Chapter 11: Ash'arism: Al-Ashari's Life and Work
Chapter 11: Ash'arism: Al-Ashari's Life and Work
Chapter 11: Ash'arism: Al-Ashari's Life and Work
Ash’arite Theology
Al-Ash'ari maintains an intermediary position between the two diametrically
opposed schools of thought prevailing at the time. He had to fight against both the
opposing parties. At the one extreme were the Mu'tazilites who made reason in
preference to revelation the sole criterion of truth and reality and, thus, passed
slowly into comparatively innocuous heretics. At the other extreme were the
orthodox groups, particularly the Zahirites, the Mujassimites (anthropomorphists),
the Muhaddithin (Traditionists), and the Jurists, all of which were wholly opposed to
the use of reason or Kalam in defending or explaining religious dogmas and
condemned any discussion about them as innovation. Al-Ash'ari wrote his Istihsan
al-Khaud mainly to meet the objections raised by the orthodox school against the use
of reason in matters of faith.
In that treatise he says: “A section of the people (i.e., the Zahirites and other orthodox
people) made capital out of their own ignorance; discussions and rational thinking
about matters of faith became a heavy burden for them, and, therefore, they became
inclined to blind faith and blind following (taqlid). They condemned those who tried
to rationalize the principles of religion as `innovators.'
They considered discussion about motion, rest, body, accident, colour, space, atom,
the leaping of atoms, and attributes of God, to be an innovation and a sin. They said
that had such discussions been the right thing, the Prophet and his Companions
would have definitely done so; they further pointed out that the Prophet, before his
death, discussed and fully explained all those matters which were necessary from
the religious point of view, leaving none of them to be discussed by his followers; and
since he did not discuss the problems mentioned above, it was evident that to discuss
them must be regarded as an innovation.”
They further contended that these so-called theological problems were either known
to the Prophet and his Companions and yet they kept silent and did not discuss them
or they were not known to them. If they knew them and yet did not discuss them, we
are also to follow them in keeping silent, and if they could remain unaware of them
we can also do so. In both cases discussion about them would be an “innovation.”
These were, in brief, their objections against the use of Kalam in matters of faith.
Al-Ash'ari, then, proceeds to justify theological discussions about matters of faith. He
tries to meet these objections in three ways. First, by turning the objections of the
orthodox against themselves by pointing out to them that the Prophet had not said
that those who would discuss these problems were to be condemned and charged
as innovators. Hence, their charging or condemning others as innovators was itself
an innovation, for it amounted to discussion about matters which the Prophet did
not discuss, and condemn the action of those whom the Prophet did not condemn.
Secondly, “the Prophet was not unaware of all these problems of body, accident,
motion, rest, atoms, etc., though he did not discuss each of them separately. The
general principles (usul) underlying these problems are present in general, not in
details, in the Qur'an and the Sunnah.” Al-Ash'ari then proceeds to prove his
contention by citing verses from the Qur'an and the sayings of the Prophet, and
thereby showing that the principles underlying the problems
of harakah, sukun, tawhid, etc., are, as a matter of fact, present in the Qur'an and the
Sunnah.11
Thirdly, “the Prophet was not unaware of these matters and knew them in detail, but
as problems about them did not arise during his life-time, there was no question of
his discussing or not discussing them.” The Companions of the Prophet discussed
and argued about many religious matters which appeared during their life-time,
although there was no direct and explicit “saying” of the Prophet about them, and
because of the absence of any explicit injunction from the Prophet they differed in
their judgments about them.
Had the question, for instance, of the creation of the Qur'an, or of atoms or
substance, been raised in so many words in the life of the Prophet, he would have
definitely discussed and explained it as he did in the case of all those problems which
were then raised. “There is no direct verdict (nass) from the Prophet, for instance, as
to whether the Qur'an is created or uncreated. If to call the Qur'an created is an
`innovation,' then, on the same ground, to call it uncreated must also be an
`innovation.”' Al-Ash'ari then concludes that Islam is not opposed to the use of
reason; on the other hand, rationalization of faith is a necessity in Islam.
Al-Ash'ari discussed the main theological problems in his Maqalat al-Islamiy-
yin and al-Ibanah `an Usul al-Diyanah.In these books al-Ash’ari selects a few principles
which distinguish the Ash'arites from the Mu'tazilite school of thought. Later on
al-Ghazali put them in a consolidated form in his Ihya 12 as the “Principles of Faith”
or Qawa'id al-`Aqa'id, and Imam Fakhr al-Din al-Razi explained them more
elaborately. The main problems about which the Ash'arites differed from the
Mu'tazilites are:
(1) The conception of God and the nature of His attributes.
(2) Freedom of the human will.
(3) The criterion of truth and the standard of good and evil.
(4) The vision (ru’yah) of God.
(5) Createdness of the Qur'an.
(6) Possibility of burdening the creatures with impossible tasks.
(7) Promise of reward and threat of punishment.
(8) The rational or non-rational basis of God's actions.
(9) Whether God is bound to do what is best for His creatures.13
The problems discussed by the Ash'arites in their system may be broadly classified
into two categories: (i) theological, and (ii) metaphysical.
2. Free will
On the question of free-will or on the ability of man to choose and produce actions,
the Ash'arites took up again an intermediary position between the libertarian and
fatalistic views, held by the Mu'tazilites and the Jabrites respectively. The orthodox
people and the Jabrites maintained a pure fatalistic view. They held that human
actions are predetermined and predestined by God.
Man has no power to produce any action. “Everything,” they contended, “is from
God.” God has absolute power over everything including human will and human
actions. The Mu'tazilites and the Qadarites, on the other hand, held that man has full
power to produce an action and has complete freedom in his choice, though the
power was created in him by God.
The Ash'arites struck a middle path. They made a distinction between creation (khalq)
and acquisition (kasb) of an action. God, according to the Ash'arites, is the creator
(khaliq) of human actions and man is the acquisitor (muktasib). “Actions of human
beings are created (makhluq) by God, the creatures are not capable of creating any
action.”20 “There is no creator except God and the actions of man are, therefore, His
creation.”21 Power (qudrah), according to them, is either (i) original (qadamah) or (ii)
derived (hadithah). The original power alone is effective. Derived power can create
nothing. The power possessed by man is given by God and as such it is derived.22
Al Ash’ari said, “The true meaning of acquisition is the occurrence of a thing or event
due to derived power, and it is an acquisition for the person by whose derived power
it takes place.”23 God is, thus, the creator of human actions and man is the acquisitor.
Man cannot create anything; he cannot initiate work. God alone can create, because
absolute creation is His prerogative. God creates in man the power and the ability to
perform an act. He also creates in him the power to make a free choice (ikhtiyar)
between two alternatives - between right and wrong.
This free choice of man is not effective in producing the action. It is the habit or
nature of God to create the action corresponding to the choice and power created
by Himself in man. Thus, the action of man is created by God, both as to initiative
and as to production or completion. Man is free only in making the choice between
alternatives and also in intending to do the particular action freely chosen: Man, in
making this choice and intending to do the act, acquires (iktisab) either the merit of
appreciation and reward from God if he makes the right choice, or the demerit of
condemnation and punishment if he makes the wrong choice.
The Ash`arites, thus, in order to avoid the fatalistic position, introduced the doctrine
of acquisition by which, they thought, they could account for man's free-will and lay
responsibility upon him. Man has no free-will in the Mu'tazilite sense; he has no real
and effective power, but has some derived power by which he acquires a share in
the production of the act: In the case of voluntary actions of human beings, there
are, so to say, two causes.
The action is the combined effect of the real cause, God, and the choice and intention
of man, the acquisitor, the possessor of ineffective power because of its being
derived power. God creates in two ways: either with a locus (mahall) or without a
locus. Human actions are His creation with a locus.24
“God creates, in man, the power, ability, choice, and will to perform an act, and man,
endowed with this derived power, chooses freely one of the alternatives and intends
or wills to do the action and, corresponding to this intention, God creates and com-
pletes the action.”25
It is this intention on the part of man which makes him responsible for his deeds.
Man cannot take the initiative in any matter, nor can he originate any action. But the
completion of the act is partially due to his intention: He, thus, acquires the merit or
demerit of the action because of his intending to do a good or bad action. Man's free
choice is, so to say, an occasion for God's causing the action corresponding to that
choice.
In this the Ash`arites come very close to the occasionalism of Malebranche which
was expounded in Europe eight centuries and a half later. This correspondence and
harmony between the choice of man and God's creation, according to the Ash'arites,
is not due to a harmony established by God previously, but because of His habit or
nature to create the harmony whenever human action is done.
This, in short, is the solution of the problem of free-will offered by the Ash'arites. The
Ashh'arite view on this problem is not free from logical and ethical difficulties. It was
really very difficult for them to reconcile the absolute determination of all events by
God with man's accountability and responsibility for his deeds. Some, of the later
Ash'arites, particularly Imam Fakhr al-Din al-Razi, discarded the veil of acquisition in
order to escape the charge of fatalism, and advocated naked determinism.26
3. The Problem of Reason and Revelation and the Criterion of Good and
Evil
The Ash`arites differ from the Mu'tazilites on the question whether reason or
revelation should be the basis or source of truth and reality: Both the schools admit
the necessity of reason for the rational understanding of faith, but they differ with
regard to the question whether revelation or reason is more fundamental and, in
case of a conflict, whether reason or revelation is to get preference.
The Mu'tazilites held that reason is more fundamental than revelation and is to be
preferred to revelation. Revelation merely confirms what is accepted by reason and,
if there be a conflict between the two, reason is to be preferred and revelation must
be so interpreted as to be in conformity with the dictates of reason.
The Ash`arites, on the other hand, held that revelation is more fundamental as the
source of ultimate truth and reality, and reason should merely confirm what is given
by revelation. The Ash`arites prefer revelation to reason in case of a conflict between
the two. As a matter of fact, this is one of the fundamental principles in which the
rational Kalam of the Mu'tazilites differs from the orthodox Kalam of the Ash'arites.
If pure reason is made the sole basis or source of truth and reality, including the truth
and reality of the most fundamental principles or concepts on which Islam is based,
it would be a pure speculative philosophy or at best a rational theology in general
and not a doctrinal theology of a particular historic religion, i. e., that of Islam in par-
ticular. Islam is based on certain fundamental principles or concepts which, being
suprasensible in nature, are incapable of rational proof. These principles, first, must
be believed in on the basis of revelation.
Revelation, thus, is the real basis of the truth and reality of these basic doctrines of
Islam. This faith, based on revelation, must be rationalized. Islam as a religion, no
doubt, admits the necessity of rationalizing its faith. But to admit the necessity of
rationalizing faith is not to admit pure reason or analytic thought to be the sole
source or basis of Islam as a religion. Reason, no doubt, has the right to judge Islam
and its basic principles, but what is to be judged is of such a nature that it cannot
submit to the judgment of reason except on its own terms.
Reason must, therefore, be subordinated to revelation. Its function is to rationalize
faith in the basic principles of Islam and not to question the validity or truth of the
principles established on the basis of revelation as embodied in the Qur'an and the
Sunnah. The problem of the criterion of good and evil follows as a corollary to the
problem of reason and revelation. The problem of good and evil is one of the most
controversial problems of Islamic theology.
The Mu'tazilites held that reason, and not revelation, is the criterion or standard of
moral judgment, i.e., of the goodness and badness of an action. The truth and moral
value of things and human actions must be determined by reason. They contended
that moral qualities of good and evil are objective; they are inherent in the very
nature of things or actions and as such can be known by reason and decided to be
good or bad.
The Ash'arites, as against the Mu'tazilites, held that revelation and not reason is the
real authority or criterion to determine what is good and what is bad. Goodness and
badness of actions (husn wa qubh) are not qualities inhering in them; these are mere
accidents (a'rad). Actions-in-themselves are neither good nor bad. Divine Law makes
them good or bad.
In order to make the ground of controversy between the Mu'tazilites and the
Ash'arites clearer, we may explain here the three different senses in which these two
terms, good and evil, are used.27
(i) Good and evil are sometimes used in the sense of perfection and defect
respectively. When we say that a certain thing or action is good or bad (for instance,
knowledge is good and ignorance is bad), we mean that it is a quality which makes
its possessor perfect or implies a defect in him.
(ii) These terms are also used in a utilitarian sense meaning gain and loss in worldly
affairs. Whatever is useful or has utility in our experience is good, and the opposite
of it is bad. So whatever is neither useful nor harmful is neither good nor bad.
Both the Ash'arites and the Mu'tazilites agree that in the two senses, mentioned
above, reason is the criterion or standard of good and evil. There is no difference of
opinion in the above two senses. But good and bad in the second sense may vary
from time to time, from individual to individual, and from place to place.
In this sense there will be nothing permanently or universally good or bad; what is
good to one may be bad to others and vice versa. This implies that good and evil are
subjective and not objective and real. Hence actions are neither good nor bad, but
experience or workability would make them so and, therefore, they can be known by
reason without the help of revelation.
(iii) Good and evil are also used in a third sense of commendable and praiseworthy
or condemnable in this world and rewardable or punishable, as the case may be, in
the other world.
The Ash'arites maintained that good and evil in their third sense must be known
through revelation, not by reason as the Mu'tazilites had held. According to the
Ash'arites, revelation alone decides whether an action is good or bad. What is
commanded by Shar' is good, and what is prohibited is bad. Shar` can convert
previously declared good into bad and vice versa.
As actions by themselves are neither good nor bad, there is nothing in them which
would make them rewardable (good) or punishable (bad). They are made rewardable
or punishable by revelation or Shar'. As there is no quality of good or evil seated in
the very nature of an act, there can be no question of knowing it by reason.
Ash’arite Metaphysics
Al-Ash'ari's interest was purely theological and his discussions did not contain much
metaphysics.41 But the subsequent Ash'arites found it impossible to achieve their
main object of defending the faith and harmonizing reason with revelation without
making reference to the ultimate nature of reality.
Al-Ash'ari's theological system was, thus, considered to be incomplete without a
support from metaphysics. The system was fully developed by the later Ash'arites,
particularly by Qadi Abu Bakr Muhammad bin Tayyyib al-Baqillani who was one of
the greatest among them. He was a Basrite, but he made Baghdad his permanent
residence and died there in 403/1013. He was a great original thinker and wrote
many valuable books on theology and various other subjects.
He made use of some purely metaphysical propositions in his theological
investigations, such as substance is an individual unity, accident has only a
momentary existence and cannot exist in quality, and perfect vacuum is possible,
and thus gave the school a metaphysical foundation.
About him a Western scholar has remarked: “It is his glory to have contributed most
important elements to, and put into fixed form what is, perhaps, the most daring
metaphysical scheme, and almost certainly the most thorough theological scheme,
ever thought out. On the one hand, the Lucretian atoms raining down through the
empty void, the self-developing monads and pre-established harmony of Leibniz;
and all the Kantian “things-in-themselves” are lame and impotent in their consistency
beside the parallel Ash'arite doctrines; and, on the other, not even the rigours of
Calvin; as developed in Dutch confessions, can compete with the unflinching
exactitude of the Muslim conclusions”.42
The Ash'arites, being primarily interested in theological problems, kept their
philosophical discussions mainly confined only to those questions which they
thought had a direct or indirect bearing on these problems.43 Willingly or unwillingly,
they had to philosophize “in order to meet the contemporary philosophers on their
own ground.” But when they began philosophizing, they were very earnest and
became great metaphysicians.
In dealing with the most important basic principles of Islam: (i) the existence of God,
as the creator of the universe, and His unity and oneness, and (ii) the belief in the
prophethood of Muhammad, they had to use certain proofs which necessitated
some metaphysical and epistemological discussions. Hence they had to develop a
theory of knowledge and a theory of reality, which were peculiarly their own. God,
the ultimate principle, is, according to the Ash'arites, a necessary existent; His
existence is identical with His essence.
In proving God's existence the Ash'arites used three arguments. Their argument
from the contingent nature of motion is not of much importance to our discussion.
The other two are:
(i) All bodies, they argued, are ultimately one in so far as their essence is concerned.
But, in spite of this basic unity, their characteristics are different. Hence there must
be an ultimate cause for these divergent characteristic, and that ultimate cause is
God.
(ii) The world is contingent. Every contingent thing must have a cause; therefore, the
world must have a cause, and as no contingent thing can be the cause, that cause
must be God. The major premise (i.e., every event must have a cause) does not
require a proof. The minor premise - the world is contingent - they proved in the
following manner: Everything that exists in the world is either a substance or a
quality. The contingent character of a quality is evident, and the contingence of
substance follows from the fact that no substance could exist apart from qualities.
The contingence of quality necessitates the contingence of substance; otherwise, the
eternity of substance would necessitate the eternity of quality.44
The Ash'arites believed in miracles which were considered to be the basis of the
proof of prophethood and, in order to defend this view, they had to deny the laws of
nature. They also denied causality in nature and made God the only cause of
everything.
Now, in order to explain the full implication of the above arguments, it was necessary
for them to develop a theory of knowledge and a metaphysics.
The world consists of things. Now, the question arises: What is meant by a thing, what
is its nature, and how far do we know it?
Al-Baqillani defined knowledge as the cognition of a thing as it is in itself.45 A thing is
defined by the Ash'arites as “that which is existent.” Everything is an existent and
every existent is a thing.46 So, according to the Ash'arites, existence, whether
necessary or contingent, is the thing or the essence of the thing-in-itself and not a
quality in addition to it, as the Mu'tazilites held.
Al-Jahiz, al-Jubba'i, and some other Mu'tazilites of the Basrite school defined a “thing”
as that which is known,47 and held that existence is a quality of it, added to its
essence. The Ash'arites, as against these Mu'tazilites, contended that if existence is
an additional quality, the essence-in-itself would be a nonexistent and hence a
non-entity and the subsequent-addition of the quality of “existence” to it would
involve a clear contradiction in so far as it would make the non-existent existent.48
This is an absurdity. The thing-in-itself which is the object of knowledge according to
the Ash'arites, is, therefore, an existent thing or a body. Everything that exists in the
world has a contingent existence and is either substance or quality. In this sense God
is not a thing.
The Aristotelian categories of thought were subjected by the Ash'arites to a searching
criticism. Only two of those categories, substance and quality, were retained by them.
The other categories, quality, place, time, etc., are nothing but relative characteristics
(i'tibarat) that exist subjectively in the mind of the knower, having no corresponding
objective reality.
Like Berkeley, the Irish philosopher, they also did not make any distinction between
the primary and secondary qualities of objects. The world, therefore, consists of
substance, on which the mind reflects, and qualities, which are not in the
thing-in-itself but only in the mind of the knower. The qualities are mere accidents
which are fleeting, transitory, and subjective relations, having only a momentary
existence. A quality or accident cannot exist in another accident but only in a
substance. No substance could ever exist apart from a quality. The substance, being
inseparable from its accidents, must also be transitory, having only a moment's
duration, just as the accidents are. Everything that exists, therefore, consists of mere
transitory units (subjective), having only a moment's duration.
The Ash'arites, thus, rejected the Aristotelian view of matter as “a permanent
potentiality (hayula) of suffering the impress of form (surah),” because a possibility is
neither an entity nor a non-entity but purely a subjectivity. With inert matter, the
active form and all causes must also go. They, too, are mere subjectivities. This led
them straight to the atomists and, as a matter of fact, they did become atomists after
their own fashion.
In this connection we may observe that the object of the Ash'arites was, like that of
Kant, to fix the relation of knowledge to the thing-in-itself; and they showed here a
great originality in their thought. On this question they not only anticipated Kant but,
in reaching the thing-in-itself, they were much more thorough than Kant. “In his
examination of human knowledge regarded as a product and not merely a process,
Kant stopped at the idea of ‘Ding an sich’ [thing-in-itself], but the Ash'arite
endeavoured to penetrate further, and maintained, against the contemporary
Agnostic-Realism, that the so-called underlying essence existed only so far as it was
brought in relation to the knowing subject.”49
Ash'arite Atomism
The substances perceived by us are atoms which come into existence from vacuity
and drop out of existence again. The world is made up of such atoms. The Ash'arite
atoms are fundamentally different from those of Democritus and Lucretius. The
Ash`arite atoms are not material; they are not permanent; they have only a
momentary existence; they are not eternal but every moment brought into being,
and then allowed to go out of existence by the Supreme Being, God, the only cause
of everything in the universe. These atoms are not only of space but of time also.
They are non-material or ideal in character. They resemble the monads of Leibniz.
But the Ash'arite monads differ from those of Leibniz in having no possibility of
self-development along certain lines. Each monad has certain qualities but has
extension neither in space nor in time. They have simply position, not bulk, and are
isolated from and independent of one another. There is absolute void between any
two monads. Space and time are subjective. All changes in the world are produced
by their entering into existence and dropping out again, but not by any change in
themselves.
The Ash'arite ontology necessitated the existence of God. Their monads must have a
cause, without which they could not have come into being, nor could there be any
harmony or connection between them. This cause must be a cause sui; otherwise
there would be an infinite regress of the causal nexus. The Ash'arites found this
cause in the free-will of God. It creates and annihilates the atoms and their qualities
and, thus, brings to pass all motion and change in the world.
The Ash'arites were, thus, thoroughgoing metaphysicians. Being was all important in
their ontology. The will of that Being or God must, therefore, be the ground of all
things. Hence they did not find any difficulty, as Leibniz did, in explaining the
harmony and coherence among the isolated, windowless, and independent monads,
constituting the one orderly world.
Leibniz had to bring in, in his monadology, a Monad of monads or God, and fall back
upon the Theory of Pre-established Harmony to bring his monads into harmonious
and orderly relations with one another, and this he could do only at the cost of his
monadology, and by abandoning his pluralistic and individualistic metaphysics.
But the Ash'arites, consistently with their ontology, fell straight back upon God, and
found in His will the ground of orderliness and harmony in the universe. They were,
thus, more thorough and consistent than Leibniz in their theory of monads. The
Ash'arite atomism approaches that of Lotze's, who in spite of his desire to save
external reality, ended in its Complete reduction to ideality. But, like Lotze, they could
not believe their atoms to be the inner working of the infinite Primal Being.
The necessary consequence of their analysis is a thorough going idealism like that of
Berkeley. Their theory of knowledge reduced the universe to a mere show of ordered
subjectivities which, as they maintained like Berkeley, found their ultimate
explanation in the will of God. Their interest, as we have already pointed out, was
mainly theological. Interest in pure monotheism was very strong with them. Their
metaphysical and epistemological discussions were actuated by a pious desire to
defend the idea of divine creations, to drive men back to God and His revelation and
compel them to see in Him the one grand fact of the universe.
The Ash'arites are here more consistent than Berkeley. God, according to them, is
the only cause in the true sense of the term. No created thing, having created power,
could be the cause of anything.
The attitude of the Ash'arites towards the law of causation was sceptical. They denied
objective validity of causality in nature. No created thing or being can be the cause
of anything. Things or beings in nature do not possess any power or quality which
could produce any effect. The so-called power which men and objects of nature seem
to possess is not an effective power, for it is a derived power, not an original power
which alone can produce effect.50 Whatever power the creatures might possess
must have been given by God, who alone possesses all real power. Being (God) is the
only Ultimate Reality.
The things of the world are composed of indivisible units monads which, every
moment, are created and annihilated; and it is God who creates and annihilates them
and their qualities, thereby bringing about all the motion and change in the world.
There is, thus, no such thing as a law of nature and the world is sustained by a
constant, ever repeated activity of God.
There is no such thing as a secondary cause; when there is the appearance of such a
cause, it is only illusionary. God produces the appearance of the effect as well as the
effect. Things of the world do not possess any permanent nature. Fire, for instance,
does not possess the nature or quality of burning; it does not burn. God creates in a
substance “a being burned” when fire touches it.
The Ash'arites thus denied power in the cause as well as the necessary connection
between the so-called cause and effect. Shibli mentions that the Ash'arites rejected
the idea of causation with a view to defending the possibility of miracles on the
manifestation of which, according to them, prophethood depended. The orthodox
school believed in miracles as well as in the universal law of causation; but they also
maintained that, at the time of manifesting a miracle, God suspends the operation
of this law and thus brings about an exception.
Asha`ari, however, maintained that a cause must have always the same effect (i.e.,
the effect of one and the cause cause could not be different at different times).
Having accepted this principle as formulated by their leader, the Ash'arites could not
agree to the orthodox view and, therefore, to prove the possibility of miracles they
rejected the law of causation altogether, According to them, there is no power in the
antecedent to produce the consequent. “We know nothing but floating impressions,
the phenomenal order of which is determined by God.”51
Objection might be raised against the Ash'arite metaphysics that it establishes in
effect a relationship between God and the atoms, but relationships, according to the
Ash'arites, are subjective illusions. In reply to this objection it may be pointed out that
all relationship applies only to contingent beings or things perceived by the senses.
It would not hold in the case of the Necessary Being, God, who is suprasensible. And
according to their principle of mukhalafah, nothing which is applied to created things
or beings can be applied to God in the same sense. God is not a natural cause but a
free cause.
This is the Ash'arite system as completed by Qadi Abu Bakr al-Baqillani. It faced a
strong opposition from the orthodox, particularly from the followers of Abmad bin
Hanbal. Al-Ashari's opinions did not get much recognition outside the Shafi'ite group
to which he belonged. The Hanafites preferred the doctrines of his contemporary
al-Maturidi who differed from al-Ash'ari in certain minor controversial points. Shibli
has mentioned nine such points.52
In Spain, Ibn Hazm (d. 456/1063) opposed the Ash'arite doctrines. The Saljuq Sultan
Tughril Beg, who was an adherent of the Hanbalite school, treated the Ash'arites very
badly, but his successor Sultan Alp Arsalan and especially his famous vizier, Nizam
al-Mulk supported the Ash`arites and put an end to the persecution to which they
had been exposed. Nizam al-Mulk founded the Nizamite Academy at Baghdad in
459/1066 for the defence of Ash'arite doctrines. It is under his patronage that Abu
al-Ma'ali `Abd al-Malik al-Juwaini got the chance of preaching the Ash'arite doctrine
freely.53
The Ash'arite system could not obtain widespread acceptance until it was
popularized by a1-Juwaini and al-Ghazali in the East and by Ibn Tumart in the West.
It was al-Juwaini who could legitimately claim the credit of making the Ash'arites'
doctrines popular. His vast learning and erudite scholarship brought him the title of
Dia' al-Din (the light of religion).
Al-Juwaini received his early education from his father, Shaikh Abu Muhammad `Abd
Allah, and after the death of his father, he got further education from his teacher,
abu Ishaq al-Isfara'ini, a great Ash'arite scholar. Al-Juwaini, in course of time, was
recognized by the scholars of the time to be Shaikh al-Islam (the chief leader of Islam)
and Imam al Haramain (the religious leader of Makkah and Madinah). For thirty
years, he continued teaching and preaching the Ash'arite doctrines.
Al-Juwaini was the teacher of al-Ghazali. He wrote many books on various subjects.
Some of these are: al-Shamil, on the principles of religion; al-Burhan, on the principles
of jurisprudence; al-`Aqidat al-Nizamiyyah; and Irshad, on theology. He was born in
419/1028 and died at Nishapur in 478/1085.53 Being the Shaikh al-Islam and the
Imam of Makkah and Madinah, al-Juwaini's Fatawa (judgments on religious matters)
used to be respected by people in general throughout the Muslim world; and for this
reason, his writings got the widest circulation and, through these writings, Ash'arite
doctrines became known everywhere.
One great theological result of the Ash'arite system was that it checked the growth
of free thought which tended to dissolve the solidarity of the Islamic Shari'ah. The
Ash`arite mode of thought had its intellectual results also.
It led to an independent criticism of Greek philosophy and prepared the ground for
philosophies propounded by men like al-Ghazali and Fakhr al-Din al-Razi. Al-Ghazali
is generally included among the Ash'arites and it is he who maybe said to have
completed the Ash'arite metaphysics. It was he who, by giving a systematic refutation
of Greek philosophy in his famous work, Tahafut al-Falasifah, completely annihilated
the dread of intellectualism which had characterized the minds of the orthodox. It
was chiefly through his influence that people began to study dogma and metaphysics
together.54
Strictly speaking, al-Ghazali was not an Ash'arite, though he admitted that the
Ash'arite mode of thought was excellent for the masses. “He held that the secret of
faith could not be revealed to the masses; for this reason he encouraged exposition
of the Ash`arite theology, and took care in persuading his disciples not to publish
the results of his private reflection.”55
Al-Ghazali made the Ash'arite theology so popular that it became practically the
theology of the Muslim community in general and has continued to remain so up to
the present time.
Bibliography
Abu al-Hasan bin Isma'il al-Ashari, Kitab al-Ibanah `an Usul al-Diyanah, Hyderabad,
Deccan, 1321/1903; Risalah fi Istihsan al-Khaud, Hyderabad, Deccan, 1323/1905,
1344/1926; Maqalat a1-Islamiyyin wa Ikhtilaf al-Musalliyyin, 2 Vols., Istanbul, 1929;
`Abd al-Karim al-Shahrastani, Kitab al-Milal wal-Nihal, ed. Cureton; Shibli, `Ilm
al-Kalam, 4th edition, Ma'arif Press, Azamgarh, 1341/1923; Qadi `Add and Sayyid
Sharif, Sharh al Mawaqif; abu al-`Ala, Sharh-i Mawaqif, Newal Kishore, Lucknow;
al- Ghazali, Ihya' ` Ulum al-Din, Newal Kishore, Lucknow;
Ibn Khallikan, Wafayat al-A'yan, 2 Vols; Shaikh Muhammad Iqbal, The Development of
Metaphysics in Persia, Bazm-i Iqbal, Lahore; al-Mas'udi, Muruj ad-Dhahab;
Dhahabi, Mizan al-I`tidal; Baihaqi, Kitab al-Asma' w-al-Sifat; D. B.
Macdonald, Development of Muslim Theology, Jurisprudence and Constitutional Theory,
Charles Scribner's Sons, New York, 1926; Ahmad Amin, Duha al-Islam, 4th edition,
Cairo, 1946; Taftazani, Sharh `Aqa'id-i Nasafi; Khayali, Sharh-i `Aqa'id-i Nasafi.