LGBTQ Z?: Hypatia Vol. 27, No. 3 (Summer 2012) © by Hypatia, Inc
LGBTQ Z?: Hypatia Vol. 27, No. 3 (Summer 2012) © by Hypatia, Inc
LGBTQ Z?: Hypatia Vol. 27, No. 3 (Summer 2012) © by Hypatia, Inc
KATHY RUDY
In this essay, I draw the discourses around bestiality/zoophilia into the realm of queer
theory in order to point to a new form of animal advocacy, something that might be
called, in shorthand, loving animals. My argument is quite simple: if all interdicts
against bestiality depend on a firm notion of exactly what sex is (and they do), and if
queer theory disrupts that firm foundation by arguing that sexuality is impossible to
define beforehand and pervades many different kinds of relations (and it does), then
viewing bestiality in the frame of queer theory can give us another way to conceptualize
the limitations of human exceptionalism. By focusing on transformative connections
between humans and animals, a new form of animal advocacy emerges through the
revolutionary power of love.
“Heavy Petting” that from the animals’ point of view, having sex with them
wasn’t nearly as harmful as killing or torturing them. Although he condemned
all sex acts where animals were killed, he brought up the interesting point that
in many cases, animals appear to initiate sex, to have erections, to seek out geni-
tal intimacy, and so on. Why, then, in this most intimate domain, is our use of
animals most vociferously condemned?
The second reality that needs to be taken into consideration for this essay
is the burgeoning pet culture in America of the last thirty or so years. Humans
have never been closer to their pets, or spent more time or money on them.1
Part of me would like to see these new developments as seeds of transgression,
or early markers of the demise of human exceptionalism. That is, in one sense
the intense relationships some of us have with pets could itself be disruptive
of the human-oriented world most of us inherited. Although I completely rec-
ognize that the vast majority of humans who participate in relationships with
their pets don’t recognize those relationships as transgressive, part of me would
like to claim that for them anyway. It’s not that the family dog is himself a
paradigm-shifting entity, but the massive scale of pet culture could signal a
shift that many of us humans have indeed fallen in love with someone besides
ourselves.
But we don’t think of pet culture that way at all. For the most part, pet ani-
mals are add-ons to postmodern, consumption-based, globalized life, not para-
digm shifters. The easiest answer, and one that I will circle around and around
in this essay, is that pets are not really threatening to twenty-first-century
American life precisely because of the deeply ingrained taboos against bestiality.
After all, we may love them, but we don’t really love them, right? We don’t ever
view our love of animals as transgressive simply because the activities of bestial-
ity and zoophilia seem so unthinkable. Loving animals is safe, for most of us,
because it is not “that.” As Midas Dekkers aptly expresses it, “the high regard in
which love for animals is held is matched only by the fierceness of the taboo on
having sex with them” (Dekkers 1994, 149).
Enter queer theory. At the most cursory level, queer theory persuasively tea-
ches us that sex itself is difficult to define; sexuality pervades many different lev-
els of many different relationships; and sexual identity is famously unstable. Sex
is an energy that can be tapped into but never nailed down. So in relation to
bestiality, queer theory points out that the “that” that is performed between
humans and animals by necessity must remain unnamed. Stated differently, the
widespread social ban on bestiality rests on a solid notion of what sex is, and
queer theory persuasively argues we simply don’t have such a thing. The inter-
dict against bestiality can only be maintained if we think we always/already
know what sex is. And, according to queer theory, we don’t.
To tell this part of the story well, I need to reveal the event that prompted
me—in the middle of writing a book about animals and ethics—to return to
Kathy Rudy 603
queer theory as a central organizing theme: that event was the death of Eve
Sedgwick in the spring of 2009. Eve was a mentor to me when I was in grad
school at Duke, and a wise senior colleague when I first joined the faculty there.
I found myself rereading some of her books after her death as a way to invite her
to be more present in my life, as a way for me to remember her well. To my
knowledge, although Eve mentions bestiality and zoophilia in passing, she never
turns her wise and clever gaze completely on the subject. The rest of this essay,
then, is something of a thought experiment connecting Eve’s insights about
queerness and sexuality with my own obsessions about animals. It has been
exceedingly fun to write this for her.
Studying with Eve Sedgwick as a young scholar was like adding a new and
different dimension to the feminist theory I brought with me to grad school.
Before Eve, I rummaged through liberal, radical, and socialist theories of gender
to make arguments about the importance and value of women in the world.
Before Eve, gender was pretty much an unchecked constant in my intellectual
landscape; it was the thing I worried over all the time in every context, but
never really saw because it loomed so large. In looking back on that time, I lived
in a very two-dimensional world where the things that “made” gender (and femi-
nism) went more or less unstudied.
Exploring feminist theory with Eve was like stepping into an Imax 3-D movie
for the first time. I wasn’t just watching the movie of gender any more; I was in
it and could see behind and beneath the structures that before had been utterly
flat. Eve was a different kind of feminist; she cared about all the regular things
the rest of us cared about, but she also cared about how gender itself was made.
In watching the world through her eyes, I got to see a differently inflected real-
ity; it wasn’t the case, as I had previously thought, that gender came first and
sexual preference flowed from there. Rather all of our identities stemmed, in
part, out of our desires. To be sure, lots of feminists before Sedgwick noted that
gender was “socially constructed.” From Beauvoir to Barrett and many others, we
already knew that gender was made, but from those perspectives it mostly looked
like society or culture or language or something outside us pressed down on us
like cookie-cutters and made us into men and women. With Eve, the thing that
made us gendered also came from inside of us. It came in the way we identified
outside ourselves, it came in the way we desired an other and made ourselves
into a person who could be in relation to that particular other; it came in the
ways we loved. Our realities are made for us through the worlds and meanings
available to us, but they are also made by the connections in the affective realm.
Whom we loved mattered, not just as a point of feminist justice but because that
process of love contained the seeds of world-making.
I was a lesbian when I knew Eve at Duke back in the 1990s. I had “come
out” in my early twenties, and it was an identity that almost fit for a long time.
Well into my thirties I tried very hard to make that description of myself work
604 Hypatia
for me. For ten years I “settled down” with one partner, focused on family life,
“owned” only two dogs and one cat (with no fenced yard). I tried very hard to
be reasonable about the animals; I would put them in kennels when we traveled
and lock them in bedrooms when we entertained. But when I wasn’t with them
I was miserable. It was like they carried a piece of my heart, and when they
weren’t involved in some function or activity, a part of me wasn’t present either.
Eve knew of these predilections and always encouraged me to think about them
in a positive frame. Claiming a solid “gay” identity never felt right to Eve, and
she filled the world with feminist queer theory to explain why “being woman” or
“being gay,” although certainly not wrong, wasn’t quite right either. “Being les-
bian” wasn’t quite right for me either, mostly because my mind was always on
the dogs. From as far back as I can remember, dogs have been the most vibrant,
colorful, and important players in the landscape of my life. When I was a child,
they were my very best friends. Soon after Eve left Duke, I found myself single,
and in part due to her influence, I decided to pay serious attention to these
intense feelings I had toward animals. Like the epigraph that opens this essay, I
wanted to return to a childhood promise to make my relationships with them
more visible and explicit.2
For me, paying attention to that childhood first love of animals was possible
only as a result of Eve’s formulation of theory. In her world, gender and sexuality
were terribly messy and unwieldy constructs, and she was absolutely delighted
when they could be rendered even messier and more unwieldy. Had she lived,
reaching outside the boundaries of the human would have been the next logical
step in her feminism. Following Eve, I filled my new house with six rescues of
various shapes and sizes, and multitudes of fosters looking for new homes. People
think I am crazy. But I have never ever been happier.
So here I sit with my six dogs, wondering, from the theory-world Eve
bequeathed to me, what could it mean to love animals? What does it mean to
make myself in relation to the love I have for these dogs? How do they help
me construct my gender, my class, my race, the inward, internal topography of
identities and desires that connect me to the world? How does living inside
this 3-D, big-screen movie with dogs all around me look to the rest of the
world? How does it feel to the dogs themselves? And how does it look to me,
inside it?
There is not an adequate name for the kind of life I lead, the way my desires
organize themselves around animals. In the first half of the twentieth century,
the heterosexual public either detested or felt sorry for women who were named
by the then emerging category “lesbian.” They thought that the only women
who would ever choose lesbianism were ugly, or unfeminine, or somehow lacking
in the ability to capture a man. Now, on the other side of gay rights, feminism,
and queer theory, such ideas seem silly or quaint, almost forgotten. But can peo-
ple like me even hope for such liberation, when choosing animals as partners or
Kathy Rudy 605
companions doesn’t really even have an adequate name? At best, we fall under
the radar of identity and are named (wrongly) as gay or straight, single or mar-
ried, parents or childless. Our most important relationships, though, are never
recognized. At worst, we are pitied. Like those early lesbians, people “feel sorry”
for us because we can’t seem to sustain “real” relationships with “real” people
(see, for example, Nast 2006a). I came out as a lesbian nearly twenty-five years
ago and although that was hard on friends and family who were homophobic,
the task of coming out as a lesbian was a piece of cake compared to coming out
as—what?
I know I love my dogs with all my heart, but I can’t figure out if that love is
sexually motivated. Queer theory has schooled me in ways that make the ques-
tion of what counts as sex seem rather unintelligible. How do we cordon off sex-
ual desire from all the other desires that move our lives? What does sex mean?
Do I think I’m having sex with my dogs when they kiss my face? How do we
know beforehand what sex is? I get more affection from my dogs than I ever did
from any girlfriend. We all always sleep together, sometimes under the blankets
when it’s cold. When I was gay, was I gay because of a narrowly defined genital
act that I performed with a person who happened to be another woman? Those
words don’t make any sense to me. I was gay then, I believe, because I chose to
share my emotional, financial, and daily life with a person of the same gender.
Now I choose to share that same life with six dogs.
Although I am not arguing that living with pets is necessarily a life-shifting
paradigm, I am suggesting that the number of people who find community and
communion with domesticated animals has both risen recently and become more
visible. In a queer frame, this phenomenon is extremely interesting, as it—loving
animals—could constitute a new way of being with another species. Put differ-
ently, queer theory teaches us that it’s not really a question of whether we have
“sex” with animals; rather it’s about recognizing and honoring the affective bonds
many of us share with other creatures. Those intense connections between
humans and animals could be seen as revolutionary, in a queer frame. But
instead, pet love is sanitized and rendered harmless by the presence of the inter-
dict against bestiality. The discourses of bestiality and zoophilia form the identity
boundary that we cannot pass through if we want our love of animals to be seen
as acceptable.
In American public culture today, conversations about bestiality and zoophilia
exist in four different locations.3 I want to look briefly at those positions, and
then move to analyze them through the lens of queer theory. Ultimately, of
course, my argument is not for or against humans having sex with animals, but is
a meditation on both the elusive nature of sex itself and the subjectivities of
human versus nonhuman animals. The line policed by the fear of bestiality is
about more than just what we can or can’t do with our pets. As we shall see, it
helps to form the very architecture of human exceptionalism.
606 Hypatia
The first two sites I speak about are (1) “bestiality” and (2) “zoophilia”; both
exist mostly on the Internet, where sex with animals is portrayed more or less as
a form of pornography. Acts are performed either by objectifying animals to the
point where they are treated as props for certain sexual encounters (bestiality),
or conversely, by endowing animals with human characteristics, such as the
desire to express love for their humans through sexual intimacy (zoophilia). The
third site is closely associated with (3) “animal rights,” where sex with animals is
strongly condemned because animals are seen as needing protection from human
manipulation in general, and sex with them can never be anything but a misuse
of human power. Finally, sex with animals is discussed in (4) “mental health” lit-
erature, where the context is almost always therapeutic intervention; these
therapy-based works reflect a dominant cultural notion that sex with animals
needs to be “cured” because it’s simply not normal. Attitudes and arguments
from these four venues give us unique vantage points to think about what sex is
and what animals are.
On many bestiality websites (1), the dominant orientation toward animals
really supports and adheres to the idea that animals are nothing more than forms
of property. On these private, for-pay websites, animals are dressed up, stimu-
lated, filmed from angles that don’t show their faces or their expressions. They
are, in short, props or tools to aid the human-centered sexual experience.4 In the
logic of these practices, sex with these “things” is no more wrong than sex with
other “things,” such as dildos, blow-up dolls, and so on. In these settings, sex acts
don’t happen “between” humans and animals; rather, humans are simply using
animals for their own pleasure and fantasy. For these bestialists, it doesn’t matter
if the animal lives or dies as a result of this activity; the goal here is human plea-
sure. Examples of using animals as things include inserting rodents into a human
rectum for pleasure, or beheading chickens and other birds at the point of
orgasm to intensify the convulsions of the sphincter, or withholding food and flu-
ids from dogs for long periods of time so they will lick and swallow various
human secretions and excretions. From this point of view, such bestial practices
aren’t wrong because animals have no subjectivity, no self-interest. After all, we
kill them to eat them or because we don’t want them infesting our homes, why
not use them for a little sexual pleasure first? Here, humans occupy a place in
the world that is unrivaled.
A counterdiscourse emerges within the realm of pornography that portrays sex
between humans and animals differently. Self-described zoophiles (2) argue that
humans involved in loving relationships with animals are distinct from bestials;
for zoophiles, animals are not “things,” rather they are full and equal partners in
sexual discovery. Zoophilia, they say, does not involve animal cruelty; it’s not
about hurting animals for human pleasure but about loving animals to pleasure
both the human and the animal. In this frame, animals are not only not
“things,” they are in fact capable of entering into something like a partnership
Kathy Rudy 607
with humans, for love and for sex. Indeed, in loving relationships, zoophilists
suggest, animals can experience such a robust subjectivity that they not only give
consent to sexual acts, they also can initiate those acts, communicate their
desires for specific kinds of pleasure, and even opt out of sex if they so choose.
In this perspective, animals aren’t less-than-human pieces of property; they
become something very close to human. From a zoophile’s perspective, although
nonhuman animals don’t use spoken or written language, they can communicate
their sexual desires in a myriad of ways. Here, nonhuman animals are elevated
to the level of human subjectivity and granted the kinds of characteristics usually
reserved only for humans.
On the other side of the debate, the taboo against sex with animals is secured
and reinforced by two unlikely bedfellows. Possibly the strongest admonition
against bestiality and/or zoophilia comes from the discourse of animal rights (3).
For theorists committed to a platform that releases animals from “enslavement”
by humans, humans and animals having sex is always and unconditionally wrong
simply because animals cannot give consent. Much like children, prisoners, or
slaves, they say, animals are subject to such coercion that they cannot participate
in meaningful sexual encounters. It’s not a question of pain or pleasure, but sim-
ply that by the very nature of their lack of agency, they cannot give consent to
such acts. Partly it’s a question of lacking a common language, but according to
many animal rights’ theorists, even if we suddenly were able to communicate
with nonhuman animals, sex between humans and animals would be wrong
because animals are not authors of their own worlds. Piers Beirne calls all sex
between human and non-human animals “interspecies sexual assault” and argues
“animals are beings without an effective voice” (Beirne 1997, 323). Essentially,
most people in the animal rights movement think that because animals are pow-
erless and voiceless, sex between humans and animals is always wrong.5
Finally, most material addressing both bestiality and zoophilia from psychologi-
cal perspectives (4) reflects disgust at the idea of human/animal sex. In these
essays and books, the desire to have sex with animals is seen as abnormal and in
need of cure. The most liberal approaches try to explain how someone came to
develop a predilection for bestiality, but I found no therapeutically based litera-
ture that advocated for acceptance of these practices. In each essay, there is the
unquestioned perception that such behavior needs to be corrected. There seems
to be a general sense of disgrace in wider American culture that fuels and rein-
forces the need for therapeutic resolution. This taboo on sex with animals is a
powerful force that also functions, I suggest, to help us differentiate ourselves from
animals very well. In the interdict against sex with animals, animals emerge as fig-
ures over which we define our superiority. In other words, maintaining the onto-
logical boundary between humans and animals requires us to feel disgusted by
breaches of that boundary, most especially around the issue of sex. Our psycholog-
ical approaches operationalize this boundary by “curing” those who cross it.
608 Hypatia
I’ve mapped the four sites as a “pro and con” diagram above (two in favor of
sex with animals, but from different positions, two opposed to sex with animals,
but also from different positions.) But in an interesting way, the pro and con
sides of the argument also act as mirrors for each other’s ontologies. That is, bes-
tialists (1) and therapists (4) both see animals as “less than human”; whereas
bestials use this less-than status as the reason to accept sex practices with ani-
mals (“who cares what happens to them, they are just things”), many therapists
see sex with animals as degrading to the humans because animals are less than
us (“we belittle humanity to engage in sex with unworthy creatures”). Similarly,
zoophiles (2) see animals as equal or equivalent to humans, and therefore think
sex with animals is fine as long as it’s not abusive, painful, or degrading; animal
rights activists (3) also see animals as equal or equivalent to humans, but because
animals are so highly regarded, many activists believe that animals need protec-
tion from human domination (much the way children or mentally handicapped
people need protection from those who would abuse them).
If Eve Sedgwick had written about sex with animals, I bet she wouldn’t be
interested in validating any of the four orientations. She would want to know
how the four views compete with one another, and on what grounds they share
in their common definitions about subjects and practices. She would want to
know how we ended up in a world where these frameworks constructed our only
options. She would want to know how the categories themselves came into
being, how they rub up against one another, how they overlook and obscure
many aspects of a life filled with animals. Eve would ask how we organized our-
selves such that animals either have to be just like us, or not like us at all, and
thus have no value. She would want to know how it was possible that all ani-
mals can exist in one category. She would want to examine how our perceptions
about the gender of animals both construct and reflect our perceptions about the
gender of our selves. Are there other ways to think about animals other than
“equal to us” or “less than us?” Are there ways to think about sex with animals
other than in terms of right or wrong? What is it that can’t be said? What other
realities do these four positions obscure?
It’s worth noting just how much slippage exists among positions that try to
define themselves against one another. What looks different on the surface may
be similar underneath (and vice versa). Eve addresses the way the subject posi-
tions of gay men and lesbians do or do not relate: “There can’t be an apriori
decision about how far it will make sense to conceptualize lesbian and gay male
identities together. Or separately” (Sedgwick 1990, 36). The same is true, for
example, for the distinction between bestiality (1) and zoophilia (2). Although
zoophiles try to distance themselves from bestials, the two occupy similar
domains on the Internet, and I suspect many viewers care little about the affec-
tive relationships zoophiles advocate. They are lumped together in the therapeu-
tic literature, and also by the condemnatory discourses of animal rights. A whole
Kathy Rudy 609
series of questions emerges to blur the distinction: How can we be certain about
what kind of bond exists behind the sex? How does one know beforehand the
difference between bestiality and zoophilia? Is a woman who becomes sexually
aroused riding a horse a bestial or a zoophile? What if she gets aroused only on
the back of one particular horse? Can emotional bonds exist, say, between a
farmer and the livestock he is about to slaughter for meat? Although killing ani-
mals in the act of sex is more associated with bestiality, what if the sex and the
killing are separated by periods of days or weeks or years? Can you love someone
and still kill her?
Slippage and condensation occur on the other side of the divide as well.
Although animal rights activists intend only to protect animals from human
abuse, in their interdicts against human/animal sex, they also shore up the psy-
chosocial position that human sex with animals is somehow abnormal. Both
positions oppose sex with animals, and in doing so they perform a kind of vio-
lence on animals by lumping them all together into one seamless identity.
Here is Eve on the question of human identity categories: “People are differ-
ent from each other. It is astonishing how few respectable conceptual tools we
have for dealing with this self-evident fact. A tiny number of inconceivably
coarse axes of categorization have been painstakingly inscribed in current critical
and political thought: gender, race, class, nationality, sexual orientation are
pretty much the available distinctions” (Sedgwick 1990, 22). With these words,
Sedgwick opened up not only the study of sexuality but also the study of human
identity to attend to complexity and messiness. I want now to extend this insight
to nonhuman animals. If, as she argues, the available tools to categorize humans
are paltry, the labels associated with animals are downright crude. Although the
discourse of species recognizes certain biological differences between animals,
most humans categorize animals only in the broadest strokes: as pets, livestock,
or wild animals. These categorizations are slippery: a given species can occupy
multiple categories (for example, feral cats, wild horses, and pet pigs all come to
mind). Our method of categorizing animals is not only blunt, it is famously
unstable. Thus, mostly we refer to all of them as “animals.”
The problem with both the animal rights and the psychotherapeutic positions
is that they want to make universal rules for all animals, and in so doing sacrifice
the richness of particularity. They advance an agenda that produces the human/
animal duality as firmly and narrowly as the homo/hetero binary. They crowd all
animals into one categorical way of thinking and tell us, even if subconsciously,
that humans and animals occupy different ontological realms, that one is
EITHER human OR animal, never neither, never both. It’s precisely the same
logic that forces us to conform to the homo/hetero binary.
What I am trying to introduce here is the possibility that as human and non-
human, animals share an intensely bonded life together, we are all becoming
something new, something part human, part animal, a part of one another. Both
610 Hypatia
antisex positions rest on the idea that all humans are different from all other
animals, and the wall between them can never be breached. Like the ways we
used to think of race or gender “identity,” these positions contend that one’s spe-
cies rests on physical markers that are immutable, that belonging to the catego-
ries of “animal” or “human” is grounded in a biological essence untouched by
culture. Positions that universalize all animals—even if allegedly to improve their
lives—are unable to explore heterogeneity and fragmentation within each cate-
gory.
Put differently, both animal rights (3) and psychosocial perspectives (4) do
not believe that borders can be crossed. Queer theory, on the other hand, tells
us that few of us have stable identities anymore, that borders are always crossed.
We’re all changing, shifting, splitting ourselves up this way and that. It labels
these processes “hailing,” “suturing,” and “interpolation”; where once we saw our-
selves affiliated in one way, a new interpretive community emerges to capture
our passions and move us differently. I am asking the reader to entertain the pos-
sibility that the same kinds of shifts and disruptions happen with categories like
“human,” “rabbit,” “ape,” or “dog.” As the result of our relationships, interpola-
tions occur; my dogs and I have changed each other such that I am no longer
only human and they are no longer only canine. For these particular dogs and
this particular person, something rather magical has happened to alter not only
the way we perceive, but also the way we live in the world.
In keeping with queer theory, I am asking the reader here to imagine the pos-
sibility that certain kinds of relationships can undo even the strongest and most
trenchant categories. No one would deny that, as a result of their physical differ-
ences, my dogs experience the world differently than I do (for example, they
hear better and smell better, but they can’t read or write, and so on). But using
only those experiences to invoke a unitary and stable world with unbridgeable
boundaries for them (what we call species) completely discounts the other expe-
riences they have had as a result of living with me, of us being a family
together.6 They know what my words mean, even if they can’t write or speak.
I’ve learned to be much more attuned to smell and sound and other shifts of
energy that are hard to put into words. These experiences matter because they
change us all.
Detractors of pet-keeping might call this kind of life sad. We are investing in
these creatures, they think, because we cannot “find” a human person to love.
But from my perspective, it looks completely different. These majestic, wonderful
beings are not empty ciphers; they have needs and desires that they communi-
cate to me in a myriad of ways, and in listening and responding to them, I am
not only changed but fulfilled. They help me carry my burdens and increase my
joys. I know I am content when they rest soundly at my feet. It’s not so much
that I am no longer a lesbian, then, it’s that the binary of gay and straight no
longer has anything to do with me. My preference these days is canine.
Kathy Rudy 611
Collectively, the four positions tell us that it’s perfectly fine to love animals,
to sleep with them, to cuddle with them, to enjoy their bodies in a myriad of
ways, but if we have “sex” with them, we immediately locate ourselves in the
dangerous territory of bestiality. As Dekkers notes:
If you drop the requirement that for sexual contact something has
to be inserted somewhere and that something has to be fiddled
with, and it is sufficient simply to cuddle, to derive a warm feeling
from each other, to kiss perhaps at times, in brief to love, then
bestiality is not a deviation but a general rule, not even some-
thing shameful but the done thing. After all, who does not wish
to be called an animal lover? (Dekkers 1994, 149)
But without a coherent and agreed upon definition of sex (which queer theory
persuasively argues is impossible), the line between “animal lover” and zoophile
is not only thin, it is nonexistent. How do we know beforehand whether loving
them constitutes “sex,” and how can such sex be so dangerous if it so nebulous
and undefined? In other words, the sense of danger associated with human/ani-
mal sex emerges as a result of a cultural anxiety about our own animality. That
is, if we do “that” (leaving “that” unnamed and unrepresented), we will lose
something about what it means to be human, to be superior.
Indeed, Dekkers, along with Alphonso Lingus, argues that sex itself turns us
humans into animals, that in orgasm, animality saturates every pore and gene
and bone of our being. As Dekkers claims, “every sexual encounter is a breaking
of bounds, and intrusion into an alien realm, every sexual encounter retains a
whiff of bestiality” (Dekkers 1994, 3).7 Both of these authors argue for the perva-
siveness of bestiality by insisting that it underlies all acts of love; in making love
even to a fellow human, we are always encountering an animal or animalized
other. Although this is clearly an interesting idea, my claim is slightly different.
I’m not so much arguing that through sex we all become animals, but more that
in deep connection, we all—humans and animals alike—become something dif-
ferent. The very contours of stable identities shift under the revolutionary power
of love.
My point, then, is not to make something called bestiality more visible, but
by using animal love in various permutations, to disrupt the stability and superi-
ority of human identity. Convincing love stories between humans and animals—
such as J. R. Ackerley’s My Dog Tulip (1956) or Mark Doty’s Dog Years (2007)—
do just this; that is, they don’t tell us of an identity called bestiality but show us
a world transformed by human/animal love. Such love destabilizes what we think
know about sex, what we think we know about gender, and what we think we
know about being human. It can lead to what Margret Grebowicz calls “an
inscription of a wholly new imaginary of animality and the condition for the
possibility of new imaginaries of gender” (Grebowicz 2010, 14).8 It can also lead,
612 Hypatia
NOTES
1. Much has been written on the recent rise of pet culture in America; a full survey
of that material is beyond the scope of this essay. See Haraway 2003; Grier 2006, Nast
2006b.
2. Of note here is a delightful chapter entitled “Why the (Lesbian) Child Requires
an Interval of Animal: The Family Dog as a Time Machine,” in Kathryn Stockton’s The
Queer Child. She writes, for example, “The family dog is not just a pet. It is a metaphor
for all that is loyal, familial, and family-photogenic” (Stockton 2009, 90). Although I like
the ways Stockton talks about the importance of animals in the life of a queer child, my
goal in this essay is to make the family dog into something much more present than a
metaphor.
3. Throughout human history, of course, the vast majority of discussions around bes-
tiality existed in the twinned realms of moral theology and juridical practices. Interdicts
against bestiality go as far back as the book of Leviticus, or farther, and are brought for-
ward in court cases involving bestiality up through the Western seventeenth century. In
most of these cases, events, and rules, bestiality is used as an attempt to regulate sexuality
more generally, and all formed the foundation of the longstanding taboo we have inher-
ited. In claiming that bestiality today resides in four locations, I do not mean to diminish
the historical record at all. Rather, my point is that the taboo against bestiality is so
widely accepted today that neither the church nor the courts need to involve themselves
in policing it. Iterations of popular culture manage to accomplish this policing just fine on
their own. For historical works on bestiality, see Canup 1990; Liliequist 1991; Godbeer
2002; Rydstrom 2003.
4. For an excellent feminist analysis of bestiality pornography, see Grebowicz 2010.
5. It’s interesting to note that many formulations of animal rights secure their argu-
ments based on the similarity of humans to nonhuman animals. As Tom Regan writes,
“we understand their behavior because we understand ourselves and our behavior…. There
is somebody there behind those canine eyes, somebody with wants and needs” (Regan
2004, 55). One might ask animal rights advocates why we couldn’t also know their wants
and needs in relation to sex.
6. Eve wrote extensively on this question of family, and as a result I am somewhat
hesitant to insert it here, unproblematized. The term sets up a hierarchy where hetero-
normative coupling resulting in human children is “natural,” and every other social
arrangement gains legitimacy only insofar as it can argue its likeness to “the family.”
Nevertheless, recuperation may be possible. As Eve writes: “it’s been a ruling intuition
for me to disengage the bonds of blood, of law, of habitation, of privacy, of compan-
ionship and succor, from the lockstep of their unanimity in the system called ‘family’”
(Sedgwick 1993, 6). I take her to mean that her familial affections were not ruled by
blood ties or marital contracts, that they floated outside these domains in ways that
were unpredictable and queer. It’s only in this sense that I want to make family with
my dogs.
7. For a similar analysis, see Lingus in Steeves 1999.
614 Hypatia
8. Of course, I do not mean to suggest that feminist theory in general or even in its
queer inflections embraces or should embrace bestiality. Many feminists would disagree.
See Adams 1995; Adams and Donovan 2007; Boggs 2010.
REFERENCES
Singer, Peter. 2001. Heavy petting. Nerve. February 14, 2009. http://www.utilitarian.net/
singer/by/2001—.htm (accessed January 2, 2012).
Steeves, H. Peter, ed. 1999. Animal others: On ethics, ontology, and animal life. In
SUNY Series in Contemporary Continental Philosophy. Albany: State University of New
York Press.
Stockton, Kathryn Bond. 2009. The queer child, or growing sideways in the twentieth century.
Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press.