Tragedy, Dialectics, and Differancee On Hegel and Derrfda': Karin de Boer
Tragedy, Dialectics, and Differancee On Hegel and Derrfda': Karin de Boer
Tragedy, Dialectics, and Differancee On Hegel and Derrfda': Karin de Boer
XXXIX
1. Introduction
In his recent article "Genuine Gasche (Perhaps)," Geoffrey
Bennington quite vehemently criticizes Gasche for claiming in
both The Tain of the Mirror and in Inventions of Difference that
Derrida straightforwardly "belongs to philosophy.'? Bennington
here argues against Gasche that deconstruction is precisely
intended to destabilize the opposition between that which is
properly philosophical and that which is not and that Derrida's
texts for that reason time and again transgress the purported
border between philosophy and literature. Whereas Gasche
maintains that Derrida's work should primarily be read against
the backdrop of the history of philosophy, Bennington holds that
Derrida's multiple readings of texts from the philosophical
tradition do not so much oblige us to turn to the same
philosophical texts as open up the possibility of "different debts
and engagements." I do not wish in any way to deny that the
literary, playful, and unpredictable commentaries advocated by
Bennington are in line with one of the strands of Derrida's
texts. Rather, it seems to me that the positions taken up by
Gasche and Bennington represent opposed determinations of
the text as such, to both of which Derrida's writings seek
simultaneously to do justice. This does not mean that they
achieve a perfect synthesis of philosophical depth and literary
playfulness but, on the contrary, that the two sides at once
enhance and thwart each other. I will argue in this article that
it is precisely this dynamic that is at issue in deconstruction.
Although I agree with Bennington that one cannot reduce
Derrida's work to its philosophical strand alone, I would
maintain that in order to clarify what is at stake in Derrida's
deconstruction of traditional oppositions such as those between
331
Karin de Boer
332
Tragedy, Dialectics, and Differance
333
Karin de Boer
334
Tragedy, Dialectics, and Difference
not only grafted onto Hegel's but also undermines the basic
presuppositions of his speculative science. In the essay
entitled "Differance" and in various other texts, Derrida
remarks in this respect that what he calls difference has a
profound affinity with Hegelian discourse and is, up to a
certain point, unable to break with it. On the other hand,
however, he holds that this differance entails a radical
displacement of Hegelian discourse:
335
Karin de Boer
336
Tragedy, Dialectics, and Differance
337
Karin de Boer
338
Tragedy, Dialectics, and Differance
339
Karin de Boer
more, spirit stages itself in such a way that it not only becomes
the actor but also the spectator of its own acting. Both its acting
and its self-spectating can take place only in and through us,
finite human beings; spirit needs us to enact itself, to divide
itself against itself, to watch its own struggles, conflicts, and
declines, and to increasingly comprehend their inner logic.
It is not evident, however, what kind of play spirit is staging
for us and for itself. Is our history to be understood as a
tragedy, a tragicomedy, a never-ending soap opera, an absurd
play, or as yet something else? Needless to say, many philoso-
phers would deny the possibility of any encompassing compre-
hension of the true nature of history. Most of them would agree,
though, that Hegel's interpretation of history as the stage of
spirit's increasing self-actualization can no longer be main-
tained. Spirit's speculative self-comprehension seems to ensue
from a certain blindness to the movement of its own history. It
is this blindness, I think, that Derrida's texts time and again
try to address.
According to Hegel, every historical culture has specific
possibilities of interpreting itself. The spirit of a certain culture
gains insight into itself through art, religion, or philosophy. This
self-elucidation of a culture constitutes in fact the core of
history itself. In the Phenomenology of Spirit and in various
other texts, Hegel analyzes the essence of natural ethical life
tSittlichheit) by starting out from Greek tragedy, notably from
the Antigone. If it is true that this first mode of ethical life has
reached its full bloom in Greek culture, and if it is also true
that the Sophoclean tragedies most eminently interpret this
life, Hegel seems right to base his philosophical interpretations
of ethical life on these tragedies. It should be emphasized that
the Phenomenology of Spirit does not at all intend to offer an
interpretation of Sophocles' Antigone. Hegel only goes along
with what he considers an eminent instance of the self-
interpretation of Greek culture at the level of the arts in order
to uncover the conflict that constitutes the core of the Antigone
as a mode of the self-differentiating dynamic of the absolute
concept.
Hegel makes clear, however, that tragedy cannot serve as a
basis for the interpretation of his own time, let alone for the
interpretation of history as such. Because individual self-
consciousness had hardly begun to develop in this period, both
Greek ethical life and its tragic self-interpretation have a
limited reach. According to Hegel, Greek culture destroyed itself
by the unavoidable emergence of a conflict between the
different ethical values that from the very outset inhered its
ethical life. This destruction prepares the way for an
organization of society based on the rights of the individual as
an abstract person (the Roman Empire}." The one-sided
character of this self-organization of society yields in its turn a
340
Tragedy, Dialectics, and Differance
341
Karin de Boer
342
Tragedy, Dialectics, and Differance
343
Karin de Boer
344
Tragedy, Dialectics, and Differance
345
Karin de Boer
Just as words can only become what they should become, that
is, meaningful, by virtue of a differencing force that simul-
taneously prevents them from definitively achieving their aim,
every human undertaking is essentially threatened by the very
means that it needs in order to accomplish itself. If it is true
that Derrida thus tries to make us aware of the radical finitude
of human life and its self-interpretations, and if it is possible to
start out from the structure inherent in Greek tragedy to
articulate precisely a kind of principle that accounts for this
radical finitude, as I have tried to do, then it is not so strange,
perhaps, to interpret the principle that seems to guide Derrida's
analyses as accounting for the tragic character of all move-
ments enacted by human beings.
Derrida turns against Aristotle and Hegel in that he no
longer understands the finite character of beings as caused by
the fact that they occur in time and need matter in order to
actually take shape. Aristotle and Hegel acknowledge the
differencing force of time as a means that makes it possible for
beings to accomplish themselves but lets itself be sublated by
the even greater force of thinking, that is to say, by the prin-
ciple of self-actualization that culminates in speculative
thought. Derrida attempts to dislodge the basic frame of meta-
physics by indicating a differencing force that is more original
than time and even underlies the process of self-actualization
that Aristotle and Hegel consider to constitute the most essen-
tial rnovemen t.I" If one endorses the idea of such a primal
differencing force, it is no longer possible to distinguish between
a realm within which all finite beings are liable to change and
decay on the one hand and a process of pure, infinite self-
actualization on the other. If the innermost dunamis of human
life is in itself radically finite, then finitude can no longer be
assigned to one side of a two-sided reality, that is to say, to
external circumstances that do not infringe upon the eternal
and essential.
Derrida would say that the distinction between the infinite
and the finite that has from the outset allowed philosophy to
346
Tragedy, Dialectics, and Differance
347
Karin de Boer
348
Tragedy, Dialectics, and Differance
Notes
1 The research on which this article is based was made possible by
a grant from the Dutch Organization for Scientific Research (NWO).
2 G. Bennington, "Genuine Gasche (Perhaps)," in Interrupting
Derrida (London/New York: Routledge, 2000), 156; his earlier article
"Deconstruction and the Philosophers: The Very Idea" in Legislations:
The Politics of Deconstruction (London/New York: Verso, 1994) is
349
Karin de Boer
350
Tragedy, Dialectics, and Differance
351
Karin de Boer
352
Tragedy, Dialectics, and Differance
353
Karin de Boer
all the masterpieces of the classical and the modern world ... the
Antigone seems to me to be the most magnificent and satisfying work
of art of this kind" (Aesth III, 549-550/11, 1217-1218). These passages
also suggest that Antigone and Creon, and by implication women and
men in general, are not totally bound by the choices of ethical life that
nature imposes on them. In the Phenomenology Hegel states that
every natural ethical action has a criminal side "because it does not do
away with the natural allocation of the two laws to the two sexes, but
rather ... remains within the sphere of natural immediacy" When 308/
282). This implies that in the further development of ethical life the
natural allocation of the two laws to the two sexes is to be sublated,
that is to say, is to play only a subordinate part in social and moral
interaction. In Glas, Derrida refers to this passage without mentioning
that this kind of 'crime' is-according to Hegel-restricted to the
natural, immediate side of ethical action. Cf. J. Derrida, Glas (Paris:
Galilee, 1974), 192a-193a/Glas, translated by J. P. Leavey and R. Rand
(Lincoln and London: Nebraska University Press, 1986), 171a. For
general interpretations of Glas, see S. Critchley, "A Commentary Upon
Derrida's Reading of Hegel in Glas;" in Hegel after Derrida, ed. by S.
Barnett, 197-226; Gaschs, "Strictly Bonded," in Inventions of
Difference, 171-198.
37 Aesth III, 549/11, 1217, translation modified.
38 Cf. "What is the function of this Christian model? In what sense
is it exemplary for speculative onto-theology? Can this model be
circumscribed and displaced as a finite and particular structure, bound
to given historical conditions? Can a history different from the one
represented here be interrogated? Can the horizon be changed? the
logic?" (Derrida, Glas, 41a-42a/33a).
39 In "Hegel: Or the Tragedy of Thinking," M. de Beistegui asserts
that the tragic sustains speculative dialectics in that the latter
"affirms its positivity only in and through a total engagement in its
opposite" in order to become itself (28). On the other hand, the tragic
in Hegel remains subordinated to its speculative reconciliation (33).
Although I agree with this interpretation, it seems to me that de
Beistegui's conception of the tragic is not specific enough to sustain his
determination of the relation between the tragic and dialectics. See
also C. Menke, Tragodie im Sittlichen, Gerechtigkeit und Freiheit nach
Hegel (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1996). In his interesting study,
Menke examines how the tragic collision between the general and the
particular reappears in modernity as the insurmountable collision
between social justice and individual self-realization.
40 Phen 309/283.
41 Cf. Aesth I, 278-279/1, 213; Aesth III, 545/11, 1214.
42 Phen 309-310/284.
43 Aesth I, 279/1, 214; Aesth III, 544-545/11, 1213-1214.
44 This is the case at several levels: the course of Oedipus's life as a
whole is determined by the omen that made his father decide to rid
himself of his newborn son. Then again, when Oedipus the king is
confronted with the plague that torments Thebes, he ordains that the
murderer of Laius be found and banned from the city; Oedipus effort
to save his city by taking away the cause of the pollution thus causes
his ultimate downfall. Oedipus's fate is intimately related to that of
Thebes: he causes both its salvation and its decline. Cf. M. Dillon,
Politics of Security. Towards a Political Philosophy of Continental
354
Tragedy, Dialectics, and Differance
355
Karin de Boer
356
Tragedy, Dialectics, and Differance
357