Without Excuse Sample 1
Without Excuse Sample 1
Without Excuse Sample 1
Edited by
David Haines
Copyright © 2020 The Davenant Press
All rights reserved.
ISBN: 1-949716-03-1
ISBN-13: 978-1-949716-03-0
John DePoe (PhD, University of Iowa) is the academic dean of the Schools
of Logic and Rhetoric at Kingdom Preparatory Academy, Lubbock Texas.
He is the author of numerous articles in journals such as Philosophia Christi,
Ratio, and the International Journal for Philosophy of Religion. He has also
contributed to numerous collaborative books. He specializes in
epistemology, metaphysics, philosophy of mind, and philosophy of religion.
iii
(esp. medieval), the philosophy of religion (esp. the problem of evil), and the
philosophy of love and sex (esp. gender and marriage).
David Haines (PhD, Université Laval) lives with his wife and their four
children in Québec. He is associate professor of philosophy and religion at
Veritas International University, associate professor of ethics at Séminaire
Baptiste Évangélique du Québec, and has taught history of Christian
Apologetics at FTE-Acadia. He is also the founding president of Association
Axiome, an association of French Evangelical scholars, and the Christian
Philosophy and Apologetics Center. He has published a number of articles
on natural theology and co-authored a book on natural law. His academic
research focuses on ancient and medieval metaphysics, C. S. Lewis,
Thomism, and natural theology.
Bernard James Mauser (PhD, Marquette University) has written for various
conservative think tanks, and he currently teaches at both Southern
iv
Evangelical Seminary and Liberty University. He was formerly a funded
scholar at the Acton Institute. He is the author of a book on the Bible called
Reading to Grow.
v
CONTENTS
Preface viii
Joseph Minich
vi
13 Van Til’s Trinitarianism: A Reformed Critique 289
Travis James Campbell
PREFACE
Joseph Minich
vii
criticism in the spirit of theological sons to a father, recognizing that Van
Til’s influence has also been for their good. These essays are, therefore, of-
fered to the church in a spirit of gratitude for our fathers in the faith and for
their virtues—even if we seek to make the case that the Van Tillian tradition
has committed several errors that have had a significant impact on the life of
the church. Balancing on these registers is difficult, and because there is to
be no party spirit in the kingdom of God, it is fitting at the outset to name
some of the ways in which the Van Tillian movement served the church dur-
ing the complex twentieth century.
Of first importance, Van Til and his disciples were confident in the au-
thority and inerrancy of Scripture. For all the ways we have perhaps disagreed
about the usefulness and necessity of extra-scriptural revelation, in no way
should we neglect the example of their unwavering confidence in Scripture
(God’s own speech to us). Indeed, for the Christian, the Bible is of the great-
est importance, the very word of God. God’s word is a source of truth and
life, that which is worthy of our reliance and which both fittingly commands
and has rightfully earned our trust. In this, we should not be one iota less
confident than the followers of Van Til.
Second, Van Tillians were conscious of the spiritual and moral battle
that often stands behind an intellectual battle. While they perhaps risked pro-
jection in certain cases, they were undoubtedly correct about the relationship
between a misshapen will and the misshapen perception of reality.
Third, the Van Tillians insist that Christianity has something to say con-
cerning all of life. While we might disagree about what this means precisely,
it is nevertheless the case that the redemption of creation through the gospel
has in its scope the whole of the world in all of its aspects. In this, they were
faithful sons of their father, Abraham Kuyper.
Fourth, the Van Tillians cultivated theological creativity, fresh insight
into Scripture, and the possibility of growth in knowledge.
Fifth, the Van Tillians were good at keeping the gospel at the fore. They
have made bold evangelists. While we might not always agree with their par-
ticular arguments, we can only covet their heart.
Sixth, whether we agree with his philosophy or not, Van Til appreciated
the importance of satisfying the Christian mind. Part of what has drawn so
many people to Van Tillianism is its desire to give a satisfying account of
reality relative to our distinctive Christian understanding. Many Christian
viii
churches are alienating to thinking persons, and Van Til sought to address
this both pastorally and professionally.
Seventh, a lot of modern work is lending credibility to the Van Tillian
insistence that Scripture at least anticipates many philosophical insights.
Eighth, Van Til’s movement has functioned (sometimes via later disci-
ples) as a gateway drug to some useful philosophical insight, particularly on
the nature of knowing.
Ninth, even if the Van Tillian movement tends towards biblicism, its
expectation of finding relevant Scriptural insight into many fields has (in
more competent hands, at least) yielded much insight and fruit. There are
many questions that might not have been asked of Scripture apart from Van
Til’s influence.
Tenth, and crucially, Van Til cultivated an awesome view of God’s gran-
deur, but also of God’s availability to the creature and sinner. In a century
when so much of Christianity has been reduced to fluff, and granting that
not all who “talk big” about God are being truly pious, it is nevertheless a
priceless legacy to have fathers who speak reverently of an awesome God, and
who lead us to the One who gives Himself to us in His creation and cove-
nant.
To the extent that we differ from our fathers and brothers, we differ as
partners, therefore, in the project of God’s kingdom. While we seek to go
beyond and even depart from them in many respects, we go as building on a
foundation and set of evangelical instincts which still inform our own con-
cerns and priorities. It is our hope and prayer that these essays are received
in the spirit they are intended—as a good-willed offering to fellow pilgrims
on the journey to Christian maturity.
ix
x
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
xi
I:
THE BIBLE, VERIFICATION, AND
FIRST PRINCIPLES OF REASON
M. Dan Kemp
INTRODUCTION
CORNELIUS VAN TIL once claimed that “We cannot subject the authori-
tative pronouncements of Scripture about reality to the scrutiny of reason
because it is reason itself that learns of its proper function from Scripture.” 1
John Frame says of Van Til’s thought that “human beings are obligated to
presuppose God in all of their thinking.” 2 Van Til and Frame claim that God
is the ultimate basis of all knowledge. One famous reply to this view claims
it is self-undermining insofar as the Bible does not consider itself to be the
sole source of knowledge of God or many other things. The Bible, the reply
goes, does not ask its immediate recipients to accept without verification the
word of a purported prophet as a word from God. Frame replied that the
verification promoted in Scripture is itself a word from God and must be
accepted as such. Thus, they say, the Bible remains the sole basis for theology,
and the integrity of sola scriptura is preserved.
In this chapter, I argue that, if the Christian Scriptures constitute or
form the basis for all human knowledge, attempts to verify the Christian
Scriptures are not epistemologically profitable. This result is particularly acute
in readings of Scripture passages that seem to provide methods of verification
for a word of God. I argue that the position put forward by Clark, Van Til,
and Frame entails a reading of these passages that renders them useless as
1 Cornelius Van Til, The Defense of the Faith (Philadelphia: Presbyterian and Reformed,
1955), 125.
2 John M. Frame, “Van Til and the Ligonier Apologetic,” Westminster Theological Journal
47 (1985): 282.
1
THE BIBLE, VERIFICATION, AND FIRST PRINCIPLES
3
The argument goes back at least as far as Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics (72b33–73a5).
See Christopher Shields’ Aristotle, 2nd ed. (New York, NY: Routledge, 2014), 133, for
a presentation and discussion of Aristotle’s argument against conceptions of demon-
strative reasoning as circular.
2
M. DAN KEMP
contribute any credence at all to the conclusion. Finally, I consider and re-
spond to possible objections.
I should address one potential concern before getting into the main of
my argument. Readers might wonder why it is worth reading a philosopher
about this question. Isn’t it arrogant for a student of philosophy, who lacks
training in the formal skills of exegesis and the relevant scholarly body of
literature, to comment on this dispute? Shouldn’t it be left to theologians and
biblical scholars? Under some circumstances, this charge might land. I do not
think it does for this debate, however, since no complicated exegesis is re-
quired for my argument. This chapter concerns the use of evidence, its rela-
tion to circular arguments, and these two things applied to particular passages
in Scripture.
In this section, I will define and motivate the view that the Bible is the source
and standard of all knowledge. To Cornelius Van Til, “The Reformed apol-
ogist assumes that nothing can be known by man about himself or the uni-
verse unless God exists and Christianity is true.” 4 Presumably, Van Til does
not intend to assert merely that if God did not exist, there could be no
knowledge because there would be nothing at all to know. This would not
provide the Reformed apologist with an apologetic, since it would not ex-
plain, but only assert, that the universe depends on God. Just as the fact that
humans could not know anything if neurons or atoms did not operate as they
do does not imply that there was no knowledge until the 1890’s, neither does
the fact that our knowledge depends on God’s existence imply that it depends
on knowledge of God’s existence. Rather, Van Til is directly asserting an epis-
temological dependence relation: that any knowledge at all depends on
knowledge of God and Christianity. In other words, no knowledge can be
had without first having knowledge of God, who can only be known by rev-
elation. Thus, the revelation of God, the Christian Bible, is the first principle
for “Christian”—that is, true and genuine—knowledge.
First Principles
Advocates for this view motivate it by noting the need for a first principle of
reason. A principle is an explanation of a thing. We can introduce this idea
3
THE BIBLE, VERIFICATION, AND FIRST PRINCIPLES
by identifying it as the answer sought for when we ask various “why” ques-
tions. Why does the earth revolve around the sun? Why is the plant in my
window tilting toward the sunlight the way it is? and so on. Legitimate an-
swers to these questions explain the phenomenon we are considering. But
say you want to know the explanation of that explaining principle. You keep
asking “why” until you reach the end of the explanatory line by reaching a
principle that explains and neither has nor requires an explanation.
The explanations of our knowledge of these principles, however, are
not identical to the explanations of the principles themselves. Humans are
not privileged to have knowledge of the world, to paraphrase Aristotle’s fa-
mous quip, from the perspective of nature, absent great study or revelation.
Hence, we also ask a different sort of “why” question. Why did the jury con-
vict the criminal? “Because he was guilty” will not suffice as an answer. “Be-
cause the jury found him guilty,” is the right sort of answer, but one which
requires further explanation. “Because the evidence was overwhelming.”
“Because several reliable witnesses testified to seeing him commit the crime.”
“Because we found a note written by the defendant saying he planned to
commit the crime.” These answers follow what has sometimes been called
an explanatory order of discovery, as opposed to the explanatory order of
causes mentioned above. If you ask someone to explain how he knows that
water turns to gas when heated to 212 degrees Fahrenheit, you do not expect
him to start telling you about how at a certain match of temperature and
atmospheric pressure, the vapor pressure of the water equals the pressure on
the water by the atmosphere, and so on. In fact, this would not answer your
question at all. In other words, you do not expect him to tell you why water
turns to gas when sufficiently heated. One can know that water behaves this
way without knowing why, from which it follows that the means by which
one comes to know that is not solely the explanation why it is that. 5
The answers we want to this latter sort of “why” question provide a
basis for believing a proposition. The basis, moreover, is a normative princi-
ple governing our beliefs rather than, say, physical laws or biology. The latter
are certainly requirements for human reason as we currently experience it
without themselves being rational bases. For example, the soundwaves and
neurons that allow me to understand what my teacher says are a cause of my
knowledge. They are not, however, the normative feature we appeal to when
5 Unless otherwise noted, any further mention of “first principles” refers to first
principles of discovery.
4
M. DAN KEMP
6 These two features are necessary but not sufficient to make a proposition a first
principle, according to Aquinas. The further feature required is motivated by the
difficult problem of how we come to know first principles. See Scott MacDonald
“Theory of Knowledge,” in The Cambridge Companion to Aquinas, ed. Norman
Kretzmann and Eleonore Stump (New York, NY: Cambridge University Press),
169–70. My thanks to David Haines for pointing this out. We need not discuss this
problem here, however, since the description of first principles above is sufficient
for my argument.
5
THE BIBLE, VERIFICATION, AND FIRST PRINCIPLES
principles would each be “ultimate” in the sense that they cannot be reason-
ably questioned as reliable guides and they provide a basis for other non-basic
beliefs. 7
If there are multiple first principles, then “the ultimate standard” does
not necessarily mean “the foundation or basis.” For instance, a principle can
be ultimate in the sense of overriding other principles. Imagine someone who
is hard of hearing. He can still get along fairly well in conversation because
his hearing still gives him some knowledge. The fallibility of this knowledge
is, however, increased due to the defects in his hearing. This greater fallibility
often leads him to make mistakes that have to be corrected. One way to cor-
rect his mistakes would be to clarify a statement by writing it down. So, he
thinks he heard someone say at a gathering that they are “getting an evening
gown,” but his friend quickly writes a note to him that says he is “moving
out of town.” Of course, he is able to read because his eyes are able to accu-
rately perceive the letters on the page. Thus, the perception of his eyes over-
rides the perception of his ears, in this case. Notice, however, that this does
not mean that his ability to hear is not its own distinct source of knowledge.
He usually does hear things correctly and does not need correction.
Some say that the Word of God is “ultimate” in that it is overriding, like
my sight in the example above. The Word of God, however, is absolutely over-
riding in that no other source of knowledge could defeat it. This view is com-
patible with recognizing multiple basic principles of knowledge, principles
that cannot be challenged and immediately provide the subject with
knowledge of some matter. For instance, one can know something by his
senses, which have no further basis, and then later be told the same thing by
someone he trusts. The same thing known is given by two distinct and inde-
pendent principles of knowledge, sense experience and trustworthy authority.
Neither is based on the other, and each is able to give knowledge of some-
thing without the other, like the way we might hear a dog barking and then
see the dog that is barking. God provides us, on this view, with the ability to
know various things and supplements or overrides those abilities with special
revelation. So, if there is more than one first principle, then “ultimate” is not
the same as “basis,” since a principle A can override a principle B under cer-
tain conditions without being the basis of beliefs that could only be known
by principle B. For instance, my trust in testimony might under certain
7 This does not imply that first principles are infallible. As the next few paragraphs
6
M. DAN KEMP
8 Gordon Clark, Trinity Lectures, “How Does Man Know God?”, 27:22.
7
THE BIBLE, VERIFICATION, AND FIRST PRINCIPLES
belief in the truth of the Christian Scriptures. On the other hand, on this
view, reason presupposes the truth of the Christian Scriptures.
According to many who have espoused this view, the necessity of al-
ways and everywhere presupposing a proposition does not preclude the pos-
sibility of providing evidence for that proposition. 9 Advocates of this view
often emphatically tell us that evidence can be best, and indeed only, given
for the existence of God when those evidences are put forth and interpreted
according to “theistic standards,” which presuppose the existence of God.
For instance, consider the cosmological argument for the existence of God.
The position we are considering claims that this argument only works if we
assume a theistic universe. Consider what John Frame has to say about this
particular argument.
9 See Thom Notaro, Van Til and the Use of Evidence (Phillipsburg, PA: Presbyterian
and Reformed, 1980) for a standard defense of this claim.
10 Frame, “A Presuppositionalist’s Response,” 81.
11 John Frame notes in The Doctrine of the Knowledge of God (Phillipsburg, NJ: Presby-
8
M. DAN KEMP
Does this circularity entail the death of all reasoning…? No: (1)
All reasoning, Christian, non-Christian, presuppositional, “clas-
sical,” is in this sense circular. There is no alternative. This is not
a challenge to the validity of reason; it is simply the way in which
reason works. (2) There are distinctions to be made between
“narrow circles” (e.g., “The Bible is God’s word because it says
it is God’s word.”) and “broad circles” (e.g., “Evidence inter-
preted according to the Christian criteria demonstrates the di-
vine authority of Scripture. Here it is:...”). Not every circular
argument is equally desirable. Some circular arguments, indeed,
should rightly be dismissed as fallacious. (3) Reasoning on
Christian criteria is persuasive because (a) it is God’s approved
way to reason, (b) it leads to true conclusions, (c) and everyone,
at some level, already knows that such reasoning leads to truth
(Romans 1, again). 12
If the Bible is the first principle of all knowledge, then no argument can be
given for the Bible as revelation of God except arguments that have a prop-
osition like “The Bible is the revelation of God” in their premises. Circularity
is not a problem, it is argued, because no view in competition with Christian-
ity is in a better position. As Greg Bahnsen puts it,
9
THE BIBLE, VERIFICATION, AND FIRST PRINCIPLES
It thus appears that we must take the Bible, its conception of sin,
its conception of Christ, and its conception of God and all that
is involved in these concepts together, or take none of them. So
also it makes very little difference whether we begin with the
notion of an absolute God or with the notion of an absolute
Bible. The one is derived from the other. They are together in-
volved in the Christian view of life. Hence we defend all or we
defend none. Only one absolute is possible, and only one abso-
lute can speak to us. Hence it must always be the same voice of
the same absolute, even though he seems to speak to us at dif-
ferent places. The Bible must be true because it alone speaks of
an absolute God. And equally true is it that we must believe in
an absolute God because the Bible tells us of one. 15
10
M. DAN KEMP
Scott Oliphint says something similar about the relationship between the Bi-
ble and God himself in the presumption of reason.
[T]his is all just another way of saying that the only way in which
we can know God—or anything else, initially—is if God gra-
ciously chooses to reveal himself to us. That revelation comes
in and through creation (thus knowledge of creation presup-
poses knowledge of God), and through his spoken (written)
Word. As creatures, therefore, there is an inextricable link—an
inextricable principial link—between God and his revelation.
From the perspective of the creature, we cannot have one with-
out the other. And that is just to say that the principia [first prin-
ciples] of theology entail each other. We know God properly by
his revelation, and we know his revelation by knowing him
properly. 16
Van Til and Oliphint appear to say that God and his revelation are somehow
both supposed to be the single basis of all knowledge.
My argument in this chapter applies to any of these positions. Even if it
is thought that the Triune God and not the Christian Scriptures is the first
principle of reason, the Christian Scriptures are presented as a more funda-
mental principle of knowledge than other epistemological standards such as
natural reason, conscience, authority, and so on.
Several biblical passages suggest that the Bible does not understand itself to
be the only source of all knowledge or the basic principle of all reason. Alt-
hough there are many relevant passages that involve verification of the word
of God, we will only look at two in this section. First, we will look at Moses’
authentication as a prophet from God to the people of Israel enslaved in
Egypt. Then we will look at the prescriptions in Deuteronomy concerning
authentication of claims to prophecy. In the next section, I will consider why
some think that these passages provide evidence against the claim that the
Bible is the basic principle of all reason.
A Rational Defense of the Christian Faith and a Critique of Presuppositional Apologetics (Grand
Rapids, MI: Zondervan, 1984), 321.
16 K. Scott Oliphint, “Covenant Model,” in Four Views on Christianity and Philosophy,
ed. Paul M. Gould and Brian Davis (Grand Rapids, MI: Zondervan), 77.
11
THE BIBLE, VERIFICATION, AND FIRST PRINCIPLES
In the early chapters of Exodus, God commands Moses to bring the Israelites
out of Egypt. Moses is told by God to tell Pharaoh and Israel that he speaks
for God. This is surely an incredible claim without a great deal of evidence.
In order to follow Moses, the people would need some reason to think he is
a proper authority, and Pharaoh would need good reason to think Moses
speaks with an authority higher than himself. Anticipating this problem, Mo-
ses asks God how he can reasonably expect the people to believe him. The
exchange is worth quoting in full.
12
M. DAN KEMP
Moses delivered the law to the people of Israel in the form of the book of
Deuteronomy just prior to their entrance into the promised land. The law
was given to the people at least in part because Moses was not to enter the
land, and so they needed a codification of the law in order to remain faithful
to God. Naturally, Deuteronomy anticipates that some would claim to re-
ceive a prophecy from God, and that such claims will need to be tested.
Again, the text is worth quoting in full.
1“The Lord your God will raise up for you a prophet like me
from among you, from your brothers—it is to him you shall lis-
ten— 16 just as you desired of the Lord your God at Horeb on
the day of the assembly, when you said, ‘Let me not hear again
the voice of the Lord my God or see this great fire any more,
lest I die.’ 17 And the Lord said to me, ‘They are right in what
they have spoken. 18 I will raise up for them a prophet like you
from among their brothers. And I will put my words in his
mouth, and he shall speak to them all that I command him.
19 And whoever will not listen to my words that he shall speak
does not come to pass or come true, that is a word that the Lord
has not spoken; the prophet has spoken it presumptuously. You
need not be afraid of him. (Dt. 18:15–22 ESV)
God mentions that he intends to communicate with Israel through a
prophet in the future. Also, however, there will be pretenders who claim to
speak in the name of God. The stakes here are high. If God speaks to a
prophet who is then ignored by the people, they will be held responsible (v.
19). Alternatively, listening to a false prophet is bound to lead the people
13
THE BIBLE, VERIFICATION, AND FIRST PRINCIPLES
away from the will of God. Hearing a Word from God, but ignoring it, and
hearing a word of man as a word from God are both dangerous. As the pas-
sage suggests, in this context, it would not always be clear which message
comes from God and which does not. So God gives the people a test to sort
out the genuine from the counterfeit prophets.
These passages illustrate the natural expectation that someone claiming
to speak for God, and therefore a Word of God, requires a significant amount
of evidence. God does not deliver the Word and then remain silent, expecting
the recipients to take it in a sheer leap of blind faith. God gives them reason
to believe that the Word is trustworthy. Moreover, the verifications displayed
in these two passages are not rare instances in the Bible. The principle is
found at various points in Scripture. The authentication of Jesus as the Mes-
siah and of Paul as an apostle, for instance, reveal the same assumption. Scrip-
ture, it seems, can be authenticated. The question at hand is whether this
authentication itself presumes what it concludes. In other words, the question
at hand is whether the Bible presupposes a single basic principle of
knowledge (i.e. God’s special revelation) or many (e.g. the Bible and natural
reason). It is to that question that I now turn.
In this section, I will briefly review the main arguments for and against the
position that Scripture, per Exodus 4 and Deuteronomy 18, does not see itself
as the sole basis of all knowledge.
The Argument
Exodus 4 and Deuteronomy 18 are prima facie evidence against the claim that
the Scripture is the sole basis of all knowledge. In response to John Frame’s
claim that the Bible must be presumed by all reason, Gary Habermas says,
Over and over again, with the help of several checks and bal-
ances, we are told to test God’s revelation to us. To be reminded
14
M. DAN KEMP
Some have argued against the thought that verification of Scripture requires
an authority external to Scripture. These objections converge on the point
that allegedly external standards given by Scripture are in fact given by Scrip-
ture, leaving intact the claim that Scripture is not authenticated by any prin-
ciple outside of itself. Frame captures this point in his reply to Habermas,
15
THE BIBLE, VERIFICATION, AND FIRST PRINCIPLES
QUESTION-BEGGING ARGUMENTS
An argument begs the question when it assumes what it claims to prove. For
instance, if I tell you that my friend is trustworthy because he tells me that he
19 See also Frame’s, The Doctrine of the Knowledge of God, 130–133, for discussion of the
16
M. DAN KEMP
is, I have clearly made a mistake by begging the question. At the end of the
day, I have argued that I should believe what my friend tells me because I
should believe what my friend tells me. Some call this feature of the argument
“circularity,” though I will use the terms interchangeably.
(1) P & Q.
(2) Therefore P.
Each of these arguments assumes what it sets out to prove. Yet they are valid
in that their conclusions follow from their premises. But these arguments
clearly beg the question. Therefore, an argument’s being question-begging
does not make it invalid.
It may come as a surprise to many that begging-the-question is a valid
argument form. One need only crack open any elementary logic textbook to
see “begging-the-question” categorized as an informal fallacy and thus fatal
to an argument’s validity. However, there are reasons why an inference like
this can be important and useful. Say that you are a logician or software de-
veloper and you need P without Q, but you only have “P & Q” for some
reason. It is important that we should have rules allowing us to validly deduce
17
THE BIBLE, VERIFICATION, AND FIRST PRINCIPLES
Imagine that you are planning to meet someone for lunch whom you have
never met in person. You arrive at the agreed upon location at the agreed
upon time but do not yet see your acquaintance. You then see someone who
looks like the person you are supposed to meet walking toward you. You’re
pretty sure, but you aren’t entirely sure. Then you notice that the person has
a distinctly “academic” look, and you know the person you are meeting is a
professor. The person is middle-aged, and you know that the person you are
supposed to meet is middle-aged. In a split second, you formulate the
thoughts in your mind. “That’s the person. It looks like the picture I saw. It
matches the profile I know of this person. The person is also looking at me
and walking toward me. Therefore, because of all these things, it is the per-
son.” Now, in this case, you have made an argument that could be formalized
in the following way.
18
M. DAN KEMP
(6) P
(7) If P, then Q.
(8) If Q, then R.
(9) If R, then P.
(10) Therefore, P.
This argument is technically valid, since each conclusion follows from
the premises. Moreover, let’s say that all its premises are true. The argument
is therefore sound. It is clearly a bad argument, however. Why? It is not be-
cause it begs the question any more or less than the valid arguments noted
before. It seems, rather, that premises (7)-(9) perform no role in establishing
(10). And if they perform no role in establishing (10), there is no point of
their presence in the argument. If someone doesn’t accept (10), then he
doesn’t accept (6), and the rest of the argument isn’t going to help him accept
the conclusion. Premises (7)-(9) become suspiciously disingenuous. They are
a lot of work with no payoff, since they add no credibility to (10) that isn’t
already present in (6).
The first kind question-begging argument is useful for isolating a prop-
osition from a conjunction of propositions. The second kind question-beg-
ging argument is useful for adding credibility to the conclusion because the
other premises independently provide evidence for the conclusion. Question-
begging arguments like (6)-(10) do not add credibility to their conclusions,
nor do they perform the simple role such as conjunction decomposition.
They are thus not useful for showing why the conclusion ought to be believed
or how it can be known. Indeed, they couldn’t be. In order for A to provide
a reason to believe B, A must be better known than B. But if A is better
19
THE BIBLE, VERIFICATION, AND FIRST PRINCIPLES
P. (premise)
Therefore, P. (conclusion)
but not this,
P. (assertion)
This strikes us as bizarre because there is no rational difference between
asserting “P” and deriving P from the truth of P. Thus, in the case that some-
one is convinced by a question-begging argument for P but not by the mere
assertion of “P,” he or she has been persuaded by some non-rational aspect of
the first argument’s presentation. The argument “P. Therefore, P.” doesn’t
make P more reasonable. Similarly, the argument (6)-(10) above asks us to do
the heavy lifting of considering (7)-(9) when (7)-(9) do not provide evidence
for (10) without (6). Instead, the interlocutor is led to believe that (6)-(9)
makes (10) more plausible in a way that is inaccessible from directly asserting
(10) from (6) or “P” from “P.” It would be better to simply assert (6) or “P”
and be done with it. If that doesn’t rationally persuade them, then inferring
“P” from “P” can’t persuade them (barring insanity). And thus, any persua-
sion reached by adding steps is sheer deception. If asserting “P” does per-
suade them, then circular arguments cannot persuade them more. Circular
arguments play no rational role to show that a conclusion is true unless, as I
showed earlier, other premises independently provide evidence for the conclu-
sion. Barring that condition, circularity is an exercise in superfluity.
Asserting “P” may be useful for one to know it, such as with the case
of self-evident truths. It may be the sort of thing one believes merely upon
understanding, such as the statement that “parts can never be greater than
the whole” or that “those who expend great effort upon another are owed
gratitude by the recipients of that beneficence.” But the inference from P to P,
either immediately or with several steps in between, does not perform any
role in showing that P is true. If it happens to be persuasive to someone, this
20 Again, for discussion of this argument, see Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics, II.19, and
20
M. DAN KEMP
can only be due to features of the argument that have nothing to do with why
the conclusion follows from the premises. Thus, circular arguments, insofar
as they are persuasive, are deceptive.
Again, question-begging arguments can be valid and sound, so it is not
correct to say they are invalid according to the sense of validity most logic
textbooks employ. They do not violate logical norms in that strict sense. And
yet, most of the time, they are argumentative mistakes. There is a certain
amount of deception involved in question-begging arguments that are psy-
chologically persuasive, as we saw before with the person who was persuaded
by “P. Therefore, P.” but not by “P.” Similarly, if someone is persuaded by
“P; Q; R; S; therefore, P.” but not by simply “P,” then something has gone
wrong. The error is not in strict validity, since P follows from P. The problem
is that the dialectic between the person giving the argument for P and the
person who does not accept P has been halted erstwhile the appearance of
progress remains.
To summarize, bad question-begging arguments violate dialectical ra-
tional norms by giving the appearance of increasing the credibility of a prop-
osition without actually doing so. So if an argument’s premises are
dependently relevant to the conclusion, and the argument contains premises
that do not work to prove that the conclusion is true, then the argument is
to no gain. Broadly circular arguments violate dialectical norms of reason by
asking the interlocutor to expend effort to no gain.
21
THE BIBLE, VERIFICATION, AND FIRST PRINCIPLES
and the signs. They are not told, however, that the signs are a standard re-
vealed by God.
This brings us to a fatal problem with Frame’s reply to Habermas. Ac-
cording to that reply, those who hold that Scripture is the sole source of all
knowledge must understand verification in passages like Ex. 4 and Dt. 18 as
broadly circular arguments. In other words, the argument does not immedi-
ately infer “P” from “P” or “This word is a Word of God” from “This word
is a Word of God.” They involve a series of inferences between the conclu-
sion and the identical proposition that shows up as a premise. But, as we saw,
broadly circular arguments are worse than narrowly circular arguments in that
they are more deceptive and fruitless in the way they violate dialectical norms
of reason. If God’s Word is the sole source of all knowledge, it is to no gain
that it provides criteria by which God’s Word can be known. That is because
the inferential steps in between do no work to show that the conclusion is
true apart from what the conclusion can do by itself. It is superfluous to give
a test to verify an item of knowledge that itself constitutes the basis of all
other knowledge. But giving a test or an argument provides the sense that
there is a point to it, that some knowledge will be gained by following it.
It follows that Frame’s view has the unwelcome consequence of making
biblical verification pointless—a whole lot of work with no real payoff. Such
verifications add no credibility to the conclusion that was not already present
before. It would be pointless to do what Scripture tells us to do in these cases
if belief in its truth could not be suspended. If the Word of God were the
sole basis of reason, it would be manifestly absurd for it to provide a means
by which to authenticate itself. It would be like a piece of writing telling you
that it (that very piece of writing) is a piece of writing if it contains the letters
“p” and “q.” It is obvious that it is already a piece of writing and one could
not recognize “p” or “q” unless one already fully granted the document in
question to be a piece of writing.
Recall how I initially presented fallacious question-begging arguments.
My presentation there corresponds to John Frame’s distinction between
“narrowly” and “broadly” circular arguments. Narrowly circular arguments
can be valid, as I have shown. Broadly circular arguments are absurd, how-
ever, because they involve effort with no payoff. So rather than improving
the situation by “broadening the circle,” as it were, this makes the arguments
worse. They are no less question-begging than narrow circular arguments, so
any appearance they have of credibility is specious. They are, in short, worse
22
M. DAN KEMP
arguments because they violate rational norms by doing a better job than
narrow circular arguments of appearing to establish a conclusion without do-
ing so. It turns out, then, that it is a problem for Frame’s understanding of
verification in Ex. 4 and Dt. 18 that sees it as broadly circular.
RESPONDING TO OBJECTIONS
No Religiously Neutral Arguments
One objection to my thesis insists that no argument for the existence of God
is possible unless it presumes the conclusion. It has been proved, the argu-
ment insists, that such “neutrality” is impossible and that every realm of
knowledge makes clear and determinate presumptions about God. In other
words, circularity is permissible because it is unavoidable. This argument will
not do. First, even if it were true that all knowledge presumes religious
knowledge, it wouldn’t follow that circular reasoning is a licit way to argue. It
would just show that all knowledge assumes God, which is compatible with
the claim that religious knowledge is indemonstrable.
More importantly, this argument blatantly commits an is/ought fallacy.
That is, it argues that because something is the case—indeed, couldn’t be
otherwise—it follows that it ought to be the case. But it clearly doesn’t follow
that just because all reasoning that humans actually do is circular, all human
reasoning therefore ought to be. My argument has not been that there are
successful arguments for the existence of God that do not presume the con-
clusion in the premises, although I think there are. My argument has been,
rather, that there is no point in making an argument for the existence of God
or the truth of Christianity that begs the question, because such an argument
serves no rational purpose. If it were true that all human knowledge was cir-
cular, there could be no knowledge at all. But since we clearly do have some
knowledge, and since circularity implies that there couldn’t be knowledge,
demonstrative knowledge isn’t circular, and any theory that implies that it is
circular is false.
John Frame anticipates in The Doctrine of the Knowledge of God the objection that
broad circularity does not have a proper use and therefore cannot be
23
THE BIBLE, VERIFICATION, AND FIRST PRINCIPLES
“A circular argument sets forth the conclusion together with its true rationale.”
The “true rationale” is “the reasons why it should be accepted.” For Frame,
the true rationale for believing in God’s Word appeals to God’s Word. “That
is all that an argument can do.” This is a simple misunderstanding of the
notion of reasons. Reasons are the sorts of things we articulate in answer to
“why” questions. They explain why it is that we ought to believe something.
Such explanations can be acceptable only if they are better known than the
propositions they demonstrate. My argument in this chapter has been that if
Christianity or the Scriptures are the first principle of all reason, then there is
no rationale for belief in them. Perspicua vera non sunt probanda. Evident truths
are not to be proved.
24
M. DAN KEMP
Universal knowledge of God and his law does not show that circular argu-
ments are proper forms of argumentation.
Someone might try to save the view in question by altering it slightly. One
move would be to say that not all parts of Scripture are basic to all knowledge.
This view has some plausibility, since it appears to be confirmed by a simple
test. Consider the following passage:
25
THE BIBLE, VERIFICATION, AND FIRST PRINCIPLES
the answer to this question. But even for them, the experience of recognizing
scriptural and non-scriptural passages should alert them to the fact that it is
their memory, rather than the Bible as a principle basic to all knowledge, that
tells them which passage is a part of the 66–book canon. An uncharitable
objector might think that this refutes by counter-example the claim that
Scripture is the sole basis of all knowledge. 22 And certainly, it does refute one
version of that claim, which is that every part of Scripture is a manifest basis
of knowledge, and thus it can be recognized as such. It would be unfair, how-
ever, to saddle advocates like Frame with this view. 23
As I see it, there are two ways to preserve the claim that Scripture is
the basis of all knowledge while avoiding the claim that every part of it is the
basis of all knowledge. First, one may say that the whole of Scripture is such
a basis, but not necessarily the parts. This seems wrong, however, since Scrip-
ture’s whole is determined by a priority of the parts. In particular, some texts
are accepted as God’s Word on the basis of other texts. Take again the pre-
scription concerning claims to prophecy in Deuteronomy 18. A genuine
prophecy received by the people of God must be tested by this passage. This
suggests that the prophecy was not known as a prophecy by its mere presen-
tation. The passage that tests it, however, is Scripture of the basic sort. It is
22 Michael Kruger says, “It is a caricature to argue that a self-attesting canon means
that even the smallest portions of Scripture, down to even a single word, can be
immediately identified by Christians as divine. Such a caricature is built on the pre-
sumption that the Spirit simply tells Christians which words are from God and which
are not. But the Spirit, as noted above, does not deliver private revelations to Chris-
tians as they read a text (or do textual criticism), but simply allows them to see the
divine qualities of Scripture that are already objectively there. Since such qualities are
bound up with the broader meaning, teaching, and doctrine communicated by a
book, they are not as applicable to individual textual variations (which, on the whole,
tend to be quite small and change very little of the overall meaning). As a result, two
different copies of the book of Galatians, though they would differ at minor points,
would both still communicate divine qualities” Canon Revisited: Establishing the Origins
and Authority of the New Testament Books (Wheaton, IL: Crossway, 2012), 101n37. Later
he says, “[T]he biblical teaching that Christ’s sheep hear his voice [i.e. that the biblical
canon is self-authenticating] does not require perfect reception by the church with
no periods of disagreement or confusion, but simply a church that, by the work of
the Holy Spirit, will collectively and corporately respond (Canon Revisited, 107). Kru-
ger here anticipates the objection against the self-attesting view of the canon on the
basis of thought experiments like the one above.
23 The answer to the question is that neither is apocryphal. They are both from the
26
M. DAN KEMP
27
THE BIBLE, VERIFICATION, AND FIRST PRINCIPLES
case, verification would not be pointless since it would genuinely increase the
credibility of a claim, that this or that text is the genuine Word of God. This
view would still have to explain why some revelations are basic just in virtue
of being revelations while others aren’t. Nevertheless, these verifications
would not be “broadly circular” either, which remains a problematic form of
argument. This seems unlikely, however, not only because Exodus 4 involves
verification of God’s word and would clearly have to be a basic text. Also, as
Habermas notes, the testing of Scripture seems to be a pattern that charac-
terizes the whole.
There is a lot of work to be done about the nature, clarity, and certainty
of knowledge as it is understood in these four articles. I understand these
28
M. DAN KEMP
24 John Calvin grants that non-circular arguments can be given for the reverence of
the Scriptures (Institutes of the Christian Religion, 1.7.3). He suggests, however, that ar-
guments are weak because, if we believe the Scriptures because of reason, then reason
has authority over the Scriptures, and reason can later contradict or oppose the Scrip-
tures. Many have said similarly. Cf. also Kruger in Canon Revisited, (Wheaton, IL:
Crossway, 2012), 80. But “the Bible is not the ultimate authority” does not follow
from “the authority of the Bible can be demonstrated by reason” in any way that
risks undermining Scriptural authority. The Scriptures cannot be known to be true
unless the law of non-contradiction were epistemically prior to it, but it doesn’t fol-
low that reason has authority over the Bible. If the best arguments tell us that Chris-
tianity is true and the Scriptures reliable, then a better argument cannot come along
and show the opposite. Furthermore, reason does not “decide” the truth, but
29
THE BIBLE, VERIFICATION, AND FIRST PRINCIPLES
CONCLUSION
First principles are known indemonstrably. They are not known by inference
from some other proposition. No argument can be given for first principles,
but the Bible seems to assume that arguments for divine revelation can be
given. Thus, Frame has not shown us why we should not read Scripture as
prima facie evidence against the view that Scripture is the first principle of all
knowledge. In fact, he makes matters worse by suggesting we “broaden the
circle.” Increasing the distance between, say, “God exists” in the conclusion
and “God exists” in the premises only gives the appearance of demonstrative
knowledge. But in fact, insofar as such arguments are subjectively persuasive,
they present a first principle as if it were something else. This is telling since
it does not necessarily count against a belief to be put forward as self-justify-
ing. But they should be asserted in their naked glory so that they can be
known by themselves (per se) or their lack of self-evidence acknowledged.
This constant inclination to regard Christianity as demonstrable may, I sug-
gest, be the result of the operative but unacknowledged belief that it does not
form the basic principle of all knowledge.
Scripture provides examples of God’s Word being tested. Further,
these instances of verification are not plausibly explained as broadly circular
arguments, that is, circular arguments that incorporate several premises.
Broadly circular arguments include premises and sub-arguments that do not
provide evidence for the conclusion. They do not make the conclusion more
credible than otherwise. Thus, they are not useful as arguments. They are
psychologically useful or persuasive, as my argument notes, but this is the
very problematic thing about them. Their usefulness is not in any rational
discerns it, and therefore submits to it. This is often overlooked; some speak as if
reason could “decide” Scripture isn’t authoritative if it could “decide” that it is. For
example, if reason could establish Scriptural authority, it is thought, then reason’s
testimony that miracles can’t happen could override the Bible’s witness to miracles.
But if reason discerns the Scriptures are authoritative, then it can’t, properly speaking,
“decide” miracles are impossible. Thus, it is possible that one can reasonably demon-
strate that God’s word is the ultimate authority on which it speaks. Muller reminds
us that God and the Scriptures are said to be first principles only loosely (“Principium
Theologiae” in Dictionary of Latin and Greek Theological Terms, 2nd ed. Grand Rapids,
MI: Baker Academic, 288–89). Even though they are made self-evident by the Spirit,
they can be demonstrated via reason. And what can be demonstrated through reason
is not a first principle strictly speaking.
30
M. DAN KEMP
element in them, and thus they are deceptive as arguments. It is therefore not
flattering to Scripture to understand it as putting forth broadly circular argu-
ments when alternative interpretations are available.
This result prompts us to consider that there may be multiple first
principles of knowledge rather than just one. Knowledge is not a system
neatly worked out from a single indemonstrable axiom. Rather, there are
many sources of knowledge—sensory experience, testimony, memory, con-
science, and divine revelation—working together to inform our judgments. 25
I leave the task of working out these various faculties of knowledge for an-
other day. 26
25 Although I cannot work out this suggestion, it should assuage those who insist the
truth of Christianity or the Christian Scripture is the basis of all knowledge. Frame
contends “allegiance to our Lord demands that we be loyal to Him, even when we
are seeking to justify our assertions about him” (The Doctrine of the Knowledge of God,
130). Reasoning that does not presume Christianity, according to this worry, is “sec-
ular.” Thus, it fails satisfy the demand that everything, including reasoning, be done
to the “glory of God” and therefore under Christ’s lordship (1 Corinthians 10:31).
But if there are multiple principles of knowledge—however fallible—arguments for
the truth of Christianity that do not presume the truth of Christianity (that is, the
arguments do not contain the proposition “Christianity is true” in any premises even
if the Christian interlocutor does not suspend belief in Christianity) do not thereby
fail to be submitted to the lordship of Christ.
26 My thanks to Harrison Lee and David Haines for comments on this paper, and to
the attendees of the 2nd Annual Davenant Institute Regional Carolinas Convivium,
who asked penetrating and insightful questions which forced me to sharpen and clar-
ify this paper.
31
MORE FROM DAVENANT PRESS
DAVENANT GUIDES
Jesus and Pacifism: An Exegetical and Historical Investigation
The Two Kingdoms: A Guide for the Perplexed
Natural Law: A Brief Introduction and Biblical Defense
DAVENANT RETRIEVALS
People of the Promise: A Mere Protestant Ecclesiology
Philosophy and the Christian: The Quest for Wisdom in the Light of Christ
The Lord is One: Reclaiming Divine Simplicity
CONVIVIUM PROCEEDINGS
For the Healing of the Nations: Essays on Creation, Redemption, and Neo-Calvinism
For Law and for Liberty: Essays on the Legacy of Protestant Political Thought
Beyond Calvin: Essays on the Diversity of the Reformed Tradition
God of Our Fathers: Classical Theism for the Contemporary Church
Reforming the Catholic Tradition: The Whole Word for the Whole Church
DAVENANT ENGAGEMENTS
Enduring Divine Absence: The Challenge of Modern Atheism
OTHER PUBLICATIONS
Ad Fontes: A Journal of Protestant Resourcement
A Pilgrim Faith: Guiding Doubting Christians on a Journey of Faith (online-only)
ABOUT THE DAVENANT INSTITUTE
The Davenant Institute aims to retrieve the riches of classical Protes-
tantism in order to renew and build up the contemporary church: building
networks of friendship and collaboration among evangelical scholars com-
mitted to Protestant resourcement, publishing resources old and new, and
offering training and discipleship for Christians thirsting after wisdom.