Warhol Goldsmith
Warhol Goldsmith
Warhol Goldsmith
The Andy Warhol Foundation for The Visual Arts, Inc. v. Lynn Goldsmith, et al.
Plaintiff-Counter-
Defendant-Appellee,
— v. —
Defendants-Counter-
Plaintiffs-Appellants.
B e f o r e:
2
Thomas B. Maddrey, Maddrey PLLC, Dallas, TX; Russell J.
Frackman, UCLA School of Law Copyright Amicus
Brief Clinic, Los Angeles, CA, for Amici Curiae The
American Society of Media Photographers, Inc., National
Press Photographers Association, Professional Photographers
of America, Graphics Artist Guild, and North American
Nature Photography Association.
created by the visual artist Andy Warhol based on a 1981 photograph of the
her studio, and in which she holds copyright. In 1984, Goldsmith’s agency,
Goldsmith, Inc., licensed the photograph to Vanity Fair magazine for use as an
did not stop with the image that Vanity Fair had commissioned him to create, but
created an additional fifteen works, which together became known as the Prince
Series.
3
Goldsmith first became aware of the Prince Series after Prince’s death in
Foundation for the Visual Arts, Inc. (“AWF”), successor to Warhol’s copyright in
the Prince Series, of the perceived violation of her copyright in the photo. In 2017,
AWF sued Goldsmith and LGL for a declaratory judgment that the Prince Series
works were non-infringing or, in the alternative, that they made fair use of
United States District Court for the Southern District of New York (John G.
Koeltl, J.) granted summary judgment to AWF on its assertion of fair use and
Goldsmith and LGL contend that the district court erred in its assessment
and application of the four fair-use factors. In particular, they argue that the
district court’s conclusion that the Prince Series works are transformative was
agree. We further agree that the district court’s error in analyzing the first factor
upon our own assessment of the record that all four factors favor Goldsmith and
4
that the Prince Series works are not fair use as a matter of law. We further
conclude that the Prince Series works are substantially similar to the Goldsmith
BACKGROUND
The relevant facts, which we draw primarily from the parties’ submissions
undisputed.
musicians. Goldsmith has been active since the 1960s, and her work has been
featured widely, including on over 100 record album covers. Goldsmith also
founded LGL, the first photo agency focused on celebrity portraiture. LGL
Goldsmith herself.
5
explor[ing] the relationship between celebrity culture and advertising.” Cariou v.
Prince, 714 F.3d 694, 706 (2d Cir. 2013). AWF is a New York not-for-profit
corporation established in 1987 after Warhol’s death. AWF holds title to and
further its mission of advancing the visual arts, “particularly work that is
musician Prince Rogers Nelson (known through most of his career simply as
“Prince”) in her studio. Goldsmith testified that, prior to Prince’s arrival at her
studio, she arranged the lighting in a way to showcase his “chiseled bone
including eyeshadow and lip gloss, which she testified was intended both to
build a rapport with Prince and to accentuate his sensuality. Goldsmith further
testified that she was trying to capture Prince’s “willing[ness] to bust through
what must be [his] immense fears to make the work that [he] wanted to [make].”
6
Nikon 35-mm camera and a mixture of 85- and 105-mm lenses, which she chose
retired to the green room shortly after the session began and ultimately left
in color. Goldsmith retained copyright in each of the photographs that she took.
Vanity Fair magazine for use as an artist reference. Esin Goknar, who was photo
7
editor at Vanity Fair in 1984, testified that the term “artist reference” meant that
an artist “would create a work of art based on [the] image reference.” Id. at 783.
Goldsmith Photograph in its November 1984 issue, once as a full page and once
license at the time and played no role in selecting the Goldsmith Photograph for
In addition to the credit that ran alongside the image, a separate attribution to
Goldsmith was included elsewhere in the issue, crediting her with the “source
8
photograph” for the Warhol illustration. Vanity Fair did not advise Goldsmith
that Warhol was the artist for whom her work would serve as a reference, and
she did not see the article when it was initially published.
based on the Goldsmith Photograph, known collectively, and together with the
Vanity Fair image, as the “Prince Series.”1 The Prince Series comprises fourteen
silkscreen prints (twelve on canvas, two on paper) and two pencil illustrations,
1
Though it acknowledged that the depiction of Prince in the Prince Series is
similar to that in the Goldsmith Photograph, AWF did not concede below that the
Goldsmith Photograph was the source image for the Prince Series, arguing
instead that “somehow, Warhol created” it. Dist. Ct. Dkt. 55 at 18. In its brief
before this Court, however, AWF describes the Goldsmith Photograph as the
“source image” for the Prince Series. Appellee’s Br. at 6-7.
9
Although the specific means that Warhol used to create the images is unknown
(and, perhaps, at this point, unknowable), Neil Printz, the editor of the Andy
any alterations Warhol chose to make, would be used to create a silkscreen. For
the canvas prints, Warhol’s general practice was to paint the background and
local colors prior to the silkscreen transfer of the image. Paper prints, meanwhile,
were generally created entirely by the silkscreen process without any painted
project an image onto paper and create a contoured pencil drawing around the
projected image.
At some point after Warhol’s death, AWF acquired title to and copyright in
the Prince Series. Between 1993 and 2004, AWF sold or otherwise transferred
custody of 12 of the original Prince Series works to third parties, and, in 1998,
transferred custody of the other four works to The Andy Warhol Museum. AWF
retains copyright in the Prince Series images and, through The Artist Rights
10
On April 22, 2016, the day after Prince died, Condé Nast, Vanity Fair’s
parent company, contacted AWF. Its initial intent in doing so was to determine
whether AWF still had the 1984 image, which Condé Nast hoped to use in
that AWF had additional images from the Prince Series, Condé Nast ultimately
Prince Series image for the cover of the planned tribute magazine. Condé Nast
published the tribute magazine in May 2016 with a Prince Series image on the
cover. Goldsmith was not given any credit or attribution for the image, which
It was at this point that Goldsmith first became aware of the Prince Series.
On April 7, 2017, AWF sued Goldsmith and LGL for a declaratory judgment of
11
On July 1, 2019, the district court granted summary judgment for AWF on
its fair-use claim. See Andy Warhol Found. for the Visual Arts, Inc. v. Goldsmith, 382
F. Supp. 3d 312, 316 (S.D.N.Y. 2019). Upon evaluating the four statutory fair-use
factors set forth in 17 U.S.C. § 107, the court concluded that: (1) the Prince Series
as “not a comfortable person” and a “vulnerable human being,” the Prince Series
portrays Prince as an “iconic, larger-than-life figure,” id. at 326; (2) although the
traditionally weigh in Goldsmith’s favor, this was “of limited importance because
the Prince Series works are transformative works,” id. at 327; (3) in creating the
Prince Series, Warhol “removed nearly all [of] the [Goldsmith] [P]hotograph’s
protectible elements,” id. at 330; and (4) the Prince Series works “are not market
substitutes that have harmed – or have the potential to harm – Goldsmith,” id. at
12
DISCUSSION
I. Standard of Review
standards set forth in Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 56(c). Cariou, 714 F.3d at
704. While fair use presents a mixed question of law and fact, it may be resolved
on summary judgment where, as here, the material facts are not in dispute. See,
e.g., Harper & Row Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enters., 471 U.S. 539, 560 (1985).
promote the Progress of Science and useful Arts.” U.S. Const. art. I, § 8, cl. 8.
Congress has exercised this delegated authority continuously since the earliest
days of the nation, beginning with the Copyright Act of 1790 and, more recently,
through the Copyright Act of 1976. Under the 1976 Act, copyright protection
extends both to the original creative work itself and to derivative works, which it
defines as, in relevant part, “a work based upon one or more preexisting works,
13
The doctrine of fair use has developed along with the law of copyright.
“[A]s Justice Story explained, ‘in truth, in literature, in science and in art, there
are, and can be, few, if any, things, which in an abstract sense, are strictly new
and original throughout. Every book in literature, science and art, borrows, and
must necessarily borrow, and use much which was well known and used
before.’” Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 510 U.S. 569, 575 (1994), quoting
Emerson v. Davies, 8 F. Cas. 615, 619 (No. 4,436) (C.C.D. Mass. 1845) (alterations
adopted). The fair use doctrine seeks to strike a balance between an artist’s
intellectual property rights to the fruits of her own creative labor, including the
right to license and develop (or refrain from licensing or developing) derivative
works based on that fruit, and “the ability of [other] authors, artists, and the rest
formally codified with the passage of the 1976 Act. The statute provides a non-
exclusive list of four factors that courts are to consider when evaluating whether
14
(1) the purpose and character of the use, including
whether such use is of a commercial nature or is for
nonprofit educational purposes;
(2) the nature of the copyrighted work;
(3) the amount and substantiality of the portion used in
relation to the copyrighted work as a whole; and
(4) the effect of the use upon the potential market for or
value of the copyrighted work.
17 U.S.C. § 107.
As the Supreme Court has held, fair use presents a holistic context-
statutory factors] are to be explored, and the results weighed together, in light of
the purposes of copyright.” Campbell, 510 U.S. at 577-78; see also, e.g., Cariou, 714
This factor requires courts to consider the extent to which the secondary
15
1. Transformative Works and Derivative Works
first factor has focused chiefly on the degree to which the use is “transformative,”
i.e., “whether the new work merely supersedes the objects of the original creation,
altering the first with new expression, meaning, or message.” 510 U.S. at 579
be perceived.” Cariou, 714 F.3d at 707, quoting Campbell, 510 U.S. at 582; see also,
e.g., Leibovitz v. Paramount Pictures Corp., 137 F.3d 109, 113-15 (2d Cir. 1998).
Campbell, parody, which “needs to mimic an original to make its point,” 510 U.S.
Comedy Partners, 682 F.3d 687, 693 (7th Cir. 2012). These examples are easily
upon it serves a manifestly different purpose from the novel itself. See Authors
16
Guild v. Google, Inc., 804 F.3d 202, 215-16 (2d Cir. 2015) (“[C]opying from an
original for the purpose of criticism or commentary on the original . . . tends most
Prince, we rejected the proposition that a secondary work must comment on the
original in order to qualify as fair use. See 714 F.3d at 706. In that case, we
taken by Patrick Cariou. See id. at 699. After concluding that the district court had
own examination of Prince’s works and concluded that twenty-five of the thirty
photographs” into his own “crude and jarring works . . . [that] incorporate[d]
color, feature[d] distorted human and other forms and settings, and measure[d]
17
between ten and nearly a hundred times the size of the photographs.” Id. Thus,
transformed in the creation of new information, new aesthetics, new insights and
understanding,” and were transformative within the meaning of this first factor.
Id., quoting Castle Rock Ent. v. Carol Publ’g Grp., 150 F.2d 132, 142 (2d Cir. 1998).
Television Corp. v. McCollum, 839 F.3d 168, 181 (2d Cir. 2016). And, as we have
previously observed, that decision has not been immune from criticism. See id.
occasion or desire to question its correctness on its own facts, our review of the
As discussed supra, both this Court and the Supreme Court have
emphasized that fair use is a context-sensitive inquiry that does not lend itself to
simple bright-line rules. E.g., Campbell, 510 U.S. at 577-78; Cariou, 714 F.3d at 705.
18
transformative as a matter of law “[i]f looking at the works side-by-side, the
secondary work has a different character, a new expression, and employs new
meaning, or message,’” Cariou, 714 F.3d at 706, quoting Campbell, 510 U.S. at 579,
whether by the use of “new aesthetics,” id., quoting Blanch, 467 F.3d at 253, by
placing the work “in a different context,” Perfect 10, Inc. v. Amazon.com, Inc., 508
F.3d 1146, 1165 (9th Cir. 2007), or by any other means is the sine qua non of
transformativeness. It does not follow, however, that any secondary work that
transformative.
Consider the five works at issue in Cariou that we did not conclude were
each undoubtedly imbued Cariou’s work with a “new aesthetic” as that phrase
19
might be colloquially understood. Prince’s Canal Zone (2007) is a collage of thirty-
six of Cariou’s photographs, most of which Prince altered by, for example,
painting over the faces and bodies of Cariou’s subjects, in some instances altering
them significantly. See Cariou, 714 F.3d at 711. In Graduation, Prince added blue
“lozenges” over the eyes and mouth of Cariou’s subject and pasted an image of
hands playing a blue guitar over his hands. Id. Both of these works certainly
imbued the originals from which they derive with a “new aesthetic;”
secondary works that add “new expression, meaning, or message” to their source
material but are nonetheless specifically excluded from the scope of fair use:
derivative works. As one of our sister circuits has observed, an overly liberal
case, risks crowding out statutory protections for derivative works. See Kienitz v.
Sconnie Nation LLC, 766 F.3d 756, 758 (7th Cir. 2014) (“To say that a new use
transforms the work is precisely to say that it is derivative and thus, one might
20
We addressed derivative works in Cariou, characterizing them as
secondary works that merely present “the same material but in a new form”
without “add[ing] something new.” 714 F.3d at 708 (citation omitted); see also
interpreted too broadly. Indeed, many derivative works “add something new” to
frequently add quite a bit to their source material: characters are combined,
eliminated, or created out of thin air; plot elements are simplified or eliminated;
new scenes are added; the moral or political implications of the original work
create such implications where the original text eschewed such matters. And all
editors, sound engineers, and myriad other individuals integral to the creation of
a film. It is for this reason that we have recognized that “[w]hen a novel is
21
converted to a film . . . [t]he invention of the original author combines with the
neither could have produced independently.” Google, 804 F.3d at 216 n.18.
Despite the extent to which the resulting movie may transform the aesthetic and
HathiTrust, 755 F.3d 87, 95 (2d Cir. 2014) (“Paradigmatic examples of derivative
neither), we typically consider the purpose of the primary and secondary works.
In Bill Graham Archives v. Dorling Kindersley Ltd., for example, we held that the
created to advertise Grateful Dead concerts was transformative because that use
was “plainly different from the original purpose for which they were created.”
448 F.3d 605, 609-10 (2d Cir. 2006). Likewise, in HathiTrust we held that the
pinpoint the exact page of any book in the catalogue on which the searched term
22
was used was a “quintessentially transformative use.” 755 F.3d at 97. In Google,
we reached the same conclusion when faced with a larger digital corpus
complete with tools that enabled researchers to track how a specific word or
phrase has been used throughout the development of the English language,
despite the fact that, unlike the database in Hathitrust, Google’s database also
permitted the searcher to view a “snippet” from the original text showing the
context in which the word or phrase had appeared. 804 F.3d at 216-17.
But purpose is perhaps a less useful metric where, as here, our task is to
assess the transformative nature of works of visual art that, at least at a high level
of generality, share the same overarching purpose (i.e., to serve as works of visual
art). While this is not the first time we have had to conduct this inquiry, our cases
on such works are considerably fewer in number, and a brief review of them
drawn from a fashion magazine where Koons had testified that he intended to
“us[e] Blanch’s image as fodder for his commentary on the social and aesthetic
consequences of mass media.” 467 F.3d at 253. Some time earlier, however, in
23
dimensional sculpture recreating a photograph, notwithstanding his claim that
301, 309-11 (2d Cir. 1992).2 And, in Cariou, we held twenty-five of Richard
Prince’s works transformative as a matter of law even though Prince had testified
that he “was not ‘trying to create anything with a new meaning or a new
each case against their respective source materials. The sculpture at issue in
was based. See 960 F.2d at 305. In Blanch, however, Koons used Blanch’s
“changes of its colors, the background against which it is portrayed, the medium,
the size of the objects pictured, [and] the objects’ details.” 467 F.3d at 253. In so
doing, Koons used Blanch’s photograph “as raw material for an entirely different
2
We note that Rogers predates the Supreme Court’s formal adoption of the
“transformative use” test and thus does not phrase its inquiry in precisely the
same manner as the cases that have followed. However, it remains a precedential
decision of this Court, and we believe it particularly relevant in this case.
24
type of art . . . that comment[ed] on existing images by juxtaposing them against
others.” Id. at 262 (Katzmann, J., concurring). And in Cariou, the copyrighted
works found to have been fairly used were, in most cases, juxtaposed with other
photographs and “obscured and altered to the point that Cariou’s original [was]
barely recognizable.” 714 F.3d at 710. The works that were found potentially
infringing in Cariou, however, were ones in which the original was altered in
ways that did not incorporate other images and that superimposed other
elements that did not obscure the original image and in which the original image
component of the impression created by the allegedly infringing work. See id. at
710-11.
work does not obviously comment on or relate back to the original or use the
original for a purpose other than that for which it was created, the bare assertion
render a work transformative. Rather, the secondary work itself must reasonably
a “new meaning or message” entirely separate from its source material. While we
25
cannot, nor do we attempt to, catalog all of the ways in which an artist may
achieve that end, we note that the works that have done so thus far have
themselves been distinct works of art that draw from numerous sources, rather
than works that simply alter or recast a single work with a new aesthetic.
Which brings us back to the Prince Series. The district court held that the
an iconic, larger-than-life figure.” Warhol, 382 F. Supp. 3d at 326. That was error.
transformative cannot turn merely on the stated or perceived intent of the artist
or the meaning or impression that a critic – or for that matter, a judge – draws
from the work. Were it otherwise, the law may well “recogniz[e] any alteration as
§ 13.05(B)(6); see also Google, 804 F.3d at 216 n.18 (“[T]he word ‘transformative,’ if
interpreted too broadly, can also seem to authorize copying that should fall
26
within the scope of an author’s derivative rights.”). Rather, as we have discussed,
the court must examine how the works may reasonably be perceived.
In conducting this inquiry, however, the district judge should not assume
the role of art critic and seek to ascertain the intent behind or meaning of the
works at issue. That is so both because judges are typically unsuited to make
Goldsmith argues, her own stated intent notwithstanding, “an audience viewing
the [Goldsmith] [P]hotograph today, across the vista of the singer’s long career,
might well see him in a different light than Goldsmith saw him that day in 1981.”
Prince’s fans might have trouble seeing the Goldsmith Photograph as depicting
anything other than the iconic songwriter and performer whose musical works
Instead, the judge must examine whether the secondary work’s use of its
3
As the Supreme Court observed over a century ago, “[i]t would be a dangerous
undertaking for persons trained only in the law to constitute themselves final
judges of the worth of pictorial illustrations, outside of the narrowest and most
obvious limits.” Bleistein v. Donaldson Lithographing Co., 188 U.S. 239, 251 (1903).
27
purpose and character, such that the secondary work stands apart from the “raw
material” used to create it. Although we do not hold that the primary work must
be “barely recognizable” within the secondary work, as was the case with the
purpose and character must, at a bare minimum, comprise something more than
the imposition of another artist’s style on the primary work such that the
secondary work remains both recognizably deriving from, and retaining the
the Prince Series is not “transformative” within the meaning of the first factor.
That is not to deny that the Warhol works display the distinct aesthetic sensibility
that many would immediately associate with Warhol’s signature style – the
elements of which are absent from the Goldsmith photo. But the same can be
said, for example, of the Ken Russell film, from a screenplay by Larry Kramer,
derived from D.H. Lawrence’s novel, Women in Love: the film is as recognizable a
“Ken Russell” as the Prince Series are recognizably “Warhols.” But the film, for
all the ways in which it transforms (that is, in the ordinary meaning of the word,
28
which indeed is used in the very definition of derivative works, see 17 U.S.C.
§ 101) its source material, is also plainly an adaptation of the Lawrence novel.
meaningful dispute that the overarching purpose and function of the two works
at issue here is identical, not merely in the broad sense that they are created as
works of visual art, but also in the narrow but essential sense that they are
portraits of the same person.4 See Gaylord v. United States, 595 F.3d 1364, 1372-73
(Fed. Cir. 2010) (photograph of Korean War Memorial used on stamp not
subdued lighting and snow since sculpture and stamp shared purpose of
“honor[ing] veterans of the Korean War”). Although this observation does not per
se preclude a conclusion that the Prince Series makes fair use of the Goldsmith
4
As much as art critics might distinguish Warhol’s aesthetic intentions from
those of portrait photographers, Warhol’s celebrity prints are invariably
identifiable likenesses of their subjects. The district court’s description of the
Prince Series works as transformative because they “can reasonably be perceived
to have transformed Prince from a vulnerable, uncomfortable person to an iconic,
larger-than-life figure,” 382 F. Supp. 3d at 326, rests implicitly on the Warhol
depiction being perceived as a recognizable depiction of Prince.
29
transformative character of Warhol’s work. But the Prince Series works can’t bear
that weight.
Warhol created the series chiefly by removing certain elements from the
flattened images with “loud, unnatural colors.” Warhol, 382 F. Supp. 3d at 326.
Nonetheless, although we do not conclude that the Prince Series works are
necessarily derivative works as a matter of law, they are much closer to presenting
the same work in a different form, that form being a high-contrast screenprint,
than they are to being works that make a transformative use of the original.
Crucially, the Prince Series retains the essential elements of the Goldsmith
Indeed, the differences between the Goldsmith Photograph and the Prince
Series here are in many respects less substantial than those made to the five
works that we could not find transformative as a matter of law in Cariou. Unlike
the Prince Series, those works unmistakably deviated from Cariou’s original
material that pulled them in new directions. See, e.g., Cariou, 714 F.3d at 711
30
(“Where [Cariou’s] photograph presents someone comfortably at home in nature,
work[s] of art such that the new work[s] were transformative,” and remanded the
case to the district court to make that determination in the first instance. Id.
In contrast, the Prince Series retains the essential elements of its source
that material and minimize others. While the cumulative effect of those
alterations may change the Goldsmith Photograph in ways that give a different
and the more distinct that artist’s style, the greater leeway that artist would have
to pilfer the creative labors of others. But the law draws no such distinctions;
31
whether the Prince Series images exhibit the style and characteristics typical of
Warhol’s work (which they do) does not bear on whether they qualify as fair use
under the Copyright Act. As Goldsmith notes, the fact that Martin Scorsese’s
recent film The Irishman is recognizably “a Scorsese” “do[es] not absolve [him] of
the obligation to license the original book” on which it is based. Appellants’ Br. at
37.
of the Prince Series itself. As used in copyright law, the words “transformative”
and “derivative” are legal terms of art that do not express the simple ideas that
they carry in ordinary usage. We do not disagree with AWF’s contention that the
a number of striking and memorable images. And our conclusion that those
images are closer to what the law deems “derivative” than “transformative” does
not imply that the Prince Series (or Warhol’s art more broadly) is “derivative,” in
Goldsmith succinctly puts it, “[t]here is little doubt . . . that the Prince Series
Br. at 36. But the task before us is not to assess the artistic worth of the Prince
32
Series nor its place within Warhol’s oeuvre; that is the domain of art historians,
critics, collectors, and the museum-going public. Rather, the question we must
answer is simply whether the law permits Warhol to claim it as his own, and
AWF to exploit it, without Goldsmith’s permission. And, at least as far as this
aspect of the first factor is concerned, we conclude that the answer to that
question is “no.”
2. Commercial Use
The statutory language of the first factor also specifically directs courts to
is commercial “tends to weigh against” finding that it is fair, we apply the test
with caution since “nearly all of the illustrative uses listed in the preamble
Campbell, 510 U.S. at 584-85 (citation and internal quotation marks omitted).5
5
To recognize this is not to read the commercial/non-profit factor out of the
statute. There are other situations in which the absence or presence of a
commercial motive may be highly significant. Producing a small number of
copies of a short story to be distributed for free to a high school English class may
be quite different from producing a similar number of copies for a lavishly bound
and illustrated “limited edition” of the work to be sold in the marketplace at a
high price.
33
And, since “[t]he crux of the profit/nonprofit distinction is . . . whether the user
stands to profit from exploitation of the copyrighted material without paying the
customary price,” Harper & Row, 471 U.S. at 562, the commercial nature of a
transformative such that the primary author should not reasonably expect to be
We agree with the district court that the Prince Series works are
commercial in nature, but that they produce an artistic value that serves the
greater public interest. See Warhol, 382 F. Supp. 3d at 325. We also agree that,
although more relevant to the character of the user than of the use, the fact that
AWF’s mission is to advance the visual arts, a mission that is doubtless in the
public interest, may militate against the simplistic assertion that AWF’s sale and
licensing of the Prince Series works necessarily derogates from a finding of fair
use. Nevertheless, just as we cannot hold that the Prince Series is transformative
as a matter of law, neither can we conclude that Warhol and AWF are entitled to
monetize it without paying Goldsmith the “customary price” for the rights to her
work, even if that monetization is used for the benefit of the public.
34
Of course, even where the secondary use is not transformative, the extent
to which it serves the public interest, either in and of itself or by generating funds
that enable the secondary user to further a public-facing mission, may be highly
finding that the use is fair, the fact that a commercial non-transformative work
may also serve the public interest or that the profits from its commercial use are
The second factor directs courts to consider the nature of the copyrighted
a greater leeway being allowed to a claim of fair use where the work is factual or
informational, and (2) whether the work is published or unpublished, with the
6
Goldsmith does not seek such remedies, and it is highly unlikely that any court
would deem them appropriate in this case. See Campbell, 510 U.S. at 578 n.10
(“[T]he goals of the copyright law . . . are not always best served by automatically
granting injunctive relief when parodists are found to have gone beyond the
bounds of fair use.”).
35
scope of fair use involving unpublished works being considerably narrower.”
Blanch, 467 F.3d at 256 (citation omitted). Although courts are required to
consider and weigh this factor, it “has rarely played a significant role in the
The district court correctly held that the Goldsmith Photograph is both
unpublished and creative but nonetheless concluded that the second factor
should favor neither party because LGL had licensed the Goldsmith Photograph
to Vanity Fair and because the Prince Series was highly transformative. See
Warhol, 382 F. Supp. 3d at 327. That was error. That Goldsmith, through LGL,
made the Goldsmith Photograph available for a single use on limited terms does
not change its status as an unpublished work nor diminish the law’s protection of
her choice of “when to make a work public and whether to withhold a work to
though we have previously held that this factor “may be of limited usefulness
where the creative work is being used for a transformative purpose,” Bill Graham
Archives, 448 F.3d at 612, this relates only to the weight assigned to it, not whom
it favors. See also Blanch, 467 F.3d at 257 (“[T]he second fair-use factor has limited
36
weight in our analysis because Koons used Blanch’s work in a transformative
manner.”).
unpublished, the district court should have found this factor to favor Goldsmith
the meaning of the first factor. And, because we disagree that the Prince Series
weight.
The third factor considers “the amount and substantiality of the portion
assessing this factor, we consider not only ‘the quantity of the materials used’ but
also ‘their quality and importance’” in relation to the original work. TCA
Television, 839 F.3d at 185, quoting Campbell, 510 U.S. at 587. The ultimate
question under this factor is whether “the quantity and value of the materials
used are reasonable in relation to the purpose of the copying.” Campbell, 510 U.S.
at 586 (citation and internal quotation marks omitted). To that end, there is no
37
one; indeed, we have rejected the proposition that this factor necessarily favors
the copyright holder even where the secondary user has copied the primary work
in toto in service of a legitimate secondary purpose. See Swatch Grp. Mgmt. Servs.
Ltd. v. Bloomberg L.P., 756 F.3d 73, 89-90 (2d Cir. 2014); see also Rogers, 960 F.2d at
taking even a small percentage of the original work has been held unfair use.”).
In this case, AWF argues, and the district court concluded, that this factor
and other expressive qualities, Warhol removed nearly all of its copyrightable
protect ideas, but only “the original or unique way that an author expresses those
subjects, lighting, angle, selection of film and camera, evoking the desired
expression, and almost any other variant involved.” Id. at 307. The cumulative
manifestation of these artistic choices – and what the law ultimately protects – is
38
the image produced in the interval between the shutter opening and closing, i.e.,
It is thus easy to understand why AWF’s contention misses the mark. The
premise of its argument is that Goldsmith cannot copyright Prince’s face. True
enough. Were it otherwise, nobody else could have taken the man’s picture
But while Goldsmith has no monopoly on Prince’s face, the law grants her a
the Goldsmith Photograph.7 Cf. Mattel, Inc. v. Goldberger Doll Mfg. Co., 365 F.3d
133, 136-37 (2d Cir. 2004) (vacating summary judgment where district court had
7
It is for this reason that the cases that AWF cites in support of its position (and
on which the district court relied) are not particularly instructive; each involves a
claim in which a second, distinct work was alleged to infringe the protected
expression of the original work, and each such claim was rejected on the basis
that the second work copied only the unprotected idea of the original. See, e.g.,
Bill Diodato Photography, LLC v. Kate Spade, LLC, 388 F. Supp. 2d 382, 393 (S.D.N.Y.
2005) (involving separate photographs of women in bathroom stalls with jauntily
placed handbags); see also infra Section III. Had Warhol used a different
photograph that Goldsmith alleged was similar enough to her own to render the
Prince Series an infringement of her work, these cases might be more instructive.
But he did not, so they are not.
39
concluded that “defendant could freely copy the central facial features of the
Barbie dolls” and holding that Mattel could not monopolize the idea of a doll
with “upturned nose, bow lips, and wide eyes,” but the law protected its specific
rendition thereof). And where, as here, the secondary user has used the
qualities such as contrast, shading, and depth of field that can be stripped away,
With that in mind, we readily conclude that the Prince Series borrows
qualitatively. While Warhol did indeed crop and flatten the Goldsmith
the images in the Prince Series makes plain that Warhol did not use the
accurately document the physical features of its subject. Instead, the Warhol
40
images are instantly recognizable as depictions or images of the Goldsmith
Photograph itself.
To confirm this, one need look no further than the other photographs of
Prince that AWF submitted in support of its motion below to evidence its
contention that Prince’s pose was not unique to the Goldsmith Photograph. [JA
1707-09] Though any of them may have been suitable as a base photograph for
Warhol’s process, we have little doubt that the Prince Series would be quite
different had Warhol used one of them instead of the Goldsmith Photograph to
create it. But the resemblance between the Prince Series works and the Goldsmith
Photograph goes even further; for example, many of the aspects of Prince’s
appearance in the Prince Series works, such as the way in which his hair appears
shorter on the left side of his face, are present in the Goldsmith Photograph yet
absent even from some other photographs that Goldsmith took of Prince during
the same photo session. In other words, whatever the effect of Warhol’s
the Prince Series. Rogers, 960 F.2d at 311. Indeed, Warhol’s process had the effect
41
of amplifying, rather than minimizing, certain aspects of the Goldsmith
Photograph.8
photograph of Prince to create the Prince Series, AWF proffers no reason why he
required Goldsmith’s photograph. See TCA Television, 839 F.3d at 181-82, 185
“defendants offer[ed] no persuasive justification” for its use). To the contrary, the
evidence in the record suggests that Warhol had no particular interest in the
of Prince, and there is no evidence that Warhol (or, for that matter, Vanity Fair)
provided.
8
For example, the fact that Prince’s mustache appears to be lighter on the right
side of his face than the left is barely noticeable in the grayscale Goldsmith
Photograph but is quite pronounced in the black-and-white Prince Series
screenprints. Moreover, this feature of the Goldsmith Photograph is, again, not
common to all other photographs of Prince even from that brief session. The
similarity is not simply an artefact of what Prince’s facial hair was like on that
date, but of the particular effects of light and angle at which Goldsmith captured
that aspect of his appearance.
42
To be clear, we do not hold that this factor will always favor the copyright
holder where the work at issue is a photograph and the photograph remains
identifiable in the secondary work. But this case is not Kienitz v. Sconnie Nation
LLC, in which a panel of the Seventh Circuit held that a t-shirt design that
expressive element such that, “as with the Cheshire Cat, only the [subject’s] smile
remain[ed]” was fair use. 766 F.3d at 759. As discussed, Warhol’s rendition of the
Goldsmith Photograph leaves quite a bit more detail, down to the glint in
Prince’s eyes where the umbrellas in Goldsmith’s studio reflected off his pupils.
Thus, though AWF urges this court to follow the Seventh Circuit’s lead, its
decision in Kienitz would not compel a different result here, even if it were
The district court, reasoning that Warhol had taken only the unprotected
held that this factor strongly favored AWF. Because we disagree on both counts,
43
D. The Effect of the Use on the Market for the Original
widespread, it will adversely affect the potential market for the copyrighted
work.” Bill Graham Archives, 448 F.3d at 613. “Analysis of this factor requires us to
balance the benefit the public will derive if the use is permitted and the personal
gain the copyright owner will receive if the use is denied.” Wright v. Warner
Books, Inc., 953 F.2d 731, 739 (2d Cir. 1991) (internal quotation marks omitted). In
assessing market harm, we ask not whether the second work would damage the
market for the first (by, for example, devaluing it through parody or criticism),
but whether it usurps the market for the first by offering a competing substitute.
See, e.g., Bill Graham Archives, 448 F.3d at 614. This analysis embraces both the
primary market for the work and any derivative markets that exist or that its
particular author claiming infringement has elected to develop such markets. See
Salinger v. Colting, 607 F.3d 68, 74, 83 (2d Cir. 2010) (affirming that fourth factor
favored J.D. Salinger in suit over unauthorized sequel to Catcher in the Rye despite
the fact that Salinger had publicly disclaimed any intent to author or authorize a
44
previously observed, the first and fourth factors are closely linked, as “the more
the copying is done to achieve a purpose that differs from the purpose of the
original, the less likely it is that the copy will serve as a satisfactory substitute for
the original.” Google, 804 F.3d at 223, citing Campbell, 510 U.S. at 591.
We agree with the district court that the primary market for the Warhol
Prince Series (that is, the market for the original works) and the Goldsmith
court’s implicit rationale that the market for Warhol’s works is the market for
“Warhols,” as doing so would permit this aspect of the fourth factor always to
have generated an active market for his own work. Notwithstanding, we see no
reason to disturb the district court’s overall conclusion that the two works occupy
does not contend that she has sought to license the Goldsmith Photograph itself,
the question under this factor is not solely whether the secondary work harms an
45
existing market for the specific work alleged to have been infringed. Cf. Castle
Rock, 150 F.3d at 145-46 (“Although Castle Rock has evidenced little if any
interest in exploiting this market for derivative works . . . the copyright law must
respect that creative and economic choice.”). Rather, we must also consider
would result in a substantially adverse impact on the potential market” for the
omitted) (alterations adopted)); see also Fox News Network, LLC v. TVEyes, Inc., 883
placing the burden of proof as to this factor on Goldsmith. See, e.g., Warhol, 382 F.
Supp. 3d at 330. While our prior cases have suggested that the rightsholder bears
some initial burden of identifying relevant markets,9 we have never held that the
rightsholder bears the burden of showing actual market harm. Nor would we so
9
See HathiTrust, 755 F.3d at 96 (“To defeat a claim of fair use, the copyright holder
must point to the market harm that results because the secondary use serves as a
substitute for the original work.”); Leibovitz, 137 F.3d at 116 n.6 (“Leibovitz has
not identified any market for a derivative work that might be harmed by the
Paramount ad. In these circumstances, the defendant had no obligation to present
evidence showing lack of harm in a market for derivative works.”).
46
hold. Fair use is an affirmative defense; as such, the ultimate burden of proving
that the secondary use does not compete in the relevant market is appropriately
borne by the party asserting the defense: the secondary user. See Campbell, 510
U.S. at 590 (“Since fair use is an affirmative defense, its proponent would have
evidence about relevant markets.”); Infinity Broadcast Corp. v. Kirkwood, 150 F.3d
104, 110 (2d Cir. 1998) (“As always, [the secondary user] bears the burden of
showing that his use does not” usurp the market for the primary work); Dr. Seuss
Enters., L.P. v. ComicMix LLC, 983 F.3d 443, 459 (9th Cir. 2020) (“Not much about
the fair use doctrine lends itself to absolute statements, but the Supreme Court
and our circuit have unequivocally placed the burden of proof on the proponent
In any case, whatever the scope of Goldsmith’s initial burden, she satisfied
it here. Setting aside AWF’s licensing of Prince Series works for use in museum
exhibits and publications about Warhol, which is not particularly relevant for the
reasons set out in our discussion of the primary market for the works, there is no
material dispute that both Goldsmith and AWF have sought to license (and
47
indeed have successfully licensed) their respective depictions of Prince10 to
succinctly states: “both [works] are illustrations of the same famous musician
with the same overlapping customer base.” Appellants’ Br. at 50. Contrary to
AWF’s assertions, that is more than enough. See Cariou, 714 F.3d at 709 (“[A]n
accused infringer has usurped the market for copyrighted works . . . where the
infringer’s target audience and the nature of the infringing content is the same as
the original.”). And, since Goldsmith has identified a relevant market, AWF’s
failure to put forth any evidence that the availability of the Prince Series works
poses no threat to Goldsmith’s actual or potential revenue in that market tilts the
AWF’s licensing of the Prince Series works to Condé Nast without crediting or
paying Goldsmith deprived her of royalty payments to which she would have
otherwise been entitled. Although we do not always consider lost royalties from
10
In Goldsmith’s case, photographs other than the Goldsmith Photograph, which
she has withheld from the market.
48
the challenged use itself under the fourth factor (as any fair use necessarily
involves the secondary user using the primary work without paying for the right
traditional or reasonable market for the primary work. See Fox News, 883 F.3d at
180; On Davis v. Gap, Inc., 246 F.3d 152, 176 (2d Cir. 2001). And here, that market
in the vein of the Prince Series, see J. App’x 584-99, and by the genesis of the
Prince Series: a licensing agreement between LGL and Vanity Fair to use the
Further, we also must consider the impact on this market if the sort of
stylized derivative image; permitting this use would effectively destroy that
broader market, as, if artists “could use such images for free, there would be little
11
Of course, if a secondary work is sufficiently transformative, the fact that its
“raw material” was acquired by means of a limited license will not necessarily
defeat a defense of fair use. As discussed supra, however, that is not the case here.
49
or no reason to pay for [them].” Barcroft Media, Ltd. v. Coed Media Grp., LLC, 297 F.
Supp. 3d 339, 355 (S.D.N.Y. 2017); see also Seuss, 983 F.3d at 461 (“[T]he
result in anyone being able to produce” their own similar derivative works based
on Oh, the Places You’ll Go!). This, in turn, risks disincentivizing artists from
producing new work by decreasing its value – the precise evil against which
Thus, although the primary market for the Goldsmith Photograph and the
Prince Series may differ, the Prince Series works pose cognizable harm to
editorial purposes and to other artists to create derivative works based on the
Goldsmith Photograph and similar works. Accordingly, the fourth factor favors
Goldsmith.
at the summary judgment stage where there are no genuine issues of material
fact.” Cariou, 714 F.3d at 704 (internal quotation marks omitted) (alteration
50
adopted) (collecting cases). As no party contends that there exist any issues of
material fact in this case, we believe it appropriate to exercise that discretion here.
Having considered each of the four factors, we find that each favors
Goldsmith. Further, although the factors are not exclusive, AWF has not
should take into account. Accordingly, we hold that AWF’s defense of fair use
AWF asks this Court to affirm the district court’s decision on the alternate
grounds that the Prince Series works are not substantially similar to the
The district court did not analyze the issue of substantial similarity
because, in its view, “it [was] plain that the Prince Series works are protected by
fair use.” Warhol, 382 F. Supp. 3d at 324. While “it is our distinctly preferred
practice to remand such issues for consideration by the district court in the first
instance,” Schonfeld v. Hilliard, 218 F.3d 164, 184 (2d Cir. 2000), we are not
51
logically antecedent to that of fair use – since there would be no need to invoke
the fair use defense in the absence of actionable infringement – and because the
factors we have already discussed with respect to fair use go a considerable way
when “an average lay observer would recognize the alleged copy as having been
F.3d 996, 1003 (2d Cir. 1995), quoting Malden Mills, Inc. v. Regency Mills, Inc., 626
F.2d 1112, 1113 (2d Cir. 1980). “On occasion, . . . we have noted that when faced
with works that have both protectable and unprotectable elements, our analysis
must be more discerning and that we instead must attempt to extract the
unprotectable elements from our consideration and ask whether the protectable
LLC v. Simone Dev. Corp., 602 F.3d 57, 66 (2d Cir. 2010) (internal citations and
quotation marks omitted). AWF and its amici contend that this “more discerning
12
We express no view on the viability of AWF’s remaining defenses, which are
appropriately considered by the district court in the first instance.
52
observer” test should apply here because photographs contain both protectable
and unprotectable elements. See Appellee’s Br. at 65; Law Professors’ Br. at 8. The
same could be said, however, of any copyrighted work: even the most
observer” test involved types of works with much “thinner” copyright protection
– i.e., works that are more likely to contain a larger share of non-copyrightable
elements. See, e.g., Zalewski v. Cicero Builder Dev., Inc., 754 F.3d 95, 102 (2d Cir.
Moomjy, Inc., 338 F.3d 127, 136 n.13 (2d Cir. 2003) (Tibetan-style carpets); Boisson
v. Banian, Ltd., 273 F.3d 262, 272 (2d Cir. 2001) (quilts). By contrast, “photographs
capture images of reality.” Brammer v. Violent Hues Prods., LLC, 922 F.3d 255, 267
(4th Cir. 2019), quoting Monge v. Maya Magazines, Inc., 688 F.3d 1164, 1177 (9th
53
the Goldsmith Photograph and apply the standard “ordinary observer” test. See
and the accused work is so substantially similar to the copyrighted work that
reasonable jurors could not differ on this issue.” Rogers, 960 F.2d at 307 (citation
omitted); see also Gaito, 602 F.3d at 63 (“The question of substantial similarity is by
Here, AWF has conceded that the Goldsmith Photograph served as the
“raw material” for the Prince Series works. See Appellee’s Br. at 6-7. AWF
nevertheless attempts to compare this case to several decisions from our sister
circuits concluding that the secondary works in question were not substantially
similar to the original photographs on which they were based. See, e.g.,
Rentmeester v. Nike, Inc., 883 F.3d 1111, 1121-23 (9th Cir. 2018) (Nike’s iconic
“Jumpman” logo and the photograph used to create it were not substantially
Pictures Television, Inc., 704 F.3d 173, 188 (1st Cir. 2013) (recreated image in made-
for-TV movie was not substantially similar to the photograph that inspired it).
54
But the secondary users in those cases did not merely copy the original
photographs at issue; they instead replicated those photographs using their own
subjects in similar poses. By contrast, Warhol did not create the Prince Series by
Photograph. Nor did he attempt to copy merely the “idea” conveyed in the
idea. This case therefore stands in sharp contrast to the situation presented by
Rentmeester, for example, in which the court explained that “[w]hat [the original]
photo and the [allegedly infringing] photo share are similarities in general ideas
basketball; a camera angle that captures the subject silhouetted against the sky.”
This is not to say that every use of an exact reproduction constitutes a work
that is substantially similar to the original. But here, given the degree to which
reasonable debate that the works are substantially similar. See Rogers, 960 F.3d
55
307-08. As we have noted above, Prince, like other celebrity performing and
creative artists, was much photographed. But any reasonable viewer with access
no difficulty identifying the latter as the source material for Warhol’s Prince
Series.
CONCLUSION
For the foregoing reasons, we REVERSE the grant of AWF’s motion for
Goldsmith and LGL’s amended counterclaim, and REMAND this case for further
56
Richard J. Sullivan, Circuit Judge, joined by Dennis Jacobs, Circuit Judge,
concurring:
I fully join the majority’s thoughtful opinion and its conclusion that the
Prince Series works are substantially similar to the Goldsmith Photograph and are
not protected by fair use. I write separately only to highlight what I see as an
to suggest that a renewed focus on the fourth fair use factor, “the effect of the use
upon the potential market for or value of the copyrighted work,” 17 U.S.C. § 107(4),
would bring greater coherence and predictability to this area of the law.
Inc., 510 U.S. 569 (1994), the “transformative” nature of a secondary work has
become the dominant focus in determining whether that work is protected by fair
use. Courts and commentators have recognized this trend and have observed that
it threatens to collapse the four statutory fair use factors into a single, dispositive
factor. See, e.g., Kienitz v. Sconnie Nation LLC, 766 F.3d 756, 758 (7th Cir. 2014)
list in § 107 but also could override 17 U.S.C. § 106(2), which protects derivative
1
test “are conclusory – they appear to label a use ‘not transformative’ as a shorthand
for ‘not fair,’ and correlatively ‘transformative’ for ‘fair’”). Indeed, one recent
empirical study found that, among a sample of 238 district and circuit court
ultimate fair use outcome 94% of the time. See Jiarui Liu, An Empirical Study of
Transformative Use in Copyright Law, 22 Stan. Tech. L. Rev. 163, 180 (2019).
This pattern is perhaps best illustrated in the district court’s opinion below.
Having concluded that the Prince Series works were transformative, the district
court found that the second fair use factor was neutral (despite noting that the
weigh in Goldsmith’s favor”) and found that the third factor weighed heavily in
AWF’s favor because “Warhol transformed Goldsmith’s work into something new
and different.” Andy Warhol Found. for the Visual Arts, Inc. v. Goldsmith, 382 F. Supp.
3d 312, 327, 330 (S.D.N.Y. 2019) (internal quotation marks omitted). But perhaps
most notably, as the majority’s opinion recognizes, the district court completely
markets after concluding that the Prince Series was transformative. See Majority
Op. at 45–50.
2
Placing dispositive weight on transformative use while reducing evidence
guidance that the fourth factor “is undoubtedly the single most important element
of fair use.” Harper & Row Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enters., 471 U.S. 539, 566 (1985).
fourth factor “is consistent with the fact that the copyright is a commercial right,
intended to protect the ability of authors to profit from the exclusive right to
merchandise their own work.” Authors Guild v. Google, Inc., 804 F.3d 202, 214 (2d
To be sure, some of this Court’s earlier decisions suggest that the Supreme
Court “retreated” from its emphasis on the fourth factor when it explained in
Campbell that “[a]ll [four fair use factors] are to be explored, and the results
weighed together, in light of the purposes of copyright,” 510 U.S. at 578. See, e.g.,
Blanch v. Koons, 467 F.3d 244, 258 n.8 (2d Cir. 2006); Castle Rock Ent., Inc. v. Carol
Publ’g Grp., Inc., 150 F.3d 132, 145 (2d Cir. 1998). But the statements in Campbell
and Harper & Row are not necessarily at odds with one another: courts can
consider all four factors while still recognizing that evidence of harm to the
3
potential market for the original work (or derivative works based on the original,
the contrary, even though Campbell is recognized for crystallizing the concept of
Wash. L. Rev. 597, 605 (2015). Campbell explained that transformative works are
more likely to be fair uses because they are less likely to “act[] as a substitute” for
or “‘supersede[] the objects’” of the original work, and are therefore less likely to
“affect the market for the original in a way cognizable under [the fourth] factor.”
510 U.S. at 591 (quoting Folsom v. Marsh, 9 F. Cas. 342, 348 (No. 4,901) (C.C.D. Mass.
1841)); see also Leval, supra at 605 n.38. Moreover, Campbell explicitly
disadvantage when they failed to address the effect [of their work] on the market
for rap derivatives” and remanded for further fact-finding on the fourth factor
despite concluding that the defendants’ secondary work was transformative. 510
U.S. at 590, 594. Campbell therefore does not stand for the proposition that
transformative use should be the dispositive factor in the fair use inquiry; rather,
4
evidence of harm to the potential market for the original work (and its derivatives)
By returning focus to the fourth fair use factor and being particularly
in” by an alleged infringer would adversely affect the potential market for the
original work, id. at 590 (internal quotation marks omitted), courts can escape the
more recent fair use decisions have placed greater emphasis on the fourth factor.
See, e.g., Capitol Records, LLC v. ReDigi Inc., 910 F.3d 649, 662 (2d Cir. 2018)
(describing the fourth factor as “undoubtedly the single most important element
of fair use” (quoting Harper & Row, 471 U.S. at 566)); Fox News Network, LLC v.
TVEyes, Inc., 883 F.3d 169, 174, 180 (2d Cir. 2018) (finding no fair use despite
in part because the technology “usurped a function for which [the plaintiff was]
Corp. v. McCollum, 839 F.3d 168, 186 (2d Cir. 2016) (recognizing that the district
affecting the licensing market for the [original work]”). And our sister circuits
5
have followed suit. See, e.g., Dr. Seuss Enters., L.P. v. ComicMix LLC, 983 F.3d 443,
459–61 (9th Cir. 2020) (emphasizing that the defendant did not “address a crucial
right for a copyright holder – the derivative works market”); Kienitz, 766 F.3d at
758 (“We think it best to stick with the statutory list, of which the most important
This is not to suggest that the majority’s opinion runs counter to this trend.
To the contrary, it properly recognizes the harm to the potential licensing markets
for the Goldsmith Photograph and its derivatives, and reaffirms that the burden
of proving a lack of market harm rests with the alleged infringer. See Majority Op.
at 45–50. I write simply to stress that this renewed attention to the fourth fair use
factor will ultimately better serve the purposes of copyright, which remains at its
potential authors by enabling them to earn money from their creations.” Google
6
DENNIS JACOBS, Circuit Judge, concurring:
concurrence. I write briefly to make a single point: the holding does not
consider, let alone decide, whether the infringement encumbers the original
It is very easy for opinions in this area (however expertly crafted) to have
related contexts.
The sixteen original works have been acquired by various galleries, art
dealers, and the Andy Warhol Museum. This case does not decide their rights to
use and dispose of those works because Goldsmith does not seek relief as to
them. She seeks only damages and royalties for licensed reproductions of the
Prince Series.
Although the Andy Warhol Foundation initiated this suit with a request
for broader declaratory relief that would cover the original works, Goldsmith did
not expressly join issue. The Declaratory Judgment Act is reserved for disputes
that are percolating over parties’ rights and obligations while harm threatens to
accrue. See United States v. Doherty, 786 F.2d 491, 498–99 (2d Cir. 1986)
(Friendly, J.); see also Broadview Chem. Corp. v. Loctite Corp., 417 F.2d 998, 1001
(2d Cir. 1969) (articulating the criteria for deciding whether to entertain a
declaratory judgment action). But Goldsmith does not claim that the original
works infringe and expresses no intention to encumber them; the opinion of the
The issue, however, still looms, and our holding may alarm or alert
possessors of other artistic works. Warhol’s works are among many pieces that
suit or uncertainty about an artwork’s status can inhibit the creativity that is a
goal of copyright.
A key consideration in this case is the effect of the Prince Series on the
As the opinion observes, the market for the photograph and the market for
the original Prince Series works are distinct. See Majority Op. at 45. An original
preponderating factor in its value. When the work is reproduced, it loses that
2
mystique, as anyone who has browsed a gift shop can appreciate. In a word, the
original works and Goldsmith’s photograph are not “substitutes.” Castle Rock
Ent., Inc. v. Carol Publ’g Grp., 150 F.3d 132, 145 (2d Cir. 1998).
Series retains the photograph’s expressive capacity for Prince portraiture and is
sought for that purpose. It may well compete for magazine covers, posters,
coffee mugs, and other media featuring the late musician. If the Foundation had
refuted the evidence of such market displacement, the weight of the analytical