On Aesthetic Disinterestedness
On Aesthetic Disinterestedness
On Aesthetic Disinterestedness
by
B118246
Abstract
Meanwhile, the judgment of an artwork should not be based on the historical background
of an artist’s experience. However, it has often seemed impossible for most people, who are not
skilled in the art of judging works of art to find satisfaction in an artwork purely on the basis of
disinterestedness. People often find themselves interested in the background and experiences of
the artist. Spectators often want to associate themselves with the artwork via the kind of elements
which are opposed to the concept of disinterestedness. For instance, discussions linked to Van
Gough are often allied to his mental problems and his life of misery.
Table of Contents
1. Introduction.............................................................................................................................................. 3
2. The Notion of Disinterestedness ............................................................................................................. 5
2.1 Background of Study ......................................................................................................................... 5
2.2 Aesthetic Judgment ........................................................................................................................... 5
2.3 Disinterestedness ................................................................................................................................ 6
2.4 Discussion ........................................................................................................................................... 7
3. Objections to the Notion of Disinterestedness .....................................................................................12
3.1 The Disinterested View is Ungagged (Schopenhauer) ..................................................................12
3.1.1 The World as a Representation...................................................................................................13
3.1.2 Idealism and Evolution ...............................................................................................................15
3.1.3 The Insufficiency of Natural Science ..........................................................................................17
3.1.4 The Will .......................................................................................................................................18
3.2 Disinterested Seeing Avoids the Realisation of Meanings of an Object (Schiller) .....................19
3.3 The Mind’s Independence: Kant’s Arguments as Defying the Freedom of the Mind’s
Independence..........................................................................................................................................24
4. Conclusion ..............................................................................................................................................27
3
On Aesthetic Disinterestedness
1. Introduction
Both beauty and ugliness are fundamental aspects of our lives. Recognising this, Immanuel
Kant explained the aesthetics of beauty in a bid to reach broader society, which he considered as
not acting in accordance with the appreciation of beauty. According to Kant, aesthetic judgment
ought to be subjective and speak with a universal voice. From this, he then coined the notion of
disinterestedness, in which he openly assumed the role of extrinsic considerations such as political
or utilitarian concerns play in the appreciation of beauty. He further contradicted the idea of
appreciating beauty based on different inclinations as a step towards the introduction of conflicts
Thinking about the widely accepted approach to beauty, Kant’s ideas seem to contradict
and not appreciate what human beings consider to be the correct way of cherishing beauty. This
raises a question of legitimacy. Is Kant’s viewpoint the correct approach to the appreciation of
beauty? This paper will look at Kant’s notion of disinterestedness by exploring his arguments as
well as the motivation behind its arguments. Additionally, the interpretations of these arguments
Since Kant came up with the idea of disinterestedness, many critics have explored their
interest in this notion. Apart from simply dismissing it as a little idea, some have openly rebuked
Kant as coming up with imaginations that are only applicable to himself. According to
Schopenhauer, for example, “the world is an object” (Schopenhauer, 2010). Although he considers
Kant’s idea as worthy of development, he objects to his idea of subjectiveness. He argues that
4
everything associated with the world can hardly be separated from the object since what the eyes
have already witnessed exists in the mind and cannot be separated from mind as far as beauty is
concerned.
Guyer comes out strongly to expose the conflict created by Kant when exploring his notion
of disinterestedness. According to Guyer (1996), Kant did not come up with a new approach to
beauty but only created a conflict in his approach to it. While Kant argues that an image speaks in
a certain voice devoid of external factors, Guyer openly says that it is next to impossible to come
up with a judgment that does not consider any external aspects of the image. Thinking of a drawing
of a forest, for example, Kant argues that one’s judgment or taste for such an image should not be
influenced by what someone previously experienced or witnessed in a forest but rather concentrate
on what the image tries to communicate. Guyer, on the other hand, considers such an act
impossible and not applicable to the people who have already experienced nature and understood
In a bid to answer the question of the legitimacy and applicability of Kant’s arguments,
this paper will consider three objections to his rather questionable philosophical approach to
beauty. Schopenhauer, Guyer and the contemporary approach to beauty will be considered,
culminating in a conclusion. By comparing each of these viewpoints, the paper will come up with
an informed decision that not only considers the applicability of Kant’s arguments but also notes
the loopholes in his philosophy that would have made it more applicable to today’s world, with its
Although the notion of disinterestedness has recently fallen from favour, it is worth noting
that it has played a significant role in philosophical aesthetics (Deligiorgi, 2005, p. 12). It has not
only enabled an understanding of what happens when people respond to a work of art; it has also
streamlined the understanding of what people should do if they have to behave properly in the face
of art. Simply put, Kant’s notion tries to overlook unstudied behaviour towards art and comes up
with an idea of what he considers correct behaviour towards art. In advancing this philosophical
notion, Immanuel Kant proposes an account of beauty that considers aesthetic judgments as both
a subjective voice and as speaking with a single universal voice. Although the properties he
identifies (subjective and universal) appear mutually exclusive, he maintains that they are
compatible if the aesthetic judgment is explained as originating in the original structure of the
brain, devoid of external influence. To expound the compatibility of these two seemingly exclusive
properties, he comes up with two major claims. The first claim considers aesthetic judgments as
disinterested. The second claim considers the universality of aesthetic judgments as being derived
from the idealist’s account of the ordinary spatiotemporal experience; that is, the ordinary
The idea that aesthetic judgment is disinterested implies that a genuine aesthetic judgment
does not need to include any extrinsic considerations, such as utilitarian or political concerns,
towards the object of judgment. Kant argues that if universality only occurs when our aesthetic
judgments are disinterested; failure to be disinterested would mean there would not be any
correlation between the two. This means that if pleasure and beauty are derived from the
6
inclinations with which people encounter an object, then the claims of the beauty of a particular
object would be varied and conflicting based on the inclinations people bring to it.
Kant’s notion of disinterestedness hinges on the idea that judgments are capable of
as a judgment that is understood based on an empirical concept such as “this is a cow”. In his work
Critique of the Power of Judgement, Kant establishes the principles under which determinative
judgments can be used to legitimise the inter-subjectivity of empirical knowledge. This work also
aims to establish the governing principles for reflective judgment of aesthetic knowledge, which
is key to the interpretation of art. Considering interaction with aesthetics, the idea that aesthetic
experience comes in handy when making judgments about a work of art should be rejected, as the
word “knowledge” fits in more with determinative judgment, which makes more reference to
previous knowledge of the subject matter. Kant also strives to question such a conflation of
knowledge when deriving the notion of disinterestedness (CPJ, §1, 5:204)1. In his take on the same
concept, he argues that the assumption of aesthetic knowledge as determinative is mistaken, as this
2.3 Disinterestedness
disinterestedness aspect of beauty described by Kant is tied to the first interaction of the person
giving judgment with the aesthetic aspect of an object. In this regard, he describes taste as a faculty
with which an object or any representation is judged without any interest whatsoever. Kant’s
1 All references to Kant's Critique of the Power of Judgment will be to the translation of the Kritik der Urteilskrqft
that Paul Guyer and Eric Matthew did for the Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant. See Immanuel
Kant, Critique of the Power of Judgement, trans. and ed. Paul Guyer and Eric Matthew (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2000).
7
reasoning implies that the interesting aspect of disinterestedness refers to the satisfaction that is
gained from combining the appearance of an object with prior knowledge of the existence of the
object. Simply put, interest, in this case, refers to the judgment that one may come up with not
because of the appearance of the object but because one feels that an object is beautiful in
comparison to others or because the appearance of the object fits a situation it is directly or
indirectly related to. The idea of empirical judgment comes into effect in such a case, as knowledge
forms the basis for such judgments. A good example of this description of interest would be when
one considers a palace beautiful not because the observer has come across the view of a palace,
but because they understand the novelty that is usually associated with such a place
2.4 Discussion
To maintain the claim of the inter-subjective nature of beauty, Kant insinuates rejection of
the claim that beauty is sensuous. This is true, as people’s interactions with beauty have proven
that people view beauty differently based on personal inclinations. Kant emphasises this by giving
examples of how perceiving things differently can describe beauty differently. One person, for
example, may consider blue as a colour that is lovely and gentle while to another it is a
representation of lifelessness and death. This is the same in the case of music, as different people
appreciate different instruments differently. While one may consider string instruments interesting,
another may feel that music is incomplete without the sound of wind instruments. According to
Kant, however, these are only charms, as they do not cover the aspect of universality, which is
essential for a true judgment of art that does not consider self-preferences (Rind, 2002, p. 40).
To develop his understanding of the interpretation of art, Kant begins by questioning how,
for example, one is suddenly affected (in a pleasurable way) by an unexpected encounter with a
8
particularly beautiful appearance when the provocative nature of the effect can neither be cognised
nor efficiently understood. As his answer, he proposes a judgment that considers the beauty of art
in two major paradoxes. First, he considers fine art as “a way of presenting that is purposive on its
own, and that furthers, even though without a purpose, the culture of our mental powers to
[facilitate] social communication” (§39, 5: 293). Secondly, Kant argues that art “must have the
look of nature, even though we are conscious of it as art” (§40, 5: 294)). Simply put, Kant believes
that although art is intentionally produced, it remains purposive without a purpose and must appear
Based on the discussions above, a very clear distinction emerges: the experience of
pleasure cannot always be considered the experience of beauty and that what is pleasurable does
not communicate with a universal point. Despite this distinction, however, any move to divorce
beauty completely from pleasure would be little informed by the happenings in the real world. The
human cognitive ability (although sometimes biased by empirical judgments) assumes that what
is beautiful is pleasuring and vice versa. With this understanding, Kant avoids the path of divorcing
the two but instead comes up with an explanation of how beauty might be pleasurable based on a
disinterested judgment that avoids any empirical knowledge or personal inclinations that may
To make this view of aesthetic interpretation understood, Kant starts by considering his
moral philosophy. According to him, a moral philosophy similarly ought to be disinterested; that
is, if one only considers acting according to one's inclinations, then one is not acting morally. He
further argues that people may choose to uphold the moral law and tend to believe they are doing
so in the right spirit, yet in an actual sense they are only being guided by their egoism. In this
regard, Kant admits, “We can never even by most strenuous self-examination, get, entirely behind
9
our covert incentives” (§58, 5:347). This is similar to the aesthetic philosophy that argues that one
may voice their views on the experience of an object as being beautiful only to realise later that
their account is very different from the universal consensus on the same.
For one to be moral, Kant posits that a person’s actions should be guided by a motive that
leads to a sensuous experience rather than be informed by one. Simply put, the subject’s views and
actions should be free from any interruptions occurring either in the real world or from one’s
conscious reasoning (Rehberg, 2013, p. 155). This implies that the success of Kant’s aesthetic
project is highly dependent on a disinterestedness that avoids scepticism at all costs. The
experience of beauty in such a case ought to be disinterested to the extent that it is not just bound
by phenomenal experience, but that the judgment made is also untraceable to any other non-
sensuous grounds. With this, the capacity to which the judgment can exert freedom is extended
while it excludes any other internal factors from influencing its interpretation.
The exclusion of scepticism and inclusion of the subject’s freedom brings us to the
freedom of the subject. Considering that the experience of beauty is not to be measured in empirical
terms, it ought to be practised in a specific way that is pure in its approach. This brings us to our
explanation that an a priori subject forms the basis of the experience of aesthetics.
Thinking of the painting Starry Night by Vincent Van Gogh, for example, Kant’s notion
of disinterestedness would assume knowledge of the features presented by night, such as the sky,
the moon and the stars. According to Kant (§41, 5: 298), a consideration of these features would
amount to empirical data, which leads to the subjectivity that would bring in bias when deducing
the beauty presented by the piece of art. Based on the notion of disinterestedness, Kant would
10
argue that the pleasure in viewing such an image is derived from the harmony of the used artistic
components and the free play of our intuition and understanding that is caused by the
purposiveness of the different forms that make up the painting. From the look of the image,
something aesthetically pleasing is represented by the blend of colours as well as the arrangement
of shapes; hence, causing pleasure without applying the concepts people hold of how a church
should look or how the different bodies of the sky ought to be arranged. When judging from a
place of disinterestedness, people do not like Starry Night because it contains their favourite colour
(blue, yellow or brown), or because it reminds them of real-life experiences such as the safety of
a particular locality at night. Such judgments would present matters of agreeableness and taste that
do not lead to a universality and hence do not appraise the nature of the true beauty of the image.
Additionally, a consideration of such factors would pollute the disinterestedness that ought to
As part of appreciating Van Gogh’s work of art, Kant would argue that the artist succeeded
in fulfilling his paradox of ‘purposefully creating something that has no purpose’. This implies
that to come up with such a painting, he conceptualised a non-concept, to come up with an idea
that is independent of the judgment of real-world happenings. Having been capable of capturing
11
an aesthetic concept and bringing it to a concrete form, Kant would consider Van Gogh in
possession of an innate or genius mental predisposition through which he obtained nature’s rules
of art (Alison, 2001, p. 125). Additionally, looking at this work, disinterestedness brings in an
expression of the artist being guided by visceral forces that enabled him to develop a concept
Still, when observing the Starry Night image, it is worth noting that the same exceptional
conceptual factors satisfy Kant’s second paradox of appearing natural. This can be attributed to
the image being naturally pleasing without bringing attention to the purpose behind its creation.
According to Kant’s second paradox, we feel an aversion towards art that seems contrived or
forced. We, therefore, appreciate fine art because it is skillfully crafted to the extent that we interact
with it as if it were something that simply existed. Although we appreciate the technique that an
artist uses to create their work, beauty is best judged by its form rather than the way in which the
As earlier stated, Kant defines the role of the mind in experiencing art as the free play of
imagination and understanding. His experience of beauty is clear and concise (§48, 5:311). In this
regard, it can be concluded that an assumption of satisfaction that correlates with other subjects
with similar cognitive faculties is only based on individual judgment and therefore wrong since it
does not take into consideration the universality of the subject. Such an experience is unique to
one person and dependent on the calibre of their imagination and the architecture of their empirical
concepts. This is in line with Kant’s arguments that refuse to consider pleasure as the basis for
judging universality (Marsden, 2002, p. 65). An aesthetic judgment should, therefore, only be
based on the cognitive apparatus involved in an ordinary experience of a piece of art if it does not
oppositional at the same time. While he aims to improve on Kant’s point of view, he also
recognises the important aspects that Kant lays out in his philosophy. According to Kant’s notion
affective states and taking a passive attitude towards the object to be contemplated. Schopenhauer
improves on this notion by developing a more complex approach that retains some aspects of
Kant’s notion while disregarding others (Atwell, 1996). He states that the aesthetic experience is
involving a passionate and active engagement with the object of contemplation (Atwell, 1996).
Schopenhauer’s philosophy is related to his notion of the metaphysical that lies beneath
the world of phenomena (Gardener, 1999). To explain this, he takes the controlled digression of a
lunatic and a genius to show how different perceptions interplay to create the images in our brain.
With this way of reasoning, Schopenhauer aims to make us understand that a lunatic is
continuously faced with encounters that amount to the fragmentation of their personal history. This
then leads to interruptions that are smoothed over by more acceptable fictions that form the basis
affected by his exceptional powers of imagination and perception. He, surprisingly, however,
classifies the lunatic and the genius as lying in close conceptual proximity (Jacquette, 2005). They
both have encounters with the horrific, leading to serious interruptions in the continuity of their
subject. For the lunatic, the perceptions include the formulation and acceptance of fictional
13
memories while for the genius it is about the temporary cessation of their normal state of being (as
understands it, although it is not a proposition that everyone understands as soon as he hears it”
(Schopenhauer, 2010). This points to his claim that “the world is an object that is related to a
subject” (Schopenhauer, 2010). “In a world full of representation, everything that in any way
belongs to the world or can belong to the world is inevitably associated with it” (Deligiorgi, 2005,
p. 56). This means that everything that can be associated with the world is being conditioned by
the subject and therefore only exists for the subject. Thus, Schopenhauer comes up with the idea
of transcendental idealism that is arguably more accessible than Kant’s. In this account, he
considers his philosophy as containing the logical results of ideas that were not properly developed
The main argument in the transcendental idealism introduced by Kant is the idea that time,
space and causality are sensuous phenomena that construct our knowledge of the thing-in-itself.
Schopenhauer argues that the three are an a priori condition for experience (Jacquette, 2005, p.
44). He, therefore, concludes that having an experience without them is impossible. To further
illustrate this and link it with Kant’s epistemological theory of contemporary scientific inquiry, he
applies this understanding of structuring of human exposure and experience to the exploration of
optics. He argues, “The understanding is the artist forming the work, whereas the human senses
are assistants that hand up the materials” (Schopenhauer, 2010). Without such knowledge, “we
should see the object inverted…Intuitive perception is, however, realized due to the fact that the
instant understanding points to the impression felt on the retina to its cause which then precisely
14
in this way presents itself as an object in space that is its accompanying form of intuition”
(Schopenhauer, 2010).
Schopenhauer’s illustration is true, based on the fact that no matter which information we
have concerning the functioning of optics, we have no access to the impression (unmodified) of
an object in its inverted form. Although the process leads to gaining knowledge, it is sealed from
the common man’s understanding. Furthermore, despite being an experience of learning, the
understanding activity is in the eyes nature of performance. The same applies to time, space and
causality, which we experience in a similar way. They form the crucial features of experience and
hence it is hardly possible to strip them away or experience what the world would be like
unmodified.
time and casualty are all essential aspects of the external world and that they appear intuitive owing
to the illusionary nature of the experience (Gardener, 1999, p. 89). By connecting the three, he
creates a picture that would portray the illusion of space as pervading all experience when one
assumes that there is a disconnect between the object and the perceiver. In reality, however, every
human being is aware of his or her senses. As Schopenhauer puts it, the sun and the earth are
unknown to human beings; the eye, however, sees the sun while the hand feels the earth (Gardener,
1999).
Although the senses bring about illusions, as per Kant’s disinterestedness, Schopenhauer
comes out too strongly arguing that such illusions are embedded in us and cannot be removed by
any argument of reason (Guyer, 1996, p. 454). Simply put, he tries to dismiss abstract knowledge
in the arguments that involve senses that determine how human beings react. He considers Kant’s
15
arguments as based on a high degree of selflessness and suggests the possibility of something
extraordinary about beauty that Kant fails to capture. While trying to develop disinterestedness,
Schopenhauer suggests that Kant’s idea does not illuminate, explain or speak to the profundity of
beauty.
realism, he accuses him of not taking the argument far enough. When analysing the transcendental
aesthetic in the critique of pure reason, for example, he considers its conviction power significant
enough to number its propositions among the incontestable truths (the truths that he considers
idealism as they ignore the possibility of time and space existing in the world. Although the world
might coincide with the perceptions of human beings, the act cannot be verified.
According to the assumptions of transcendental realism, the world is something that cannot
be determinately intelligible. When assuming that space, time and causality are a reality but rather
limited, we have to face the issue of what lies on the other sides of their boundaries. Furthermore,
if they were assumed unlimited, we have to face the problem of the identity of the universe as well
as infinite regress (Gardener, 1999, p. 93). Disinterestedness, however, assumes the possible
Does Schopenhauer do the exact opposite to Kant, who tries to eliminate the world from
the picture when analysing a perception? According to Schopenhauer, “The world exists extended
in space and time continues to move regularly according to the strict rules of causality that are only
a physiological phenomenon of the brain” (Tauber, 2006, p. 24). This implies that the world
16
exposes the brain to certain categories that can then be drawn up by an understanding. He,
therefore, comes with a conclusion that the brain is hard-wired to propagate the illusions of
transcendental realism. This is coupled with a suggestion that the brain is a product of human
Darwin’s Origin of Species. Just like Darwin theory of survival of the fittest, Schopenhauer
concludes that continuous use leads to an increased functionality while a lack of use alludes to
possible extinction. This implies that the images that we continuously see are embedded in our
brains. When disinterestedness is being applied, it is hardly possible to assume what has been
embedded in our brains, as it becomes part of our reference as far as beauty appreciation is
concerned.
Just like Darwin, Schopenhauer believes that all plants adapt to their soil and climate, and
so do animals. The prey that becomes food has to be protected from its natural hunter to a certain
extent (Gardener, 1999, p. 95). To enable a safe and healthy thriving of organic life, nature has
provided an environment that allows the thriving of life. Similarly, nature has an impact on the
brain (specifically the intellect) of the higher animals as it is the most important organ directed
outwards. For such animals, a wider and more accurate range of vision and comprehension is
With the provision of intellect by nature, the human brain has become so sophisticated that
it has achieved the ability to experience abstract reflections and enjoy the nature of reality. This
implies that human beings live according to a transcendental realism, while we ought to
counterintuitive conclusions. Although Kant argues that subjectivity can be done away with in the
appreciation of art, Schopenhauer argues that nature’s provision is part of us and cannot be done
17
away with. With brains guided by idealism, we can we can hardly switch off our feelings,
gravity and electricity. He goes on to explain that science is only able to classify their existence
but has never bothered to inform us of why such forces exist. With this, he aims to identify the
natural science as incapable of explaining natural forces, and only capable of describing and
trying to explain all phenomena based on their physical cause and effect. The phenomena it tries
to explain are referred to by their causes but remain inexplicable themselves. As such, he insinuates
that scientific explanations betray the causes of nature and hence no one can determine whether
the explanations given are the real ones. Based on the fact that they cannot be proved by science
or any other field of study, the forces to which scientists attribute the governance of natural
phenomena remain a tragic enterprise. In conclusion, he argues that the forces manifested in nature
will remain an eternal secret; something “entirely strange and unknown” (Schopenhauer, 2010).
In the above critique of science, Schopenhauer comes out strongly against the idea that all
phenomena can be explained from an underlying physical structure (Gardener, 1999, p. 99). He
feels compelled to adopt a view of natural forces that consider pure potentiality since he sees the
fundamental forces of nature as entities that have powers devoid of structural ground; a view that
he suggests is supported by the modern-day field theory. Having adopted this view from Kant,
Schopenhauer advances it to add relevance to transcendental idealism by arguing that matter exists
through pure causality and hence any action towards it is general and unmodified.
18
Having displayed the inability of science to probe the fundamental nature of the forces that
govern reality, Schopenhauer goes on to describe the path of objective knowledge as not going
beyond the representation of any phenomenon. He uses the human body to explain this point by
arguing that a vision of the human body only gives a representation like it would for any other
object (Tauber, 2006). By considering its movements and actions, however, it becomes slightly
He goes on to explain that a perception of the human body is a perfect example of a project
from which one can gain both objective and subjective knowledge. Although science views
phenomena from a third person perspective, the human body gives the first-person perspective of
an object among many objects. With the body being two-sided (with both an inside perspective
and an outside physical appearance), Schopenhauer concludes that the body is the only object he
knows of that is not merely a one-sided representation. With this, he introduces another aspect of
the body, which he refers to as ‘the will’. The word will be used to convey that the body has the
will to do whatever it pleases as well as being included in certain decisions, such as wishing,
striving, loving, fearing, hating and all other decisions that directly constitute human weal and
With his introduction of objective phenomena into his two-sided body, Schopenhauer
means to convey that the act of the will and the action of the body are two different states, which
do not stand in a relation of cause and effect. In his attempt to define the relationship between the
two, he considers the action of the body as an act of the will that is objectified (a perception). With
this, he considers desire not as leading to action but rather that desire is an objective phenomenon.
Additionally, he argues that the acts of a will do not grow into an action.
19
Schopenhauer’s idea of the will is a major source of confusion, especially when it is used
to explain perceptions and as the reason for why different people perceive things differently.
Although he uses this reasoning to object to Kant’s approach to objects and subjects, he further
extends the will to inorganic matter. His argument is motivated by his quest to attain a higher genus
under which he can subsume all natural species, in a bid to find the knowledge of which
perceptions are identical. However, this contradicts his arguments on the Darwinian theory, as it
is practically impossible to find what is identical in all of nature’s species without introducing
science.
In a series of letters (known as the Kallias-Briefen) that contain sketches of Schiller's theory
of beauty, he proposes a theory that challenges some of the assumptions made by Kant in his notion
of disinterestedness. Generally, Kant’s judgment of taste is based on the conclusion that even
though aesthetic judgments are made universal, there are no possible objective principles that
could be used to assess the judgments. Schiller, however, criticises this conclusion by arguing that
if no objective principle of the judgment of beauty exists, then it would not be possible to secure
assent to a universal judgment of taste (Maftei, 2013). Schiller’s judgment is based mainly on the
subject’s feelings. He tries to show that it would not be possible to secure assent for a universally
accepted way of judging tastes and perceptions. In this, he considers the qualities of the objects
that interplay in asserting our agreements with regard to a particular object (Roehr, 2003). To
conclude his arguments, Schiller argues that even if people are incapable of demonstrating
aesthetic judgments, it does not mean that there is an objective principle for judging what is beauty.
To start with, Schiller ascribes the principle of beauty in practical rather than theoretical
reasons. To him, the principle of beauty ought not to presuppose an object’s concept since it is not
20
cognitive or constitutive. According to Kant’s senses, this principle is only regulative. Owing to
its practicability, Schiller considers the possibility of treating objects like “appearances of
freedom”. This implies that the beautiful may be analogous to freedom, although it is not an
instantiation of freedom. This is similar to Kant’s definition of beauty, which is given as the
freedom to understand both morality and aesthetics. According to Schiller, beauty is defined as the
While explaining perceptions and the judgment of taste, Schiller acknowledges that a
reason could be explained from either a practical perspective or a theoretical one. To him, practical
reasoning connects representation with the will for the sake of action. This is also applicable to the
forms of beauty that are either free or necessary. He considers that the use of practical reasons free
actions as part of moral judgments while the use of practical reasons for necessary actions forms
an aesthetic judgment.
Schiller considers aesthetic judgment an example of a practical reason, unlike Kant. This
is because it applies its principles to events that occur in the natural world. Schiller’s portrayal of
beauty, in the same way, evades the norm that describes beauty as a form of moral freedom. He
rather considers this as freedom only in its appearance. Considering the regulative principle, beauty
is not just a sensible manifestation of an idea but rather a revelation of a freedom. Schiller,
however, fails to explain the reason why freedom in appearance is not considered equal to beauty
In Schiller’s aesthetic letters, he comes up with the thesis that “it is through beauty that we
achieve freedom”. This thesis also paves the way for one of his major theses: aesthetic education.
In this, he shows that harmony between nature and a person is only restored when one acquires an
21
experience of beauty. This thesis was specifically aimed at demonstrating a person’s right to civil
freedom. He argues that the right to civil freedom only becomes practical when one demonstrates
people’s capacity for moral freedom. Although political, this idea was a major milestone in
connecting Schiller’s approach to beauty and aesthetics. Simply put, it explains the relationship
between existence in the amoral state and moral virtues, which interplay in the appreciation of
beauty. Schiller’s main point in this thesis is that one cannot exist in a moral state without first
educating one’s moral virtue. This is a direct rejection of Kant’s approach to the same. While Kant
argues that all forms of external influences (including education and moral virtues) bring a bias to
the recognition of beauty, Schiller goes for the option that they cannot be ignored since they have
In his letters, Schiller identifies three notions of freedom, of which two are opposed to
Kant’s freedom of autonomy (Beiser, 2005, p. 67). The freedom of choice, for example, is
considered as resulting from the inability to determine what he refers to as the ‘aesthetic condition’.
not defined by anything in a positive way. He, therefore, argues that a particular aesthetic condition
leads to awarding different freedoms to particular aesthetic conditions. This is the freedom by
which one is not constrained to act morally. Simply put, an aesthetic condition leads to the
generation of a state of indeterminacy based on the moral choice made. This, however, also unfolds
to sustain an individual moral choice, which is the basis for every individual choice.
freedom to us. This implies that beauty does not produce a moral result but rather gives us the
freedom and the capacity to do good actions (Beiser, 2005, p. 76). Simply put, beauty carries no
specific intellectual, moral object. Unlike Kant, who considers the value of art as based on its
22
natural appearance, Schiller comes up with a notion that considers the beauty of art as based on its
freedom. He gives the specifics of this freedom as moral freedom rather than freedom of choice in
an absolute infinite manner. To complement this, Schiller comfortably concludes that it will be
A close observation of Schiller’s approach to beauty reveals the tension between the
notions of freedom that he presents throughout his theories (Du Marsais, 2010, p. 149). The
freedoms belong to different paradigms and do not match. Although he gives a clear distinction
between his two major freedoms (moral freedom and aesthetic freedom), he leaves some gaps,
especially in sentiments about the perceptions of beauty described by Kant. After explaining his
idea of autonomy, for example, he comes up with the notion of neutral will. This not only presents
itself as beyond the laws of nature but also goes beyond Kant’s will. Although Schiller comes up
with this notion long before coming into contact with Kant’s ideas, he modifies it after Kant’s
release of the Critique of the Power of Judgment. This time, he considers the natural will as
“perfectly free between inclination and duty, as no physical necessity ought to enter as a sharer in
the magisterial personality” (§32, 5:283). This is not only ambiguous but also confusing,
considering that his first approach had considered the freedom of beauty as determining our our
attitudes towards aesthetics. Although his work is mainly focused on actuality/reality, this
approach to the appreciation of nature totals confusion as one has to struggle between maintaining
Schiller’s work gives great significance to realism as well as reconciliation of the dualism
of sensibility and intellect (Barnouw, 1980, p. 58). This is evident in his letters, which advocate
for freedom that is located in the middle of the realm of ‘un-determinedness’. This refers to a
possibility of existing between the realism of nature and reason, hence neutralising the absolute
23
determinedness of the two. From here, he then introduces the notion of a play drive by arguing
that aesthetic freedom is placed between acting according to the laws of nature and the forces of
the material drive. This is one of the attempts that shows Schiller’s efforts to reconcile Kantian
dualism.
As earlier highlighted, Schiller’s and Kant’s concerns regarding the role of duty and
freedom in aesthetics cannot be reconciled. A study of Schiller’s approach to aesthetics shows that
Kant’s consideration of the relationship between desire and duty does not support the ideology of
needing the motivation of duty to act independently, even when they go against our feelings. This
implies that the claims of pure, practical reason brought forth by Kant cannot be reconciled with
our feelings about our feelings to both aesthetic and teleological judgments. This can only be
achieved by a reasonable portrayal of morality and beauty, as well as for the cultivation of moral
feelings.
Although Schiller has continuously endorsed Kant’s position on the superiority of moral
reason, he departs from Kant on the issue of the theory of duty. For this particular topic, Schiller
continuously supports Kant's ideology on the freedom of the superiority held by the moral law and
its legislative role of practical reason over the human senses. Schiller, however, brings in a view
that accuses the tyranny of duty of being barbaric by arguing that it suppresses human passions,
hence creating flaws in human moral understanding despite the almost impossible task of fulfilling
Finally, Schiller considers the Kantian ontological difference of the regimes of beauty and
goodness as misplaced. He argues that moral praxis and aesthetic experience ought to be on the
24
same ontological level, and then he considers aesthetic education as having a real effect on
morality.
3.3 The Mind’s Independence: Kant’s Arguments as Defying the Freedom of the Mind’s
Independence
Although Kant’s theory of disinterestedness has been widely appreciated, the unit would
be correct when arguing that most of the conclusions drawn from the theory are in conflict with
some widely held views of nature as well as the significance of the common experience of natural
beauty. To start with, Kant considers it a key conclusion that the proper objects of aesthetic
appreciation are the temporal and spatial forms of objects, as opposed to their material properties,
such as tone or colour, or abstract properties, such as their meaning, conceptual significance or
content (Guyer, 1978, p. 455). This conflicts with the natural beliefs that the beauty of the sunset,
for example, lies in its magnificent colour display or that of the Pieta in its characteristic deep
expression of emotion. In other words, Kant’s basic principles conflict with natural intuitions in a
Kant’s interpretations discourage a serious consideration of his theory would stand. He, for
example, asserts that certain objects are beautiful based on experiences that show no particular
with the judgment and, hence, are only a result of his imagination, which does not in any way
consider how the normal world operates. According to Kant, “one must not be in the least pre-
posed in favor of the existence of a thing, but must be quite indifferent in order to play part of a
judge in matters regarding taste” (Guyer, 1978, p. 457). However, and on the contrary, it is
certainly true that one is already disposed in favour of an object for a particular reason (its value,
25
for example) and, hence, could barely make a fair assessment of aesthetic merits by ignoring any
of such dispositions. This would only be the case when the beauty of an object cannot engender a
genuine desire or concern. This becomes apparent, for example, in the case of maintenance of art;
one would probably decide whether to maintain a piece of art based on aspects such as its worth,
contemporary aesthetic reasons or the reason besides its existence in their lives among others. For
this reason, one could have two pieces of art and only take good care of one, because one does not
judge the pieces of art based on neutrality, as Kant would argue, but rather from specific reasons,
Furthermore, Kant’s theory of disinterestedness denies that the experience of beauty can
have a direct effect on human desires or generate interest in the existence of beautiful objects. In
attempting to compensate for his exclusion of direct connection between the judgment of taste and
between the two. However, this is extremely contrary to the humanist beliefs on the existence of
art (Guyer, 1996, p. 460). Kant indirectly connects intellectual interest to beauty in an analogy that
combines aesthetic response to moral feelings. He achieves this by using practical reasons of
interest in beauty that conform to the conditions of our wholly disinterested delight and then
maintains that this foundation justifies interest in the beauty of nature but not that of art. Simply
put, he tries to draw the conclusion that the virtuousness of taste is not often achieved but is rather
based on vain, selfish and injurious passions. This is also coupled with the argument that the
interest in the beauty of art is based on no significant proof that would explain its manner of
Thinking of interpreting the above conclusions, however, Kant asserts that beauty can
generate no significant interest and that natural beauty is entirely more significant than artistic
26
beauty. In the normal world, however, this is unproven and no theoretical or scientific explanation
can be used to prove such sentiments. According to Guyer (1996, p. 462), an interpretation of
Kant’s theories would show that these are not really consequences of it. Kant’s formalist
preference for design over colour and composition, for example, shows that his opinions are in no
way a direct consequence of his theory, whatever he himself may have thought. In the case of his
thesis that aesthetic judgment asserts no interest, the actual consequences of his theory appear not
Kant’s explanation of aesthetic judgment does not imply that people cannot take a
particular form of interest in beautiful objects. It also does not imply that we ought to look beyond
the phenomena of aesthetic responses when it comes to explaining our desires with respect to
beauty portrayed in works of art. This implies that Kant’s theory places no significance on its
objects and hence is not comparable with the supposition that the experience of beauty can directly
and naturally generate certain desires with respect to the perceived beautiful objects (Guyer, 1978,
p. 465). This implies that it is simply not necessary for Kant to resort to the theory of intellectual
and indirect interest in beauty to explain humanly desires. His claim that only natural objects, and
not artistic ones, generate such desires can also be ignored in this case. It is interesting to note,
however, that Kant’s theory of aesthetic response can be supplemented by a theory of a further
moral and intellectual interest in beauty. More exploration of this case would also prove that his
distinction between natural and artistic beauty is unjustified. Kant’s own account, for example,
explains that paradigmatic cases of artistic beauty have as much claim to our intellectual interest
Thinking of the objects that Kant uses to support his arguments, he presents an adoption of
example, he uses the example of a palace: “If asked whether a palace before me is beautiful, I
might say no on the ground that I do not care for the things made merely to be gripped at, a good
restaurant would please me more, or I might dismiss the building by condemning the vanity of the
great who exploit the populace to build such things” (Guyer, 1978, p. 467). From a normative point
of view, however, all such responses are irrelevant to the question of beauty. They are based on
moral or utilitarian concerns rather than a purely aesthetic concern. Such examples are not just
misplaced but even irrelevant with regard to the notion of disinterestedness. The examples imply
that Kant does manifest concerns that are interested in delight and connected to objects’ real
existence as well as their representation. Although he goes beyond the exploration of the natural
forms of beauty, he incorporates his feelings towards the external environment, creating a bias
based on his assumption that everyone would have a similar perception that intentionally ignores
Finally, disinterested pleasure is based on two central claims that have brought forward
multiple critical debates. First, Kant considers “disinterested pleasure as devoid of all interest”
(§32, 5:283) and second, “the judgment of taste does not arouse any specific interests” (§50,
5:320). The latter is problematic as it fails to allow for an external relationship between interests
and aesthetic judgment. Guyer considers this as part of an error on Kant’s part. According to
Guyer, it is absurd to claim that an object’s beauty cannot bring about any genuine desire since the
beauty of an object forms a major reason for why one would be interested in taking an interest in
4. Conclusion
in opposing Kant’s notion of disinterestedness with regard to disinterested pleasure and the
28
judgment of taste. Additionally, Schiller and Guyer manage to successfully object to Kant’s idea
of disinterested pleasure, owing to their ability to separate Kant’s arguments from reality. Simply
put, all the extensive arguments brought forward by these philosophers revolve around whether
pleasure can or cannot produce desire by itself (Hammermeister, 2002, pp. 83-85). Immanuel Kant
admits that human beings are concerned with beauty from several angles, hence implying that
desire may probably follow from the judgment of beauty. Additionally, Kant also admits that such
desires cannot trace their origin only to pleasure from the beautiful. Kant’s thesis on the notion of
disinterestedness is therefore very controversial, owing to its own components. Kant tries to
separate reality from imagination but, unfortunately, has ended up being categorised as someone
who uses fantasy to come up with an approach to reality. Although most philosophers respect
Kant’s work, it is important to argue that this is not the type of work to follow blindly.
29
References
Alison E (2001), Kant`s theory of Taste: A reading of the Critique of Aesthetic Judgement,
Atwell, J. E. (1996), ''Art as liberation: a central theme of Schopenhauer's philosophy''. In: Dale
Barnouw, J. (1980). ”The Morality of the Sublime: Kant and Schiller”. Studies in Romanticism
19 (4) pp 497-514.
Bell D (1992). The Art of Judgment in Immanuel Kant: Critical Assessments, Vol. IV, ed. Ruth
Deligiorgi, K. (2005). Kant and the Culture of Enlightenment. Albany: SUNY Press.
Deligiorgi, K. (2006). ”Grace as Guide to Morals? Schiller’s Aesthetic Turn in Ethics”. History
Gardener, S (1999). ''Schopenhauer, Will, and the Unconscious''. In: The Cambridge Companion
Guyer P. (1978). The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 36 (4) pp. 449-470
30
Guyer, P (1996). ''Pleasure and knowledge in Schopenhauer's aesthetics''. In: Dale Jacquette
(ed.), Schopenhauer, Philosophy and the Arts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
pp. 109-132.
Hammermeister K, (2002). The German Aesthetic Tradition. Cambridge and New York:
2005.
Theme,” in: G. Raţă, P. Runcan, M. Marsonet (eds.), Applied Social Sciences. Philosophy
Palgrave Macmillan.
Paul G and Eric M, & Paul G, (2000) Critique of the Power of Judgment, by Immanuel Kant,
Rehberg, (2013), “On a Feeling for All:” Cogito, 74, pp. 150-66.
Roehr, S. (2003). ”Freedom and Autonomy in Schiller”. Journal of the History of Ideas 64 (1),
119-134.
31
Schopenhauer A., (2010). The World as Will and Representation: Volume I. Tr. Judith Norman,
University Press.
Tauber, Z. (2006). “Aesthetic Education for Morality: Schiller and Kant”. Journal of Aesthetic
Van Gogh (1889). The Sattry Night, Google arts and culture, Retrierved on June 18, 2018, from
https://artsandculture.google.com/asset/the-starry-night/bgEuwDxel93-Pg?hl=en