (3rd ed.). London: Longrnans Green, 1880.
Baudelaire, C. De l'essence du rire. In Oeuvres completes. Paris: Gallimard, 1961.
(Originally published, 1855.)
Berlyne, D. E. Laughter, humor, and play. In G. Lindzey & E. Aronson (Eds.), The
handbook of social psychology (Vol. 3, 2nd ed.). Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley,
1969.
Berlyne, D. E. Humor and its kin. In J. H. Goldstein & P. E. McGhee (Eds.), The
psychology of humor. New York: Academic Press 1972.
Disparagement Humor 105
Bryant, J., Brown, D., Comisky, P. W., & Zillmann, D. Sports and spectators:
Commentary and appreciation. Journal of Communication, 1982,32(1), 109-119.
Cantor, J. R What is funny to whom?: The role of gender. Journal of Communication,
1976,26(3),164-172.
Cantor, J. R, & Zillmann, D. Resentment toward victimized protagonists and severity of
misfortunes they suffer as factors in humor appreciation. Journal of Experimental
Research in Personality, 1973,6,321-329.
Carus, P. On the philosophy of laughing. Monist, 1898,8.
Chapman, A. J., Smith, 1. R, & Foot, H. C. Language, humour and intergroup relations.
In H. Giles (Ed.), Language, ethnicity and intergroup relations. New York:
Academic Press, 1977.
Dunlap, K. Old and new viewpoints in psychology. St. Louis: Meaby, 1925.
Freud, S. Der Witz und seine Beziehung zum Unbewussten. Frankfurt: Fischer
Biicherei, 1958. (Originally published, 1905.)
Hazlitt, W. On the pleasure of hating. In Essays. New York: Macmillan, 1926.
(Originally published, 1826.)
Hobbes T. Human nature, or the fundamental elements of policy. In Sir W. Molesworth
(Ed.), The English works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury (Vol. 4). London: J.
Bohn, 1840. Aalen: Scientia Verlag, 1966. (Originally published, 1650.)
Hobbes, T. Leviathan. Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1968. (Originally published, 165l.)
James, W. The principles of psychology (Vol. 1). New York: Holt, 1890.
Jones, J. M. Cognitivefactors in the appreciation of humor: A theoretical and empirical
analysis. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Yale University, 1970.
Keith-Spiegel, P. Early conceptions of humor: Varieties and issues. In 1. H. Goldstein &
P. E. McGhee (Eds.), The psychology of humor. New York: Academic Press,
1972.
La Fave, L. Humor judgments as a function of reference groups: An experimental
study. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, University of Oklahoma, 196 (
La Fave, L. Humor judgments as a function of reference groups and identification
classes. In 1. H. Goldstein & P. E. McGhee (Eds.), The psychology of humor.
New York: Academic Press, 1972.
La Fave, L. Ethnic humour: From paradoxes towards principles. In A. J. Chapman &
H. C. Foot (Eds.), It's a funny thing, humour. Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1977.
La Fave, L., Haddad, J., & Maesen, W. A. Superiority, enhanced self-esteem, and
perceived incongruity humour theory. In A. J. Chapman & H. C. Foot (Eds.),
Humour and laughter: Theory, research and applications. London: Wiley, 1976.
La Fave, L., Haddad, J., & Marshall, N. Humor judgments as a function of
identification classes. Sociology and Social Research, 1974, 58, 184-194.
La Fave, L., McCarthy, K., & Haddad, J. Humor judgments as a function of
identification classes: Canadian vs. American. Journal of Psychology, 1973, 85,
53-59.
Leacock, S. B. Humour: Its theory and technique. London: Lane, 1935.
Losco, J., & Epstein, S. Humor preference as a subtle measure of attitudes toward the
same and the opposite sex. Journal of Personality, 1975,43,321-334.
McGhee, P. E. On the cognitive origins of incongruity humor: Fantasy assimilation
versus reality assimilation. In J. H. Goldstein & P. E. McGhee (Eds.), The
psychology of humor. New York: Academic Press, 1972.
McGhee, P. E., & Duffey, N. S. Racial-ethnic differences in the onset of children's
106 Dolf Zillmann
Humor Development:
Toward a Life Span Approach
PAUL E. McGHEE
Several chapters in the volume edited by McGhee and Chapman (1980) were
designed to stimulate research in areas of children's behavior and development
that should have close links to humor development. Tower and Singer (1980)
discuss the importance of imaginative play in early childhood, noting the
cognitive, social, and emotional benefits it has for the child. Since humor is seen
as evolving out of imaginative play, these benefits hold for humor as well.
McGhee (1979, 1983) and Horgan (1981) have similarly noted the early close
relationship between humor and imaginative play. Gardner (1980) discusses
the close relationship between humor and the realms of metaphor and story
comprehension (literary development). Shultz and Robillard (1980) provide a
systematic analysis of phonology, morphology, semantics, syntax, and prag-
matics as a means of determining probable sources of linguistic humor in
children as a result of violation oflearned rules. McGhee (l980a) discussed the
relationship between humorous and nonhumorous forms of creativity, between
fantasy play and humor, and between creating versus responding to humor, and
presented data on behavioral precursors of high amounts of fantasy play.
Davies and Apter (1980) presented data on the effect of humor on learning
among children and noted the general lack of research in this area.
Horgan (1981) has opened up a promising new area of research by studying
in detail the humor of her daughter between 16 and 48 months of age. Focusing
on both linguistic and cognitive issues, she provided support for McGhee's
(1979) proposed stage sequence of humor development. While her daughter's
humor seemed to be very advanced at each age level (apparently due to the
early exposure to language games), the sequential changes in her humor
productions are noteworthy. The earliest form of humor shown by the child
(Kelly) took the combined form of executing actions appropriate to another
object and giving an accompanying mislabeling of the present object. Kelly
learned the word "shoe" at 16 months of age, at a point where her vocabulary
was less than 20 words. "Several days later, she put her foot through the
armhole of a nightgown, saying 'shoe,' accompanied by shrieks of laughter.
Later that day, she put her foot into a tennis ball can, saying 'shoe' and
laughing" (p. 218). Horgan referred to this as violation of semantic categories.
Horgan also noted that as soon as Kelly began forming two-word sentences, she
started forming jokes based on violation of semantic restrictions (e.g., "bed cry"
plus laughter).
Humor Development: Toward a Life Span Approach III
Throughout her development, the acquisition of a new word would stimulate a joke
attempt of this type. When she was I; II I told her I was proud of her. She correctly
surmised that only people are proud of you. She used ajoke to 'show off (and to test)
her knowledge: Daddy's proud of you. Grandma's proud of you. Uncle David's
proud of you. Hamburger NOT proud of you. Ha, ha. Of course, sometimes her
analyses were incorrect and her jokes failed. After asking me why men could not wear
dresses and contemplating my response about customs, she concluded that customs
were something that only men had. Daddy has a custom. Uncle David has a custom.
Mommy has a custom! Ha, ha, mommies can't have customs! The clock has a
custom! Ha, ha, clocks can't have customs! (p. 219)
While these types of joking should normally appear at later ages, they support
the general notion that a "mastery-play cycle" occurs in connection with all
incongruity-based humor and make-believe play. Horgan adds an important
extension of the notion of a master-play cycle with her observation that humor
initiation that takes the form of producing distortions of acquired knowledge
may serve to check the accuracy or firmness of one's understanding by testing
hypotheses about the nature of that knowledge. A similar notion was advanced
over a decade ago by Helmers (1965). In a related position, Alford (1980)
proposed that "humor enhances our awareness of our expectations" (p. 253).
This sort of joke-telling is a very effective strategy for a language learner: you hear a
new word, make a hypothesis about the semantic restrictions, and test your hypothesis
by violating those restrictions. Thus, Kelly learned from our responses that she had
correctly analysed proud. but had incorrectly analysed custom. (Horgan, 1981,
p.219)
One of the major issues associated with the early development of humor
concerns the question of when the capacity for humor first appears. Also, does
the earliest humor occur in connection with simple incongruities or in
connection with tendentious content (Freud, 1905/1960)? McGhee (1979) has
argued that symbolically mediated incongruity humor is the first form of humor
experienced by children, but no pertinent data have been available in
connection with this issue. Horgan (1981), however, did find that elements
relating to conflict over sex, aggression, or siblings did not appear in Kelly's
jokes until after 28 months. This suggests that nontendentious forms of humor
do appear first.
Studies of children's humor have generally not included different socio-
economic (SES) or raciaVethnic groups. While subjects other than white middle-
class children have occasionally been used, no attempt has been made to
determine how humor development may vary as a function of SES or raciaV
ethnic status. McGhee and Kach (1981) and McGhee and Duffey (1983a,
1983b) recently attempted to change this state of affairs by studying the humor
of preschool black, Mexican-American, and Anglo children. The latter two
studies look at age and group differences in preferences for different types of
disparagement humor and are discussed in Chapter 5. McGhee and Kach
(1981) tested children between about 3 and 6 years of age by giving them
"clown hats" and providing them with a general set to try to be funny. Black and
Mexical-American low-income and Anglo middle-income children were placed
together in same-sex and same-age pairs in a small room and were told that they
could do or say anything they wanted to in order to try to be funny. Their
behavior was videotaped for a 6-minute period.
Few age differences (3 to 4h vs. 4h to 6) were observed in the kinds of humor
produced among any of the three subject groups, a finding that is consistent with
McGhee's (1979) view that major changes in the quality of humor occur at
about 3 and 7 years of age. In a comparison between black and Mexican-
American children (both low income), group differences were obtained only for
two infrequently occurring behaviors. So these two groups were combined for
subsequent comparisons with the middle-class Anglo group. A general
distinction was made between verbal and vocal forms of humor and physical or
behavioral forms. The low- and middle-income groups did not differ on any
form of behavioral attempts at humor (e.g., making faces, falling down,
wrestling-pushing-hitting, and running-jumping-dancing). For all three groups,
the latter two categories were the most frequent behavioral categories of humor.
McGhee and Kach noted, however, that these activities (commonly known as
"rough and tumble play") generally occur in the broader context of having fun,
and may not have constituted specific attempts to be funny-at least in the same
sense that falling down is an attempt to be funny. The only significant group
differences occurred for verbal and vocal forms of humor. The middle-income
Anglo children showed more frequent nonwordlnonsense-word sequences,
"taboo" words or statements, screaming and squealing, and yelling and
Humor Development: Toward a Life Span Approach 113
The present section considers a number of broad issues that must be addressed
by any thorough analysis of humor development. In most cases, only limited
attention has been given to these issues-even in the context of investigations of
children's humor. None of these issues have been raised in connection with a
life-span approach to studying humor development.
114 Paul E. McGhee
While well over 100 studies of children's humor have been published since
1970, this apparently obvious question has not yet been asked. Most of the
research has focused on appreciation of cartoons or jokes selected in advance by
the experimenter, although a few studies have examined humor comprehension
or frequency of humor initiation in naturalistic settings.
It is now generally agreed that humor is a complex multidimensional
phenomenon, so the key question becomes which aspects of humor remain
relatively unchanged (or change in an unsystematic way) and which show
systematic change as a function of increasing age? In the latter case, we must
also consider whether the pattern of changes described holds for people
generally or varies as a function of individual experience or status variables.
kind or level of humor an individual can understand, then the transition from
concrete- to formal-operational reasoning should lead to a new level of humor
comprehension and appreciation. However, no attempt has yet been made to
determine the nature of new forms of humor that accompany the new cognitive
capacities of early adolescence. Neither Shultz (1972, 1976) nor McGhee
(1979) attempted to link humor development to cognitive development beyond
the concrete-operational period.
There is no apparent basis for expecting any general developmental trend for
humor comprehension beyond adolescence. Developmental psychologists are
generally agreed that formal operations thinking is the peak level of functioning
achieved throughout adulthood for most individuals. Beyond adolescence, then,
age-related differences in humor comprehension should be best explained in
terms of influences on individual differences in comprehension. If a general age
trend in humor comprehension does hold for the adult years, it would most
likely be based on the greater experience (and its associated increased
familiarity with the elements composing jokes) ofthe older adult. In the case of
advanced aging, there is some basis for predicting a negative relationship
between age and humor comprehension. While the question of the extent (if
any) of cognitive deterioration associated with advanced aging remains
controversial, Schaier and Cicirelli (1976) argued that a gradual loss of
operational thought capacities should lead conservation-violation jokes, which
are directly dependent on concrete-operational thought for comprehension, to
become funnier (because understanding them becomes more of a challenge)
with increasing age. They tested 50- to 80-year-olds and found that compre-
hension did drop with increasing age while appreciation went up. Investigations
of age-related changes in humor comprehension, then, may show systematic
developmental changes only at the two ends of the life cycle.
the social situation (work vs. home vs. church, etc.). Thus, any developmental
changes that occur may be observed in some contexts, but not others.
To this point, this section has focused on developmental changes in humor that
are generally characteristic of individuals as they move from infancy through
old age. This is generally referred to as the nomothetic approach. This is
probably the best starting point for a life span investigation of humor
development since age differences are especially striking during childhood.
Within these general age-related changes, however, individual differences in the
frequency, content, and types of humor initiation and in the manner and
intensity of humor responsiveness are equally striking. During the adult and
aging years, individual differences in humor should prove to be more
pronounced than similarities within age group.
Brodzinsky and Rightmyer (1980) have recently stressed the need for more
research on individual differences in humor development, noting that two
general approaches to such research might be adopted. The differential
approach is similar to the nomothetic approach in that it is aimed at producing
general laws or descriptions of behavior. It differs, however, because of its focus
on how general patterns of development vary as a function of subjects'
differential status on some dimension used to group individuals (sex, SES, a
personality measure, etc.). The goal of the differential approach is to determine
why developmental trends vary as a function of the status variable studied.
Brodzinsky and Rightmyer noted that most research on individual differences in
humor development has been based on this approach.
The idiographic (or ipsative) approach focuses on developmental change and
continuity within the individual, regardless of how such patterns relate to those
Humor Development: Toward a Life Span Approach 119
along these lines with very young children, but comparable studies need to be
extended across the life span. SES, racial-ethnic, or sex differences in humor
that occur at one point in the life span will not necessarily occur at other age
levels (see discussion below on continuity/stability of humor).
Research on cognitive style may hold the most promise (within the
differential approach) for improving our understanding certain aspects of humor
development across the life span. Cognitive style refers to the manner in which
an individual processes information-in our case, information contained in a
cartoon or joke. Brodzinsky and his associates (Brodzinsky, 1975, 1977;
Brodzinsky, Feuer, & Owens, 1977; Brodzinsky, Tew, & Palkovitz, 1979) have
completed a series of studies with children ranging between 6 and 12 years of
age linking degree of reflection-impulsivity (Kagan, Rosman, Day, Albert, &
Phillips, 1964) or conceptual tempo to humor comprehension and appreciation.
These studies consistently show that reflective children (slow accurates on the
Matching Familiar Figures Test) show better humor comprehension than
impulsives (fast inaccurates), but impulsives show more laughter. Presumably,
it is the cautious and more systematic information processing strategies of the
reflective child that lead to increased understanding of what is going on in a
joke. Impulsive children, on the other hand, tend to show elevated overt mirth in
spite of this reduced comprehension.
It is important to note that when prompted by the experimenter to rethink the
meaning of jokes or ambiguous sentences, impulsive children showed compre-
hension scores comparable to those of reflective children (Brodzinsky, 1977;
Brodzinsky et aI., 1977). This supports the view that humor differences among
these children are a matter of cognitive style, not cognitive ability. It does
appear, however, that reflective children are more discriminating in the amount
of smiling and laughing they show to jokes. While reflectives showed varying
amounts of mirth depending on the complexity of the joke, impulsives showed
equal levels of laughter to all jokes-and even laughed at nonjoke control
stimuli.
These findings clearly demonstrate the kind of difficulties that plague the
humor researcher and may partially account for the inconsistent findings often
obtained in different areas of humor research. While there has been little serious
discussion of how individuals go about "deciding" how funny a joke is or how
much to laugh at it (see Chapter 2 for a discussion of metacognitive processing
issues), most investigators appear to assume that qualities of the humor stimulus
play a central role in determining the nature and level of response that occurs.
But this appears to be true only for reflective children. If laughter is the key
dependent variable, the nature of the data obtained may greatly depend on the
relative number of reflectives and impulsives in different experimental con-
ditions. Future studies might profitably treat reflection-impulsivity as a
"blocking factor" and expose equal numbers of reflectives and impulsives to
each experimental condition.
Amount of reflection-impulsivity has not been related to humor measures in
adolescent, adult, or aging populations. However, the fact that this aspect of
Humor Development: Toward a Life Span Approach 121
cognitive style has been found to be stable over periods of several years
(Bronson, 1966, 1967; Kagan & Kogan, 1970; Sigel & Brodzinsky, 1977)
suggests that its relationship to humor comprehension and appreciation may
also be relatively stable.
The significance of Brodzinsky' s work within the differential approach lies in
the fact that it has clear implications for how different (groups of) individuals
begin to develop their own unique sense of humor. Even though underlying
acquisition of particular cognitive skills determines which jokes a child has the
capacity to understand, reflective children are likely to become more cognitively
focused in their sense of humor and to be less overtly responsive (Le., laugh
less). At later ages, these individuals may develop a preference for more subtle
or complex forms of humor. These may also be the persons who develop a
"dry" sense of humor. Impulsive children, who are less discriminating in their
laughter, are likely to become best known for the responsive aspects of their
sense of humor. Full comprehension does not seem to be necessary for them to
erupt in hearty laughter. Impulsives have also been found to show greater
elevation of laughter than reflectives under conditions of social facilitation
(Brodzinsky, Tew, & Palkovitz, 1979), suggesting that their tendency to "laugh
at anything" may be even more exaggerated in the presence of laughing
others.
Thomae (1979) noted that data published from long-term longitudinal studies
over the past 25 years have "pointed to a high degree of consistency of
personality from early adolescence into adulthood" (p. 287). Using the research
on conceptual tempo as a model, it should be fruitful to relate highly stable
dimensions of personality to humor initiation, responsiveness, and develop-
ment. Once the role of key personality dimensions, SES, sex, cognitive level,
and other subject status variables in humor development has been determined,
we will be in a better position to evaluate findings resulting from the ideographic
approach (discussed below). We will not fully understand humor development
until we can simultaneously consider (and meaningfully interpret) information
associated with: (1) general developmental trends in humor development, (2)
variations in general trends as a function of status variables, and (3) individual
experiences and characteristics associated with humor differences. At this
point, most of our knowledge of humor development has come from the first
research strategy. The need for additional research using the other two
strategies is clear.
since their samples were clearly atypical relative to the general population.
Also, no attempt was made to compare background characteristics of
professionals in writing or performing humor to those of other individuals who
do not make a living in connection with humor. For example, the finding that
comics or comedy writers experience high amounts of early stress or conflict
would not be of particular interest if a nonhumor control group showed the same
kind of background.
Fisher and Fisher (1981) recently reported findings of a detailed analysis of
the background and current psychological characteristics of a group of
comedians and clowns. Their approach was more systematic than those of prior
investigators, in that they utilized a standardized interview procedure and
administered the same psychological tests to all subjects. They also included
two control groups, permitting a better judgment of the potential significance of
a given characteristic or experience for the development of humor-related
behavior. This project is a good model for other investigators planning to use a
case-history approach to studying humor development. This kind of approach is
necessary to identify early precursors that serve to channel the child in the
direction of enhanced humor development. It must be remembered, however,
that data obtained for professional humorists will not necessarily generalize to
individuals with enhanced humor development in the general population. The
Fishers' findings are discussed in detail in Chapter 4 of Volume II.
One study has been completed that examined the relationship between both
early maternal behavior and early characteristics of the child's own behavior
and subsequent humor behavior. McGhee (1980b) observed the frequency of
laughter and verbal and behavioral initiation of humor among 3- to 5-year-old
and 6- to II-year-old children who were part of the longitudinal sample of the
Fels Research Institute. Data from detailed observations of maternal behavior
were available (in the permanent Fels files) from birth through 6 years of age,
while observational data on children were available from age 3 up to the child's
present age.
Only a few characteristics of early maternal behavior were found to be
predictive of sense-of-humor development (defined in terms of a combined
score, based on frequency of verbal and behavioral initiation of humor and
frequency of laughter during spontaneous social play), but the nature of these
predictions depended on the age at which the child's humor-related behavior
was observed. Boys and girls, 3 to 5 years of age, who showed heightened
humor development had a history of very positive relationships with their
mothers. Their mothers were generally warm and approving and tended to baby
and be protective of them up to age three. This had the effect of providing these
children with an environment that was free of conflict, danger, and difficult-to-
solve problems. While these same variables continued to be predictive of the
preschooler's sense of humor after age three, they were accompanied by an
association with a lack of maternal affection. This reduced affection is
especially noteworthy in view of the reversed pattern of predictions from
maternal behavior among the older children.
Humor Development: Toward a Life Span Approach 123
Stability of Humor
It has been suggested here that some aspects of humor development are shared
by all individuals (at least during childhood and perhaps adolescence), while
other aspects are shared only by certain subgroups or are unique to the
individual. The present section discusses mechanisms and processes that might
account for changes in humor comprehension, appreciation, or production at
different points in the life span.
Reinforcement and Modeling. The most probable explanation for the fact that
some individuals initiate more humor than others is that they have received
greater reinforcement for doing so. Thus, the pertinent issues become: (1) the
nature of these reinforcements, (2) the importance of the age at which they
occur, and (3) their source in the social environment. Surprisingly, virtually no
Humor Development: Toward a Life Span Approach 127
attempt has been made to investigate the effect of parental or peer reinforcement
of efforts at humor on subsequent measures of the quantity or quality of humor
shown.
Two types of reinforcement may be distinguished in connection with humor:
intrinsic and extrinsic (presumably social). Considerable attention has been
given to the intrinsic reinforcing properties of humor. Berlyne (1960, 1969,
1972) has explained humor in terms of its association with underlying changes
in arousal, arguing that moderate arousal boosts and arousal jags (a larger
arousal increase followed by a sudden drop in arousal) have high reinforcement
potential regardless of their source (this view is discussed in detail in Chapter
2). McGhee (1979) offered a related position, drawing from Piaget's (1952)
notion that the "need" to explore novelty is built into a child's nervous system.
In support of this view, considerable evidence is available indicating that infants
show the greatest attention (and smile more) to moderate levels of discrepancy
from prior experience (McCall & McGhee, 1977). Both Singer (1973) and
McGhee (1979) have argued that this built-in tendency may be one of the
strongest motivating forces behind young children's frequent engagement in
fantasy activity (including humor). In short, incongruity humor and other forms
of fantasy activity are reinforcing because they provide new forms of stimulation
and help maintain an optimally interesting environment.
These views suggest that humor is intrinsically enjoyable and that the
tendency to produce humor should be strengthened simply by coming up with
ideas thought to be funny. Presumably, this source of reinforcement is operating
on a similar basis in all young children with comparable levels of intelligence.
Extreme individual differences in humor initiation as early as the late preschool
years, then, must be explained on the basis of other sources of reinforcement.
The most obvious probable source of such reinforcement, of course, is the
child's parents. Surprisingly, no attempt has been made to observe parental
reactions to their children in order to determine their impact on humor
development. There is considerable evidence from case histories that profes-
sional comedians, clowns, and comedy writers tended to have models of joking
and clowning in one or both parents (or a grandmother) during childhood
(Fisher & Fisher, 1981; Fry & Allen, 1975; Janus, 1975; Wilde, 1968). These
parents were likely to have reinforced comparable behaviors in their children. In
some cases, these professionals also imitated radio or television models as
children (Schwartz, 1978).
Bell and McGhee (1982) obtained data consistent with these findings in a
large sample of college students. Males who rated themselves as being more
frequent initiators of humor also rated their fathers as having done more joking
and clowning. The same relationship was obtained with mothers among female
subjects. In neither case was this relationship significant for the parent of the
opposite sex. McGhee (l980b), however, found that among elementary school
children, observed frequency of humor initiation in spontaneous social play was
not significantly related to a home visitor's recall of maternal joking and
clowning while interacting with their children (no data were available for
128 Paul E. McGhee
fathers). Bass (1981) found that parents who participated more in their
children's pretend play in a laboratory setting had children who more frequently
engaged in pretend. While this study did not focus on humor, the close
relationship between preschoolers' humor and make-believe play suggests that
this relationship should hold for humor as well.
Assuming that future research will demonstrate that social reinforcement does
increase the frequency of attempts at humor initiation, attention should also be
given to why parental or peer laughter at jokes or clowning behavior is
reinforcing. The positive attention and affection gained from others' laughter
may prove to be important at all ages. This may be an especially strong
influence on children who have higher needs to obtain attention or affection
from parents or peers. Since data for both young adults and children point to
dominance and aggression as early characteristics of the person who initiates a
lot of humor, these individuals may have experienced less frequent positive
sources of attention than less dominating and less aggressive children. As
suggested earlier, these children may have learned quite early that joking or
clowning produced positive reactions in other people but still allowed them to
maintain a sense of power or control over others.
Humor might also be more reinforcing for some individuals than others
because it helps reduce anxiety or stress. Thus, children who experience greater
amounts of conflict while growing up should have greater incentive to develop
effective humor skills. Regardless of the basis for the reinforcing properties of
others' laughter, future research should include a determination of the
effectiveness of such reinforcement at different points during the life span. The
limited available evidence suggests that individuals who show enhanced humor
development were already working on developing humor skills by the time they
entered school. While varying influences undoubtedly contributed to the
increased clowning and joking of different individuals, it remains to be
determined whether comparable influences would be equally effective in
increasing attempts at humor in adolescence and early or late adulthood. Future
research should include subjects across the life span and determine not only
factors that are conducive to increased humor production at different age levels,
but also those that contribute toward reduced joking, clowning, and laughter.
Both sets of influences may prove to be relatively independent of age,
depending instead on variation in experiences of life circumstances.
The laughter component of sense of humor appears to be especially sensitive
to social influence, suggesting that parental modeling of laughter could
contribute significantly to humor development. Chapman (1973b), Chapman
and Wright (1976), Fuller and Sheehy-Skeffington (1974), and Smyth and
Fuller (1972) found that laughter of others facilitates one's own laughter. Also,
both children and adults show increased laughter in the presence of canned
laughter (from a laugh track) (Chapman, 1973a; Cupchik & Leventhal, 1974;
Leventhal & Cupchik, 1975; Leventhal & Mace, 1970). There remains some
question, however, as to whether this socially facilitated laughter is humorous
laughter or just social laughter. The fact that these studies also indicate that
Humor Development: Toward a Life Span Approach 129
CONCLUSIONS
Our present understanding of humor development amounts to a limited
understanding of the development of children's humor in the preadolescent
years. No attempt has been made to study humor development in adolescence,
adulthood, or the aging years. The only exception to this can be found in the
small number of studies of early backgrounds of professional humorists. While a
great deal of research has been completed on college students and adults (as
may be seen in the rest of the chapters in these two volumes), this research has
not focused on developmental changes in humor. Many studies of children have
similarly not been developmental in nature. All of these studies, however, can
serve as a starting point for a life-span investigation of humor development. An
attempt has been made here to underscore general issues that must be
considered in any developmental approach to humor, regardless of the period of
the life span in question. The greatest need at the present time would appear to
be information on the relative stability of humor-related behavior at different
parts of the life span. Assuming that certain aspects of humor turn out to be
relatively stable, while others vary as a function of age and context,
130 Paul E. McGhee
REFERENCE NOTE
1. Bell, N. J., & McGhee, P. E. Social interaction implications of humor. Paper
presented at meeting of the Southwestern Society for Research in Human Develop-
ment, Galveston, 1982.
REFERENCES
Alford, R. The structure of human experience: Expectancy and affect: the case of humor.
Journal of Social Biological Structure, 1980,3,247-254.
Bass, S. H. The relationship between parental behavior and children's pretend play.
Unpublished Masters thesis, Texas Tech University, 1981.
Bates, E. (Ed.), The emergence o/symbols: Cognition and communication in infancy.
New York: Academic Press, 1979.
Berlyne, D. E. Conflict, arousal and curiosity. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1960.
Berlyne, D. E. Laughter, humor and play. In G. Lindzey & E. Aronson (Eds.),
Handbook o/Social Psychology (2nd ed., Vol. 3). Reading, Massachusetts: Addison-
Wesley, 1969.
Berlyne, D. E. Humor and its kin. In J. H. Golstein & P. E. McGhee (Eds.), The
psychology o/humor. New York: Academic Press, 1972.
Brackett, C. W. Laughing and crying of pre-school children. Journal 0/ Experimental
Education, 1933,2,119-126.
Brodzinsky, D. M. The role of conceptual tempo and stimulus characteristics in
children's humor development. Developmental Psychology, 1975, 11, 843-850
Brodzinsky, D. M. Children's comprehension and appreciation of verbal jokes in relation
to conceptual tempo. Child Development, 1977,48,960-967.
Brodzinsky, D. M., Feuer, V., & Owens, J. Detection of linguistic ambiguity by
reflective, impulsive, fast-accurate and slow-inaccurate children. Journal 0/ Educa-
tional Psychology, 1977, 69, 237-243.
Brodzinsky, D. M.. & Rightmyer, J. Individual differences in children's humour
development. In P. E. McGhee & A. J. Chapman (Eds.), Children's humour.
Chichester, England: Wiley, 1980.
Brodzinsky, D. M., Tew, J. D., & Palkovitz, R. Control of humorous affect in relation to
children's conceptual tempo. Developmental Psychology, 1979, 15,275-279.
Bronson, W. C. Central orientations: A study of behavior organization from childhood to
adolescence. Child Development, 1966,37, 793-810.
Humor Development: Toward a Life Span Approach 131
Helmers, H. Sprache und humor des kindes. Stuttgart, Germany: Ernst Klett Verlag,
1965.
Horgan, D. Learning to tell jokes: A case study of metalinguistic abilities. Journal of
Child Language, 1981,8,217-224.
Janus, S. S. The great comedians: Personality and other factors. The American Journal
of Psychoanalysis, 1975,35, 169-174.
Kagan, J. & Kogan, N. Individual variation in cognitive processes. In P. H. Mussen
(Ed.), Carmichael's manual of child pscyhology (Vol. I). New York: Wiley, 1970.
Kagan, J., Rosman, B. L., Day, D., Albert, J., & Phillips, W. Information processing in
the child: Significance of analytic and reflective attitudes. Psychological Monographs,
1964, 78, (I, Whole No. 578).
Kirshenblatt-Gimblett. B. (Ed.), Speech play. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania
Press, 1976.
Kris, E. Ego development in the comic. International Journal ofPsychoanalysis, 1938,
19, 77-90.
La Fave, L. Humor judgments as a function of reference groups and identification
classes. In J. H. Goldstein & P. E. McGhee (Eds.), The psychology of humor.
New York: Academic Press, 1972.
La Fave, L., Haddad, J., & Maesen, W. A. Superiority, enhanced self-esteem, and
perceived incongruity humour theory. In A. J. Chapman & H. C. Foot (Eds.),
Humour and laughter: Theory, research and applications. London: Wiley, 1976.
Leventhal, H. & Cupchik, G. C. The informational and facilitative effects of an audience
upon expression and evaluation of humorous stimuli. Journal ofExperimental Social
Psychology, 1975. 11, 363-380.
Leventhal, H. & Mace, W. The effect of laughter on evaluation of a slapstick movie.
Journal of Personality, 1970,38, 16-30.
McCall, R. B. & McGhee, P. E. The discrepancy hypothesis of attention and affect in
infants. In I. C. Uzgiris & F. Weizmann (Eds.), The structuring of experience. New
York: Plenum, 1977.
McDowell, J. H. Children's riddling. Bloomington, Ind.: Indiana University Press,
1979.
McGhee, P. E. Children's appreciation of humor: A test of the cognitive congruency
principle. Child Development, 1976,47, 420-426.
McGhee, P. E. Humor: Its origin and development. San Francisco: Freeman,
1979.
McGhee, P. E. Development of the creative aspects of humour. In P. E. McGhee &
A. J. Chapman (Eds.), Children's humour. Chichester, England: Wiley, 1980. (a)
McGhee, P. E. Development of the sense of humour in childhood: A longitudinal study.
In P. E. McGhee & A. J. Chapman (Eds.), Children's humour. Chichester, England:
Wiley, 1980. (b)
McGhee, P. E. Play, incongruity and humor. In T. D. Yawkey & A. D. Pelligrini (Eds.),
Child's play: Developmental and applied. Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum, 1983.
McGhee. P. E. & Chapman, A. J. (Eds.). Children's humour. Chichester, England:
Wiley, 1980.
McGhee, P. E. & Duffey, N. S. Racial-ethnic differences in the onset of children's
appreciation of humor victimizing different racial-ethnic groups. Journal of Cross-
Cultural Psychology, 1983, 14,29-40. (a)
McGhee, P. E. & Duffey, N. S. The role of identity of the victim in the development of
disparagement humor. Journal of General Psychology, 1983, 108, 257-270. (b)
Humor Development: Toward a Life Span Approach 133
ANTONY J. CHAPMAN
and large humor studies have not been sufficiently exhaustive in the measures
and procedures adopted. A fourth reason is that precious few psychologists
have examined the disparate circumstances under which humor is created and
instigated; nearly all researchers have confined themselves to studying
responses to humor stimuli, and they themselves have selected and arranged the
presentation of stimuli.
There are also other reasons why our corpus of knowledge is surprisingly
spartan, and one of prime significance to this chapter relates to the inadequate
consideration given to the social dimensions of experiments: research has been
too insensitive, truncated, and even asocial. It has tended to be laboratory
based; and, like many of the more subtle aspects of human behavior, humor
loses much of its character when placed under insensitive laboratory scrutiny.
Under such scrutiny there is typically a conscientious purging of all possible
causes of bias and extraneous influence. But with the baby can go the bath
water, and often the price to be paid for "experimental realism" is a crucial loss
of "mundane realism" (cf. Breakwell, Foot, & Gilmour, 1982).
An index as to the artificiality and sterility of much of the humor research to
date is that the majority of researchers do not incorporate any measure of
laughter in their work. One suspects that this is because they know from
experience that many of the persons they are observing will not actually laugh.
Hence humor researchers, particularly psychologists, have tended to focus on
the content, structure, and psychological function of humor, and in so doing they
have tended to disregard its immediate behavioral consequences. Yet in the
layperson's mind humor and laughter are stored together. Indeed, for many
people, the quality of a joke, a comic performance, or a humorous anecdote may
be remembered by the amount of laughter personally emitted.
Behavioral measures, particularly duration and frequency of laughing and
smiling, have been embodied in only a small proportion of studies, usually those
of a more naturalistic brand. Often these studies have also included subjective
evaluations of funniness: that is, ratings solicited and registered as in other
humor studies. It is a matter for some concern, then, that the two types of
measures (viz., expressive behaviors and subjective ratings) are not always well
correlated (cf. Leventhal & Cupchik, 1975; Leventhal & Mace, 1970; Young &
Frye, 1966). Our own research is not typical in this regard, but the general lack
of consistent and statistically significant correlations must cast doubt on the
value and validity of research methods and ipso facto on the generality of
research conclusions.
To anyone glancing through published articles, it is immediately apparent
that dependent variables are coarse. Doubtless new and refined behavioral
measures could be developed that would be more sensitive than the common
duration and frequency varieties. More than a decade ago Pollio, Mers, and
Lucchesi (1972) demonstrated the potential of oscillographic recordings of
laughter. From the traces of a sound spectroscope one can, for example, extract
measures of amplitude, latency, and patterning of responses. As far as smiling is
concerned, human ethologists have already proffered a large number of
138 Antony J. Chapman
laughter, and the amount and richness of self-perceived laughter may partly
govern an individual's judgment as to the funniness of the antecedent humor ( cf.
Bem, 1967). There is always the possibility that some humor stimuli may be
more susceptible than others to context for their maximal impact: that is, a
subject's rank ordering of stimuli for funniness might change according to
whether those stimuli were received under strictly controlled laboratory
circumstances or, say, under more naturalistic settings when laughter might
emanate freely. Expressed more formally, it is unwise to proceed as though it
were known that the inhibitory effects of the laboratory are invariably of a
uniform, linear nature. The potency of some types of humor, some joke
structures, some forms of presentation, and so forth, may be affected relatively
more than others.
A second important issue, namely, that experimenters can influence humor
responsiveness, leads us toward something resembling Pandora's box. It may be
that experimenters more readily affect expressive reactions than subjective
assessments, or laughter more than smiling. Some experimenters may have
greater influence than others across all measures. Some may influence some
individuals but not others. The possible artifacts and confoundings are various
and intricate, and they are daunting to anyone endeavoring to concoct a simple
experiment. In the text that follows we see that to begin contemplating these
effects is to do more than indulge in idle and disquieting speculation. There are
already some empirical grounds for believing that experimenter effects can be of
central importance. In humor research with children, some of the salience,
pervasiveness, and complexities of experimenter effects have already come to
light. In the coarse of time they should themselves illuminate our main subject
matter, humor, and responsiveness to humor.
This section summarizes data already published by the author and his
colleagues and briefly presents some new findings on experimenter effects. The
raison d'etre of the research is to demonstrate the significance of social
psychological variables for humor responsiveness and for humor research
generally. In the main the work relates to the influence ofthe social environment
on children's responsiveness to one another in humor situations. As a matter of
policy, the experimenter has usually been physically absent from those
situations. From the studies reviewed there are good reasons to suppose that
effects associated with child-companions would be magnified if the companion
were instead an adult (e.g., an experimenter).
Most of the studies are based on a naturalistic form of laboratory experiment,
and the theoretical underpinnings are derived from social facilitation theory ( cf.
Geen & Gange, 1977; Glaser, 1982; Weaver, 1978), social intimacy theory
(cf. Patterson, 1976, 1982), and laughter theory (e.g., Berlyne, 1969;
140 Antony J. Chapman
Chapman, Note 1, in press; Chapman & Foot, 1981; Rothbart, 1973, 1976).
The children are 4 to 11 years old and come from lower-class and middle-class
British homes. They are of mixed ability and are usually tested in pairs, where
pairings are formed randomly from same-sex classmates. While in a mobile
laboratory (cf. Foot & Chapman, 1975) situated on their school grounds, they
have been videotaped listening to tape-recorded humor or watching comedy
cartoon films. Subsequently the videotapes have been transcribed by the
experimenter( s) and assistants using an event-recorder system that in recent
times has been computerized (cf. Chapman, Smith, & Foot, 1980; Gormly,
Chapman, Foot, & Sweeney, 1980). In accounts published elsewhere various
dependent measures have been described, but it suffices here to refer just to
duration scores for laughter and smiling. In most of our research, as intimat.ed
previously, expressive responses for boys and girls have been closely match~d
to subjective ratings offunniness (Chapman, 1976; Chapman et at, 1980).
The mobile laboratory has two compartments, the main one of which is a
children's playroom. It is extremely pleasant for children; as subjects they give
every indication of thoroughly enjoying their visits. The second compartment is
smaller and houses the experimenter( s) and recording apparatuses. The video
installation comprises several microphones, a microphone-mixer unit, three
cameras, several monitors, and a split-screen device. A second video system is
installed for showing color cassettes, and the main monitor within that system is
the sole item of electronics visible to children. As far as we have been able to
discern no children have ever discovered that they were being filmed in our
humor study or even known that we had special interests in humor and laughter.
These and other general aspects of methodology have been discussed elsewhere
(e.g., Chapman, 1976, 1979; Chapman et at, 1980). However, in view of
above comments about the insensitivity and contrived nature of most humor
research, it is as well to note here that subjects paid "warm-up" visits to the
laboratory and were thoroughly acquainted with the experimenter(s) before any
trial was started. (Without warm-ups, Chapman & Speck, 1977, found that
first-born children were more responsive than others in the early stages of
triadic sessions; no doubt other studies on individual differences would show
that warm-up sessions are an essential requisite for "social" research.) No child
was ever noticed displaying discomfort or apprehension. On the contrary, an air
of eager excitement runs through a school while the "caravan"/"trailer" is
there.
Studies now to be summarized were originally conceived against the
background of general impressions about humor and laughter being essentially
social. If in everyday life humor is initiated according to social circumstances
and according to the composition of the surrounding company, and if overt and
covert reactions are determined or modified by corresponding circumstances,
then in empirical settings the social climate may play a fundamental role in
creating research outcomes. Unless adequate precautions are taken, the
experimenter is likely to be a prominent and unwitting influence in defining and
developing the parameters of that climate. It was considered not outside the
Humor and Laughter in Social Interaction 141
claimed in any study. In our research, such laughter is common (cf. Chapman,
Note 2). On occasions, however, we too have inadvertently contrived to stifle it.
The laughter of adult subjects in the study by Osborne and Chapman (1977)
was more of a private, tranquil, and transitory kind than seemed apposite for the
humor. Our personal impressions were that it bore none of the hallmarks of
laughter occurring routinely outside the laboratory: it did not appear dynamic,
attractive, or infectious, and there were no profound body movements, tears, or
noticeable changes in respiration.
A part of the explanation for our being able to simulate "real-life" laughter in
an unprecedented and reliable way is that generally our subjects do not know
that they are observed. The single exception with children is this second study,
the Osborne and Chapman experiments, that was specifically designed to
determine whether humor responsiveness may be suppressed by knowledge of
being observed.
The subjects were 7- and 8-year-olds, and they listened to tape-recorded
humor on their own (for details of the humor, see Chapman, 1972). Eight pairs
were informed of a viewing-screen facility in the mobile laboratory; a second
eight pairs were not so informed. The former were specifically told that, because
the experimenter was otherwise occupied, he would not have the time or
opportunity to look through the screen. In other respects all pairs were given
identical instructions. For instance, all were given the same information as to
how the experimenter knew when it was time to return to their playroom, having
been told previously that the dividing walVscreen was "completely sound-
proofed" (Chapman, Note 3).
It was found that children who did not know that they could be observed
laughed four times as much as the others but smiled only 60% as much (two-
tailed p < .005, for both behaviors). It would appear that in place of laughter a
more subdued form of behavior (in this case, smiling) can appear when subjects
are aware that they can be observed. However it should be emphasized that as
far as could be ascertained subjects were not thinking in terms of participation in
a study, let alone a humor study where laughter might be deemed an appropriate
or expected reaction. They were encouraged to see their involvement as one of
several visits to the "caravan," for which apparently there was no special or
ulterior purpose and that required no effort on their part-in the school context,
it was described by the teachers as "a treat." One may speculate, therefore, that
observation can kill the spontaneity in natural laughter and that the attenuation
of laughter would have been greater in this study if the children had known that
they were under continuous observation. It seems to be the case that subjects'
laughter is diminished in quantity and quality whenever there is a hint, however
subtle, that it is an expected behavior or that it is to be observed by someone in
an objective manner. In humor research, then, there is much to be said for the
spatial and temporal removal of the experimenter from observationaVtesting
environments. Whether or not that removal is practicable is quite another
matter.
Humor and Laughter in Social Interaction 143
So often in published research one wants, as a reader, to know more about the
procedural details than is reported. Correspondingly, at least in social
psychological works, one often, as a writer, craves for more space-then one
could supply more precise information and refer to matters that as a general rule
may not be so much as mentioned. It could be that a lot of this material is far
from redundant. This third study shows that experimental data may be
influenced by procedures "outside the experiment," that is, in those periods
prior to the onset of trials, rarely it ever mentioned, when in fact there is room
for massive heterogeneity in the treatment of the children (or adults) who are
about to serve as subjects.
The experiment arose from informal observations in the earliest days of our
research (Chapman, 1972). An experimenter sometimes felt an awkwardness
with a particular child or pair of children while en route from a classroom to the
mobile laboratory; for no obvious reason the interaction was stilted and
overformal. This was usually associated with a "quiet" experimental trial, one
in which there was relatively little responsiveness to the humor and, for dyads,
perhaps little social interaction. With triads and larger groups no corresponding
effect was noticeable to the experimenter. For various schools it would take
between 2 and 4 minutes to walk to the laboratory, and several techniques were
tried for occupying those periods of time. The present study is a preliminary
investigation of the efficacy of two such techniques, both involving interaction
between experimenter and pairs of subjects.
In one condition 10 same-sex pairs of 7- and 8-year-olds were engaged in a
question-and-answer form of sustained interaction in which a series of
predetermined questions was posed until arrival at the laboratory. As they
stepped out of the classroom children were told of the need to answer questions.
The questions were nonthreatening, covering routine aspects of school, the
number, ages, and sex of their siblings, holidays, pastimes, and favorite
television programs. In a second condition, a second set of 10 same-sex pairs of
7- and 8-year-olds were allowed to determine the interaction for themselves:
members of a pair, singly or together, were allowed to run ahead, or to walk
alongside the experimenter and talk as they pleased. The experimenter would
respond as necessary to keep the conversation going, if he sensed that was what
the children wanted. If a child wished to hold his hand, that too was allowed. Of
course the specific nature of the experiment was a taboo topic, and no
information was given that was contained in instructions to be conveyed inside
the laboratory. Once inside, all children received standard intructions and so
forth, and they listened to the same humor as in Study II.
No hypotheses were developed formally, but the outcome was consonant
with that expected from prior experiences. Children subjected beforehand to the
experimenter-determined interaction laughed only 20% as much as those in the
self-determined, open-ended interaction, and they smiled less than half as much.
144 Antony J. Chapman
In statistical terms the differences were highly significant (two-tailedp < .001,
for both behaviors). Formalizing and ritualizing the "preexperiment" pro-
cedures clearly had a massively adverse effect on children's responsiveness.
Subsequently subjects of experiments always found their own way to the
laboratory door for experimental trials, and the experimenter awaited their
arrival inside the playroom. Usually this has been the practice after the first of
the warm-up visits. What has happened in other humor studies is known only to
the individual researchers and their close colleagues, but identified here is still
another important cluster of variables that has to be reckoned with. It would not
be safe to imagine that effects are "randomized out" through balanced
experimental designs, for the effects may be more salient for particular types of
humor or particular classes of subjects, and so forth. Doubtless different
researchers would exert varying influence overall, any individual researcher
would vary in influence within and across days, and individual differences
between experimenters would presumably interact with individual differences
between subjects.
another (Chapman, 1976); whether the companion can attend to humor, though
it may not matter whether it be the same humor (e.g., Chapman, 1974, 1975b;
Chapman & Wright, 1976); and whether or not the companion while laughing
encroaches into the body space of the subject (Chapman, 1976). If there is more
than one companion, then the amount that those companions look at one
another is a powerful influence on the subject's overt mirth (Chapman, 1975b).
As indicated later, the age of the companion can have some consequence for so-
called "humorous laughter" (Chapman, Note 4, 1979a), but an age difference
of two years between 7 and 9-as between subjects and confederates-has no
noticeable effect (e.g., Chapman & Wright, 1976). Whether the subject and
companion are friends is an extremely important factor (e.g., Foot, Chapman,
& Smith, 1980), and above all it appears to be the case that sharing the social
situation is crucial for the facilitation of "humorous laughter" (e.g., Chapman,
1975b, 1976; Foot, Chapman, & Smith, 1977). When the companion is
another child of approximately the same age, then the subject's laughter and
smiling are invariably enhanced relative to "baseline" levels of solitary
children. That is the case even when the companion appears to ignore the
subject and is dour and unresponsive to the humor. However, equivalent studies
using adult companions (e.g., Study I above; Chapman et aI., 1980) have
sometimes yielded reduced responsiveness in children.
Other studies have been outlined in Chapman et al. (1980). They stem
directly from those just mentioned but are more obviously naturalistic. As well
as being based in the mobile laboratory several studies have incorporated
observations of children in the playground, in the classroom, and in the school
hall. Like earlier studies, these have invariably included a variety of SUbjective
measures, and occasionally indices of children's joke-telling and humor creation
have also been included. Most studies have embodied a form of replication and/
or extension of those mentioned above. At the same time, additional dimensions
of systematic inquiry have fostered the emergence of new findings. For instance,
facilitation effects were found to be greater when small groups were increased in
size from two to four members, but an increase from four to six produced no
further effect. When shown the same cartoon films, small and large groups
differed in how and where they laughed: not only did members of large groups
(e.g., 50 members) laugh appreciably longer overall, but some of the events
triggering their laughter drew only blank expressions from children in the small
groups. Similarly, repeated presentations of films led to increased laughter in
large but not small groups. There was evidence, too, of a developmental trend in
susceptibility to social influence: with increasing age across the 5- to 8-year-old
range there was an increase in the social facilitation of laughter and smiling.
A combination of mechanisms may account for the facilitation effects (cf.
Chapman, 1973b). For example, the subject's behavioral responses may be
amplified by the companion making the subject more reactive to the humor, by
providing extra eliciting stimuli for laughter, by dis inhibiting responses, and/or
by drawing the subject's attention to humor stimuli that otherwise would have
passed by unnoticed. Attention-gaining and attention-maintaining aspects to
146 Antony J. Chapman
humor and laughter are particularly exercised when situations are experienced
as low in intimacy (cf. Foot et aI., 1977). Conversely an attention-breaking
function may be brought into force when a situation is too high in intimacy. Both
these functions are restorative, deployed to regain a more pleasant level of
intimacy.
We have found an interesting sex difference in this regard: in both like-sex
and mixed-sex dyads/groups boys give the appearance of preferring lower levels
of intimacy than girls, and the attention-gaining/maintaining function is
enforced less by them. It has been our impression that the girls in our research
have generally tended to be more sociable: they have seemed to concentrate
more on the social elements of their environments, while the boys have instead
concentrated more on the humor per se. This impression has been gleaned
during the course of many studies involving several thousands of children aged 4
to II years; that is, across the entire age span studied. The girls tend to be more
attentive to their companions (e.g., in terms oflooking a good deal more at their
faces and in terms of reciprocating reactions and generally sequencing their
behaviors to suit those of their companions), but relative to the boys they are
affected rather little by the age and sex of those companions.
A sex difference in age-of-companion effects was brought out clearly in an
experiment in which 7-year-olds, 9-year-olds, and II-year-olds were paired in
five age combinations (7/7, 7/9, 9/9, 9/11, 11 /11); members of pairs were of
like-sex so that in a 5 X 2 design, sex of dyad was the second independent
factor. Consistent with our usual practice, and again within the constraints of
the design, children were randomly assigned to groups, and test sessions were
sequentially randomized. Care was taken that the members of any dyad were
not acquainted, other than by sight (cf. Chapman, Smith, Foot, & Pritchard,
1979; Foot, Chapman, & Smith, 1979). The children listened to humor, as in
Study II above, and duration and frequency measures were taken for laughter,
smiling, and eye contact (cf. Chapman, Note 5). On none of these measures was
there an age-of-comparison effect for girls. Nor was there any effect for 7-year-
old-boys. However, for 9-and Il-year-old boys, there were effects on all
measures: the 9-year-olds' scores were significantly greater when with com-
panions of the same age or older than when with a younger companion, and the
scores of II-year-old boys were likewise greater with same-age companions
than with younger ones. In this study, as before, the girls seemed more sensitive
to the congeniality of the prevailing social situation. At least in terms of looking
behavior, they were relatively more attentive than boys to their companions and
this was particularly so for those who were assigned younger companions. Sex
differences in the initiation of humor are probably yet more marked (Chapman
et aI., 1980), but we have not studied them extensively. Nonetheless, it is safe to
say that children as young as 7 years regard joke-telling as something of a male
prerogative, and in the company of the experimenter they seemed often to
compete with each other to respond first, to respond most, and even to respond
most effusively.
Humor and Laughter in Social Interaction 147
The presence and behavior of companions, whatever their ages, are usually
so overwhelmingly influential that even the label "humorous laughter" begins to
seem inappropriate: it has to be recognized as something of a misnomer. Humor
may often help to engender laughter but so may other stimuli (cf. Chapman &
Foot, 1976, 1977) and it may be sufficient on only very rare occasions; the
social climate probably has to be right for Pollio et al.'s "explosive" laughter,
otherwise internal amusement may be all that prevails. A "social arousal"
explanation has been advanced (e.g., Chapman, 1975a, 1975b, 1976) in which
it is suggested that "humorous laughter" is instigated to alleviate the
individual's arousal when it reaches uncomfortable proportions in everyday
encounters. In any two-person interaction a ceiling level of intimacy is gradually
attained (Patterson, 1976), but it can be envisaged that the parties involved
occasionally fall out of synchrony: one may begin to promote intimacy rather
more swiftly than the other finds comfortable. The injection of humor into the
conversation allows the other interactant to rapidly diminish his or her
discomfort by laughing. Externally provided humor may serve equally well.
Dissipation of arousal can come about, for example, through momentarily
withdrawing from the conversation and through temporarily reducing the
strength of various nonverbal signals: that is, the eyes can be closed, the head
thrown back, the body turned away, interpersonal proximity decreased, and so
forth. Conversely interactants who work in unison toward a speedy growth in
intimacy can capitalize on joke-telling: this allows them to stare continuously, to
reduce interpersonal distance, and so forth, and it is especially at such moments
that laughter can itself induce and augment laughter in others.
The great virtue of moderating social interactions in this fashion is that the
mid-term and longer-term effects are usually in the direction of boosting
friendliness. An interaction has been pleasantly disrupted, mutually com-
fortable levels of nonverbal responsiveness have been invoked, and the dialogue
is then continued with intimacy again ascending. There are few events as
pleasurable as laughing uproariously at a shared joke, and through germane
humor, appropriately phrased and delivered, one can with some impunity pry
for information, issue rebukes, disclose attitudes, and so on. Also, laughter can
help to alleviate various forms of motivational arousal (Chapman, 1975b;
Levine, 1969), and under most circumstances it is seen as a harmless and
attractive behavior, having connotations of joie de vivre.
The "social arousal" explanation is not intended to encompass theater or
cinema audiences where by design there is considerable attenuation in the
immediacy of social cues normally associated with companionship. In audi-
toriums, small groups of friends and acquaintances sit among strangers, and
some people may be entirely among strangers; all sit in low illumination, and
their seating configurations are impersonal. A professional entertainment aspect
predominates, and presumably there is then a more direct relationship between
quality of comic performance and amount of laughter generated. But a
successful comic does not simply regurgitate a prearranged set of jokes (cf. Fry
148 Antony J. Chapman
& Allen, 1975), that would not be enough to overcome the intrinsic passivity of
the audience and the inert formality of the environment. Most comedians and
comediennes "interact" subtly with their audiences. They may apparently take
those audiences into their confidence and invite everyone, seemingly on an
individual basis, to identify with the predicaments depicted, with the fictitious
protagonists, and with the role they ascribe themselves in the proceedings
described. Typically psychological and socioeconomic features that they have
in common with the audience are accentuated, and they portray themselves as
honest and open characters, or perhaps as naive pawns in events beyond their
understanding. Personal feelings and perhaps preposterous actions may be
divulged. Or at least there is a pretence that all this is so. Hence, for each of
us as members of such an audience, the comic artist seems to be in direct
communication. So it is for each individual, and so it is when any of us is
engrossed with the characters in a film or a book; it is as though we were
there.
For most of us laughter bubbles to the fore only rarely when there is no one
else around. These are occasions when we relive amusing accidents or when in
daydreams we conjure up thoughts of others. Sometimes an author can levitate
us so that we "lose" ourselves in the story and imagine ourselves as first-hand
witnesses to funny events. When we laugh it is as though we were actually
present. Therein lies an explanation as to why laughter, an essentially social
response, can find expression when we are on our own: we may be alone
physically, but we are not alone psychologically-there is, at those moments, a
great deal of incongruence between the physical and psychological environ-
ments.
GROUP INFLUENCES
So far in this chapter, after the introductory remarks, there has been a tacit and
almost exclusive emphasis on research with children. This reflects the slant of
the author's own contributions, though it has been argued that the methodo-
logical implications arising therefrom could apply with equal compulsion to
studies of young and old. It also reflects the fact that research on children's
humor has advanced considerably more than that on adults (cf. McGhee, 1979;
McGhee & Chapman, 1980). In this section of the chapter, the emphasis on
children is maintained as far as possible, but in examining the literature
pertaining to group influences, a broader sweep is necessitated because, against
the drift of other trends, most analyses in their original form refer to adults
only.
In the main, social psychological contributions to the humor literature are
concerned more with group processes than with interaction as such, and aside
from some of the areas of concentrated effort surveyed elsewhere (see Chapter 8
by Fine), the impact of those contributions has been diffuse, not to say
negligible. A tenet of most research, at all levels of social psychological
Humor and Laughter in Social Interaction 149
analysis, is that humor and laughter are linked to communication (cf. Davis &
Farina, 1970; Gruner, 1976, 1978; La Gaipa, 1977; Zillmann, 1977). Even so,
a diverse range of matters has been addressed, relating to structure, content, and
function of humor, and studies are disparate both in conceptual and methodo-
logical domains. In recent times there has been a small but welcome growth of
anthropological and cross-cultural research as well as research at the level of
society (e.g., Goldstein, 1977; Matusewicz, 1976; Wilson, 1979; see also
Chapters 8 & 9).
Although a distinctive social-developmental approach has yet to take form,
many of the functions and processes identified for adults are observable in
children aged 7 years or so (cf. Chapman et aI., 1980). How and when they
begin to emerge is a matter for speculation. Jacobson (1947), for example, has
argued that laughter grows as a social response during childhood. If so, most
development is early in life, for in 7-year-olds one can witness comic activity
constituting an integral part of coping strategies (cf. Coser, 1959; Mechanic,
1962; Milgram, 1965); in many classrooms a "clown" (cf. Goodchilds, 1959;
Klapp, 1950) is easily detected-usually a boy, highly popular, and regarded
with much affection, but not one of the group's leaders; a group's "pecking
order" (cf. Coser, 1960) can be seen in operation, with regard to who is the
target of the humor, who instigates it, and how much response there is from the
group as a whole: and "cognitive similarity" (cf. Wolosin, 1975) within group
members is a factor governing the regularity with which humor is created and
the amount of reaction from group members. As yet no one has suggested for
children, as Wolosin (1975) has done for adults, that different phases in the life
of a group are notable for the differential propensity for laughter. However, we
have formed the impression that children as young as 7 years are able to
manipulate humor to test the standing of their relationships and to help transfer
the group from one stage of development to another (cf. Tuckman, 1965).
Informal observations suggest that still younger schoolchildren can use humor
to induce change in group esteem.
These assertions are derived from informal observations and remain to be
tested, but an experiment on ethnic humor showed convincingly that, like
adults, children as young as 4 years can reveal their group allegiances and
antagonisms by the amount they respond to humor (Chapman, Smith, & Foot,
1977); these results were entirely consonant with Zillmann and Cantor's (1976)
disposition theory of mirth. Adults certainly vary their humor and responsive-
ness according to group identities. For example, in the case of men, a preference
for sexist humor is confined to instances where women are the butts, and for
women there is a corresponding preference for humor in which men are the butts
(e.g., Chapman & Gadfield, 1976).
In a number of studies humor has been shown to have broad implications for
intergroup relations. Although to the proverbial "fly-on-the-wall," a joke may
appear innocuous, it may in fact serve multiple and contrasting functions for
other recipients. For instance, for members of one group, a joke may increase
morale and consolidate them as a group while at the same time sustaining or
150 Antony J. Chapman
NONHUMOROUSLAUGHTER
It has been emphasized elsewhere (e.g., Chapman, in press; Chapman & Foot,
1976, 1977; Giles & Oxford, 1970; Sherman, 1975, 1977), but bears saying
again, that much laughter is generated under circumstances devoid of humor,
and of course not all "humorous laughter" is genuinely shared or pleasurable.
Sometimes "humor" is offensive to certain members of an audience who might
well dispute whether it is actually "humor." It is not uncommon for people to
laugh at others. Probably all of us know how hurtful and debilitating it can be
when on the receiving end of such laughter. Good jokes may be quickly
forgotten (cf. Chapman, 1973a; Chapman & Crompton, 1978), but not so the
occasion when someone laughs at us.
Without devising a total taxonomy of human experience, it may be
impossible to delineate sets of conditions under which laughter is never to be
observed. Laughter can prosper when individuals are oppressed, impoverished,
or in acute pain: those very circumstances may be manna for laughter. As far as
we know laughter can erupt in association with any of the emotions; certainly it
can be witnessed in fear, embarrassment, contempt, and grief, as well as in love
152 Antony J. Chapman
and joy. It has been intimidated that for humorous laughter a "playful mood"
must be a part of the proceedings (cf. McGhee, 1979), but sometimes laughter
can constitute part of a stoic effort to safeguard against loss of face or to disguise
embarrassment. Occasionally, then, it is feigned or forced, and the person's
demeanor is far from light hearted at that time. Such laughter is not likely to be
exuberant and uncontrolled, but some forms of nonhumorous laughter are
extremely effusive: that which can arise from tickling a child is a case in point.
In tickling, the playful attitude is all important, and for anyone child only a
limited number of others may be successful in producing the convulsive forms of
behavior and the total satiation that ensues (Rickwood, 1978).
In other words, in tickling, and in all the other nonhumorous events that can
lead to laughter, the social environment again seems to be more than catalytic.
Even if one considers infancy and the very first laughs that occur, there are
grounds for believing that an appropriate social context is crucial (cf. Sroufe &
Waters, 1976). It has been shown, for instance, that some stimuli, such as a
face mask, can be used on different occasions to evoke both laughter and crying;
which of these behaviors manifests itself depends upon the social context in
which the stimuli are featured. Alas, however, psychological knowledge about
nonhumorous laughter is starkly sparse-even more so than for humorous
laughter. As yet there is no substantial body of empirical research.
REFERENCE NOTES
1. Chapman, A. J. Humor and social responsiveness. Paper presented at the Bi-Annual
General Meeting of the European Association of Experimental Social Psychology,
Weimar (DDR), 1978.
2. Chapman, A. J. Children's humour and laughter. Paper presented to the Annual
Conference of the British Psychological Society, Developmental Section, Durham,
1982.
3. Chapman, A. J. Response to humor or to the social situation? Paper presented to the
Third International Conference on Humor, Washington, D.C., 1982.
4. Chapman, A. J. Children's social interactions in same-age and mixed-age dyads.
Paper presented to the Developmental Section at the London Conference of the
British Psychological Society, 1977.
5. Chapman, A. J. Mixed-age effects in children's social and humor responsiveness.
Paper presented to the Second International Conference on Humor, Los Angeles,
1979.
REFERENCES
Bem, D. J. Self-perception: An alternative interpretation of cognitive dissonance
phenomenon. Psychological Review, 1967, 74, 183-200.
Humor and Laughter in Social Interaction 153
Fry, W. F., Jr., & Allen, M. Make 'em laugh: Life studies ofcomedy writers. Palo Alto,
Cal.: Science and Behavior Books, 1975.
Green, R G., & Gange, J. J. Drive theory of social facilitation: Twelve years of theory
and research. Psychological Bulletin. 1977,84, 1267-1288.
Giles, H. Bourhis, R Y., Gadfield, N. J., Davies, G. J., & Davies, A. P. Cognitive
aspects of humour in social interaction: A model and some linguistic data. In A. 1.
Chapman & H. C. Foot (Eds.), Humour and laughter: Theory, research and
applications. Chichester, Eng.: Wiley, 1976.
Giles, H., & Oxford, G. S. Towards a multidimensional theory ofiaughter causation and
its social implications. Bulletin of the British Psychological Society, 1970, 23,
97-105.
Glaser, A. N. Drive theory of social facilitation: A critical appraisal. British Journal of
Social Psychology, 1982,21,265-282.
Goldstein, J. H. Theoretical notes on humor. Journal of Communication, 1976, 26,
102-112.
Goldstein, J. H. Cross-cultural research: Humor here and there. In A. J. Chapman &
H. C. Foot (Eds.), It's afunny thing, humor. Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1977.
Goodchilds, J. D. Effects of being witty on position in the social structure of a small
group. Sociometry, 1959,22,261-272.
Goodchilds, J. D. On being witty: Causes, correlates and consequences. In J. H.
Goldstein & P. E. McGhee (Eds.),The Psychology of humor: Theoretical perspec-
tives and empirical issues. New York: Academic Press, 1972.
Goodchilds,1. D., & Smith, E. E. The wit and his group. Human Relations, 1964,17,
23-31.
Goodrich, A. J., Henry, J., & Goodrich, D. W. Laughter in psychiatric statT
conferences: A sociopsychiatric analysis. American Journal of Orthopsychiatry,
1954,24,175-184.
Gormly, C. M. R, Chapman, A. J., Foot, H. c., & Sweeney, C. A. Accomodation in
children's mixed-age social interactions. In H. Giles, W. P. Robinson, & P. M. Smith
(Eds.), Language: Social psychological perspectives. Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1980.
Gregg, A., Miller, M., & Linton, E. Laughter situations as an indication of social
responsiveness in young children. In D. S. Thomas (Ed.), Some new techniques for
studying social behavior. New York: Teachers College, 1929.
Gruner, C. R Wit and humour in mass communication. In A. J. Chapman & H. C. Foot
(Eds.), Humour and laughter: Theory, research and applications. Chichester, Eng.:
Wiley, 1976.
Gruner, C. R Understanding laughter: The workings of wit and humor. Chicago:
Nelson Hall, 1978.
Hertzler, J. O. Laughter: A socio-scientific analysis. New York: Exposition Press,
1970.
Jacobson, E. The child's laughter. Psychoanalytic Study of the Child, 1946,2,39-60.
Kane, T. R, Suls, J. M., & Tedeschi, J. Humour as a tool of social interaction. In A. J.
Chapman & H. C. Foot (Eds.), It's afunny thing, humour. Oxford: Pergamon Press,
1977.
Kenderdine, M. Laughter in the pre-school child. Child Development, 1931,2, 228-230.
Klapp, O. E. The tool as a social type. American Journal of Sociology, 1950, 55,
157-162.
156 Antony J. Chapman
Smith, E. E., & Goodchilds, J. D. Characteristics of the witty group member: The wit as
leader. American Psychologist, 1959, 14, 375-376.
Smith, E. E. & Goodchilds, J. D. The wit in large and small established groups.
Psychological Reports, 1963, 13,273-274.
Sroufe, L. A., & Waters, E. The ontogenesis of laughter and smiling: A perspective on
the organization of development in infancy. Psychological Review, 1976, 83,
173-189.
Sykes, A. J. M. Joking relationships in an industrial setting. American Anthropologist,
1966,68, 188-193.
Tajfel, H. Social identity and intergroup behaviour. Social Sciences Information, 1974,
13,65-93.
Tuckman, B. W. Developmental sequence in small groups. Psychological Bulletin,
1965, 63, 384-399.
Van Hooff, J. A. R. A. M. A comparative approach to the phylogeny of laughter and
smiling. In R. A. Hinde (Ed.), Non-verbal communication. Cambridge, Eng.:
Cambridge University Press, 1972.
Weaver, S. M. Mild social stress and human performance: the role of competition,
evaluation and the presence of others. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, University
of Durham, 1978.
Wilson, C. O. A study of laughter situations among young children. Unpublished
doctoral dissertation, University of Nebraska, 1931.
Wilson, C. P. Jokes: Form, content, use and junction. London: Academic Press,
1979.
Wolosin, R. J. Cognitive similarity and group laughter. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 1975. 32, 503-509.
Young, R. D., & Frye, M. Some are laughing: Some are not-why? Psychological
Reports, 1966, 18. 747-754.
Zenner, W. Joking and ethnic stereotyping. Anthropological Quarterly, 1970, 43,
93-113.
Zillmann, D. Humour and communication: Introduction. In A. J. Chapman & H. C.
Foot (Eds.), It's a funny thing. humour. Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1977.
Zillmann, D., & Cantor, J. R. A disposition theory of humour and mirth. In A. J.
Chapman & H. C. Foot (Eds.), Humour and laughter: Theory, research and
applications. Chichester. Eng.: Wiley, 1976.
Chapter 8
Most humor and laughter imply a social relationship, a connection between self
and other. Just as one cannot tickle oneself, so, too, one can hardly tell oneself a
joke or playa prank on oneself. A jocular event typically requires a minimum of
two persons to succeed-or, for that matter, to fail. Although I shall not argue
whether an event is funny if there is no one present to observe it, any adequate
understanding of the dynamics of humor must include a social analysis.
Despite the importance of a social approach to humor, sociologists have not
studied humor with anything like the frequency or fervor of their colleagues in
psychology. Humor has not been the legitimate subject area in sociology that is
has been in psychology. Part of the reason for this difference is related to the
way in which humor has been treated in the two disciplines. In psychology,
jokes or cartoons can be used effectively as experimental stimuli, and these
stimuli are easy to administer to subjects. Since the primary concern of the
psychologist is the reaction of the individual to the stimuli, the social
relationship is not important; the social relationship that does exist-that
between the subject and the experimenter-is typically ignored (for exceptions
see Davis & Farina, 1970; Shurcliff, 1968). The sociologist typically examines
the social context of humor. Although this generalization does not apply to all
types of humor research in sociology, at the very least the social context must
implicitly be taken into account. This increases the difficulty of research. No
longer can humorous stimuli be given to individual subjects, but rather the social
forces that influence the creation and appreciation of humor must be
considered.
It is not true that few sociological studies of humor have been published.
Although the number does not approach those in psychology, over the past 40
160 Gary Alan Fine
years there has been a steady, if small, stream of articles that examine humor as
social communication. In this chapter I shall provide a brief description of the
major traditions of sociological research on humor. With the growth and
increased specialization of sociology, there has been a modest growth in the
number of humor studies (most recently by scholars who can be classified as
belonging to the symbolic interactionist tradition), but at the same time there
have been fewer studies dealing with humor in the leading sociological journals.
In the period 1942-1959 there were six articles dealing with humor in the
American Sociological Review and the American Journal of Sociology, the
two leading American sociological journals. Since 1959 there has not been an
article primarily on humor published in either; the sociology of humor is not
defined as a topic of general interest for scholars in sociology.
Still, there have been several attempts to apply sociological theory to humor.
Perhaps this represents part of the problem with this subfield. Humor
researchers typically take established sociological traditions and attempt to
apply them to humor rather than generating new theories. Among the areas
where humor research has been conducted in sociology are: the relationship
between humor and social roles, the nature of joking relationships, the
contextual rules of humor performance, ethnomethodological approaches to
humor and laughter in conversation, humor and group culture, reference group
theory, humor and ethnic group relations, and humor and social control. This
diverse array of topics indicates that humor is a tool that can be used in
numerous ways and has implications for understanding many corners of our
social environment.
Humor is by its nature an indication of some sort of discontinuity in the social
system. This discontinuity is what gives humor its power and, indeed, its humor.
As Murray Davis astutely notes: " ... I contend that sociologists without a
sense of humor will never be able to understand the workings of the social
world, for humor separates its seemingly seamless joints, making them visible,"
(Davis, 1979, p. 109). Whether we call this visibility of the seemingly seamless
joints bisociation (as does Koestler, 1964) or incongruity, it is apparent that
humor reflects a contrast in meaning between two incompatible views of a
scene. Humor results from the audience resolving these two conflicting images
in a way that makes sense, given the distorted logic of humor. Humor is a
puzzle, a problem that must be solved for mirth to result. That humor can be
thought of in terms of incongruity, however, does not mean that that is the only
way in which it can be viewed. Some argue that incongruity alone is not
sufficient for humor, although most agree that there needs to be some element of
surprise for a remark to be considered humorous. However, other possible
motivations have been proposed for humor that are more directly sociological or
psychological, whereas the incongruity model is primarily grounded in treating
humor as a text.
The two most common alternative models for humor involve thinking of it as
arising out of a sense of superiority (the Hobbesian view, which has most
forcefully been stated recently, by Gruner, 1979) or as reflecting relief in being
Sociological Approaches to the Study of Humor 161
Within most societies there are roles or positions that are conducive to the
display performance of humor. Some people are allowed to joke and others are
even expected to joke. In this chapter I will examine four roles commonly
encountered in American culture: the fool, the clown, the joker, and the
comedian. Although these roles overlap, there is enough that distinguishes them
to treat them separately.
The Fool
The fool has had a long and one might even say a distinguished history
throughout the world. It is common to think offools in light of their roles at court
functions, in terms of Medieval European fools-such as Lear's fool in
Shakespeare's King Lear. However, I shall not describe the literary, historical,
or anthropological position of the fool (see Welsford, 1935; Willeford, 1969).
The fool is a figure of fun, who derives much of his humorous power from the
fact that he actually is, or is playing the role of someone who is "foolish" or
intellectually insufficient. Much of the humor of the fool role comes from the
combination of his public stupidity with his insight.
Klapp (1962), in discussing major social types in American life, names the
fool, along with the hero and the villain. In an early article, Klapp (1949)
suggests that there are 10 types of fools, distinguishable on the basis of their
behavior: (l) antic fool, (2) comic fool, (3) rash fool, (4) clumsy fool, (5)
deformed fool, (6) simple fool, (7) weak fool, (8) comic butt, (9) pompous fool,
and (10) mock hero. In his later book (1962), he limits the categories to five,
divided on the basis of the fool's functions:
1) incompetents (clumsy, rash, simple, weak) who illustrate and penalize ludicrous
role failures;
2) types which discount people who claim more than they have, thus correcting
certain status-abuses and pretensions;
3) non-conforming types which ridicule deviants and outsiders;
4) overconformers who suffer comic rebuke because they have been too enthusiastic
in complying with group standards; and
5) certain types (especially comic butt, clever fool) having conspicuous functions as
outlets for aggressive tension.
(Klapp, 1962, p. 69).
162 Gary Alan Fine
Because of Klapp's concern with depicting the fool as a social type, he does not
describe what fools actually do; rather, he presents the symbolic images of the
fool and connects these images to prominent figures who might be seen as fools
of various types. For Klapp, fool types reveal our national character. People are
what they laugh at, and, through laughing, they are engaging in social control
and in unifying themselves through "the communion of laughter." Daniels and
Daniels (1964) claim that the fool role is a tolerated deviant type. As such, the
"career fool" has rules of conduct that differ from the rules applied to others.
The career fool has a "licensed freedom." For this freedom the fool has to be
willing to be the butt of jokes and the target of laughter. People do not just show
disrespect for the fool; they admire what the fool can get away with-
particularly the license that he has with his superiors (for example, in the
military). Daniels and Daniels conclude that: "The fool can be the embodiment
of each man's wish to escape from the full burden of responsibility which he
carries" (1964, p. 227). Because of his privileged position, the fool has a special
power.
The Clown
Closely related to the fool in popular terminology and global scope (e.g.,
Charles, 1945) is the clown. Indeed, we may use the two terms interchangeably
to describe an acquaintance. The clown, however, has the second meaning of a
performer, as in circuses (for a structural, semiotic analysis of clowns see
Bouissac, 1976; see Tarachow, 1951 for a psychoanalytic view). Whether one
sees the circus clown as mediating between cultural order and natural disorder,
between the adult and the child, or between joy and sadness, there is something
about the clown's behavior that is both realistic and absurd. Unlike most comic
actors, there is a basic sadness in the clown's behavior-a sense that the clown
is almost part of "polite" society, but not quite. The keying for this
clownishness is, in the circus, the makeup that the clown wears, a throwback to
tribal society and perhaps a reaffirmation of cultural evolution. In everyday
interaction, the clown and the fool are virtually identical, with clowns being
most similar to Klapp's functional categories one and three: Incompetents and
Nonconforming Types. However, many clowns wish to appear clownish; their
clowning behavior is more deliberate than is true of many fools.
Bales (1970) categorizes group members into 27 personality "types" based
on the dimensions of Dominance versus Submission (Upward-Neutral-
Downward), Affectivity (Positive-Neutral-Negative), and Task-Oriented ver-
sus Emotionally Expressive (Foward-Neutral-Backward). He sees the clown as
Upward and Backward (UB):
The [UBI member ... seems ascendant and expressive, nontask oriented, perhaps
unconventional or even deviant. He seems neither clearly friendly nor unfriendly, but
entertaining. joking. dramatic, relativistic. free in his associations, taking pleasure in
Sociological Approaches to the Study of Humor 163
play, activity, novelty, and creativity. In the realization of his own values he seems to
be trying to move toward value-relativism and expression of underlying emotions and
feelings. "Life is more a festival than a workship for moral discipline." (p. 245)
Bales notes that suffering may be part of this individual's social role. Continual
joking places a strain on the social system, just as does continual seriousness.
The clown may find his act inappropriate if used too frequently or with too great
intensity, because, as Bales notes, it prevents the group from achieving its task-
oriented goals.
Some people have a humorous remark for all occasions. Their witty or sarcastic
remarks put a situation into a perspective-a perspective that often diminishes
the situation's significance. As Duncan (1962) notes, humor is a "passage by
incongruity from one view to another which society provides as an escape from
the crushing weight of traditions or the painful anxiety developed by conflicting
loyalties" (p. 257). Jokers lift, at least temporarily, this "crushing weight" and
so can be important members of a group (Davis, Gebhard, Huson, & Spaeth,
1961).
There is evidence that the wit or joker is typically a high status group
member, often dominant and gregarious, and strongly influences the direction of
group interaction (Dunphy, 1969; O'Connell, 1969). The wit appears not only
to be a definite personality type (see Chapter 4 by Fisher and Fisher in Volume
II) but also to have a clear social role (Cloyd, 1964; Goodchilds, 1959, 1972;
Goodchilds & Smith, 1964; Smith & Goodchilds, 1959). Goodchilds and
Smith made a distinction between the sarcastic wit and the clowning wit, finding
the former more influential than the latter. Further, there is evidence that groups
that contain a deliberate wit do better on a problem-solving task than do groups
without such wits (Goodchilds & Smith, 1964). This is possibly due to the
joker's introduction of new ideas for others to react to.
Insufficient research has been conducted on the practical joker to understand
the social role of this person. Of course there are different types of practical
jokers varying in the humor and viciousness of their jokes (see Grotjahn, 1957).
Like jokes generally, practical jokes provide a diversion for the group and may
promote group solidarity (Posen, 1974; Scott, 1974; Roy, 1959-1960).
The Comedian
Recently books and articles have been written about the background of the
comedian (Fry & Allen, 1975; Janus, 1975; Fisher & Fisher, 1981) and some
has been written about comedic style (see Pollio & Edgerly, 1976). Perhaps
more important to the sociologist of humor is how comedians go about making
164 Gary Alan Fine
HUMOR IN CONTEXT
Joking Relationships
see also Homans, 1950; White, Boorman, & Brieger, 1976}, the now classic
study of industrial sociology. In the bank wiring room, workers joked with each
other, played tricks on each other, and otherwise had a good time in the course
of the workday, as much as was possible given the constraints of the situation.
Perhaps the most influential study of joking in a factory was the participant
observation conducted by Roy (1959-1960; see Handelman, 1976). Roy found
that one set of machine operators had developed a quite intricate set of joking
norms and procedures by which they structured the workday and dealt with
potential personal conflict and strains. These joking occasions came to be
ritualized, such as "banana time" (the memorable title of Roy's article), which
consisted of one worker stealing another worker's banana-an event that
occurred each day at nearly the same time. While the ritualized quality of the
joking day is surprising (but see Nickerson, 1974) and is due to the isolated
conditions in which these men worked, joking relationships are found among
peers in all occupations. Studies of department store clerks (Bradney, 1957),
coal miners (Vaught & Smith, 1980), mental hospital employees (Coser, 1960),
and printing-press workers (Sykes, 1966) have yielded similar findings showing
that workers kid and joke with each other to relieve the tedium of the work.
These findings are consistent with the finding in the "sociology of work" that
there is always an "underside" or unofficial aspect to any job.
Contextual Rules
Joking is a strategic activity. By that I mean that not everyone canjoke about all
topics in all situations. Joking must be understood in light of the presentation of
self that one is displaying in the joke and in light of the expectations of one's
audience.
Defining the situational rules for joking is difficult in that the standards for
appropriate joking are not explicit and may not even be known consciously. The
appropriateness of joking depends on the situation. Since jokes can be used to
define both situations and selves (Fine, 1983), one should examine the goals of
humor. Jokes that are designed to "put down" another person will differ in
content depending on whether that person is present. If the target is present,
such jokes typically maintain a veneer of diplomacy covering their message; if
the target is absent, such niceties can be ignored and replaced by brutal
sarcasm. Although jokes are used to focus on uncomfortable topics (such as
dying), making them acceptable or manageable, the joker must be very careful
to ensure that the joke does not irreparably destroy any social relationships
(Emerson, 1969). While jokes create social meanings (e.g., Zijderveld, 1968),
such social construction must occur on a solid foundation.
There are circumstances in which people expect to laugh and as a result
almost anything will receive a laugh. This is particularly true at some comedy
performances at which the audience has a prior positive attitude to the
Sociological Approaches to the Study of Humor 167
comedian and on certain occasions among friends when they find that they can't
control their giggling (what Fry, 1963, calls a "humor orgy"). In such
circumstances one might say that people have become sensitized to laugh, and
that they do so with vigor and gusto.
Researchers have analyzed specific contextual components of humor such as
status and sex roles. With regard to the former it is well established that humor
is more often directed down the status hierarchy than up it, particularly in light
of formal role relations. Coser's (1959) now classic analysis of humor in a
psychiatric staff conference demonstrates that doctors were far more likely to
make jokes at the expense of nurses or interns than the reverse (see also
Goodrich, Henry, & Goodrich, 1954). The superiority theory of humor (cf.
Gruner, 1979) claims that a joke is basically an attack, and even those who
refuse to accept this perspective completely cannot deny that much humor does
contain aggressive elements. From this it is apparent that a joke that is publicly
aimed at a superior is a rare and fragile thing. Yet, humor can be used by
superiors to promote rapport with subordinates (Malone, 1980), or by
psychiatrists with patients (Greenwald, 1977; Mindess, 1976; O'Connell,
1976).
Humor is also a strategic tool to communicate sexual desire between men and
women; however, the only published studies examine how men communicate
with women through laughter and jokes. Davis and Farina (1970) demonstrated
experimentally that men laugh more at risque jokes when they are told by an
attractive female than when they are told by an unattractive female. An
ethnographic study indicates how risque jokes operate in context. Walle (1976)
investigated the so-called "bar rush," that time near closing when men search
for women to "pick up." Walle suggests that the shift from an impersonal to a
personal relationship can be facilitated through humor. By communicating
through sexual humor the man can gauge the woman's willingness for additional
contact without having a direct invitation rejected. If the jokes produce a
positive response, the male assumes (often correctly) that the woman is open to
intimate contact. Even if the jokes are rejected. the man at least keeps some
measure of self-esteem in that the woman did not reject him-just his jokes.
Humor also plays a role in establishing community. Just as obscene humor
can gauge sexual availability, so it can be used to indicate that one is a
knowledgeable member of a social group. In a study of preadolescent joking
(Fine, 1982), I found that obscene humorous talk was a regular part of
preadolescent life, and that it served as a marker for indicating that the speaker
was competent in those sexual areas that preadolescents believe characterize
adult life. Such remarks, however, are localized in time and space; pre-
adolescents are careful to ensure that their adult guardians are absent before
they make overtly sexual jokes. Sexual joking, in addition to demonstrating
communitas, also provides a setting in which boys can learn about sexual
matters without revealing their ignorance "seriously." While some serious
discussions of sexual behavior do occur, much material is transmitted in joking
encounters (Fine. 1982. 59-66).
168 Gary Alan Fine
Conversational Analysis
Perhaps the group of sociological researchers who have given humor and
laughter the greatest amount of "serious" attention are ethnomethodologists and
conversational analysts. They ask how listeners know that there is a call for
laughter at the end of a skein of talk-how can people make sense out of these
strange, ambiguous things that we call humor, laughter, and smiling?
What is a smile? Kinesthetist Ray Birwhistell ( 1970) notes that while smiling
appears to be universal in all cultures, the rules for smiling must be learned.
Specifically he suggests that smiles do not overrule context-that is, that a smile
must be appropriate to the context; it doesn't change the context or meaning of a
situation. Birdwhistell notes that just saying that someone smiled doesn't mean
much:
heheh in some slot that makes it an inappropriate intrusion is one way to suggest
the foolishness of some first speaker-as when one gigles during a story in
which a speaker expects sympathy for an interactional error. In short, hehehs
can accomplish complex interactional ends by communicating messages
(Schenkein, 1972, p. 371).
Implicit in conversational analysis is the assumption that one's behaviors are,
if not consciously chosen, at least precisely regulated in a way that would seem
to exclude random or accidental behavior. Ironically, conversational analysis
that is supposedly an offshoot of ethnomethodology and phenomenological
sociology is one of the most deterministic of sociologies, although the source of
this determinism is typically not specified.
In addition to laughter, jokes have been analyzed by conversational analysts,
most notably Harvey Sacks. Sacks (1975, 1978) analyzed a single "dirty joke"
told by one teenage boy to two others. He demonstrates that this joke follows
conventions of talk and is an "artful" piece of narrative. By this Sacks means
"that not only is it ... elaborately organized, but that some aspects of its
elaborate organization can be found to be occupied with the following kind of
job: concealing some of the ways the joke works on its recipients from those
recipients, while directing them to attend to it in rather sharp ways" (1978, p.
250). Without detailing Sacks's subtle argument about the significance of this
joke about oral sex, the argument is that jokes are highly complex constructions
that may operate (somehow-the motivation is not clear) in ways that the
participants don't quite realize and that carry with them a considerable subtlety
of knowledge about the construction of stories generally (parallel construction)
and the construction of dirty jokes in particular (secondary meanings). In this
joke, the boys are refering to the meanings that marriage, sexuality, and oral-
genital interactions have for them. Even minor details such as pauses, internal
laughter, or attribution can provide the basis for making the narrative
meaningful. At the heart of the ethnomethodological analysis of humor is the
belief that all talk is meaningful, and that only a close reading of the text can
provide the analytic insight necessary to peel away the seeming randomness of
talk.
Humor can provide a symbolic resource for various kinds of groups. Anyone
who has participated in a group for any length of time can attest to the fact that
certain remarks come to characterize groups, and often these remarks are in the
form of jokes or witticisms. As Abrahams (1978) notes:
... [A]s soon as a group begins to sense its enduring "groupness" through both
shared goings on and the expectation of what is to come (as in waiting in a queue
170 Gary Alan Fine
overnight or being stranded at an airport for days), the development of new expressive
lore will go from small items to larger ones; special in-group terms Uargon, slang,
cant), nicknames, proverbs, superstitions and situated joking will arise. (p. 23)
I have termed the localized culture of a group its idioculture, specifying it as "a
system of knowledge, beliefs, behaviors, and customs shared by members of an
interacting group to which members can refer and employ as the basis of further
interaction" (Fine, 1979, p. 734). Members find that they share experiences in
common and these experiences can be referred to with the expectation that they
will be understood by other members of the group and can be used to create
meaning in the group. Humor is particularly useful in this way in that it allows
the group to deal collectively with a wide range of content that could not be
expressible otherwise (Fine, 1977).
The power of the group culture can be recognized by anyone who enters a
group that has been in existence for some time. Most groups, particularly those
characterized by informality, develop a set of joking references that may be
unrecognizable to those outside the group (Domhoff, 1974). Thus, the ritual of
"banana time" is meaningless unless one had been a part of the group
(Handelman, 1976, Roy, 1959-1960). Nowhere is this more apparent than in
the study of Boontling (Adams, 1971), a secret language created by a group of
men in the Northern California town of Boonville. This group was apparently
close friends, and it was easy to see how the nucleus of the secret language could
develop. The primary functions of Boontling were that it was an enjoyable
linguistic game to play, that speakers could make humorous remarks about
nonspeakers without their being aware of what was being said, and that
nonusers could be made to make linguistic gaffes, such as the example of how a
middle-aged female was lured to use the Boontling world for bear manure
("beartrack") to refer to a berry cobbler (Adams, 1971, p. 28).
How does a humorous remark come to characterize a group and to be used by
them? I have proposed five mechanisms through which humor enters the
idioculture of a group (Fine, 1977). First, for a remark to become part of an
idioculture its content must be comprehensible to the group. While the remark
need not have been heard in that form, it must, after the fact, make sense. Ajoke
about a subject of which an audience is totally unaware will not provoke a smile,
unless the subject matter is fully explained within the joke. Second, the remark
must be usable in the group context-not taboo or otherwise offensive.
Dropping one's trousers might in some circumstances be wildly amusing, but in
other groups would be shocking or sexually arousing. Third, the humorous
remark must be functional. It must support a goal toward which members are
striving (e.g., relief or social control). The humorous remark must also be
appropriate in light of the friendship and power relations in the group (as
discussed above). Humor typically supports the status hierarchy of the group.
Finally, the humorous remark must be "triggered." Numerous potentially
humorous remarks might meet the four other criteria, but only a few actually
Sociological Approaches to the Study of Humor 171
enter the idioculture of a group and are repeated sufficiently often that they
come to characterize the group. A triggering mechanism is defined as an event
that produces humor; because of the huge range of events that could potentially
trigger humor, this suggests that the a priori prediction of the humor culture of a
group is impossible and reminds us of the situationally grounded character of
humor.
Probably no other area in the sociology of humor has received as much attention
as has the relationship between reference groups and humor. Sociologists
(Hyman, 1942; Merton, 1968; Sherif, 1936) claim that an individual views the
world from a social frame of reference; this framework is often derived, at least
in part, from the groups to which he/she belongs. The first study that examined
the effect of group affiliation on humor was conducted 50 years ago by Wolff,
Smith, and Murray (1934). They attempted to determine whether there were
differences between the responses of Jews and gentiles to jokes that disparaged
Jews. In accord with their expectations, the researchers found that anti-Jewish
jokes were funnier to gentiles than to Jews. For the gentiles, the Jews in the
jokes were "unaffiliated objects" and, thus, liable to being made fun of, while for
Jews the Jewish butts had a positive valence. The investigators then attempted
to substantiate their hypothesis with regard to "unaffiliated objects." They
argued that if the Jews in the humor were replaced by another group, there
should be no differences between Jews and gentiles in the humor ratings. The
anti-Jewish jokes were changed to anti-Scottish jokes, a change that made sense
since the original humor dealt with the shared negative stereotypes of greed and
stinginess. The researchers discovered to their surprise that Jews found these
anti-Scottish jokes less humorous than did non-Scottish gentiles. The authors
had not considered that subjects could identify with groups of which they were
not members. They comment in a post hoc analysis that "one type of affiliation
was based upon resemblance-affiliation by similiarity-to the extent that
subjects who are conscious of possessing a trait enjoy hearing that trait praised
in others and dislike hearing it debased" (Wolff et aI., 1934, p. 361).
Following in this tradition, Middleton (1959) explored the subcultural
variation in humor by comparing the appeal of racial jokes disparaging blacks
and whites to matched groups of subjects of both races. Middleton assumed that
white subjects would react more favorably than blacks to antiblack humor, and
conversely, that black subjects would be more receptive than whites to antiwhite
jokes. In fact, Middleton found that black subjects reacted more favorably to
antiwhite jokes than did white subjects, but, counter to prediction, black subjects
reported enjoying the antiblack humor no less than did whites. Apparently racial
172 Gary Alan Fine
groups are (were) membership groups to which subjects would not necessarily
psychologically relate as reference groups.
LaF ave (1961; see also 1972) attempted a more extensive test of reference
group theory. He presented written religious jokes to each of four groups of
subjects. Each subject group consisted of members from one of four religious
sects: Southern Baptists, Catholics, Jehovah's Witnesses, and agnostics.
Subjects evaluated jokes that contained dialogue between representatives of two
(of the four) presumably antagonistic groups. LaFave's results supported his
vicarious superiority hypothesis. Jokes tended to be judged as relatively funny
by those individuals whose reference group was esteemed and whose out-group
was disparaged, and conversely, not funny by those whose reference group was
disparaged and out-group esteemed. Further, jokes that esteemed a person's
reference group were preferred to those esteeming a nonreference group;
likewise, jokes lampooning a person's reference group were judged unfunny
relative to those belittling one of the out-groups.
Since the early 1960s a large number of studies have attempted, usually
successfully, to expand and replicate Lafave's findings. Studies of political
attitudes have been particularly common (Linsk & Fine, 1981; Priest, 1966;
Priest & Abrahams, 1970; Zillmann, Bryant, & Cantor, 1974). These studies
generally found that one enjoys jokes aimed at one's political foes better than
those aimed at one's friends. Similar findings have emerged from studies on
attitudes toward feminism (La Fave, et aI., 1976; Priest, 1972). Other studies
have examined student sit-ins (La Fave, Haddad, & Marshall, 1975),
Canadian-American relations (La Fave, McCarthy, & Haddad, 1973), and
relations between professors and students (La Fave, Haddad, & Maesen,
1976). While researchers disagree as to whether there is a curvilinear
relationship between the vitriol of attacks against an out-group and humor
appreciation (Priest, 1972; Zillmann & Bryant, 1974) or a linear relationship
(La Fave, et aI., 1976), there is general agreement that reference group theory
(by whatever name: disposition theory, identification class theory, or social
identification theory) helps to explain the evaluation of group-directed humor.
There is evidence that the reference group effect applies not only to the
evaluation of humor, but to the perception of the actual target of humor as well.
Linsk and Fine (1981) found that when presented with potentially ambiguous
cartoons, subjects were more likely to define them as attacking a group that they
denigrated rather than one that they supported. This finding of perceptual
selectivity was more pronounced for political attitudes (liberalism-
conservatism) than for support for women's liberation. In the latter case,
perceptual selectivity only applied to male respondents but not to females, who
showed the expected evaluation effect.
These studies support the notion that meaning is read into humor, rather than
necessarily being present all along. As LaFave, Haddad, and Maesen (1976)
comment: "Nothing is funny to everyone and anything seems potentially funny
to someone" (p. 85).
Sociological Approaches to the Study of Humor 173
Cohesion
One of the first goals of any group is to remain unified in the face of a variety of
actual or potential forces that might disrupt or threaten it. Groups under stress
may develop a sense of humor as a response to this threat. Perhaps the most
obvious example of this phenomenon is "gallows humor." Gallows humor is
that humor that grows out of a tragic situation in which an oppressed group
attempts to transform their misery by poking fun at their oppressors. Actually
the term "poking fun" may be misleading in that the humor is bitter and
corrosive but has the effect of making all the group members realize that they
are in the same situation, thus indirectly building their confidence. The classic
study of gallows humor by Obrdlik (1942) describes the humor of the Czech
freedom fighters battling long odds against the Nazi invaders and their Czech
collaborators. Similar analyses have suggested that humor performed a
cohesive role among concentration camp inmates (Kogon, 1958) and in the civil
rights movement (Arnez and Anthony, 1968).
Often if the members of one group laugh at the actions of another group, it
serves to integrate the first group, through what Dupreel (1928) calls "the
laughter of inclusion." This laughter need not only apply to oppressed groups
but can be a cohesive device for any social group. Miller (1967) in his
examination of a Chippewa Indian tribal council found that one of their
categories of humor is humor that promotes group solidarity. He notes that this
humor is directed internally through testing, mutual ribbing, good fellowship,
and even humorous self-deprecation. In a spirit of harmony, the group realizes
that the fact that they are able to laugh at each other's foibles indicates that they
have a trusting, communal relationship. Likewise, the fact that there is shared
laughter is a social marker that indicates that group members share a common
perspective (Dresser, 1967) and, hence, reduces the ambiguity about the moral
boundries of the group (Davies, 1982). We can think of laughter as communi-
cation of approval from the laugher to the teller of the joking remark, and in
174 Gary Alan Fine
cases in which there is loud, long, and unanimous laughter, the message is that
there is consensus on the message of the joke.
Rather than discuss these two social functions of humor separately, it makes
sense to view them together in that they are often found in the same remark, and
whether they serve functions of control or conflict can depend on the way in
which the humor is used. These functions are analogous to the reference-group
effect described above. Both deal with an individual's orientation to a group,
and for both the affective relationship to a group makes the joke or the humorous
response appropriate or inappropriate. Whereas the reference group analysis
focuses on the internal attitudes and perspectives of the individual, the conflict!
control perspective focuses on the public behaviors of group members.
Many sociologists (Martineau, 1967, 1972; Stephenson, 1951) have argued
that humor serves two major social functions: social conflict and social control.
Conflict humor includes such forms as: irony, satire, sarcasm, burlesque,
caricature, and parody. It is indirect aggression and serves to separate a group
from an undesireable, deviant out-group and may even provoke hostility by that
group, as in the case of satiric remarks designed to anger the opposing group
(see Elliot, 1960).
The control function of humor, and incidently laughter (Lumley, 1925), is
aggressive as well. It differs, however, in that it does not divide or separate
groups but attempts to make group members accept group norms and disavow
deviance, often through ridicule (Powell, 1977). As Highet ( 1962) comments:
"The purpose of satire is, through laughter and invective, to cure folly and
punish evil" (p. 156). The "kidding" that occurs among friends may well be an
example of this kind of humor. Although overtly nonpunitive, it reveals the
expectations that friends have for each other (Fine, 1983).
Martineau (1972) differentiates between in-group and out-group directed
humor. Depending on the type of humor (esteeming or disparaging), humor may
control in-group behavior, foster demoralization and social disintegration ofthe
group, or induce a hostile attitude toward an out-group. The outcome of the
humor depends on the position of the teller, his attitude to the target group, and
the social situation.
The group functions of humor have been particularly studied for the civil
rights movement. Arnaz and Anthony (1968) see "Negro humor" as social
satire and argue that the items a group laughs at reflects their culture. This
humor may serve three purposes: ( 1) a satire of the customs of the group, akin to
a control function; (2) public humor, poking fun at the group, that serves control
functions and also relieves the aggression that others feel toward them-in this
case reducing conflict; and (3) social satire that the in-group directs at their
foe-that produces social solidarity and may also increase conflict. The
analyses of black humor over the past 50 years suggests that one of the
Sociological Approaches to the Study of Humor 175
Depending on the circumstance, interethnic joking may bind the two groups
together or may serve to separate them and provoke conflict.
CONCLUSIONS
REFERENCE NOTES
1. Tomlinson, G. The contextualization of humor. Unpublished manuscript, 1977.
2. Jefferson, G., Sacks, H., & Schegloff, E. Preliminary notes on the sequential
organization of laughter. Unpublished manuscript, 1973.
REFERENCES
Abrahams, R. D. Deep down in the jungle. Revised Edition. Chicago: Aldine, 1970.
Abrahams, R D. Towards a sociological theory of folklore: Performance services. In
R H. Byington (Ed.), Working Americans: Contemporary approaches to occu-
pational folklife. Washington: Smithsonian Folkore Studies, Number 3, 1978.
Sociological Approaches to the Study of Humor 177
Fine, G. A. Humor in situ: The role of humour in small group culture. In A. J. Chapman
& H. C. Foot (Eds.), It's a funny thing, humour. Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1977.
Fine, G. A. Small groups and culture creation: The idioculture of Little League baseball
teams. American Sociological Review, 1979,44,733-745.
Fine, G. A. The natural history of preadolescent male friendship groups. In H. Foot,
A. J. Chapman, & J. Smith, Friendship and social relations in childhood.
Chichester, Eng.: Wiley, 1980.
Fine, G. A. Impression management and preadolescent behavior. In S. Asher &
J. Gottman (Eds.), The development of children's friendships. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1981.
Fine, G. A. Rude words: Insults and narration in preadolescent obscene talk. Maledicta,
1982,5,51-68.
Fine, G. A. Humorous interaction and the social construction of meaning: Making sense
in a jocular vein. In N. K. Denzin (Ed.), Studies in symbolic interaction (Vol. 5).
Greenwich, Conn.: JAI Press, 1983.
Fisher, S., & Fisher, R L. Pretend the world is funny and forever: A psychological
analysis of comedians, clowns, and actors. Hillsdale, N. J.: Lawrence Erlbaum,
1981.
Fry, W., Jr. Sweet madness: A study of humor. Palo Alto, Cal.: Pacific, 1963.
Fry, W., Jr. & Allen, M. Make 'em laugh. Palo Alto, Cal.: Science and Behavior Books,
1975.
Goodchilds, J. D. Effects of being witty on position in the social structure of a small
group. Sociometry, 1959,22,261-272.
Goodchilds, J. D. On being witty: Causes, correlates, and consequences. In J. H.
Goldstein & P. E. McGhee (Eds.), The psychology of humor. New York: Academic
Press, 1972.
Goodchilds, J. D., & Smith, E. E. The wit in his group. Human Relations, 1964, 17,
23-31.
Goodrich, A. J., Henry, J. & Goodrich, D. W. Laughter in psychiatric staff conferences:
A sociopsychiatric analysis. American Journal of Orthopsychiatry, 1954, 24,
175-184.
Greenwald, H. Humor in psychotherapy. In A. J. Chapman & H. C. Foot (Eds.), It's a
funny thing, humour. Oxford: Pergamon Press, 1977.
Gruner, C. Understanding laughter. Chicago: Nelson-Hall, 1979.
Hammond, P. B. Mossi joking. Ethnology, 1964,3,259-267.
Handelman, D. Re-thinking "banana time": Symbolic integration in a work setting.
Urban Life, 1976, 4, 433-448.
Hannerz, U. Soulside. New York: Columbia University Press, 1969.
Highet, G. The anatomy of satire. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1962.
Homans, G. C. The human group. New York: Harcourt, Brace and World, 1950.
Hyman, H. The psychology of status. Archives of Psychology, 1942,38, 1-94.
Janus, S. S. The great comedians: Personality and other factors. American Journal of
Psychoanalysis, 1975,35, 169-174.
Jefferson, G. A technique for inviting laughter and its subsequent acceptance declina-
tion. In G. Psathas (Ed.), Everyday language: Studies of ethnomethodology. New
York: Irvington, 1979.
Klapp, O. E. The fool as a social type. American Journal of Sociology, 1949, 55,
157-162.
Klapp, O. E. Heroes, villains, and fools. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1962.
Sociological Approaches to the Study of Humor 179
Welsford, E. Thefool: His social and literary history, London: Farber & Farber, 1935.
White, H., Boorman, S., & Brieger, R. Social structure from multiple networks, I.
Blockmodels of roles and positions. American Journal of Sociology, 1976, 81,
730-780.
Willeford, W. Thefool and his scepter: A study in clowns and their audience. Evanston,
Ill.: Northwestern University Press, 1969.
Wolff, H. A., Smith, C. E., & Murray, H. A. The psychology of humor, I. A study of
responses to race-disparagement jokes. Journal ofAbnormal and Social Psychology,
1934,28, 341-365.
Zenner, W. Joking and ethnic stereotyping. Anthropological Quarterly, 1970, 43,
93-113.
Zijderveld, A. C. Jokes and their relation to social reality. Social Research, 1968,35,
286-311.
Zillmann, D., & Bryant, J. Retaliatory equity as a factor in human appreciation. Journal
of Experimental Social Psychology, 1974,10,480-488.
Zillmann, D., Bruant, J., & Cantor, J. R. Brutality of assault in political cartoons
affecting humor appreciation. Journal of Research in Personality, 1974, 7,
334-345.
Chapter 9
MAHADEV L. APTE
The objectives of this paper are the following: (1) to outline the state of the art of
humor research in terms of its nature and scope in anthropology; (2) to examine
methodological issues in the general area of anthropological research and their
impact on humor research; and (3) to discuss anthropological contributions to
theoretical developments in humor research.
Anthropology is a broad discipline and includes archaeology, linguistic
anthropology, physical anthropology, and sociocultural anthropology. How-
ever, this paper will be restricted to humor research in sociocultural anthro-
pology. Archaeology has no direct relevance to the study of humor, and the
focus of humor research in physical anthropology has been on investigating the
phylogenetic aspects of laughter and smiling as expressions of emotions among
higher primates (Andrew, 1963, 1965; Eibl-Eibesfeldt, 1970; Van Hooff,
1972).
and range of variation among sociocultural systems over time and space; and
( 4) to develop general theories about numerous aspects of human sociocultural
existence. These objectives are not separate but interdependent and mutually
reinforcing. However, each objective involves different methodologies and
perspectives.
The first objective involves detailed ethnographic data gathering pertaining to
individual cultural systems and subsequent analysis and description. Anthro-
pological literature is full of ethnographic accounts obtained by participant
observation of individual societies and cultures from all corners of the world.
The holistic approach, so fundamental to sociocultural anthropology in the
study of individual sociocultural systems, is based on the rationale that
particular aspects of such systems cannot be understood in isolation but only as
parts of the whole. It is the integration of many aspects that makes the system
operative and functional.
The second and third objectives entail comparisons of different cultural
systems for the purpose of developing generalizations and formulating hypo-
theses. Such comparisons may be limited in nature, involving just a few
cultures, or they may be extensive, involving many cultures from different parts
of the world. While anthropologists discuss universals, they recognize that
"true" universals do not exist simply because all human societies in the world
have not been described. Nonetheless, the goal is to strive for broad-based
generalizations about cross-cultural uniformities by developing hypotheses from
the comparison of even a few cultures, then testing them by examining
additional cultures. Comparisons also lead to an awareness of differences
among cultures (Kobben, 1970).
The last objective, which is the culmination of the others, is to develop
general theories to explain the diverse and multifaceted nature of human
existence and the underlying common biological and psychological foundations.
Such theory building involves: (1) formulation of conceptual categories useful
for analyzing and explaining individual cultures; (2) development of broad
typologies that help determine the range and scope of-cross-cultural variation;
(3) development of hypotheses and generalizations that enumerate not only
properties common to human sociocultural systems but also interconnections
between their structural elements; and ( 4) hypotheses that explain why specific
aspects are characteristic of some cultures but not of others.
institutionalized joking within the context of kinship and other types of social
relationships; humor in religion; description and analysis of tricksters, the
mythological and folkloristic figures considered ludicruous: linguistic humor,
especially verbal banter, insults, riddles, and so forth; and in recent years, the
nature and sociocultural significance of play and games. In addition, brief and
sporadic descriptive accounts of humorous episodes, types of humor, attitudes
toward humor, appropriate or inappropriate humor in various social inter-
actions, techniques used in humor, and so forth, are scattered in ethnographies
of many cultures. The focus of such accounts is not the analysis of humor per se,
but its relevance to other aspects of culture.
Among the five topics mentioned above, the first three have received
considerable attention by anthropologists. The existing anthroplogicalliterature
pertaining to each topic is summarized below with special emphasis on some
broad trends.
is that between nephew and maternal uncle. Generally, the nephew takes all
kinds of liberties with his uncle who bears them without retaliation for a variety
of reasons. Kin-based joking relationships also occur among potential sexual or
marriage partners in many societies. For instance, cross cousins who are
preferential marriage partners in many African cultures joke freely with each
other and engage in sexual exchanges and horseplay. Joking relationships
between men of certain kinship categories are common as are those between
men and women. However, existing literature indicates that women rarely
establish kin-based joking relationships with other women.
In preliterate and traditional societies in Africa there also occur joking
relationships between clans, tribes, and villages. These actually exist between
individuals belonging to different clans, tribes, or villages that collectively have
relations of either hostility or dependence and reciprocity. In the case of clans it
may depend on whether their totem objectives either complement or oppose
each other. For instance, among the Amba people of Northern Rhodesia,
persons from the Crocodile clan have joking relationships with members of the
Fish clan and those of the Snake clan with those of the Grass clan
(Stephaniszyn, 1950). Colson (1953) and Stephaniszyn (1950) give lists of
such paired clans having joking relationships. A related and important aspect of
such interclan joking relationships is mutual assistance in making funeral
arrangements in the event of the death of either partner. Therefore such
relationships are also called "funeral friendships." Funeral friends joke about
such arrangements as they do about each other's clan objects. They also take
extreme liberties in mutual insults by way of referring to each other's sexual
organs. According to Stephaniszyn (1950), not all individuals take advantage of
existing opportunities to form interclan joking relationships, especially those
based on funeral friendships.
While anthropologists have used the term "joking" to describe diverse
behavioral interactions among individuals, many ethnographic descriptions of
such behavior raise doubts about whether the interaction is indeed joking.
Often, what is described appears to be cruel and harrassing. Even when joking
takes place it is ritualized and conventional rather than spontaneous and
innovative. As Sharman (1969) has noted, it is even debatable in some
instances whether anthropologists studying joking behavior were really inter-
ested in humor. Rather, they were interested in the significance of joking
relationships to social structure, and the study of humor per se had no place, at
least originally, in such anthropological research.
Existing studies of nonkin joking relationships in industrial societies suggest
that these occur in the context of workplace such as offices of white-collar
workers (Howell, 1973), hospitals (Coser, 1960), factories (Handelman &
Kapferer, 1972; Lundberg, 1969; Sykes 1966), department stores (Bradney,
1957), and shipyards (Pilcher, 1972) or in the context of informal social
gatherings (Loudon, 1970; Malefijt, 1968). The major attribute of nonkin joking
relationships is that they are voluntary in nature and are oriented toward
specific individuals with both partners willing to establish them. Friendship is
188 Mahadev L. Apte
often their basis. While nonkin joking involves sexual teasing, innuendos, and
some horseplay, one specific study emphasizing the sexual nature of such
relationships in a factory (Sykes, 1966) suggests that those who engage in
obscene joking and horseplay in public are not likely to have sexual
relationships in private.
In general, joking occurring in nonkin relationships appears to be creative
rather than ritualized. It also seems to be conducive to group solidarity and
identity. While women in appropriate kinship categories in pre literate societies
do not seem to develop joking relationships, those in industrial societies do
establish joking relationships with other women.
In order to indicate the nature of anthropological studies of joking relation-
ships, two studies are summarized below, one of kin-based and another of the
nonkin type. Hammond (1964) has described joking relationships among the
Mossi in the Voltaic Republic of West Africa. There occur the following types
of joking relationships among the Mossi: (1) between a man and his mother's
elder brothers and their wives; (2) between a man and his wife's sisters, and
between a woman and her husband's brothers; (3) between clans; (4) between
males who belong to the same age sets; (5) between certain villages; and (6)
between Mossi and other ethnic groups. Hammond lists separation, reciprocity,
ambivalence, equality, and independence as the five structural features that
characterize the relationships between joking partners.
While Hammond discusses all of the types listed above, he gives a more
detailed description of what he calls sibling-in-Iaw joking. Married men and
women joke with their spouses' siblings when they visit. Such joking generally
involves humorous deriding of the sibling-in-Iaw's appearance, lack of energy,
skill at work, intelligence, or ability to perform household chores such as
cooking satisfactorily. Those being derided cannot take offence but can joke
back in similar fashion. Hammond's major observation is that while such joking
may appear to be for pleasure, it serves the function of a person indirectly
communicating dissatisfaction with his/her spouse's work, appearance, be-
havior, and so forth. In other words, while joking is carried out with a sibling-in-
law, it may actually be aimed at one's spouse. Direct criticism of one's spouse is
generally avoided because the potential for marital conflict is high due to clan
exogamy, the considerable age difference between husbands and wives, stress
due to polygyny, subordinate status of women, and possible dissatisfaction of a
wife's parents at the inadequacy of bride-wealth payments (Hammond, 1964,
p. 264). Hammond concludes on the basis of his analysis that the function of
joking relationships among the Mossi is social control, reduction of frustration
without face-ta-face conflict, and maintenance of communication.
Pilcher (1972) conducted an ethnographic study of the community of
longshoremen and their families working and living in and around Portland,
Oregon. He found that joking behavior among longshoremen was closely linked
to the work place and was characterized by blasphemy, cursing, obscenity,
insults, and nicknames. Pilcher emphasized that obscenities used by long-
shoremen to address each other did not express hostility, but rather suggested
Humor Research, Methodology, and Theory in Anthropology 189
"friendship, affection, and warm personal feelings" (p. 103). Thus the "mutual
vituperation" of the workers expressed "exactly the opposite of its overt
meaning" (p. 103).
As soon as men arrived at the docks before the start of work and gathered in
the lunchroom, they began to insult each other, and there developed a
competition of who could come up with the most vile insult. Combined with
verbal assaults there were bodily assaults that were carried out so realistically
as to fool outsiders. However, the longshoremen themselves perceived such
actions as merely games from which to derive a good deal of enjoyment. An
important aspect of this joking behavior was that it was not carried out in front
of family members, women, or any schoolchildren visiting the docks.
It was theorized by Pilcher that joking relationships and related behavior
among longshoremen were the result of work-related tension due to the danger
of working on ships, which created irrational anger and aggression. Joking
behavior was the accepted way of releasing this tension and controlling
aggression. Pilcher felt that this function of joking fitted quite well in the
framework suggested by Radcliffe-Brown (1940, 1949), namely, that joking
behavior controls real aggressive and antagonistic feelings so that a "stable
system of social behavior may be maintained through group solidarity"
(p. 112).
chasing women and young girls, and pretending phallic advances toward them
are common practices of ritual clowns among American Indian tribes as well as
in African and Asian cultures. Simulated or real consumption of feces and urine
or water mixed with mud is also part of such humor, as is exaggerated
performance of defecation and urination.
Humor in religion also involves burlesque of foreigners and of those in
authority. The latter seems a way of social control since such burlesque often
criticizes those who did not carry out their official duties properly or were
arrogant and high handed. Burlesque of foreigners satisfies collective ethno-
centrism.
In American Indian cultures the privilege of ritual clowning is generally
restricted to members of clown societies, secret fraternities, and sodalities.
Those who act as clowns often have a high status. They are also associated with
supernatural spirits and are believed to have special magical and healing powers
(Makarius, 1970). During religious ceremonies among the American Indian
cultures, clowns serve other functions such as keeping order, gathering materials
needed for ritual activities, and so forth. Young men who wish to act as clowns
have to serve as apprentices for some years before they are recognized as full-
fledged ritual clowns.
Ritual humor occurring among American Indians in Mexico and the
southwestern United States has been described by many anthropologists
(Bourke, 1891; Bricker 1973; Crumrine, 1969; Parsons & Beals, 1934; Titiev,
1975). The following is a summary of ritual clowning from Crumrine (1969)
who has described and analyzed its occurrence during the Easter ceremonial
among the Mayo Indians in Mexico. Crumrine has also presented a general
theory explaining the occurrence of ritual clowning among American Indians on
the basis of his description and analysis. Only the descriptive part of his paper
is summarized below.
Ritual clowns among the Mayo Indians belong to a sodality, dress in an
unusual fashion, and wear helmet-type masks made of goat or sheep hide. Most
masks are worn with the long black, white, or brown hair of the hide on the
outside and have "long, narrow pointed ears, a long pointed nose, and a face
area cleared of hair with painted eyes and mouth" (Crumrine, 1969, p. 3). The
clowns cover themselves with a large white cloth sewed to a blanket, wear khaki
color pants, leather belts with deer or goat hoof rattles around their waists, and
strings of cocoon rattles around their lower legs to support their pants. They
carry wooden knives and swords, which they clack together to attract attention;
others carry drums, violins, toy guns, balls, or small wooden phalli. Overall, a
ritual clown's dress creates "a striking, troubling, and intriguing creature." They
also have" a characteristic shaking motion, slightly like a dog shaking off water,
which sets in motion all their rattles" (p. 3).
These ritual clowns engage in burlesquing many activities. They parody
marriage ceremonies in which one clown impersonates a female, takes the arm
of another, and the two march with great pomp from the end of the church to the
center of the altar while being teased and pestered by a third clown. As soon as
192 Mahadev L. Apte
the "marriage" at the altar is over, they engage in horseplay, pressing their
masks together several times creating the "realistic illusion" of kissing and then
pantomime sexual intercourse as the female clown lies on the floor. The clowns
imitate animal sexual behavior during which one climbs on the back of another
with much bouncing and shaking of the cocoon rattles. They hold the wooden
phalli they carry between their legs and suggestively play with them.
Illness and curing activities are also burlesqued. One clown pretends to eat a
tomato and "immediately falls to the floor, writhing with pain. He grasps his
stomach, his chest or his legs" (p. 2). By rattling he attacts the attention of other
clowns who gather around him, massage his body, and poke him in the
stomach.
The clowns tease the participants in the ceremonial. They engage in contrary
behavior such as crossing themselves with the left instead of the right hand.
They are also preoccupied with oral and anal behavior. They pretend to feed
themselves feces, use a rubber doll's foot at the end of their wooden swords to
poke around the other clowns' anuses. Such "goosing" is frequent. A clown
carrying a glass baby bottle with a rubber nipple sucks it, sticks it up to the anus
of another and sucks it again. The clowns even pretend to "defecate" upon the
sacred objects.
Different historical explanations have been proposed by anthropologists for
the existence of the institution of ritual clowning among American Indians.
Beals has suggested that ritual impersonation and humor existed among the
Indians of Mexico and southwestern United States before their contact with the
Spanish missionaries and their subsequent conversion to Christianity. Parsons,
on the other hand, suggests that ritual clowning was introduced by the Spanish
conquests (Parsons & Beals, 1934). Interestingly, contrary behavior, a major
aspect of ritual humor, occurs in many African cultures (Norbeck, 1963;
Turner, 1964) and also during religious ceremonies among the Hindus in South
Asia (Marriott, 1968; Miller, 1973).
been many, originating with Boas (1898) and continuing until the present
(Abrahams, 1968; Boas, 1914; Carroll, 1981; Levi-Strauss, 1955; Lowie,
1909; Radin, 1914, 1952, 1956/1969; Ricketts, 1964, 1966; Schemerler,
1931; Thompson, 1946, 1966; Vogelin, 1949).
Studies of tricksters from areas of the world other than North America are
relatively few. Luomala (1949) has presented a detailed analysis of the trickster
from Oceania called Maui. Evans-Pritchard (1967) has edited an anthology of
Zande trickster tales from East Africa. Herskovits and Herskovits (1958) have
analyzed the tales of two tricksters from Dahomean oral literature. Finnegan
(1970) has evaluated the trickster characters from the narratives of many
African cultures. Only a couple of comparative studies of the trickster theme
from different parts of the world have been undertaken. Street (1972) has
compared the Zande and Winnebago tricksters and Apte (Note 1) has
presented a detailed analysis of the trickster concept, taking into consideration
tricksters from many parts of the world.
Tricksters are male personages of unusual origin and are considered to be
immortal. They are anthropomorphic or theriomorphic in shape, have unusual
anatomical and physiological traits, behave in incongruent ways, and display
strange personalities. Among American Indians, tricksters have been identified
with the bluejay, coyote, hare, mink, and raven. In African cultures, such
animals as the antelope, jackal, spider, squirrel, tortoise, and weasel are
portrayed as tricksters (Finnegan, 1970). Individual trickster figures are
assumed to possess the physical characteristics of the specific animals
associated with them. However, most tricksters are capable of transforming
themselves into any object, animal, or human. They also possess anatomical
and physiological incongruities such as a grotesque form, intestines outside the
body, a long penis wrapped around the body, eyes that are uneven and both
inside and outside the sockets, and so forth. Tricksters also lack a sense of unity
and coordination of their body parts. They generally have an insatiable appetite
for food and sex and have little or no control over the body processes of waste
elimination.
Most trickster tales consist of the advantures tricksters engage in to satisfy
their basal desires. They steal, cheat, injure, or even kill animals and humans
and seduce women to achieve their goals. They do not hesitate to behave in
ways that are taboo, deviant, outrageous, and generally antisocial. However,
tricksters do not always succeed in achieving their goals. They are frequently
outsmarted by others or they suffer the consequences of their own stupidity.
While individual tricksters in different cultures seem to be characterized by
specific personality traits, it is possible to extrapolate some common ones. Most
tricksters are pranksters and egotistical. They are clever, selfish, cruel,
deceitful, cunning, and sly. However, they are also boastful, foolish, lazy,
inordinate, and ineffective. They are infantile, lack restraints and social
responsibilities, are prone to blunders, and lack the ability to distinguish
between good and evil. They get distracted easily from what they set out to do
and often lose sight of their objectives.
194 Mahadev L. Apte
Ethnographic Research
Anthropologists who invest their time, energy, money, and so forth, into
choosing a field site and going there are likely to retain their chosen setting and
change their research plans rather than the other way around (LeVine,
1970).
Ethnographic research is exploratory and open-ended because fieldwork on
which it is based is unstructured, at least in the early stages when the
ethnographer has to adjust to the reality of living in another culture. Despite the
new emphasis on "scientific rigor" and on objective and standarized procedures
for ethnographic research (Pelto & Pelto, 1978), a personal approach whereby
an investigator immerses himself in a culture in order to empathize and
communicate with its members is still preferred by many sociocultural
anthropologists (Honigmann, 1976).
These trends plus the highly elusive nature of humor suggest a personalized,
unstructured approach in studying it in the field. The ethnographic study of
humor, in my view, should be exploratory in nature and should be open-ended.
The lack of substantive data on many aspects of humor in specific cultures is not
conducive to the development of specific hypotheses that can be tested. Thus,
while it is possible to undertake fieldwork to study only humor, the actual
investigation should remain open-ended as opposed to being restricted just to
humor.
including the ethnographer, greetings, and overall positive feelings and attitudes.
There is much subjectivity, subtlety, and intuition involved in properly
interpreting the expressions of smiling and laughter, and a personal approach is
inevitable. Generally, extreme degrees of smiling or laughter may suggest
humor stimuli, but the ethnographer nevertheless needs to verify such an
assumption.
Ethnographers have traditionally grappled with the issue of how many
instances of a cultural phenomenon need to be witnessed or how many
informants need to have reported it to claim that a pattern exists. Whiting and
Whiting (1970) have suggested stability of the behavior over time and paired
comparisons in which one individual consistently exhibits a certain behavior
when interacting with another as possible criteria for pattern establishment.
This issue is closely related to sampling. While the best sample for pattern
discovery may be a random one, Honigmann (1970) is of the opinion that the
nonprobability sampling method is widely used and is acceptable in anthro-
pology. He prefers a "judgment sampling" where the ethnographer selects
informants with distinctive qualifications such as occupational status, sex, age,
length of residence in the community, and so forth. This provides more valid
data than "opportunistic sampling" where the ethnographer depends only on
those people with whom he becomes familiar in the exploratory stages of his
fieldwork. Unfortunately ethnographers tend to rely on opportunistic sampling
for their data. In this connection Honigmann (1976) is of the opinion that the
major criterion in pattern establishment is the ethnographer's confidence in the
generalization he develops, which is traditionally inductive in nature.
Some scholars (Agar, 1980; Middleton, 1970) have suggested the role of
learner or of a student! child for the ethnographer in order to find out the patterns
of culture. In such a role, the ethnographer may unintentionally or deliberately
commit many faux pas and thus may become the butt of humor in the field
situation. Exploiting such instances for questioning and getting information and
opinions should help the ethnographer to discover notions of appropriate
patterns of behavior, appearance, role playing, and customs, and the values and
ideologies supporting them. Therefore, the learner's role is useful to an
ethnographer studying humor as is evident from accounts provided by some
anthropologists (Bohannan, 1966; Boissevain, 1970; Chagnon, 1968; Lee,
1969).
It has generally been accepted in anthropology that certain kinds of
ethnographic data gathered by the technique of participant observation are
subjectively conceptualized and cannot always be quantified. Therefore, pattern
establishment and development of generalizations is a matter of personal
judgment. Such is often the case with regard to humor. The kinds of controlled
experiments conducted by psychologists in their humor research are neither
possible nor feasible in the actual field setting of ethnographic research.
Observation, careful recording, constant checking and rechecking of infor-
mation, sensitivity to informants' comments, intuitive judgments regarding the
plausibility of explanations offered, constant reformulation and reconceptuali-
Humor Research, Methodology. and Theory in Anthropology 201
Comparative Studies
is based on available ethnographic data from several cultures and posits many
hypotheses that emphasize cross-cultural uniformities and differences in humor
and the interconnections of humor to other sociocultural factors. In particular,
these hypotheses pertain to such topics as: joking relationships; nature of the
trickster; relationship of language use and attitudes to development of linguistic
humor; the role of performance in humor; differences between men's and
women's humor; and the relationship between socialization processes and
children's humor. In order to go beyond this first comprehensive comparative
treatment of humor in anthropology, what is needed is the gathering of extensive
detailed ethnographic data on humor from many more cultures, systematic
analyses of humor phenomena in individual societies, and careful, well-
conceived comparative studies that use systematic methodology.
Joking Relationships
hostility, release of tension, and avoidance ofreal conflict. Even earlier Lowie
(1920) proposed that the major function of the joking relationship was social
control. Other proposed functional theories of the joking relationship include
emotional catharsis and indirect communication (Hammond, 1964), release of
sexual impulses and aggression (Murdock, 1949), pure entertainment and
drama (Kennedy, 1970), social etiquette and screening procedures for group
membership (MalefIjt, 1968), release of strenuous and dangerous work-related
tension (Pilcher, 1972), symbolic indicators of strong affinal ties (Freedman,
1977), exclusiveness of association (Stevens, 1978), a badge of group identity
(Lundberg, 1969), and exploration of potential closeness in social relations
(Howell, 1973). This list of functional explanations is by no means complete.
Many of the above anthropologists consider their theories to be global. While
some (Freedman, 1977; Stevens, 1978) have proposed only unitary functional
explanations, others (Hammond, 1964; MalefIjt, 1968; Radcliffe-Brown, 1940,
1949) have proposed multiple ones. It is not clear in the case of those who
propose several functional theories whether each joking activity serves all
functions, or if the context determines the function. The possibility that different
types of joking relationships may have different functions has not been taken
into account.
Most functional theories are merely inferred. Thus they are speculative and
hypothetical in nature and have not been empirically validated. Many of them
have been inductively developed as they are often based on observations and
analysis of joking relationships in a single culture.
Another drawback of anthropological theories of both kin-based and nonkin
joking relationships is that the concept of friendship and its importance in joking
relationships, especially nonkin relationships in industrial societies, has not
been satisfactorily studied.
Humor in Religion
Trickster Tales
Such scholars as Boas ( 1898), Ricketts (1964, 1966), and Radin (1969) have
proposed that the trickster figures, which are configurations of opposite roles,
are found primarily in societies in the earlier stages of cultural evolution, such as
hunting! gathering ones. As cultures move to the agricultural state, the two roles
get separated, the figures become purely tricksters, and they occupy a less
important place than culture heroes in the oral literature of agricultural
societies.
General Comments
CONCLUSIONS
The objectives of this paper were to present briefly the nature and scope of
anthropological research, methodology, and theories of humor and to empha-
size the many problems inherent in humor research in anthropology. Sugges-
tions were made for future anthropological research on humor with the hope that
researchers will broaden their horizons by attempting to gather ethnographic
data on many aspects of humor in numerous sociocultural domains hitherto not
208 Mahadev L. Apte
REFERENCE NOTE
1. Apte, M. L. Humor and laughter: An anthropological perspective. Book in
preparation, 1983.
REFERENCES
Abrahams, R. D. Trickster, the outrageous hero. In T. P. Coffin (Ed.), Our living
traditions: An introduction to Americanfolklore. New York: Basic Books, Inc., 1968.
Agar, M. H. The professional stranger. New York: Academic Press, 1980.
Amarasingham, L. R. Laughter as cure: Joking and exorcism in a Singalese curing
ritual. Doctoral dissertation, Cornell University, 1974.
Andrew, R. J. Evolution offacial expression. Science, 1963, 142, 1034-1041.
Andrew, R. J. The origins of facial expressions. Scientific American, 1965,213,88-94.
Beidelman, T. O. Utani: Some Kaguru notions of death, sexuality and affinity.
Southwestern Journal of Anthropology, 1966,22,354-380.
Berreman, G. D. Behind many masks. Ithaca, NY: The Society for Applied
Anthropology, 1962, Monograph No.4.
Boas, F. Introduction. In J. Teit (Ed.), Traditions of the Thompson River Indians of
British Columbia. Memoirs of the American Folklore Society, 1898,6,1-18.
Boas, F. Mythology and folktales of the North American Indians. Journal ofAmerican
Folklore, 1914,27,374-410.
Bohannon, L. Shakespeare in the bush. Natural History, 1966, 75(7), 28-33.
Boissevain, J. Fieldwork in Malta. In G. D. Spindler (Ed.), Being an anthropologist:
Fieldwork in eleven cultures. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1970.
Bourke, J. G. Scatological rites of all nations. Washington: W. H. Lowdermilk and
Company, 1891.
Bradney, P. The joking relationship in industry. Human Relations, 1957, 10, 179-187.
Brant, C. S. On joking relationships. American Anthropologist, 1948, 50, 106-162.
Bricker, V. R. Ritual humor in highland Chiapas. Austin: University of Texas Press,
1973.
Broude, G. J. and Greene, S. J. Cross-cultural codes on twenty sexual attitudes and
practices. Ethnology, 1976, 15,409-429.
Brukman, J. "Tongue play": Constitutive and interpertive properties of sexual joking
encounters among the Koya of South India. In M. Sanches and B. Blount (Eds.),
Sociocultural dimensions of language use. New York: Academic Press, 1975.
Humor Research, Methodology, and Theory in Anthropology 209
Carroll, M. P. Levi-Strauss, Freud, and the trickster: A new perspective upon an old
problem. American Ethnologist, 1981, 8, 301-313.
Chagnon, N. Yanomamo: The fierce people. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston,
1968.
Charles, L. H. The clown's function. Journal of American Folklore, 1945, 58,
25-34.
Codere, H. The amiable side of Kwakiutl life: The potlatch and the play potlatch.
American Anthropologist, 1956, 58, 334-351.
Colson, E. Clan and the joking-relationship among the Pleateau Tonga of Northern
Rhodesia. Kroeber Anthropological Society Papers, 1953, 10, 45-60.
Coser, R L. Laughter among colleagues: A study of social functions of humor among the
staff of a mental hospital. Psychiatry, 1960, 23, 81-95.
Crumrine, N. R. Capakoba, the Mayo Easter ceremonial impersonator: Explanations of
ritual clowning. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religon, 1969,8, 1-22.
Edgerton, R B. and Langness, L. L. Methods and styles in the study of culture. San
Francisco: Chandler and Sharp, 1974.
Eibl-Eibesfeldt, I. Ethology: The biology of behavior. New York: Holt, Rinehart and
Winston, 1970.
Ember, M. Taxonomy in comparative studies. In R Naroll and R Cohen (Eds.), A
handbook of method in cultural anthropology. Garden City, N.Y.: Natural History
Press, 1970.
Evans-Pritchard, E. E. Some collective expressions of obscenity in Africa. Journal of
the Royal Anthropological Institute of Great Britain and Ireland, 1929, 59,
311-331.
Evans-Pritchard, E. E. The Zande trickster. London: Oxford University Press, 1967.
Finnegan, R Oral literature in Africa. London: Oxford University Press, 1970.
Freedman, 1. Joking, affinity and the exchange of ritual services among the Kiga of
Northern Rwanda: An essay on joking relationship theory. Man, 1977, 12, 154-165.
Gluckman, M. The role of the sexes in Wiko circumcision ceremonies. In M. Fortes
(Ed.). Social structure. New York: Russell and Russell, 1963.
Goody, J. R The mother's brother and the sister's son in West Africa. Journal of the
Royal Anthropological Institute, 1959,89,61-88.
Hammond, P. B. Mossi joking. Ethnology, 1964,3,259-267.
Handelman, D. and Kapferer, B. Forms of joking activity: A comparative approach.
American Anthropologist, 1972, 74, 484-517.
Herskovits, M. J. and Herskovits, F. S. Dahomean narrative. Evanston, Ill.:
Northwestern University Press, 1958.
Hieb, L. A. The Hopi ritual clown: Life as it should not be. Doctoral dissertation,
Princeton University, 1972.
Hill, W. W. and Hill, D. W. Navaho coyote tales and their position in the Southern
Athabascan group. Journal of American Folklore, 1945, 58, 317-343.
Hoebel, E. A. Anthropology. New York: McGraw-Hill Book Company, 1966.
Honigmann, J. J. An interpretation of the social-psychological functions of the ritual
clown. Character and Personality, 1942, 10, 220-226.
Honigmann, J. J. Sampling in ethnographic field work. In R Naroll and R. Cohen
(Eds.), A handbook ofmethod in cultural anthropology. Garden City, N.Y.: Natural
History Press, 1970.
Honigmann, J. J. The personal approach in cultural anthropological research. Current
Anthropology, 1976, 17, 243-261.
210 Mahadev L. Apte
Middleton, J. Entry into the field: Africa. In R. Naroll and R. Cohen (Eds.), A
handbook of method in cultural anthropology. Garden City, N.Y.: Natural History
Press, 1970.
Miller, D. B. Holi-Dulhendi: Licensed rebellion in a North Indian village. South Asia,
1973,3, 15-22.
Moore, F. W. (Ed.), Readings in cross-cultural methodology. New Haven, Conn.:
HRAF Press, 1961.
Moore, F. W. The human relations area file. In R. Naroll and R. Cohen (Eds.), A
handbook of method in cultural anthropology, Garden City, N.Y.: Natural History
Press, 1970.
Moreau, R. E. Joking relationships in Tanganyika. Africa, 1943, 14, 386-400.
Murdock, G. P. Social structure. New York: The Macmillan Co., 1949.
Nadel, S. F. A black byzantium. London: Oxford University Press, 1946. (Originally
published in 1942.)
Nadel. S. F. Nupe religion. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1954.
Naroll, R. and Cohen, R. (Eds.), A handbook of method in cultural anthropology.
Garden City, N.Y.: Natural History Press, 1970.
Nimmo, H. A. Bajau sex and reproduction. Ethnology, 1970,9,251-262.
Norbeck, E. Religion in primitive society. New York: Harper and Brothers, 1961.
Norbeck, E. African rituals of conflict. American Anthropologist, 1963,65,1254-1279.
Norbeck, E. Religion in human life: Anthropological views. New York: Holt, Rinehart
and Winston, 1974.
Norbeck, E., and Ferrar, C. R. (Eds.) North American Indian clowns and creativity.
1977 Proceedings of the American Ethnological Society. New York: West Publishing
Company, 1979.
Opler, M. E. Myths and legends of the Lipan Apache Indians. Memoirs of American
Folklore Society, Vol. 36. New York: J. J. Augustin, 1940.
Parsons, E. C. and Beals, R. L. The sacred clowns of the Pueblo and Mayo-Yaqui
Indians. American Anthropologist, 1934, 36, 491-514.
Pelto, P. 1. and Pelto, G. H. Anthropological research: The structure of inquiry. New
York: Cambridge University Press, 1978.
Pilcher, W. W. The Portland longshoremen: A dispersed urban community. New York:
Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1972.
Radcliffe-Brown, A. R. On joking relationships. Africa, 1940, 13, 195-210.
Radcliffe-Brown, A. R. A further note on joking relationships. Africa, 1949, 19,
133-140.
Radin, P. Religion of the North American Indians. Journal ofAmerican Folklore, 1914,
27, 335-373.
Radin, P. (Ed.). Africanfolktales and sculpture. New York: Bollingen Foundation, Inc.,
1952.
Radin, P. The trickster. New York: Greenwood Press, 1969. (Originally published in
1956.)
Ray, V. F. The contrary behavior pattern in American Indian ceremonialism.
Southwestern Journal of Anthropology, 1945,1,75-113.
Ricketts, M. L. The structure and religious significance of the trickster-transformer-
culture hero in the mythology of the North American Indians. Doctoral dissertation,
University of Chicago, 1964.
212 Mahadev L. Apte
HOWARD R. POLLIO
Every theory both depends upon and attempts to explain a particular set of facts
or observations. It seems fair, for example, to say that Hobbes considered a
deformed person or someone slipping on a wet street as crucial for his theory of
humor and that Bergson had something like a marionette or a jack-in-the-box in
mind. Kant saw the unexpected denouement of a clever comic remark as crucial
whereas Freud openly admitted that, for the case of sexual humor at least, he
was thinking about a smutty joke told by men of breeding in the presence ( either
real or imagined) of a lady of breeding. Each theorist started from a different
reference point and the specific nature of these starting points has served to
provide each theory with its own unique orientation and assumptions.
Similarly, the theory offered in the present paper grows out of a particular set
of questions and concerns. Although most of these seem to deal with the
underside of human life-that is, the taboo, the profane, the scatalogical, the
hostile- I offer them with the justification that it was the data and not personal
perversity that made me choose them as central to a theory of humor.
1. Why are successful, professional comedians paid so much money and why
do we honor them so little? Why do they often tend to come from minority
groups?
2. Why are sex and aggression major themes for evoking loud and long laughter
and why are word play and/or intellectual incongruity not nearly as powerful
or successful?
3. Why should humor about taboo topics produced by peers or by professional
comedians evoke more laughter (and be judged as funnier) in a group of
friends than in a group of strangers?
214 Howard R. Pollio
In his book, The Act of Creation (1964), Koestler offered a diagram very much
like the one in Figure 10-1 to express his understanding of laughter and the
Notes toward a Field Theory of Humor 215
We simply do not know how to define ourselves except in relation to other members of
our species. If we reject, therefore, the standards of one group, we will soon accept the
standards of another. The moment of choice is a moment of heightened self-
awareness, but that moment is, and will always be, fleeting.
The spirit of humor is synonymous with that moment. It is iconoclastic. It is
rebellious ... Its joy is the joy of release, and release is exciting only as reaction to the
constricting conditions out of which it is born. (1971, pp. 40-41)
iftheir response to the joke was a "proper" one and if their cohorts responded in
the same way. Although some degree of social constraint is experienced in a
group of friends, it is a good deal less intense than in groups of strangers.
These results and observations suggest that we laugh at taboo jokes not only,
or even primarily, because we have overcome an "internal" source of inhibition
as Freud (1905/1960) seemed to suggest, but because we have overcome
constraints in the here-and-now of our contemporary situation. Comedians and
other purveyors of laughter generally tackle taboo topics for just this reason:
They mean to highlight the specific, and sometimes arbitrary, social forces that
constrain our world. Although we may talk about the hostility of a comedian
like Don Rickels we realize that he is only exploding the ordinary conventions
of social interactions-conventions that at one time or another have coerced us
all-and in so doing he frees us from them for the moment. The comedian
ordinarily has a natural safeguard built into his/her antics in that most jokes or
comic remarks are brief and it is this brevity that both allows them to elude
social constraint (as Freud said long ago) as well as to minimize any experience
of personal discomfort we might have in laughing at them. The hostile comedian
offers us a trade-off: a moment of discomfort for a moment of freedom.
Profane/sacred clowns, to come now to our fourth question, also use the fact
that laughter provides momentary freedom from constraint. Here, however, the
clown-priest is attempting to let other members of his society know that he (as
priest) understands that the various prohibitions and religious rules of the
society are confining and that people might wish to be free ofthem. By attacking
them in ritual, comic form he asserts they are difficult, he asserts he knows you
want to be free of them, and he asserts they are necessary. The close
relationship between the sacred and the profane is one in which a mocking of
sacred rules reinforces their sanctity and the comic-priest (and his cohorts)
know and respect this even as their humor ceremonies provide temporary relief
from prohibitions significant to the group. Be defaming the sacred, the comic-
priest publicly recognizes the difficulty of observance and, in so doing, reasserts
the moral order. "Even as he (the comic fool) plays out his deviant role, he
serves as a defining boundary of what is proper ... (and) ... may have the
effect of encouraging the stability of a system by preventing it from going too far
in anyone extreme direction" (Fisher and Fisher, 1981, p. 192).
This analysis further strengthens the hypothesis that laughter must be
considered not only in terms of its meaning for an individual but also in terms of
its meaning for other people. Bergson (1911/1956) undoubtedly had this in
mind when he wrote that to "understand laughter we must put it back into its
natural environment, which is society, and above all we must determine its
functioning, which is a social one.... Laughter always implies a kind of secret
freemasonry or even complicity, with other laughters, real or imagined"
(p. 4-5). Laughter begets laughter for people who are, or are in the process of
becoming, a group and the truth of this assertion is nowhere better seen than in
the ability of a record or tape containing nothing but laughter to evoke laughter
in an audience. Even the distant TV station understands the social nature of
Notes toward a Field Theory of Humor 219
For both the laughing person and for the person with whom he or she is
laughing, there is a reasonable congruity in experience that can best be
220 Howard R. Pollio
Figure 10-3. Contemporary social representations for the "happy face" and the
"unhappy face."
Notes toward a Field Theory of Humor 221
an invitation to interact. This second type of smile may range from a bonding
smile between infant and caretaker, to a seductive smile between consenting
adults, to a smile of entreaty (or appeasement) between individuals of unequal
rank or power.
The distinction between smile as incomplete laugh and smile as invitati'on to
interact can perhaps be seen best in the developing child. As is well documented
(Ambrose, 1961; McGhee, 1979; Nowicki, 1977) smiling regularly precedes
laughing in infant development, often by as much as 2-3 months. From both a
theoretical and an empirical standpoint (Bowlby, 1969; Goldstein, 1957) the
earliest smiles produced by the infant and responded to by the mothering one
usually function as signals of bonding; they both request-and confirm-the
bond between infant and adult. Although the smile continues to have this
meaning (and effect), certain theorists such as Kagan (1971 )-and Piaget
before, and McGhee (1979) after-have attempted to interpret smiling as a
sign of rudimentary understanding brought about by an infant's growing ability
to assimilate an originally unfamiliar event to an existing schema. Under this
interpretation the smile means: "I've understood or mastered something I
originally found strange or puzzling." This smile of recognition, or mastery,
signals the end of a problem and thereby seems more related to a triumphant
laugh than to the bonding smile that often transpires between the younger infant
and his or her parent.
While it is possible to view the infant's earliest laughs as simply adding noise
to the smile of bonding, the major concomitants to laughter in both older infants
and preschool children turn out to be more intensely exciting events that
alternately frighten the child and assure him/her that everything is "really all
right" (Ambrose, 1961; Nowicki, 1977; Rothbart, 1976). The game of peek-a-
boo or of throwing the infant in the air and catching him/her are characteristic of
such events for the infant; jumping off a high platform or going down a big slide
are characteristic of such events for the preschool child.
In all of these situations, laughter seems to occur only once the danger is over
and the child is free to abandon him/herself to the now nonfrightening, but
previously frightening, situation. Although not yet the experience of radical
freedom it will later become, this laughter does indicate the end to a potentially
frightening state of affairs in which the child experienced being affected by
"forces" outside him/herself. On this basis, the laugh may simply mean: "I am
now free from the experience of danger" and serves to connect it with the
meaning of its more adult counterpart. In terms of adults present in the situation,
the young child's laugh is a clear reaching out that only can be responded to by
laughter. As such, it provides the adult with an experience of communion with
the child on the basis of freedom from their shared situation. This twofold
consequence would seem reason enough for adults to repeat the cycle, thereby
strengthening, even further, the bond between parent and child.
This line of analysis would seem to help answer our sixth and last question.
From the present point of view, smiling must be seen as a gesture of invitation to
bond whereas laughter must be seen as a gesture of communion through shared
222 Howard R. Pollio
freedom from constraint. Both laughing and smiling are centrifugal activities
that afford the person a means of reaching beyond him/herself. For the case of
smiling, however, such reaching out would seem to have a clear target in other
people; for the case of laughing, such reaching out would initially seem to be
unconcerned with other people and simply represent an explosive reaction to
the present situation. If shared by others, however, laughter also is capable of
bringing about an experience of social communion.
If we move from the side of gesture to that of experience, laughing and smiling
again yield somewhat different pictures. Laughing, preeminently, provides
momentary release from social and/or personal restraint and seems to present a
prototypic body experience of freedom. Smiling, on the other hand, provides an
experience of bodily lightness, as well as an orientation toward others, and
seems to present a prototypic body experience of happiness or satisfaction. For
both laughing and smiling, however, the behaviors are not epiphenomenal to
some more basic experience of humor; rather, by their very bodily form, they
provide the experiential and interpersonal ground out of which humor as a
uniquely human process must be defined and understood both by the laughing!
smiling person as well as by the theorist who would attempt to capture its
meaning.
William James brought psychology into the twentieth century with his book
Principles a/Psychology (1890/1950). In this encyclopedic work he sketched a
theory of emotion that since that time has come to be called the J ames-Lange
theory. As a first approximation, he described the theory as follows:
Our natural way of thinking about ... emotions is that the ... perception of some fact
excites ... the emotion, and that this latter state of mind gives rise to the bodily
expression. My theory, on the contrary, is that bodily changes follow directly the
perception of the exciting fact, and that our feeling of (these) changes is the emotion.
Common-sense says, we lose our fortune, are sorry and weep; we meet a bear, are
frightened and run; we are insulted by a rival, are angry and strike. The hypothesis
here to be defended ... says that this order of sequence is incorrect and that we feel
sorry because we cry, angry because we strike, afraid because we tremble, and not that
we cry, strike, or tremble, because we are sorry, angry, or fearful, as the case may be.
(James, 1890/1950, pp. 449-450)
Notes toward a Field Theory of Humor 223
Although the fate of this approach to emotion had been argued for the past 80
years or so, much of the debate has been of the form: which comes first, the
emotional experience or the bodily reaction. Regardless of the answer-
emotion first, bodily reaction second; bodily reaction first, emotion second-
simply asking the question in this way assumes a mind/body split that James did
not intend. If we read further in the chapter on emotion, we find James points
out that" if our hypothesis is true, it makes us realize more deeply than ever how
much of our mental life is knit up with our corporeal form, in the strictest sense
of the term" (James, 1890/1950, p. 467). If we substitute "experience" for
"mental life," we can see that James tried to describe emotional phenomena in
terms of an indissoluable union between experience and corporeality that later
theorists would couch in Cartesian, cause-effect, language. For James there was
no separation between behavior and experience when the person was in the
midst of an emotional event.
Does this mean that the scientific attempt to define sequential (causal)
relationships between emotional experiences, bodily reactions, and mental
states is wrong? The answer here is no if we can be sure that the attempt does
not mistake its analytic approach as anything more than an intellectual
construction deriving its support from a more primary experience of unity
among (what will later be called) "elements" of the event. The danger with a
strictly analytic approach to laughing (and smiling) is that it may tend to
forget-or even hide-its rootedness in the more direct and less reflected
experiences that precede formal scientific analysis. When we return to the
unreflected world of emotional experience we find no separation of movement
and experience; only the unity of a lughing/smiling person in this or that
situation, talking to this or that person, concerning this or that topic. Laughing
and smiling are total person events in which experience and bodily movements
are given as two distinct, but inseparable, moments of the same event that later
reflection may divide into components for purpose of analysis.
Does this mean that it is impossible to produce smiling and laughing as a
consequence of some prior "mental event," or, alternatively, to produce an
experience of lightness or joy on the basis of simply setting one's face and body
in the form of a smile or laugh? The answer to both questions is, again, no; it is
quite clear that we can smile or laugh as a consequence of "wanting to smile or
laugh" (we are all actors to some degree) and that we can and do experience
some of the "emotion" associated with smiling and laughing if we place our
bodies in the proper form. These "facts," however, have little effect on either
James's theory or on the one proposed in in the present paper because they refer
not to naturally occurring events but to events that have been deliberately
performed to determine if it is possible to produce, on demand, either the
"bodily" response or the "emotional" reaction associated with humor. As such,
these questions request mechanical movements and contrived emotions and not
the living response/experience appropriate to more naturally occurring humor-
ous events.
224 Howard R. Pollio
Superiority theories of humor originate in the insight that laughter often seems
to accompany feeling superior toward some other person or situation. Keith-
Speigel (1972) summarize this general approach quite well when she noted:
... laUghter is caused either by some sudden act oftheir own, that pleaseth them; or
by the apprehension of some deformed thing in another, by comparison whereof they
suddenly applaud themselves. And it is incident most to them, that are conscious of
the fewest abilities in themselves; who are forced to keep themselves in their own
favour, by observing the imperfections of other men. (1651/1914, p. 36)
The first aspect of this quotation to note is that it concerns only laughter; if
smiling is considered at all it is generally described as a weak or low level cousin
to the laugh as conveyed in French by the word sous-rire (sublaugh) and in
German by the word liicheln (little laugh). What this emphasis on laughter
suggests in the context of superiority theory is that such principles have more to
do with the experience offreedom from one's body and situation and less to do
with the experience of lightness or invitation characteristic of smiling.
With this limitation in mind, superiority theories appeal to situations in which
the body of some other person, or of the laughing person him or herself, is quite
significant. Consider the first of these situations-sudden victory over an
opponent-that for many theories (e.g., Gruner, 1979; Rapp, 1951) is the
prototype. Being involved with an opponent, in either a life and death struggle or
in an athletic event, involves the body of both participants in a very confined
and confining way. With victory, however, the body of the victor is freed from
Notes toward a Field Theory of Humor 225
control by the opponent (or situation) whereas the body of the vanquished is
more tightly confined by constraints imposed by the superior athlete or
combatant. Laughter is obviously the proper response for it provides a further
augmentation to the relief appropriate to release from bodily or situational
confinement.
The remaining situations do not so literally involve an experience of freedom
from bodily constraint. They do, however, clearly focus the laugher on the
bodily activities of another person. In all of these cases, the body has been made
focal by an act (falling down) or by a characteristic (large nose, etc.) of the
person in question. For the laugher to experience freedom here he/she must
first identify with the other person and then respond (with laughter) to the fact
that the body of the other, which I identify with because he/she is another
person, is not my body and that I, at this moment, am free of the unfortunate
situation of his/her body. This kind of laughter, even though it might seem to
assert only superiority, also asserts a reaching out toward the "victim" in
sympathy. Only ifI identify with the victim as like me in some way will I be able
to laugh at his/her situation and, thereby, express the freedom I feel from his or
her unfortunate actions or body.
The person falling down also may laugh. The crucial factor here seems to be
that the person experiences the falling body as different from his/her ordinary
body and, if the fall is not serious, will possibly experience a moment offreedom
from body and situation. Laughter has the possibility of bringing about more
laughter, and laughter on the part of the victim may represent an implicit request
for a response from someone else. As Scogin and Pollio (1980) noted in a
different context, what is called "nervous laughter" may have a similar intent:
As a highly focused body event representing a request for relationship with
others.
Bergson (1911/1956) offered a somewhat different analysis of superiority
humor in tenns of his famous fonnula for what is laughable-the mechanical
encrusted on the living-in which the comic person is seen as a thing with life
removed. If laughter is the unique human behavior that expresses momentary
freedom from body, then a mechanical body only calls attention to the fact that
our body (fortunately) is no such thing, and we laugh both as a recognition of the
difference and as affinnation of its significance. What we also affinn by
laughing is our identification with the thing-like aspect of our body even as we
somewhat shakily assert our intennittent freedom from it. As Plessner (1970)
put it: We both are a body and have body and laughter is our expression of this
fact of existence.
superiority theories of humor, then the double take and the experience of
surprise at unexpected events represent reference situations for incongruity
theories. All theories of humor, in one way or another, seem to recognize that
"unexpectedness," or at least "suddenness," is an important aspect to events
and situations that evoke laughter and smiling; the difference for incongruity
theories is that this fact becomes a central postulate. What is also usually
recognized by most theories is that unexpected, illogical, or surprising elements
often bring about reactions incompatible with laughter such as being curious,
puzzled, confused, or shocked. The double take provides an appropriate bodily
description of what the person does in responding to such events because it
suggests the person takes another look in order to resolve the situation into
something familiar or to determine that the situation is not very important, even
if surprising.
This description of what happens following the perception of an incongruous
event fits well with recent cognitive theories of humor (Shultz, 1976; Suls,
1972) that describe two stages as necessary for getting the point of a joke:
puzzlement at incongruity and ( subsequent) resolution of incongruity. Although
there has been some question as to whether resolution is necessary for joke
appreciation (Rothbart, 1976) the general consensus seems to be that some sort
of resolution does take place even if only to recognize that no sensible resolution
is possible. What incongruity theory in its cognitive form seems to have done is
to put both the first and second takes, of the more observable double take, into
the head of the would-be laughter in the form of two cognitive processes:
puzzlement and resolution. Unfortunately, cognitive theories tend to consider
incongruity and its resolution as purely mental acts and thereby come to
undervalue-or even exclude entirely-the embodied, total-person response to
such situations.
That incongruity need not be a cognitive event to evoke laughter is well
documented in a study by Nerhardt (1970) who had subjects in a laboratory
evaluate the heaviness of a set of weights. Results were quite clear in showing
that subjects laughed when asked to judge a weight that was a good deal heavier
or lighter than the relatively narrow training series presented to them for initial
evaluation. A similar experiment was reported by Deckers and Kizer (1974)
who noted that subjects laughed and smiled when presented with weights well
above and well below an initial test series. They also found more laughter and
smiling were evoked by an unexpected heavier weight than by an unexpected
lighter weight although there was no such asymmetry in results reported by
Nerhardt.
What seems most important about these experiments is that in attempting to
elucidate the relationship of laughter to incongruity, a motor task, rather than a
verbal-conceptual task, was used. These results thus call attention to the role of
the body in responding directly to "incongruous" or "unexpected" events. Ifwe
take the point of view of the subject in one or both of these experiments, it is
possible to see that the subject must have developed an expected amount of heft
required to deal with weights in the training series. If lifting the final weight did
Notes toward a Field Theory of Humor 227
not come off easily because it was much heavier than the training series, the
subject literally was forced to a "second take" (i.e., heft) of the weight. If the
final item was much lighter, the subject was also required to do a "double take"
to attenuate his or her reaction relative to the force required. In both cases, the
subject was thrown back directly on his/her body and in both cases forced to
recognize the thing-like nature of that body and of his/her intermittent freedom
from it. In these experiments, the subject was first made more aware of his/her
body and on discovering that it was not incompetent in dealing with the now-
changed situation was able to experience freedom both from the puzzling nature
of the situation and from a body initially" surprised" by that situation.
It is important to note that the subject ultimately was able to resolve the
situation and that the double take (more accurately, double heft) was
accomplished easily in both the "heavier" and "lighter" cases. It seems
reasonable to wonder what would happen if the final weight were nailed down or
so heavy that it could not be lifted. Under these circumstances, unexpectedness
might lead not to puzzlement, resolution, and laughter in that order but to
puzzlement, frustration, and anger in that order. Being able to lift the weight
successfully seems an important ingredient in yielding laughter; if the subject
were unable to lift the weight, puzzlement would likely become resentment at
having been tricked. Under such circumstances, incongruity would become
treachery and laughter, anger as the limits of bodily constraint were not
overcome but further emphasized by the task.
The structure of these experiments serves to define what is meant by
unexpected (and incongruous) in a remarkabley clear and nonmentalistic way:
It is simply the strength of lift learned in regard to the range of weights used in
the training series. As such, the limits of the series (translated into body exertion
required for .a given lift) define the limits of expected response. Like all
boundaries they both define and constrain what mayor may not be done in the
situation. In this regard, they are like the rules of more intellectual tasks, such as
those defined by language or concepts, that also both encourage and limit what
may be thought or said in particular context. If laughter expresses an experience
of freedom, then unexpectedness provokes laughter only if the limits of a
structure (or stricture) are exceeded and their constraints overcome. Laughter
signals a sudden, successful, and temporary end to the limits imposed by a
situation whether this situation requires direct motoric action, as in lifting
weights, or more "cognitive" action, as in solving intellectual tasks or jokes.
Both in terms of its conditions of emergence and resolution, timing is all
important: Prolonged incongruity leads only to frustration or ennui whereas
slowly emerging incongruity is neither surprising nor absorbing. As both Freud
and Shakespeare noted, brevity is the soul of wit, and too-long, too drawn-out
jokes, like too-long, too drawn-out problems, only yield experiences of
annoyance and not release. To be sure when a long drawn-out problem is finally
solved, the resulting cry of "Eureka!" is likely to contain laughter; just as surely,
however, a long drawn-out problem will often lead only to an abandonment of
the problem or to a feeling of discomfort brought about by an inability to get free
228 Howard R. Pollio
of it. There is a tradeoff between being captured by a problem and getting free of
it and if either is experienced as taking too long, laughter is unlikely. It also is
important to note that the moment of freedom itself has to be relatively brief, for
being disembodied (i.e., free from the constraints of body and situation) for too
long may be experienced as uncomfortable. Both the incongruous event and its
resolution must be brief if the situation is to be experienced as laughable rather
than as unsettling.
While this analysis of incongruity has been pursued in terms of bodily
incongruity, it also applies to more intellectual situations and tasks not only
because the human being is a unified field comprising both mind and body, but
because compelling problems always have bodily concomitants. Noncompelling
incongruities such as occur in simple word play or trivial jokes-that can be
described as forcing only an intellectual double take-evoke slight smiles and
not loud laughs and, in this case, the smile truly is an attentuated laugh as befits
a small problem. In its more powerful fOI"Q1, laughter at incongruity indicates
both that the event has been compelling in its control and that its resolution is
experienced as freedom from such control. Under this interpretation, incon-
gruity theory merges with superiority theory and both, in turn, must be seen as
deriving from a more general analysis of the meaning of laughing and smiling as
human events that depend both on us and on the people with whom we laugh
and smile. There seems to be no alternative but to conclude that humor is an
embodied field event involving issues of limits and transcendence and that this is
the case whether we start with incongruity or superiority as our basic theoretical
premise.
REFERENCES
Ambrose, A. J. The development of the smiling response in early infancy. In B. Foss
(Ed.), Determinants of in/ant behavior. New York: Wiley, 1961.
Berger, P. L., and Luckmann, T. The social construction of reality. New York: Anchor
Books, 1966.
Bergson, H. Laughter: An essay on the meaning of the comic. New York: McMillan,
1956. (Originally published 1911.)
Bowlby, J. Attachment and loss. New York: Basic Books, 1969.
Deckers, L., and Kizer, P. A note on weight discrepancy and humor. Journal of
Psychology, 1974,86,309-312.
230 Howard R. Pollio
Fisher, S., and Fisher, R. Pretend the world is funny and forever. Hillsdale, N.J.:
Erlbaum, 1981.
Freud, S. Jokes and their relation to the unconscious. New York: Norton, 1960.
(Originally published, 1905.)
Goldstein, K. The smiling of the infant and the problem of understanding the "other."
Journal of Psychology, 1957,44,175-191.
Gruner, C. R. Understanding laughter: The workings of wit and humor. Chicago:
Nelson-Hall, 1978.
Hobbes, T. Leviathan. New York: Dutton, 1914. (Originally published, 1651.)
James, W. The principles of psychology. New York: Dover, 1950. (Originally
published, 1890.)
Kagan, J. Change and continuity in infancy. New York: Wiley, 1971.
Keith-Spiegel, P. Early conceptions of humor: Varieties and issues. In J. H. Goldstein
and P. E. McGhee (Eds.), The psychology of humor. New York: Academic Press,
1972.
Koestler, A. The act of creation. London: Hutchinson, 1964.
Lewin, K. A dynamic theory ofpersonality. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1935.
Lewin, K. Field theory in social science. New York: Harper, 1951.
McDougall, W. Why do we laugh? Scribners, 1922, 71,359-363.
McGhee, P. E. Humor: Its origin and development. San Francisco: Freeman, 1979.
Mindess, H. Laughter and liberation. Los Angeles: Nash, 1971.
Murphy, B., and Pollio, H. R. The many faces of humor. Psychological Record, 1975,
25, 545-558.
Nerhardt, G. Humor and inclination to laugh: Emotional reactions to stimuli of different
divergence from a range of expectancy. Scandinavian Journal of Psychology, 1970,
11, 185-195.
Nowicki, D. R. Smiling and laughing in human infancy: A naturalistic perspective.
Unpublished doctoral dissertation, The University of Tennessee, 1977.
Plessner, H. Laughing and crying. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press, 1970.
Rapp, A. The origins of wit and humor. New York: Dutton, 1951.
Rothbart, M. Incongruity, problem-solving, and laughter. In A. J. Chapman and H. C.
Foot (Eds.), Humour and laughter: Theory, research and applications. London:
Wiley, 1976.
Scogin, F. J., and Pollio, H. R Targeting and the humorous episode in group process.
Human Relations. 1980,33,831-852.
Shultz, T. A cognitive-developmental analysis of humour. In A. J. Chapman and H. C.
Foot (Eds.), Humour and laughter: Theory, research and applications. London:
Wiley. 1976.
Suls, J. M. A two-stage model for the appreciation of jokes and cartoons: An
information-processing analysis. In J. H. Goldstein and P. E. McGhee (Eds.), The
psychology of humor. New York: Academic Press, 1972.
Author Index
Roman type refers to page numbers in Volume I, italic type refers to page numbers in
Volume II.
Greene, S.J., 203 Hezel, R., 148, 165, 168, 169, 173,
Greenwald, H., 167, 178,65,86 175, 185, 186, 187, 188, 191, 193
Gregg, A., 136, 155 Hicks, V., 79, 86
Grossman, S., 65, 75, 86 Hieb, L.A., 189,209
Grotjahn, M., 163, 178,65, 87, 111, Highet, G., 174, 178
121, 126 Hill, C.E., 71, 86
Gruner, C.R, 149, 155, 160, 167, 178, Hill, D.W., 192,209
224,230,162, 163, 164, 170, 192 Hill, H., 120, 126, 136, 141
Gula, J., 173, 185, 191 Hill, W.W., 192, 209
Gumpert, J., 98, 101, 106 Hillyard, S.A., 18, 36
Gur, R.C., 25, 28, 34, 36, 102, 107 Hinton, J.L., 155, 170
Hirsch-Pasek, K., 72, 74, 76, 82
Haberman, G., 20, 36 Hobbes, T., 86,91,98, 105,224,230,
Haddad, J., 88, 89, 90, 91, 105, 116, 35
132, 172, 176, 179 Hoebel, E.A., 194,209
Hager, J.C., 8, 11 Homans, G.C., 166, 178
Haley, J., 65, 87 Honigmann, J.J., 190, 195, 196,200,
Hall, G.C., 102, 106 202, 206, 209
Hall, M.M., 102, 106 Horibe, F., 45, 46, 57, 70, 76, 77,
Hamby, S., 26, 27, 29, 37 78, 83, 133
Hammond, P.B., 165, 178, 186, 188, Horn, G., 178, 192
205, 209 Horowitz, S., 97, 106
Hamnett, I., 65, 82 Hosta, G., 99, 101, 107
Handelman, D., 166, 170, 178, 185, Houston, A.C., 148, 170
187, 209 Howard, J.H., 189,210
Handelman, S.M., v Howell, RW., 185, 186, 187,205,209
Hannerz, U., 175, 178 Huber, A., 69, 74, 82, 87
Hansotia, P., 98, 101, 106 Humphrey, G.L., 181, 191
Haring, L., 65, 82 Humphries, D.A., 4, 11
Harman, J., 16, 17,35 Hungerbuhler, J.P., 25, 28, 34, 36, 102,
Harries, L., 65, 82 107
Harris, A.J., 153, 170 Huson, C., 163, 177
Harris, L., 165, 168, 186, 187, 188, 191 Hutchison, S.A., 124, 126
Harris, P.E., 16, 36 Hyman, H., 171, 178
Hauck, W.E., 178, 192
Hay, T.A., 95, 107 Inge, M.T., 142
Hayes, D.S., 149, 170 lonesco, E., 37, 40
Haymaker, W., 93, 95, 106 Ironside, R., 93, 95, 97, 106
Haynes, RB., 166, 170
Hayworth, D., 113, 126 Jacobson, E., 149, 155
Hazlitt, W., 40, 55, 87,105,113, 126 Jacome, D.E., 98, 106
Heisenberg, W., 25 Jaffe, A., 123, 126
Helmers, H., Ill, 132 Jaffe, L., 123, 126
Henry, J., 151, 155, 167, 178,121, 126 James, W., 87, 105,222,223,230
Herron, E.W., 55, 59 Jandolo, B., 100, 106
Herskovits, F.S., 193,209 Jankelevitch, V., 78, 87
Herskovits, M.J., 193,209 Janus, B.R, 42, 47, 59
Hertzler, J.O., 7, 12, 135, 155 Janus, S.S., 121, 123, 125, 127, 132,
Hesse, H., 29, 31 163, 178,42, 47, 55, 59
Author Index 237
Pollio, H.R, viii, 2, 8, 9, 12, 137, 141, Robinson, V.M., VI: 109, 110, 111, 112,
156,163,179,217,219,225,230 114, 115, 116, 120, 121, 122, 123,
Pompili, A., 100, 106 127
Ponder, M.R, 46, 47, 57 Roethlisberger, F.J., 165, 180
Posen, I.S., 163, 179 Rogal, 0.,98, 107
Potts, R, 148, 170 Roger, J., 98, 99, 107
Powell, B.S., 123, 127 Rogers, C., 121, 127
Powell, C., 156, 174, 179 Rogers, M.P., 93, 107
Powelson, J., 29, 30, 34 Rogers, P., 41, 43, 59
Prange, A.J., 175, 179 Rogers, W., 1
Priest, RF., 92, 106, 172, 179 Rokeach, M., 156, 160, 172
Prince, G., 18, 21 Roland, e.G., 122, 127
Pritchard, E., 146, 154 Rosadini, G., 28, 36
Pruskauer-Apostol, B., 93, 106 Rose, G.J., 111, 127
Roses, A.O., 99, 106
Quesney, L.F., 97, 106 Rosman, B.L., 120, 132
Rossi, G.F., 28,36
Radcliffe-Brown, A.R, 151, 156, 165, Rothbart, M.K., 20,32,36,46,47,50,
180,186,189,204,205,211,39, 53, 54, 56, 104, 106, 140, 156,
40 221, 226, 230
Rader, C., 16, 18,35 Rothman, RA., 149, 171
Radin, P., 190, 193,207,211 Roubicek, J., 99, 107
Ramos, J., 129, 131 Routh, D.K., 41, 55
Ransohoff, R, 136, 156, 175, 180 Roy, D.F., 163, 170, 180
Rao, T.A., 96, 100, 107 Rubin, L., Jr., 136, 142
Rapp, A., 86, 106, 224, 230 Ryan, J.K., 150, 171
Ray, V.F., 190,211
Reardon, K.R, 165, 168, 182, 190 Sackheim, H.A., 25, 28, 34, 36, 102,
Redlich, F.C., 79, 87 107
Reese, RL., 122, 127 Sacks, H., 168, 169, 176, 180
Reich, P., 93, 107 Saenger, G., 150, 171
Reid, L.N., 164, 168 Safer, M.A., 22, 36, 49, 56
Reid, P.T., 155, 171 Sakamoto, Y., 100, 102, 108
Reilly, S., 184, 185, 191 Salameh, W.A., vi, 43, 45, 47, 53, 54,
Reiner, C., 144 55, 57, 58, 59, 81, 85, 87
Reitz, R, 176, 193 Salutin, M., 164, 180
Reivich, M., 25, 36 Sanders, e., 164, 180
Reps, P., 31 Sapolsky, B.S., 95,107,154, 165, 168,
Rice, M.L., 148, 170 171, 184, 191
Richardson, C., 152, 167 Sargent, S., 162, 168
Richman, J., 153, 171 Savage, D., 100, 108
Ricketts, M.L., 192, 193,207,211,212 Schachter, S., 16, 36, 119, 127
Rickwood, L.V., 152, 156 Schaier, A.H., 109, 115, 133
Rightmyer, J., 118, 119, 130 Scheff, T.J., 109, 110, 118, 124, 127
Rivier, J., 101, 105 Schegcoff, E., 168, 176
Roback, A.A., 79, 87 Schemerle~ H., 193, 212
Robillard, J., 59, 73, 74, 83, 110, 113, Schenkein, J.N., 168, 180
133 Scherer, K.R, 9, 12
Author Index 241
Roman type refers to page numbers in Volume I, italic type refers to page numbers in
Volume II.