Kant, Self-Awareness and Self-Reference: Andrew Brook
Kant, Self-Awareness and Self-Reference: Andrew Brook
Kant, Self-Awareness and Self-Reference: Andrew Brook
Introduction
1. I explore the issues in this paper at greater length in Brook 1994: Ch’s 4, 7 and 8.
Unless otherwise noted, references to Kant are to the Critique of Pure Reason, in the Akademie
pagination using the standard ‘A’ and ‘B’ notation for the first two editions (the only two that
Kant prepared himself). A reference to one edition only means that the passage in question
appeared only in that edition. Translations start from Norman Kemp Smith’s 1927 translation and
Guyer and Woods’ 1998 translation and have been checked against the original text.
first we have a long, detailed piece of digging to do.
One standard argument for (1), that certain indexicals are essential, goes as follows.2 To
know that I wrote a certain book a few years ago, it is not enough to know that someone over six
feet tall wrote that book, or that someone who teaches philosophy at a particular university wrote
that book, or ... or ... or ... , for I could know all these things without knowing that it was me who
has these properties (and I could know that it was me who wrote that book and not know that any
of these things are properties of me). Nor would it help to add details of a more identifying kind
— the person whose office number is 123 in building ABC, the person whose office phone
number is ... . If I don’t know that that office is my office, that that phone number is my phone
number, I could know all these things and still not know that it was me who wrote the book. And
vice-versa — through bizarre selective amnesia, I could cease to know all such things about
myself and yet continue to know that it was me who wrote the book. As Shoemaker puts it,
... no matter how detailed a token-reflexive-free description of a person is, ... it
cannot possibly entail that I am that person [1968: 560].
What a curious piece of knowledge – if it even is knowledge!
The standard argument for (2), that certain references to self do not require descriptive
identification, goes as follows:
My use of the word ‘I’ as the subject of [statements such as ‘I feel pain’ or ‘I see a
canary’] is not due to my having identified as myself something [otherwise recognized]
of which I know, or believe, or wish to say, that the predicate of my statement applies to it
[1968: 558].
Whether Kant was aware of (1) is an intriguing question, as we will see. He was clearly
aware of (2). Consider this passage:
In attaching ‘I’ to our thoughts, we designate the subject ... without noting in it any
quality whatsoever — in fact, without knowing anything of it either directly or by
inference [1781: A355].
This “attaching ‘I’ to our thoughts” business is interesting. In the kind of self-awareness in
question, one is aware not just of oneself. One is aware of oneself as oneself. One is aware that it
is oneself of which one is aware. Put in Fregean terms, one is not just aware of the being who
happens to be oneself. One is presented to oneself in a certain way, namely, as oneself (see
Ezcurdia, 2001). By “attaching ‘I’ to our thoughts”, Kant seems to have had something like this
in mind, something like “using ‘I’ to refer to myself as the subject of my thoughts”. Since, on
Kant’s view, it is not just identifying properties but any properties whatsoever that I need not
know in order to refer to myself as myself,3 ‘non-ascriptive reference to self’ might capture what
is special about this form of awareness of self better than Shoemaker’s ‘self-reference without
identification’ (Brook 1975: 188).
2. Though most often associated with Castañeda and Perry, a version of it can be found
even earlier in Nagel (1965).
3. Being myself is not a property of me, i.e., something that I and other things could have
in common.
But (2) is logically linked to (1). If I am aware of myself as myself without inferring this
from anything else that I know about myself, my knowledge that it is myself of whom I am
aware has to be independent, at least in some respects, of knowing anything else about myself. I
can be aware of myself as myself without being aware of myself as anything except — myself.
This shows that (2), of which Kant was clearly aware, requires something like (1). The existence
of such a link between (1) and (2) does not establish that Kant was aware of (1), of course, but is
still interesting. As we will see, there is some evidence that he was.
Moreover, Kant went further with these issues than any contemporary theorist. Unlike
theorists of the past few decades, Kant had the makings of a theory to explain (1) and (2).
Peacocke (2001) is the first contemporary theorist to have anything like such a theory.
Kant called the mode of reference to self that gives rise to awareness without
identification transcendental designation. In Section 1 we will explore this notion to see what
exactly it amounts to and how much Kant knew of the kind of reference that we use to achieve it.
Section 2 lays out Kant’s understanding of how awareness of oneself as oneself is different from
awareness of one’s psychological states (the latter is what Kant usually meant by ‘inner sense’)
and oneself as an object among other objects. Section 3 lays out a further key element of Kant’s
theory, the notion of what I call the global representation. Kant held that one appears to oneself
as a single common subject of a large number of psychological states (1781: A350). The notion
of the global representation is closely related to that idea. Section 4 draws the elements of the
theory together and in Section 5 we show how it explains (1) and (2). The theory turns out to
have implications for some other things, too, immunity to error through misidentification in
particular.
Kant’s most common way of describing the awareness of self yielded by transcendental
designation is this: “... through the ‘I’, as simple representation, nothing manifold is
given” (B135). If the kind of reference that yields awareness of oneself as oneself, awareness of
oneself as subject, is non-ascriptive, then the resulting awareness will not, or certainly need not,
present any properties of oneself.
If awareness of self as subject is non-ascriptive, the reason, of course, is not that the self
is some strange, indefinable being; as Kant brilliantly discerned, it is because of the nature of the
acts of reference used to gain this awareness. Kant spoke of this kind of referring only a few
times but when he did, he achieved insights into it that have only been rediscovered in the past
thirty-five years.4
transcendental designation, there is another, transcendent mind beyond such awareness? There is
little reason to think that he did (Brook 1994,Ch. 4:5). To be sure, he thought that there is a lot
about the mind that we cannot know — but here he meant the ordinary mind of self-awareness
and introspection, not some second, transcendent entity.
5. One can compare what Kant says about reference to self to his doctrine that existence
is not a predicate (A598=B626). In the same way that being aware of something’s existence is
not to be aware of any quality of it, being aware of oneself as oneself is something over and
above being aware of qualities of oneself. In his criticism of Leibniz’s Amphiboly, Kant says
much the same thing about space and time — to be aware of space and time is to be aware of
something over and above the qualities of space and time (A276=B332; see A281=B337).
6. Note that all the phrases just cited are from no earlier than the Paralogism chapter of
the first edition. Kant seems not to have developed his theory of reference to self until he needed
it to attack rational psychology. Note, too, that they are all from the first edition. In the second
Second, what if Kant’s work also has the basics of the idea that certain indexicals are
essential? That would be a good indication that he understood at least some aspects of reference
to self without identification fairly well, because the latter phenomenon requires the former:
indexical reference to self could not be essential unless there is a way of doing such acts of
reference that is independent of (non-indexical) identification.
Whether Kant was aware that, for certain purposes, use of indexicals like ‘I’ is essential is
not easy to settle with perfect confidence. Such evidence as there is, however, points to the
conclusion that he was. Specifically, Kant argues that awareness of certain things presupposes
awareness of oneself as “subject of the categories” in a way quite reminiscent of Shoemaker’s
claim that:
no matter how detailed a token-reflexive-free description of a person is, ... it cannot
possibly entail that I am that person [1968: 560].
Here is what Kant says:
The subject of the categories cannot by thinking the categories [i.e. applying them to
objects] acquire a concept of itself as an object of the categories. For in order to think
them, its pure self-consciousness, which is what was to be explained, must itself be
presupposed [B422].
This passage is from the extremely obscure second edition version of the Paralogisms chapter but
the phrase ‘its pure self-consciousness’ seems to refer to awareness of oneself as oneself,
awareness of oneself as subject. If so, what it seems to be saying is something like this:
Judgments about oneself, i.e., ascriptions of properties to oneself, ‘presuppose ... pure self-
consciousness’, i.e., awareness of oneself via an act of ascription-free transcendental designation.
We find what may be the same claim in the first edition: “it is ... very evident that I cannot know
as an object that which I must presuppose to know any object ... .” (A402).
A second passage, this time from Kant’s introduction to the chapter on the Paralogisms,
offers similar suggestions. The passage begins with a famous variant on the ‘no manifold’ theme
that we saw at the beginning of this section:
Through this I or he or it (the thing) which thinks, nothing further is represented than a
transcendental subject of the thoughts = X.
and then goes on:
It is known only through the thoughts which are its predicates, and of it, apart from them,
we cannot have any concept whatsoever, but can only revolve in a perpetual circle, since
any judgment upon it has always already made use of its representation [A346=B404].
The last clause is what interests us: “any judgment upon it has always already made use of its
representation”. Kant seems to be saying two things. On the one hand, to know that anything is
edition, Kant moved his discussion of awareness of oneself as subject to the Transcendental
Deduction — and, regrettably, deleted most of the interesting details. A different but equally
stripped-down version can be found in “The Psychological Idea,” §46 of the Prolegomena (1783;
Ak. IV:333-4).
true of me, I must first know that it is me of whom it is true. That would seem to require some
awareness of myself that could not be derived from any knowledge of (what are in fact my)
properties. Furthermore (a point that will become vital later), this awareness of myself as myself
is not via some independent representation of myself. The only representations involved are
representations of the objects of which I am aware. Awareness of self is somehow part of
representations of objects. We do not have ‘Ich-Vorstellungen’ of the sort envisioned by Frege or
Husserl.
In short, these two passages seem to be saying something like this. In order to apply the
categories to oneself, i.e., in order to make ‘any judgment upon’ oneself or know oneself as an
object, one must already and independently be aware of oneself as subject, i.e., as oneself. But
this is nothing less than the core of the idea of the essential indexical.
To summarize our results so far. Kant seems to have been aware of two features of
reference to self that Shoemaker views as distinctive:
(1) Kant was clearly aware of what Shoemaker calls reference to self without
identification; in his jargon, we designate the subject “transcendentally, without
noting in it any properties whatsoever” (A355); and,
(2) There are indications that Kant was also aware of the idea of the essential indexical.
In his terms, awareness of properties as properties of oneself presupposes
awareness of oneself as subject, as oneself.
If so, there is reason to think that Kant did know what he had found when he hit on
transcendental designation.
Few of Kant’s students have paid much attention to transcendental designation. Doubtless
there are many reasons for this. Kant managed to give a clear statement of what he thought about
the topic only once in the whole Critique, namely, on A355. Not only is this description
exceedingly brief but he dropped both it and the term in the second edition. It is also buried in
the middle of an obscure and what many, I think wrongly, take to be a parochial discussion of the
simplicity of the soul. Perhaps most importantly, the remarkable insights into the mechanics of
reference to and awareness of self that Kant sketched there were lost again with his death, to
reappear at the earliest with Wittgenstein (1933-4: 66-70) in his notion of the use of ‘I’ as subject
and probably not until Castañeda and Shoemaker.7 Indeed, it would have been difficult for
anyone to have recognized what Kant had spotted prior to Castañeda’s and Shoemaker’s work.
Kant himself lacked the apparatus needed to describe his discoveries adequately.
7. Though Shoemaker attributes the core of his treatment to Wittgenstein, one wonders.
In his later writings Wittgenstein seems to have maintained that apparently self-referential uses
of ‘I’ and cognates in fact are not referential at all. It is hard to tell whether he held the same
view in his middle period. Perhaps we could put it this way: Kant anticipated what may be one
thread in Wittgenstein’s middle period work; Shoemaker developed the idea that Kant had
anticipated, probably without knowing that Kant had worked on it.
Kant was not merely aware of some of the distinctive features of non-ascriptive self-
awareness. Unlike recent theorists prior to Peacocke, he had the makings of a theory to explain
them. Kant held that one gains awareness of oneself as oneself, as subject, in a way very
different from the way in which one gains awareness not just of external objects but also of one’s
own psychological states (and even of oneself when one is an object of one’s own mental states
— for example, when one sees oneself in a mirror). He also held that the awareness of self that
results is different from awareness of anything else in certain respects, respects that explain the
resulting peculiarities. Let us start with how one becomes aware of oneself and what the resulting
awareness is like.
Kant’s theory of self-awareness compares and contrasts in interesting ways with some
contemporary views. We just suggested a parallel between Kant’s views and Peacocke’s and we
will return to it. Kant’s views also contrast with some current theories, Rosenthal’s higher-order
thought theory and Dretske’s displaced perception theory in particular. These contrasts bring out
some of the originality and power of Kant’s theory, as we will see when we get to them..
Since the distinctions just canvassed are part of Kant’s doctrine of inner sense, we should
start with an account of is doctrine of inner sense but we won’t. His doctrine of inner sense is a
mess. Here are just a few of the problems. Kant insists that all representational states are in inner
sense, including those representing the objects of outer sense (i.e., spatially located objects),8 but
he also says that the object of inner sense is the soul, the object of outer sense the body
(including one’s own). He comes close to denying that we can be aware of the denizens of inner
sense — they do not represent inner objects and have no manifold of their own. Yet he also says
that we can be aware of them — representations can themselves be objects of representations
— and that representations can make us aware of themselves. In its role as a form of or means to
awareness of self, apperception ought to be part of inner sense. Yet Kant regularly contrasted
apperception, a means to awareness of oneself and one’s acts of thinking, with inner sense as a
means to awareness of — what? Presumably, particular representations: perceptions,
imaginings, memories, etc. Here is a passage from the Anthropology:
§24. Inner sense is not pure apperception, consciousness of what we are doing; for this
belongs to the power of thinking. It is, rather, consciousness of what we undergo as we
are affected by the play of our own thoughts. This consciousness rests on inner intuition,
and so on the relation of ideas (as they are either simultaneous or successive). [1798, Ak.
VII:161]
And these are just the most obvious problems. As I said, Kant’s doctrine of inner sense is a mess.
Nevertheless, the quotation just introduced contains three interesting ideas. The first starts
from the distinction between awareness of oneself and awareness in ‘inner intuition’ of ‘what we
undergo’, i.e., awareness of our representational states. One of the things that we undergo in
inner intuition is representation of oneself. If so, there is an important distinction between
8. “Whatever the origins of our representations, whether they are due to the influence of
outer things, or are produced through inner causes, whether they arise a priori, or being
appearances have an empirical origin, they must all, as modifications of the mind, belong to
inner sense.” (A98-9).
“apperceptive” awareness of self and awareness of self in intuitions. As Kant puts it in the
second-edition Deduction,
... the I that I think is distinct from the I that it, itself, intuits ...; I am given to myself
beyond that which is given in intuition, and yet know myself, like other phenomena, only
as I appear to myself, not as I am ... [B155].9
This distinction between the ‘I that I think’ and the I that this I ‘intuits’ is the distinction between
being aware of oneself as subject of all of one’s representational states and being aware of
oneself as the object of some of them.
The second idea is the suggestion that apperceptive awareness of self is “consciousness
of what we are doing” — doing. For Kant, we become aware of objects of representation via
apperceptive acts of synthesis tying a manifold of intuition into coherent, recognizable,
reidentifiable particulars. However, the standard way of becoming aware of an act of
representing is quite different from this. We become aware of acts of representing not by
receiving intuitions but by doing them: “... synthesis ..., as an act, ... is conscious to itself, even
without sensibility” (B153); “... this representation is an act of spontaneity, that is, it cannot be
regarded as belonging to sensibility” (B132). Kant tells us that here we do not represent by
forming an object. That is not to say that acts of representing are not themselves represented in
inner sense; they certainly are. It is just that they are not the object of a representation.
We can be aware of acts of representing via intuition, too, of course, but what is special
about them is that we can be aware of them just by doing them, just by representing something.
Another Kantian way of capturing what he had in mind here would be to distinguish between
‘awareness by doing’ and ‘awareness by having an image’ (for Kant, we are aware of all
intentional objects in images [A120] — he even thought that all intentional objects are
represented spatially [B154-5, B156, B158-9]). The point he is making is that we do not need to
represent acts of representing in images. The passage from B153 cited above makes that clear.
Equally, we can be aware of ourselves as subject just by doing acts of representing. When
I am aware of myself as the subject of a representation, I am aware of myself as doing the act of
representing. One can of course be aware of oneself via intuition, too — by seeing oneself, for
example, in a mirror. This is the way in which one becomes aware of one’s size, shape, colour,
etc. But when one is aware of oneself as the subject of one’s own representations or agent of
one’s acts, it is by being aware of acts of representing by doing them. Here is a passage from
later in the Critique where Kant says this very clearly:
Man, ... who knows the rest of nature solely through the senses, knows himself also
through pure apperception; and this, indeed, in acts and inner determinations which he
cannot regard as impressions of the senses [A546=B574].
How does awareness of our own acts of representing and of ourselves as their subject work?
The act of representing makes us aware of three things. Consider the sentence:
1. I am looking at the words on the screen in front of me.
9. In German, the first part is, “Wie aber das Ich, der Ich denke, von dem Ich, das sich
selbst anschauet, unterschieden ... .” Kemp Smith translates this, “How the ‘I’ that thinks can be
distinct from the ‘I’ that intuits itself ...” and inserts some unhelpful emendations.
Kant’s claim seems to be that the representation of the words on the screen is all the experience I
need to be aware not just of the words and the screen but also of the act of seeing them and of
who is seeing them, namely, me. A single representation can do all three jobs. In Kant’s words,
the awareness of the latter two items is given “not indeed in, but with ... intuitions” (B161).
Let us introduce a term for this function. Let us call an act of representing that can make
me aware of its object, itself and myself the representational base of my becoming aware of
these items. Almost any representation will do. Imagining Pegasus will do just as well as
perceiving external objects such as computer screens. Indeed, representational states which have
no apparent object such as pains or feelings of hunger will do just as well. Nor does a
representation itself have to be recognized to provide a representational base for self-awareness.
Just recognizing the object of a representation is enough for me to be aware that it is me who is
aware of it. Having the representational base for recognition of a state is not actually recognizing
it, nor indeed myself, but it is to have all the representation I need. This is why, to return to a
point made earlier, the basis of awareness of oneself is not some separate Ich-Vorstellung.
This theory of self-awareness is remarkably powerful. It rests on an idea that next saw the
light of day in any clear form in Peacocke’s (2001) theory. In the delta theory, having a property
is sufficient in relevant cases for its subject to refer to and ascribe the property to itself — just
Kant’s most basic idea. Kant’s theory also neatly avoids some of the problems that afflict other
leading current theories of self-awareness.
Consider, for example, Rosenthal’s (1991) higher-order thought theory. According to this
theory, to be conscious of some representational state, A, one must have another representation (a
thought) of which A is the object. For Kant, all we need is A itself. A representation itself has the
power to make us aware of it. Rosenthal’s view runs foul of objections such as that lots of
creatures conscious of their own states don’t seem to have such complicated thoughts, and that
the model readily leads to a regress of thoughts about thoughts about thoughts, and there is little
independent reason to postulate such a hierarchy of thoughts. Now of course Rosenthal has
answers to such objects — but for what we might call Kant’s same-order model, no such
objections arise. Advantage Kant.
Or consider Dretske’s (1995) displaced perception view of self-awareness. Here when we
are aware of our own representations (and, by extension, ourselves as their subject?), this is a
matter of inference from what we are representing, that this thing is being represented. Hence his
term ‘displaced perception’. This theory runs foul of the objection that we seem to know a lot
about our representations that goes well beyond what is being represented in them, e.g., whether
they are striking or faint, in one sensible modality or another, perception, memory or
imagination, and so on and so forth. Despite a superficial resemblance engendered by the idea
that representation of an object is all we need for awareness of the representation itself, Kant’s
theory is not a displaced perception theory. Indeed, nothing is displaced from the object being
represented. Representation of the act of representing and representation of self are distinct
activities. It is just that a single representations provide for all three; we do not need a distinct
representations for each act. Once again, Kant is safe from objections that face others. Once
again, advantage Kant.
Now the third idea introduced in the passage quoted earlier. It is this. When one is aware
of oneself as subject by doing acts of representing, one is not aware of oneself as an object of
representation of any kind. (By ‘object’ I mean intentional object.) Here are some passages: “it is
... very evident that I cannot know as an object that which I must presuppose to know any object
... .” (A402). “[The representation] ‘I’ is ... as little an intuition as it is a concept of any
object” (A382). “The proposition, ‘I think’, in so far as it amounts to the assertion, ‘I exist
thinking’ ... determines the subject (which is then at the same time object) in respect of
existence” (B429; second emphasis mine). To be aware of myself as an object requires not only
“spontaneity of thought”, that is, acts of transcendental apperception, but also “receptivity of
intuition”; that is, it requires “the thought of myself applied to the empirical intuition of
myself” (B430-31).
Let us spell this idea that awareness of oneself as subject as not awareness of oneself as
an object of a representation out a bit. Kant tended to tie awareness of objects very closely to
sensibility, to appearances and intuitions (see A104); all awareness of objects seems to be via
sensibility. But, as Kant put it, “... synthesis ..., as an act, ... is conscious to itself, even without
sensibility” (B153); being aware of an act of representing by doing it is not being aware of it by
receiving intuitions of it. In addition, he says that the “unity of the synthesis of the
manifold” (i.e., that we are representing the manifold in a single representation) is given “not
indeed in, but with ... intuitions”. Since one is aware of oneself as subject by being aware of acts
of representing by doing them, not via intuitions in sensibility (B430), it would follow that one is
not aware of oneself as a represented object. (On the other hand, Kant does say that the subject is
an object, the ‘transcendental’ object of inner sense, at A341 and A361. Because he uses
Gegenstand, not Objekt on those occasions, I take him to be talking about objects in a loose way
here that does not negate the distinction so carefully drawn in the passages quoted above.)
For Kant, this distinction between awareness of self by doing acts of synthesis and
awareness of things as objects is of fundamental importance. When one is aware of oneself by
doing cognitive and perceptual acts, one is aware of oneself as spontaneous, rational, self-
legislating, free — as the doer of deeds, not just as a passive receptacle for representations: “I
exist as an intelligence which is conscious solely of its power of combination” (B158-159), of
“the activity of the self” (B68) (Sellars, 1970-1; Pippin, 1987).
To close this section, let me situate Kant vis-à-vis one more strand in recent thought
about self-awareness, the so-called noncognitivist approach associated with the later
Wittgenstein. Strangely enough, some recent commentators, Powell (1990 for example, have
taken Kant’s assertion that awareness of self as subject is not intuitional awareness of objects to
be an assertion that what seems to be reference to self as subject is not a referential act at all and
even that there is nothing there to refer to. The idea is this. If all (noninferential) awareness of
things is intuition of objects, then, if uses of ‘I’ are nonintuitional, they are either nonreferential
or do not give us awareness of anything or both. I know of nothing in Kant that could support
such an interpretation and it is not plausible in its own right. As Shoemaker says, “in making a
judgment like ‘I feel pain’ one is aware of [no]thing less than the fact that one does, oneself, feel
pain.” (1968: 563). I think these exotic readings of Kant rest on two mistakes. One is the mistake
of thinking that, for Kant, all noninferential awareness is intuitional. The other is the mistake of
confusing non-ascriptive reference with absence of reference.
To summarize this section: According to Kant, we have two ways of becoming aware of
ourselves — by working intuitions up into intentional objects and by being aware of acts of
representing and of oneself as their subject by doing them. The former makes us aware of
represented objects, the latter makes us aware of ourselves as the subject and agent of the act of
representing. This distinction anchors Kant’s theory of the peculiarities of awareness of oneself
as subject. Before we can lay out that theory, we need to add one further element.
10. It is notoriously difficult to elucidate the kind of unity involved (Brook 1994, Ch. II:
5). However, noticing that it has both synchronic and diachronic dimensions can help us sort out
where immunity to error through misidentification could occur and where it could not, as we will
see later.
manifold] ... to a transcendental unity... [A108].
Kant seems to mean that what allows me to become aware of my identity as the common subject
of my various representations is that I can be aware of the single, unified and unifying acts of
representing by which I combine the objects of these representations, and sometimes also the
representations themselves, into a single object of a global representation. Kant called these acts
transcendental apperception. I think he was expressing the same idea when he said in the second
edition that I am aware of myself as the single common subject of a certain group of experiences
by being aware of “the identity of the consciousness in ... conjoined ... representations” (B133).
Put differently, Kant thought that synthesis into global objects is a necessary condition of
awareness of self as common subject. Without objects of representation being tied together as a
single complex object of a single representation, one might be aware of the subject of an
individual representation but one could not be aware of the subject of one such representation as
the subject of other such representations. Rather, I should have “as many-coloured and diverse a
self as I have representations of which I am conscious ...” (B134) — as are in fact had by me,
for I would not, of course, be aware that it was me. It takes a global representation to serve as the
representational base of awareness of self as common subject.11
Is a global act of unifying representation also sufficient for being aware of oneself as
subject? No; despite many claims to the contrary, notably by Strawson (1966), Kant was clear
that one could represent objects without being aware of oneself (A113; A117fn.; B132). If one
can have representations of which one is not aware, as was suggested earlier, one could have
global representations of which one is not aware — for example, if one’s attention was totally
focussed on the complex scene being represented. Even if each global representation is the full
representational base of self-awareness, a direction of attention or some cognitive apparatus
necessary for taking advantage of the available representational opportunities might be missing.12
(Something like this might explain why nonhuman animals are not aware of themselves as
subjects.)
To summarize. One’s global representation is the representational base of being aware of
objects, of the representation itself, and of oneself as the common subject of one’s
representations. We turn now to the theory of the peculiarities of self-awareness that can be built
on this base. All the pieces of it are to be found in Kant.
The basic idea behind the theory whose pieces can be found in Kant is fairly simple.
When the medium of awareness of oneself is the doing of acts of representing, the medium
imposes sharp constraints on what the resulting awareness can be like. These constraints account
for the peculiarities of awareness of self as subject identified at the beginning of this paper. That
Kant spotted distinctive features of “reference to self without identification” is remarkable
enough. That he had the makings of a theory to explain some of them is even more remarkable.
11. Discussions with Richard DeVidi saved me from some errors here.
12. Kant was aware of attention but discussed it only once in the first Critique (B156 fn.).
As we saw in Section 2, the special awareness that we have of ourselves as subject is not the only
form of awareness of self that we have but it is different from intuitional awareness of oneself as
an object and the differences can explain some of the peculiarities of self-awareness.
This theory is neither easy to spot nor simple to unravel. Kant never laid it out
completely, indeed he only hints at some of its most important features. Thus any reconstruction
of it is bound to be speculative. The key component of the theory, not surprisingly, is the global
representation. If A355 is the crucial text for Kant’s view of awareness of self as subject and the
kind of reference that yields it, A108 is the crucial text for the theory of why those things are as
they are. Between them these two pages contain the core of Kant’s whole picture of self-
awareness. Regrettably, they could not be more obscure.
One can be aware of oneself by seeing oneself in a mirror, by acts and states of inner
sense such as feelings, thoughts, etc., being objects of representations, by inferring things about
oneself from other things of which one is aware, by being aware of oneself through perceptions
of one’s body, behaviour, etc. in outer sense (A347), and perhaps in other ways. In all these
cases, one would be aware of oneself as the object of a representation.
To be aware of myself as an object, I need a representation devoted to that (intentional)
object, a representation of which the thing that is me rather than something else is the object.
Now return to the earlier claim that any representation that I am having can be the
representational base of awareness of self as subject, no matter what its object is.13 If that is right,
then all representations of which I am aware by having them present the same subject to me,
namely, me, and in the same way, as me. A fortiori, the single common subject of a global
representation is presented to itself as the same subject throughout this global representation. If
so, when one is aware of oneself as oneself, as subject, this awareness is not experience-dividing,
to use a term of Bennett’s — “i.e., [statements expressing it have] no direct implications of the
form ‘I shall experience C rather than D’” (Bennett, 1974: 80). In a statement such as
1. I am looking at the words on the screen in front of me,
the verb expression or the object expression may divide experience but the subject expression
does not. In this, awareness of self as subject is unlike all other awareness.
Why is this kind of awareness of self not experience-dividing? As Kant puts it, “if I want
to observe the mere ‘I’ in the change of all representations, I have no other correlatum to use in
my comparisons except again myself” (A366; cf. A346=B404, B422). That is to say, I could not
compare this ‘I’ to or contrast it with what is presented in any representation I am having in
which it does not appear. To use Wittgenstein’s phrase once more, awareness of oneself as
subject has no neighbour. In no representation of which I am aware by having it does the subject
appear differently from how it appears in any other.14 If so, I could not distinguish the self
13. Even some representations that might be somebody else’s by some other criterion
seem to provide that possibility. This will complicate the business of immunity to error through
misidentification when we get to it.
14. An obscure remark in the attack on the third Paralogism may be based on the same
idea: “in the apperception, time is represented... only in me” (A362). Part of what Kant may have
meant here is that all my representations that locate something in time or are themselves located
in time will also represent myself.
presented in one such representation from the self presented in any other such representation.
We can now explain why, when one appears to oneself as oneself, one is not appearing as
the object of a representation. A representation is individuated, differentiated from other
representations, by its object. But no representation of mine is made different from any other
representation of mine by the fact that it makes me aware of myself as its subject. To represent
something as an object is to place it vis-à-vis other objects, and usually to ascribe properties to it.
If so, to appear in a representation as subject is not to appear as an object of any kind, just as
Kant said (A342=B400). ( Interesting enough, Shoemaker says something similar [1968: 563-4].)
The basis in theory for Kant’s insistence that one’s awareness of oneself as subject is not
via “noting qualities” of oneself can be put this way. We can distinguish the subject from all
objects (A342=B400). What we cannot do is compare it to, contrast it with, one object rather
than another. If so, awareness of self as subject does not distinguish me from or identify me with
anything of which I am aware as an object, anything in “the world”. Something of great interest
follows: so far as anything my awareness of myself as subject could tell me, I could be any
object or any compilation of objects or any succession of objects whatsoever. Not by accident are
these exactly the topics of the first three Paralogisms. One of the mistakes of rational psychology
is precisely to take the simplicity (lack of manifoldness) in the unified representation of self to be
a representation of simplicity and unity. Kant, of course, insists that awareness of self as subject
tells us nothing about what the self is like (A355; B156).
Let us now put the idea of the representational base and the observations we have just
made about awareness of self as subject to work on some of the peculiarities of awareness of self
as subject discussed at the beginning of the paper. First, (2), self-reference without identification.
Two questions. First, how is self-reference with identification possible? It is possible
because awareness of oneself as the subject of representations of which one is aware by having
them (what a phrase!), one always appears to oneself in the same way. Thus, to recognize oneself
as subject does not differentiate the entity thus recognized from anything else presented as
subject. If a representation does not thus differentiate, does not divide experience, then one does
not need to ascribe properties to it in order to achieve reference, indeed unique reference, to it. If
representation can be without ascription in this way, then it is possible that, as Kant put it,
“through the ‘I’, as simple representation, nothing manifold is given” (B135), that there is a way
of referring to oneself that cannot be “accompanied by any further representation” (B132), in
which ‘I’ can only ‘denote’, not ‘represent’ (A382), can designate “only
transcendentally” (A355), that can “have no special designation” (A341/2=B399). This
awareness is a ‘bare consciousness’ (A346=B404; B158) that is not knowledge (B157).
Second question. Must self-reference take place without identification if one is aware of
oneself as subject at all? It must. If I appear to myself in the same way in every representation of
which I am aware by having it, not is awareness of self as subject without ascription possible, it
must occur without ascription. Ascribing properties would produce just the differentiations that
are not there in awareness of self as subject. But this allows us to explain (2), self-reference
without identification. If self-awareness requires reference to self, and if self-awareness takes
place with no ascription, then reference to self must take place with no identification. If so, we
have explained (2).
And also (1), the essential indexical. The idea of the essential indexical is that to make
references to self via ascribing properties, one must be able to make references to self that do not
ascribe properties. What alternative to ascriptive reference is there? So far as I know, only
indexical reference. If so, indexical reference is essential to awareness of oneself as subject.
Castañeda (1966) seems to hold that this feature of awareness of self as subject is simply a brute
fact of self-awareness and cannot be further explained. Had Kant ever have thought about the
issue, I conclude, he would have disagreed.
However, this does not explain everything that needs to be explained. Castañeda and
Shoemaker argue not only that indexical references to oneself are essential, but that in them one
must refer to oneself as oneself (or cognate). Does Kant have anything to explain this final
feature of indexical reference to self? Not that I know of.
The materials that Kant left us can help with some other things, however. First, an
element of his account shows that indexical reference using ‘I’ or cognates is essential in a
narrower range of cases than Castañeda and Perry thought. They claim that from knowledge of
properties by themselves, one could not know that the properties were one’s own unless one
already knew of oneself and as oneself. Notice that the way in which one is aware of the
property is not specified here. If we become aware of certain properties in a certain way, the
claim does not hold. Consider feeling a pain and becoming aware of it by feeling it. When I am
aware of a pain by feeling it, I know or certainly can know that it is a pain of mine. Yet we
described the pain non-token-reflexively (‘the person involved is aware of the pain by feeling
it’.) If so, the claim that indexical reference is essential holds in a narrower range of cases than
has been thought.
Indexical reference is essential only in those situations in which how one is aware of a
state or event does not settle who has that state or event. Roughly, how one is aware of a state or
event settles ownership for psychological states where there are two or more ways of becoming
aware of them, namely, by having them and by observing and inferring them in various ways and
one is aware of the state by having it. The element in Kant’s account that makes this narrowing
possible is, of course, his distinction between awareness of a state by having it and awareness of
it as the object of a representation.
This distinction, between awareness by having an experience and being aware in other
ways, can also be put to work to explain — and again to limit — Shoemaker’s notion of
immunity to error. This, as we said, is the idea that certain judgments are “immune to error
through misidentification with respect to the first person” (1970: 269-70; see 1968: 556) What
Shoemaker meant, as we saw at the beginning of this essay, is that in some situations we cannot
become aware of a person by being aware of certain experiences, take that person to be oneself,
and be wrong. To take the most plausible kind of example, I could not be aware of seeing a
scene, decide that it is me seeing it, and be wrong. Shoemaker introduced the notion in the
context of past-tense memory judgments but if it ever obtains, it obtains most clearly in the
present. (We will return to the past-tense cases in a moment.)
Kant’s account suggests that if I am ever immune to error in identifying a person as
myself, it could only be when I am aware of the person in question by having the experiences or
doing the actions via which I am picking out the person. Clearly there is no such immunity when
I am aware even of myself on any other basis, e.g., by looking in a mirror, seeing a body part, or
hearing someone discussed.
Indeed, there may be no such immunity even in some cases where I am aware of
experiences or actions by having or doing them. Suppose that one could be aware of a feeling by
feeling it when this feeling, as judged by any other criterion, is someone else’s. Feeling a feeling
is one criterion for a feeling being one’s own but it is not the only one. Perhaps changes in the
feeling are causally dependent on another’s body, the feeling has as its object a scene represented
from the perspective of another person, another person (or at any rate another body) can report
on the feeling in exactly the way that I can, and so on. If application of the various criteria for
who is having that feeling produced a mixed result of this sort, then Shoemaker would not be
obviously right to hold that we are immune to error through misidentification with respect to the
first person even about some experiences and actions of which we are aware by having or doing
them.15 Nor does such a split seem impossible. One could imagine wiring that let one feel a
feeling, perceive a scene, etc., where these feelings and perceptions were in every other respect
associated with another person. They were seen through the other’s eyes, the other person can
report having and feeling them in exactly the same way and on the basis of exactly the same kind
of experience as I can, and so forth. Simply being aware of a perception, feeling, etc., by having
it does not render the question of whose perception or feeling it is trivial.
Still further, if immunity to error through misidentification with respect to the first person
obtains at all, it obtains only of states, feelings, actions, etc., that one is currently undergoing.
There is no immunity with respect to things that I remember having or doing. When I remember
some thought or feeling or action from the point of view of thinking or feeling or doing it, I will
“automatically assume” (Parfit 1970: 15) that it is me who thought or felt or did it; I will be in
the same situation as if it were me that I am aware of. Yet, if traces of autobiographical memories
(more exactly, autobiographical q-memories) can be transferred from person to person in certain
ways, this need not be true. Suppose that I (q-)remember seeing the scene from the top of Mt.
Robson. I will ‘automatically assume’ that it was me who saw that scene. Yet I have never been
on top of Mt. Robson. Sally has, however, and memory-traces set up in her when she saw that
scene have been transferred to me. If so, it is Sally that I am remembering seeing it, not me. I
take it to be me because I remember the scene from the point of view from which she saw it but
it is still her that I am (q-)remembering. If this analysis is right, there is no immunity to error
through misidentification in autobiographical (q-)memory.16
The ur-phenomenon for Kant is the manifoldlessness of the self’s appearance to itself.
15. Powell (1990) raises some doubts about whether such immunity is unique to first-
personal reference, referring to Evans’ similar thoughts (1982). He also challenges Anscombe’s
appeal to this immunity as a reason to think that uses of ‘I’, etc., are non-referential. Strangely, in
the end he himself opts for a non-referentialist reading of Kant!
16. Evans (1982: 238) disagrees. He thinks that some autobiographical memories are
immune to error through misidentification with respect to the first person. It seems to me that he
runs two notions together, namely, awareness of self without identification and immunity to error
through misidentification. They need to be kept separate.
Interestingly, this lack of qualitative manifold appears even phenomenologically. One can easily
observe in oneself that having a representation gives one information about that representation
(what type of representation it is, how it was formed, what we are representing by it, etc.) but it
merely presents oneself as subject of it. True, the self is presented as me and this might be a
mode of presentation of a sort (Ezcurdia, 2001) but it is at best an extremely stripped down mode
of presentation. Beyond this ‘information’ that the thing presented is me, the representation tells
me nothing about myself. This barrenness in one’s awareness of oneself as subject was perhaps
one of the things that led Hume to think that no subject is to be found in self-awareness at all.
To summarize. Kant seems to have anticipated the idea of the essential indexical. He
unquestionably anticipated the idea of reference to self without identification. And he sketched a
most interesting theory of why it must be so. The theory is based on his claim that having a
representation, any representation, is the representational base for awareness of self as subject. It
seems unlikely that anything like immunity to error through misidentification would ever have
occurred to him — but his theory can help us limit and think more clearly about this notion, too.
Not a bad record for someone writing over 200 years ago!
Nor have we exhausted Kant’s contribution to our understanding of self-awareness, not
by any means. For example, his distinction between awareness of self as subject via doing acts of
apperceptive synthesis and awareness of one’s psychological states via representations in inner
sense is very much like the distinction Evans (1982, Ch. 7) draws between nonidentificatory
awareness of self and introspection. Again and also like Evans, Kant was interested in how
awareness of oneself as subject and awareness of oneself as object among other objects connect.
For example, how can we know that the thing of which we are aware as subject is one of the
things of which we are aware as object (B155)? These issues deserves their own unhurried
treatment. Here I hope to have shown that Kant anticipated some of the most important ideas on
self-reference and self-awareness of the past thirty-five years.
References