Evolution: The Pleasures of Pluralism
Evolution: The Pleasures of Pluralism
Evolution: The Pleasures of Pluralism
(https://www.nybooks.com/articles/1997/06/26/evolution-the-pleasures-of-pluralism)
Charles Darwin began the last paragraph of The Origin of Species (1859) with a famous metaphor about life’s
diversity and ecological complexity:
It is interesting to contemplate an entangled bank, clothed with many plants of many kinds, with birds singing on the
bushes, with various insects flitting about, and with worms crawling through the damp earth, and to reflect that these
elaborately constructed forms, so different from each other, and dependent on each other in so complex a manner,
have all been produced by laws acting around us.
He then begins the final sentence of the book with an equally famous statement: “There is grandeur in this view
of life...”
For Darwin, as for any scientist, a kind of ultimate satisfaction (Darwin’s “grandeur”) must reside in the prospect
that so much variety and complexity might be generated from natural regularities—the “laws acting around us”—
accessible to our intellect and empirical probing. But what is the proper relationship between underlying laws and
explicit results? The “fundamentalists” among evolutionary theorists revel in the belief that one overarching law—
Darwin’s central principle of natural selection—can render the full complexity of outcomes (by working in
conjunction with auxiliary principles, like sexual reproduction, that enhance its rate and power).
The “pluralists,” on the other hand—a long line of thinkers including Darwin himself, however ironic this may
seem since the fundamentalists use the cloak of his name for their distortion of his position—accept natural
selection as a paramount principle (truly primus inter pares), but then argue that a set of additional laws, as well
as a large role for history’s unpredictable contingencies, must also be invoked to explain the basic patterns and
regularities of the evolutionary pathways of life. Both sides locate the “grandeur” of “this view of life” in the
explanation of complex and particular outcomes by general principles, but ultra-Darwinian fundamentalists pursue
one true way, while pluralists seek to identify a set of interacting explanatory modes, all fully intelligible, although
not reducible to a single grand principle like natural selection.
The first part of this article outlined the general fallacies of ultra-Darwinian fundamentalism, especially in the light
of new theories and discoveries in the core disciplines of developmental biology, paleontology, and population
geneticsi. In this second and concluding part, I shall analyze a prominent philosopher’s influential but misguided
ultra-Darwinian manifesto—Darwin’s Dangerous Idea, by Daniel Dennett. I shall also take up the methodology
of so-called “evolutionary psychology”—a field now in vogue as a marketplace for ultra-Darwinian explanatory
doctrine. Evolutionary psychology could, in my view, become a fruitful science by replacing its current penchant
for narrow, and often barren, speculation with respect for the pluralistic range of available alternatives that are just
as evolutionary in status, more probable in actual occurrence, and not limited to the blinkered view that
evolutionary explanations must identify adaptations produced by natural selection.
1.
Daniel Dennett devotes the longest chapter in Darwin’s Dangerous Idea to an excoriating caricature of my ideas,
all in order to bolster his defense of Darwinian fundamentalism. If an argued case can be discerned at all amid the
slurs and sneers, it would have to be described as an effort to claim that I have, thanks to some literary skill, tried
to raise a few piddling, insignificant, and basically conventional ideas to “revolutionary” status, challenging what
he takes to be the true Darwinian scripture. Dennett claims that I have promulgated three “false alarms” as
supposed revolutions against the version of Darwinism that he and his fellow defenders of evolutionary orthodoxy
continue to espouse.
Dennett first attacks my view that punctuated equilibrium is the dominant pattern of evolutionary change in the
history of living organisms. This theory, formulated by Niles Eldredge and me in 1972, proposes that the two most
general observations made by paleontologists form a genuine and primary pattern of evolution, and do not arise
as artifacts of an imperfect fossil record. The first observation notes that most new species originate in a geological
“moment.” The second holds that species generally do not change in any substantial or directional way during
their geological lifetimes—usually a long period averaging five to ten million years for fossil invertebrate species.
Punctuated equilibrium does not challenge accepted genetic ideas about the rates at which species emerge (for the
geological “moment” of a single rock layer may represent many thousand years of accumulation). But the theory
does contravene conventional Darwinian expectations for gradual change over geological periods, and does
suggest a substantial revision of standard views about the causes of long-term evolutionary trends. For such trends
must now be explained by the higher rates at which some species branch off from others, and the greater durations
of some stable species as distinguished from others, and not as the slow and continuous transformation of single
populations.
In his second attack, Dennett denigrates the importance of nonadaptive side consequences (“spandrels” in my
terminology) as sources for later and fruitful reuse. In principle, spandrels define the major category of important
evolutionary features that do not arise as adaptations. Since organisms are complex and highly integrated entities,
any adaptive change must automatically “throw off” a series of structural byproducts—like the mold marks on an
old bottle or, in the case of an architectural spandrel itself, the triangular space “left over” between a rounded arch
and the rectangular frame of wall and ceiling. Such byproducts may later be co-opted for useful purposes, but they
didn’t arise as adaptations. Reading and writing are now highly adaptive for humans, but the mental machinery
for these crucial capacities must have originated as spandrels that were co-opted later, for the brain reached its
current size and conformation tens of thousands of years before any human invented reading or writing.
Third, and finally, Dennett denies theoretical importance to the roles of contingency and chance in the history of
life, a history that has few predictable particulars and no inherent directionality, especially given the persistence
of bacteria as the most common and dominant form of life on Earth ever since their origin as the first fossilized
creatures some 3.5 billion years agoii. Bacteria are biochemically more diverse, and live in a wider range of
environments (including near-boiling waters, and pore spaces in rocks up to two miles beneath the earth’s surface),
than all other living things combined. The number of E. coli cells in the gut of each human being exceeds the total
number of human beings that have ever lived. Moreover, if recent reports of Martian fossil bacteria are true, then
bacterial domination may be interplanetary or universal, and not merely earthly.
These three concepts work as pluralistic correctives to both the poverty and limited explanatory power of the ultra-
Darwinian research program. Punctuated equilibrium requires that substantial evolutionary trends over geological
time, the primary phenomenon of macroevolution, be explained by the greater long-term success of some species
versus others within a group of species descended from a common ancestor. Such trends cannot be explained, as
Darwinian fundamentalists would prefer, as the adaptive success of individual organisms in conventional
competition, extrapolated through geological time as the slow and steady transformation of populations by natural
selection. The principle of spandrels, discussed at greater length later in this article, stresses the role that
nonadaptive side consequences play in structuring the directions and potentials of future evolutionary change.
Taken together, punctuated equilibrium and spandrels invoke the operation of several important principles in
addition (and sometimes even opposed) to conventional natural selection working in the engineering mode that
Dennett sees as the only valid mechanism of evolution.
My third pluralistic corrective to traditional theory does not invoke other principles in addition to natural selection,
but rather stresses the limits faced by any set of general principles in our quest to explain the actual patterns of
life’s history. Crank your algorithm of natural selection to your heart’s content, and you cannot grind out the
contingent patterns built during the earth’s geological history. You will get predictable pieces here and there
(convergent evolution of wings in flying creatures), but you will also encounter too much randomness from a
plethora of sources, too many additional principles from within biological theory, and too many unpredictable
impacts from environmental histories beyond biology (including those occasional meteors)—all showing that the
theory of natural selection must work in concert with several other principles of change to explain the observed
pattern of evolution.
S ince Dennett shows so little understanding of evolutionary theory beyond natural selection, his critique of my
work amounts to little more than sniping at false targets of his own construction. He never deals with my ideas
as such, but proceeds by hint, innuendo, false attribution, and error. I will cite concrete examples in four categories:
1. False assimilation to statements made by other authors. Since Dennett can’t nail me on his desired charges
(for I never said the things he wishes to lay upon me), he often invents a ridiculous interpretation, which he
attributes to others and not to me, and then hopes out loud that I never meant such a thing. For example,
Dennett invents and attributes to “some” writers an absurd mischaracterization of my views on the Cambrian
explosion, the short episode (535-530 million years ago) when nearly all the major groups of animals make
their first appearance in the fossil record, including the creatures preserved in the Burgess Shale:
Some say this misses Gould’s point: “What is special about the spectacular diversity of the Burgess Shale fauna is
that these weren’t just new species, but whole new phyla! These were radically novel designs!” I trust this was never
Gould’s point, because if it was, it was an embarrassing fallacy of retrospective coronation.
It would be—but since I have never even hinted at such a silly view, why bother to point out how stupid I would
be if I ever had?
In an even more unfair example, Dennett conjectures about what I might believe (but I don’t, and he cites nothing
to support his supposition), and then seems to pretend that I hold such a view by attacking someone else who truly
does:
Is it likely that Gould could be so confused about the nature of algorithms? As we shall see in chapter 15, Roger
Penrose, one of the world’s most distinguished mathematicians, wrote a major book (1989) on Turing machines,
algorithms, and the impossibility of Artificial Intelligence, and his whole book is based on that confusion. This is not
really such an implausible error, on either thinker’s part [I have now become an explicit supporter of the idea—]. A
person who really doesn’t like Darwin’s dangerous idea often finds it hard to get the idea in focus.
2. False characterization. Dennett depicts me as constantly and explicitly claiming to invent one scientific
“revolution” after another. No characterization appears more frequently throughout the chapter, and none
could be so false. “Gould,” he states, “has gone from revolution to revolution. So far, his declarations of
revolution have all been false alarms.” We then learn that “the spandrel revolution (against panadaptationism)
and the exaptation revolution (against preadaptationism) evaporate on closer inspection,” and that “Gould’s
attempted revolution against gradualism was actually his first.” In a final summary, we learn that “Gould’s
self-styled revolutions …all evaporate.”
Of course, I am never quoted directly as making any personal claim about a “revolution,” self-styled or
otherwise—and for a good reason: I have, quite consciously and on principle, never used the word to describe my
work. I have too much admiration for my dear friend, the late Thomas Kuhn, and I have also too often watched
foolish and ambitious colleagues trying to wrap themselves in a caricature of his “paradigm” in order to proclaim
their own revolutions, ever to engage in such a farce myself.
Dennett says that I started all this revolution mongering in my first paper on punctuated equilibrium, published in
1972. In that work, by contrast, I paid homage to Kuhn’s influence, and explicitly disavowed any such fatuous
intention: “We have no desire,” I wrote (with Niles Eldredge) in 1972,
to enter the tedious debate over what is, or is not,… a paradigm [in Kuhn’s terminology]. In using the neutral word
picture, we trust that readers will understand our concern with alternate ways of seeing the world that render the same
facts in different ways.
The details of Dennett’s discussions also rest largely on ridicule and mischaracterization. For example, he
denigrates the principle of spandrels by mockery, not argument.
Gould wants to convince us that adaptation is not “pervasive,” so he needs to have a term for the (presumably many)
biological features that are not adaptations. They are to be called “spandrels.” Spandrels are, um, things that aren’t
adaptations, whatever they are.
But I have always defined spandrels precisely as one particular and eminently testable kind of nonadaptive
structure—an architectural byproduct, or what Darwin called, in his own favorite and pluralistic example of
nonadaptation, a “correlation of growth.”
D ennett’s account of punctuated equilibrium is a farrago of false charges, finally capped on the last page by a
grudging glimmer of understanding that the theory might be trying to say something interesting and new after
all. We first learn that “Gould has several times changed his mind about just what he and Eldredge were claiming.”
We have, of course, often altered and expanded the theory in recognizing further implications and dropping
untenable corollaries—as any active and interesting formulation of a scientific theory must continually do. The
basic principles have, however, remained intact and have, I believe, gained strength. But Dennett cares little about
this method of scientific work; he is only interested in charging me with flimflam and backpedaling.
In particular, he claims that we turned the theory into a phony revolutionary claim for abrupt, or “saltational,” non-
Darwinian change, i.e., the sudden transformation of one ancestral species into another of markedly different form.
Of course, Dennett cannot quote us on this—because we never said such a thing. He acknowledges my frequently
published complaint that this charge is a standard mischaracterization, and he quotes several of our rebuttals. But,
for Dennett, the situation remains entirely our fault: “Confusion on this score still abounds, however, and Gould
has had to keep issuing his disclaimers.”
Dennett can’t support his charge of revolution mongering with any quotation from me, but since he remains
convinced of his claim, he quotes me in supposed support, when I am obviously making an almost opposite point—
a clear illustration of the power of an idée fixe to trigger a misreading. Dennett begins with the standard canard:
“For a while, Gould was proposing that the first step in the establishment of any (my emphasis) new species was
a doozy—a non-Darwinian saltation.” To illustrate this claim, Dennett quotes from a 1980 paper, in which I wrote:
Speciation is not always an extension of gradual, adaptive allelic substitution to greater effect, but may represent, as
Goldschmidt argued, a different style of genetic change—rapid reorganization of the genome, perhaps nonadaptive.
This statement still strikes me as entirely reasonable, and I see no reason to modify it today. I said that some
instances of speciation—probably only a small percentage—proceed in this rapid mode. “Not always” surely
means “not all the time, but usually.” It cannot mean “never”—as Dennett charges in claiming that I attribute
“any” speciation event to the opposite mode of saltation. In other words, I am trying to carve out a modest space
for an unconventional mechanism at low frequency—and Dennett charges me with advocating a revolution based
on universal occurrence for this unorthodox mode.
3. High density of error. A fair test can be made for a nonprofessional’s grasp of scientific material by noting the
frequency of factual errors in his descriptions of technical work. I do not claim that any of these minor mistakes
produces great distortion, but Dennett’s high density of errors, on easy points that only require accurate reading
or copying, indicates an apparent indifference to the vital details that build the history of life.
Dennett’s account of my book Wonderful Life includes the following errors in only four pages. He misstates the
date of the Cambrian explosion by 70 million years—“a time around six hundred million years ago when the
multicellular organisms really took off.” The actual date is 530 million years ago. He then states (a serious error
this time) that C.D. Walcott based his original Burgess Shale work on “literal dissection of some of the fossils”—
when I emphasize in my book (as a major theme of my narrative) that Walcott failed precisely because he did not
dissect the specimens, which he incorrectly interpreted as squashed absolutely flat. Dennett then says twice that
most of the Burgess Shale species perished as rapidly as they arose—“most of them vanished just as suddenly”—
when I clearly state that we know nothing at all about the manner of their dying, because they left no fossil record
after the Burgess beds. Finally, Dennett lists eight of the wonderful Burgess creatures in a single sentence—and
he spells three of their names wrong. I don’t wish to harp on trivialities but Dennett could legitimately accuse me
of disrespectful inattention if I listed Dennett, Dawkins, and Maynard Smith as the apostles of ultra-Darwinism.
4. Gratuitous speculation about motives. In Dennett’s last few pages he apparently feels he must figure out why
I could be so obtuse (since he doesn’t regard me as stupid). “It might seem disingenuous,” he writes, “for me
not even to mention the obvious ‘rival’ explanations crying to be considered: politics and religion.” Dennett
has no clue about my political or religious views, and he has never bothered to ask me—but did lack of data
ever derail the ultra-Darwinian game of adaptationist storytelling? So we first hear a little red-baiting. Then,
in a surprise turnaround, I become a closet theist who secretly hates Darwinism because “Humanity cannot be
special enough to matter if it is the product of merely algorithmic processes.” As evidence, Dennett writes:
Gould often quotes the Bible in his monthly columns, and sometimes the rhetorical effect is striking. Surely, one
thinks, an article with this opening sentence has to have been written by a religious man: “Just as the Lord holds the
whole world in his hands, how we long to enfold an entire subject into a witty epigram.”
I do often quote the Bible as great literature, but this time I was only citing a famous African-American folk song.
2.
The fallacy of Dennett’s argument also undermines his other imperialist hope—that the universal acid of natural
selection might reduce human cultural change to the Darwinian algorithm as well. Dennett, following Dawkins
once again, tries to identify human thoughts and actions as “memes,” thus viewing them as units that are subject
to a form of selection analogous to natural selection of genes. Cultural change, working by memetic selection, then
becomes as algorithmic as biological change operating by natural selection on genes—thus uniting the evolution
of organisms and thoughts under a single ultra-Darwinian rubric:
According to Darwin’s dangerous idea…not only all your children and your children’s children, but all your
brainchildren and your brainchildren’s brainchildren must grow from the common stock of Design elements, genes
and memes…. Life and all its glories are thus united under a single perspective.
But, as Dennett himself correctly and repeatedly emphasizes, the generality of an algorithm depends upon
“substrate neutrality.” That is, the various materials (substrates) subject to the mechanism (natural selection in this
case) must all permit the mechanism to work in the same effective manner. If one kind of substrate tweaks the
mechanism to operate differently (or, even worse, not to work at all), then the algorithm fails. To choose a
somewhat silly example that actually played an important role in recent American foreign policy, the cold war
“domino theory” held that communism must be stopped everywhere because if one country turned red, then others
would do so as well, for countries are like dominos standing on their ends and placed one behind the other—so
that the toppling of one must propagate down the entire line to topple all. Now if you devised a general formula
(an algorithm) to describe the necessary propagation of such toppling, and wanted to cite the algorithm as a general
rule for all systems made of a series of separate objects, then the generality of your algorithm would depend upon
substrate neutrality—that is, upon the algorithm’s common working, regardless of substrate (similarly for dominos
and nations in this case). The domino theory failed because differences in substrate affect the outcome, and such
differences can even derail the operation of the algorithm. Dominoes must topple, but the second nation in a line
might brace itself, stay upright upon impact, and therefore fail to propagate the collapse.
Natural selection does not enjoy this necessary substrate neutrality. As the great evolutionist R.A. Fisher showed
many years ago in the founding document of modern Darwinism (The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection,
l930), natural selection requires Mendelian inheritance to be effective. Genetic evolution works upon such a
substrate and can therefore be Darwinian. Cultural (or memetic) change manifestly operates on the radically
different substrate of Lamarckian inheritance, or the passage of acquired characters to subsequent generations.
Whatever we invent in our lifetimes, we can pass on to our children by our writing and teaching. Evolutionists
have long understood that Darwinism cannot operate effectively in systems of Lamarckian inheritance—for
Lamarckian change has such a clear direction, and permits evolution to proceed so rapidly, that the much slower
process of natural selection shrinks to insignificance before the Lamarckian juggernaut.
T his crucial difference between biological and cultural evolution also undermines the self-proclaimed
revolutionary pretensions of a much publicized doctrine—“evolutionary psychology”— that could be quite
useful if proponents would trade their propensity for cultism and ultra-Darwinian fealty for a healthy dose of
modestyiii.
Drawing on my preceding discussion, may I propose a good rule of thumb in judging public announcements by
scientists: always be especially suspicious of claims for revolutionary status, especially since Thomas Kuhn
reformulated the history of science to make “revolution” the explicit object of every ambitious scientist’s fancy.
Carol K. Yoon, a perceptive science writer for The New York Times, cut through the rhetoric to the weak foundation
below when she wrote: “‘It’s a scientific revolution,’ [a prominent supporter of evolutionary psychology] said of
this newly named science, which sometimes seems an uncomfortable mixture of scientific method and cocktail
party conversation.”
Humans are animals and the mind evolved; therefore, all curious people must support the quest for an evolutionary
psychology. But the movement that has commandeered this name adopts a fatally restrictive view of the meaning
and range of evolutionary explanation. “Evolutionary psychology” has, in short, fallen into the same ultra-
Darwinian trap that ensnared Daniel Dennett and his confrères—for disciples of this new art confine evolutionary
accounts to the workings of natural selection and consequent adaptation for personal reproductive success.
Evolutionary psychology, as a putative science of human behavior, itself evolved by “descent with modification”
from 1970s-style sociobiology. But the new species, like many children striving for independence, shuns its actual
ancestry by taking a new name and exaggerating some genuine differences while ignoring the much larger amount
of shared doctrine—all done, I assume, to avoid the odor of sociobiology’s dubious political implications and
speculative failures (amid some solid successes when based on interesting theory and firm data, mostly from
nonhuman species).
T hree major claims define the core commitments of evolutionary psychology; each embodies a considerable
strength and a serious (in one case, fatal) weakness:
1. Modularity. Human behavior and mental operations can be divided into a relatively discrete set of items, or
mental organs. (In one prominent study, for example, authors designate a “cheater detector” as a mental organ,
since the ability to discern infidelity and other forms of prevarication can be so vital to Darwinian success—
the adaptationist rationale.) The argument for modularity flows, in part, from exciting work in neurobiology
and cognitive science on localization of function within the brain—as shown, for example, in the precise
mapping, to different areas of the cerebral cortex, of mental operations formerly regarded as only arbitrarily
divisible by social convention (production of vowels and consonants, for example, or the naming of animals
and tools).
Ironically, though, neurobiology and evolutionary psychology employ the concept of modularity for opposite
theoretical purposes. Neurobiologists do so to stress the complexity of an integrated organ. Evolutionary
psychology uses modularity to atomize behavior into a priori, subjectively defined, and poorly separated items
(not known modules empirically demonstrated by neurological study), so that selective value and adaptive
significance can be postulated for individual items, as the ultra-Darwinian approach requires.
2. Universality. Evolutionary psychologists generally restrict their study to universal aspects of human behavior
and mentality, thereby explicitly avoiding the study of differences among individuals or groups. They argue
that variations among individuals, and such groups as races and social classes, only reflect the influence of
diverse environments upon a common biological heritage. In this sense, they argue, evolutionary psychology
adopts a “liberal” position in contrast with the conservative implications of most previous evolutionary
arguments about behavior, which viewed variation among individuals and groups as results of different, and
largely unalterable, genetic constitutions.
I welcome much of this change; but, in one important respect, this new approach to universals and differences
continues to follow the old strategy of finding an adaptationist narrative (often in the purely speculative or
storytelling mode) to account for genetic differences built by natural selection. For the most-publicized work in
evolutionary psychology has centered on the universality in all human societies of a particular kind of difference:
the putative evolutionary reasons for supposedly universal behavioral differences between males and females.
3. Adaptation. Evolutionary psychologists claim that they have reformed the old adaptationism of sociobiology
into a new and exciting approach. They will no longer just assume, they now say, that all prominent and
universal behaviors must, ipso facto, be adaptive to modern humans in boosting reproductive success. They
recognize, instead, that many such behaviors may be tragically out of whack with the needs of modern life,
and may even lead to our destruction—aggressivity in a nuclear age, for example.
Again, I applaud this development. If this principle were advanced in conjunction with the recognition that a
putative evolutionary origin does not necessarily imply an adaptive value at all, then evolutionary psychology
could make a substantial advance in applying Darwinian theory to human behavior. But the advocates of
evolutionary psychology proceed in the opposite direction by twisting the observation that the behavior of modern
humans may not necessarily have adaptive value into an even more dogmatic, and even less scientifically testable,
panadaptationist claim. Evolutionary universals may not be adaptive now, they say, but such behaviors must have
arisen as adaptations in the different ancestral environment of life as small bands of hunter-gatherers on the African
savannas—for evolutionary theory “means” a search for adaptive origins.
The task of evolutionary psychology then turns into a speculative search for reasons why a behavior that may harm
us now must once have originated for adaptive purposes. To take an illustration proposed seriously by Robert
Wright in The Moral Animal, a sweet tooth leads to unhealthy obesity today but must have arisen as an adaptation.
Wright therefore states:
The classic example of an adaptation that has outlived its logic is the sweet tooth. Our fondness for sweetness was
designed for an environment in which fruit existed but candy didn’t.
This ranks as pure guesswork in the cocktail party mode; Wright presents no neurological evidence of a brain
module for sweetness, and no paleontological data about ancestral feeding. This “just-so story” therefore cannot
stand as a “classic example of an adaptation” in any sense deserving the name of science.
M uch of evolutionary psychology therefore devolves into a search for the so-called EEA, or “environment of
evolutionary adaptation” that allegedly prevailed in prehistoric times. Evolutionary psychologists have
gained some sophistication in recognizing that they need not postulate current utility to advance a Darwinian
argument; but they have made their enterprise even more fatuous by placing their central postulate outside the
primary definition of science—for claims about an EEA usually cannot be tested in principle but only subjected
to speculation. At least an argument about modern utility can be tested by studying the current impact of a given
feature upon reproductive success. Indeed, the disproof of many key sociobiological speculations about current
utility pushed evolutionary psychology to the revised tactic of searching for an EEA instead.
But how can we possibly know in detail what small bands of hunter-gatherers did in Africa two million years ago?
These ancestors left some tools and bones, and paleoanthropologists can make some ingenious inferences from
such evidence. But how can we possibly obtain the key information that would be required to show the validity of
adaptive tales about an EEA: relations of kinship, social structures and sizes of groups, different activities of males
and females, the roles of religion, symbolizing, storytelling, and a hundred other central aspects of human life that
cannot be traced in fossils? We do not even know the original environment of our ancestors—did ancestral humans
stay in one region or move about? How did environments vary through years and centuries?
In short, evolutionary psychology is as ultra-Darwinian as any previous behavioral theory in insisting upon
adaptive reasons for origin as the key desideratum of the enterprise. But the chief strategy proposed by evolutionary
psychologists for identifying adaptation is untestable, and therefore unscientific. This central problem does not
restrain leading disciples from indulging in reveries about the ubiquity of original adaptation as the source of
revolutionary power for the putative new science. I detect not a shred of caution in this proclamation by Wright—
embodying the three principal claims of evolutionary psychology as listed above:
The thousands and thousands of genes that influence human behavior—genes that build the brain and govern
neurotransmitters and other hormones, thus defining our “mental organs” [note the modularity claim]—are here for
a reason. And the reason is that they goaded our ancestors into getting their genes into the next generation [the claim
for adaptation in the EEA]. If the theory of natural selection is correct, then essentially everything about the human
mind should be intelligible in these terms [the ultra-Darwinian faith in adaptationism]. The basic ways we feel about
each other, the basic kinds of things we think about each other and say to each other [note the claim for universality],
are with us today by virtue of their past contribution to genetic fitness.
Wright’s closing sermon is more suitable to a Sunday pulpit than a work of science:
The theory of natural selection is so elegant and powerful as to inspire a kind of faith in it—not blind faith, really….
But faith nonetheless; there is a point after which one no longer entertains the possibility of encountering some fact
that would call the whole theory into question.
I must admit to having reached this point. Natural selection has now been shown to plausibly account for so much
about life in general and the human mind in particular that I have little doubt that it can account for the rest.
This adaptationist premise is the fatal flaw of evolutionary psychology in its current form. The premise also
seriously compromises—by turning a useful principle into a central dogma with asserted powers for nearly
universal explanation—the most promising theory of evolutionary psychology: the recognition that differing
Darwinian requirements for males and females imply distinct adaptive behaviors centered upon male advantage
in spreading sperm as widely as possible (since a male need invest no energy in reproduction beyond a single
ejaculation) and female strategies for extracting additional time and attention from males (in the form of parental
care or supply of provisions, etc.). (In most sexually reproducing species, males generate large numbers of “cheap”
sperm, while females make relatively few, “energetically expensive” eggs, and then must invest much time and
many resources in nurturing the next generation).
This principle of differential “parental investment” makes Darwinian sense and probably does underlie some
different, and broadly general, emotional propensities of human males and females. But contrary to claims in a
recent deluge of magazine articles, parental investment will not explain the full panoply of supposed sexual
differences so dear to pop psychology. For example, I do not believe that members of my gender are willing to
rear babies only because clever females beguile us. A man may feel love for a baby because the infant looks so
darling and dependent, and because a father sees a bit of himself in his progeny. This feeling need not arise as a
specifically selected Darwinian adaptation for my reproductive success, or as the result of a female ruse, culturally
imposed. Direct adaptation is only one mode of evolutionary origin. After all, I also have nipples not because I
need them, but because women do, and all humans share the same basic pathways of embryological development.
If evolutionary psychologists continue to push the theory of parental investment as a central dogma, they will
eventually suffer the fate of the Freudians, who also had some good insights but failed spectacularly, and with
serious harm imposed upon millions of people (women, for example, who were labeled as “frigid” when they
couldn’t make an impossible physiological transition from clitoral to vaginal orgasm), because they elevated a
limited guide into a rigid creed that became more of an untestable and unchangeable religion than a science.
E xclusive adaptationism suffers fatally from two broad classes of error, one external to Darwinian theory, the
other internal. The external error arises from fundamental differences in principle and mechanism between,
on the one hand, genetic Darwinian evolution and, on the other, human cultural change, which cannot be basically
Darwinian at all. Since every participant in these debates, including Dennett and the evolutionary psychologists,
agrees that much of human behavior arises by culturally induced rather than genetically coded change, giving total
authority to Darwinian explanation requires that culture also work in a Darwinian manner. (Dennett, as discussed
earlier, makes such a claim for cultural change in arguing for the “substrate neutrality” of natural selection.) But
for two fundamental reasons (and a host of other factors), cultural change unfolds virtually in antithesis to
Darwinian requirements.
First, topological: As the common metaphor proclaims, biological evolution builds a tree of life—a system based
upon continuous diversification and separation. A lineage, after branching off from ancestors as a new species,
attains an entirely independent evolutionary fate. Nature cannot make a new mammalian species by mixing 20
percent dugong with 30 percent rat and 50 percent aardvark. But cultural change works largely by an opposite
process of joining, or interconnection, of lineages. Marco Polo visits China and returns with many of the customs
and skills that later distinguish Italian culture. I speak English because my grandparents migrated to America.
Moreover, this interdigitation implies that human cultural change needn’t even follow genealogical lines—the
most basic requirement of a Darwinian evolutionary process—for even the most distant cultural lineages can
borrow from each other with ease. If we want a biological metaphor for cultural change, we should probably
invoke infection rather than evolution.
Second, causal: As argued above, human cultural change operates fundamentally in the Lamarckian mode, while
genetic evolution remains firmly Darwinian. Lamarckian processes are so labile, so directional, and so rapid that
they overwhelm Darwinian rates of change. Since Lamarckian and Darwinian systems work so differently, cultural
change will receive only limited (and metaphorical) illumination from Darwinism.
The internal error of adaptationism arises from a failure to recognize that even the strictest operation of pure
Darwinism builds organisms full of nonadaptive parts and behaviors. Nonadaptations arise for many reasons in
Darwinian systems, but consider only my favorite principle of “spandrels.”
All organisms evolve as complex and interconnected wholes, not as loose alliances of separate parts, each
independently optimized by natural selection. Any adaptive change must also generate, in addition, a set of
spandrels, or nonadaptive byproducts. These spandrels may later be “co-opted” for a secondary use. But we would
make an egregious logical error if we argued that these secondary uses explain the existence of a spandrel. I may
realize someday that my favorite boomerang fits beautifully into the arched space of my living room spandrel, but
you would think me pretty silly if I argued that the spandrel exists to house the boomerang. Similarly, snails build
their shells by winding a tube around an axis of coiling. This geometric process leaves an empty cylindrical space,
called an umbilicus, along the axis. A few species of snails use the umbilicus as a brooding chamber for storing
eggs. But the umbilicus arose as a nonadaptive spandrel, not as an adaptation for reproduction. The overwhelming
majority of snails do not use their umbilici for brooding, or for much of anything.
If any organ is, prima facie, replete with spandrels, the human brain must be our finest candidate—thus making
adaptationism a particularly dubious approach to human behavior. I can adopt (indeed I do) the most conventional
Darwinian argument for why the human brain evolved to large size—and the nonadaptationist principle of
spandrels may still dominate human nature. I am content to believe that the human brain became large by natural
selection, and for adaptive reasons—that is, for some set of activities that our savanna ancestors could only perform
with bigger brains.
D oes this argument imply that all genetically and biologically based attributes of our universal human nature
must therefore be adaptations? Of course not. Many, if not most, universal behaviors are probably spandrels,
often co-opted later in human history for important secondary functions. The human brain is the most complicated
device for reasoning and calculating, and for expressing emotion, ever evolved on earth. Natural selection made
the human brain big, but most of our mental properties and potentials may be spandrels—that is, nonadaptive side
consequences of building a device with such structural complexity. If I put a small computer (no match for a brain)
in my factory, my adaptive reasons for so doing (to keep accounts and issue paychecks) represent a tiny subset of
what the computer, by virtue of inherent structure, can do (factor-analyze my data on land snails, beat or tie anyone
perpetually in tic-tac-toe). In pure numbers, the spandrels overwhelm the adaptations.
The human brain must be bursting with spandrels that are essential to human nature and vital to our self-
understanding but that arose as nonadaptations, and are therefore outside the compass of evolutionary psychology,
or any other ultra-Darwinian theory. The brain did not enlarge by natural selection so that we would be able to
read or write. Even such an eminently functional and universal institution as religion arose largely as a spandrel if
we accept Freud’s old and sensible argument that humans invented religious belief largely to accommodate the
most terrifying fact that our large brains forced us to acknowledge: the inevitability of personal mortality. We can
scarcely argue that the brain got large so that we would know we must die!
In summary, Darwin cut to the heart of nature by insisting so forcefully that “natural selection has been the main,
but not the exclusive means of modification”—and that hard-line adaptationism could only represent a simplistic
caricature and distortion of his theory. We live in a world of enormous complexity in organic design and
diversity—a world where some features of organisms evolved by an algorithmic form of natural selection, some
by an equally algorithmic theory of unselected neutrality, some by the vagaries of history’s contingency, and some
as byproducts of other processes. Why should such a complex and various world yield to one narrowly construed
cause? Let us have a cast of cranes, some more important and general, others for particular things—but all subject
to scientific understanding, and all working together in a comprehensible way. Why not admit for theory the same
delight that Robert Louis Stevenson expressed for objects in his “Happy Thought”:
The world is so full of a number of things,
I’m sure we should all be as happy as kings.
Letters:
Daniel C. Dennett
‘Darwinian Fundamentalism’: An Exchange
August 14, 1997
i “Darwinian Fundamentalism,” The New York Review, June 12, 1997, pp. 34-37.
ii See my recent book Full House (Crown, 1996) for an account of this.
iii See such technical works as J. Barkow, L. Cosmides, and J. Tooby, The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation
of Culture (Oxford University Press, 1992); and D.M. Buss, The Evolution of Desire (Basic Books, 1994); and, especially, for its
impact by good writing and egregiously simplistic argument, the popular book of R. Wright, The Moral Animal: Why We Are the
Way We Are: The New Science of Evolutionary Psychology (Random House, 1994).