Ethics of Science and Technology Assessment
Ethics of Science and Technology Assessment
Ethics of Science and Technology Assessment
Volume 31
Book Series of the Europäische Akademie zur Erforschung
von Folgen wissenschaftlich-technischer Entwicklungen
Bad Neuenahr-Ahrweiler GmbH
edited by Carl Friedrich Gethmann
G. Hanekamp (Ed.)
Business Ethics
of Innovation
123
Series Editor
Professor Dr. Dr. h.c. Carl Friedrich Gethmann
Europäische Akademie GmbH
Wilhelmstr. 56, 53474 Bad Neuenahr-Ahrweiler, Germany
Editor
Dr. Gerd Hanekamp
Wissenschaftsrat
Brohler Str. 11, 50968 Köln, Germany
Desk Editor
Friederike Wütscher
Europäische Akademie GmbH
Wilhelmstr. 56, 53474 Bad Neuenahr-Ahrweiler, Germany
ISSN 1860-4803
ISBN 978-3-540-72309-7 Springer Berlin Heidelberg New York
This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved, whether the whole or part of the material
is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broad-
casting, reproduction on microfilm or in any other way, and storage in data banks. Duplication of
this publication or parts thereof is permitted only under the provisions of the German Copyright Law
of September 9, 1965, in its current version, and permission for use must always be obtained from
Springer. Violations are liable for prosecution under the German Copyright Law.
Springer is a part of Springer Science+Business Media
springer.com
© Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2007
The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, etc. in this publication does not
imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant
protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use.
Typesetting: Köllen-Druck+Verlag GmbH, Bonn + Berlin
Production: LE-TEX Jelonek, Schmidt & Vöckler GbR, Leipzig
Cover: eStudioCalamar S.L., F.Steinen-Broo, Girona, Spanien
Printed on acid-free paper 60/3180/YL - 5 4 3 2 1 0
The Europäische Akademie
The Europäische Akademie zur Erforschung von Folgen wissenschaftlich-technischer
Entwicklungen GmbH is concerned with the scientific study of consequences of
scientific and technological advance for the individual and social life and for the
natural environment. The Europäische Akademie intends to contribute to a ratio-
nal way of society of dealing with the consequences of scientific and technological
developments. This aim is mainly realised in the development of recommendations
for options to act, from the point of view of long-term societal acceptance. The
work of the Europäische Akademie mostly takes place in temporary interdisci-
plinary project groups, whose members are recognised scientists from European
universities. Overarching issues, e.g. from the fields of Technology Assessment or
Ethic of Science, are dealt with by the staff of the Europäische Akademie.
The Series
The series Ethics of Science and Technology Assessment (Wissenschaftsethik und
Technikfolgenbeurteilung) serves to publish the results of the work of the Eu-
ropäische Akademie. It is published by the academy’s director. Besides the final
results of the project groups the series includes volumes on general questions of
ethics of science and technology assessment as well as other monographic studies.
Preface
Crane, Andrew, Professor of Policy and holds the George R. Gardiner Chair
in Business Ethics at the Schulich School of Business, York University,
Toronto. He is interested in various aspects of business ethics, including the
role of morality in marketing and consumption; the contribution of evolu-
tionary narratives to environmental management; the implementation of
fair trade policies; and the contribution of Foucauldian thought to business
ethics. Recent work appeared in “Academy of Management Review”, “Journal
of Business Research”, “Organization Studies”, “Journal of Business Ethics”
and “Business Ethics Quarterly”. He holds a BSc from Warwick University
and a PhD in Business Studies from Nottingham University. Previously, he
was a Professor of Business Ethics and Director of the MBA in CSR at Not-
tingham University Business School, UK.
E-mail: acrane@schulich.yorku.ca
Steinmann, Horst, Professor em. Dr. Dres. h.c., studied Business Administra-
tion at the Universität Göttingen 1954–1959 (Dipl.-Kfm.) and at the Institut
Européen d’Administration des Affaires (INSEAD), Fontainebleau, 1964/65
(MBA). 1962 Dr. rer. nat. and 1967 Habilitation (TU Clausthal). 1968–1970
Full Professor of Operations Research at the FU Berlin; 1970–1999 Full Pro-
fessor of Business Administration and General Management at the Univer-
sität Erlangen-Nürnberg. Doctor honoris causa Universität Bern (1996) and
University Robert Schuman Strassbourg (1999). Founder of the German
Business Ethics Network (1993). Main interests: General Management, Busi-
ness Ethics, Corporate Governance, Philosophy of Science.
E-mail: horst.steinmann@wiso.uni- erlangen.de
Table of Contents
Preface
Foreword
List of Authors
Objectives
Business ethics of innovation explores the philosophical aspects and impli-
cations of innovations from the perspective of the firm (Hanekamp 2005).
This endeavor most likely will have consequences for this perspective. It will
2 Gerd Hanekamp
invention
availability market
Innovation
inclusion/exclusion knowledge/capability
state
community society
invention
availability market
Innovation
inclusion/exclusion knowledge/capability
business economy
In the case of HIV/AIDS medication e.g. there are the states where the
pharmaceutical firms producing the medication are operating, the developing
world states that are most intensely affected, there are different communities
in these states possibly having a particular view on the disease, there are the
firms themselves, and there are the respective societies and economies as more
abstract entities that are affected and have an influence on the situation. All
these can view innovations in terms of the aspects listed above. For a business
actor it can be essential to consider them comprehensively in order to ade-
quately address the corresponding interests or problems in their decisions.
For a particular problem the two dimensions can be systematically pre-
sented in a simple two-dimensional matrix (see below). The cells of the
1 Introduction
The fundamental defect of global society today is not that the reach of corpora-
tions is too big, but that our ability to govern is too small. We face governance gaps
and governance failures on a monumental scale. Our core challenge, therefore, is to
stimulate social and political processes that will help bridge the gaps and reduce the
failures. The dynamic interplay between business, civil society, and the public sec-
tor constitutes an essential platform from which to mount the campaign.
It was John Ruggie from Harvard Law School, appointed by Kofi Annan as
“Special Representative on the issue of human rights and transnational cor-
porations”, who made this statement on the occasion of the Carl Bertels-
mann Prize International Symposium in 2002 (Ruggie 2002:2). As a profes-
sor of “International Affairs” Ruggie supported the UN-Secretary in devel-
oping and introducing the “Global Compact”. The Global Compact is an
attempt to involve corporations and other institutions in a world-wide pro-
gram to respect and support – within their sphere of influence – 10 funda-
mental principles, concerning human rights, social standards (labor and
working conditions), the environment and freedom from corruption.
It is this political context of global governance and the involvement of
multinational corporations in processes of creating new political and social
institutions which form the actual background of this paper. What I would
like to elaborate on a bit is the role which corporate ethics could and indeed
should play in this context (see also Steinmann 2003). This is a highly con-
troversial topic in the discipline of management theory because what is at
stake here is nothing less than the rationale, the “raison d’être”, of the private
corporation in capitalist market economies of the future. But the topic is
also highly controversial in and between other academic disciplines, like eco-
nomics, politics, and here especially the “Theory of International Relations”,
moreover: sociology, philosophy, political philosophy, international law, and
so forth.
In view of this state of affairs and in line with central philosophical ideas
of the German philosophical school of “Methodolocigal Constructivism”
(Lorenzen 1987, Janich 2001) I regard it to be an important task of manage-
ment theory (as the first and immediate addressee of business practice) to
8 Horst Steinmann
take on, where necessary, an interactive role as a kind of mediator and trans-
lator between problems of business practice and other academic disciplines
able to contribute to the solution of the problem at hand (Steinmann and
Scherer 2002); and this with the objective to come, first of all, to a common
understanding of the empirical situation within which to act and, secondly,
working on adequate normative orientations for change. In order to fulfill
this role management theory has to grasp and to conceptualize, on the level
of language, the respective problems of business practice; and this in such a
way that the basic notions required for tackling these problems can be
picked up by other disciplines for further (interdisciplinary) research.
It is from this methodological perspective that we have proposed, within
the national context, a notion of corporate ethics (Steinmann and Löhr
1994). I shall present this notion very briefly (2). Its core idea is that man-
agers of private corporations should be held responsible and accountable not
only for making sufficient profits but for contributing, at the same time,
directly to the public interest by peacefully solving those conflicts with its
stakeholders which arise out of corporate strategy. The notion of “strategy-
centered peaceful conflict resolution” is at the heart of my concept of corpo-
rate ethics, and this not merely as a laudable activity (as is the case e.g. with
philanthropic corporate givings), but as a moral duty which is not at the dis-
creation of management.
I want to show that this concept is so general that it can be applied to the
global political context mentioned by Ruggie (3). To do this I shall sketch
what Kofie Annan in his millenium address (Annan 2000) has called “Global
Public Policy Networks” as a representative example of what is actually going
on in practice. I maintain that what these networks offer could be under-
stood as a manifestation of corporate ethics.
What follows, then, are some remarks on a number of urgent questions
for future research of different disciplines needed to develop a theory of the
firm which can cope with the problems of corporate governance in a global-
ized world (4). What I am not going to do is to outline such a theory; its time
is still to come. I shall, instead, mention at the end some basic ideas which
may have the potential to improve the actual situtation (5).
1
It is in this sense that the Senate und the House of Representatives of Minnesota/
USA dealt with a proposal to intgrate the public interest into company law by
„imposing liability on a corporation and its board for damages caused to the pub-
lic interest.“ See www.revisor.leg.state.min.us/bin/bldbill.php?bill=S1529.0 &s...
Corporate Ethics and Globalization – Global Rules and Private Actors 11
3
The development of the Sentencing Guidelines up to the present is documented
in www.ussc.gov.
16 Horst Steinmann
World Trade Organization, World Monetary Fund) have gained the special
attention of the UN as important institutional arrangements for global gov-
ernance. Kofi Annan referred to challenges of global political governance in
his 1999-speech at the World Economic Forum in Davos and in his mille-
nium address of 2000. In both documents he raises the more and more
pressing question where in the world new loci of responsibility do emerge and
what institutions could form part of a new global political order, institutions
which are able and legitimized to solve the upcoming problems and conflicts
in a globalized economy. Here is his answer (Reinicke and Deng 2000:XVIII):
The United Nations once dealt with governments. By now we know that peace and
prosperity cannot be achieved without partnerships involving governments, inter-
national organizations, the business community, and civil society.
What Annan has in mind, inter alia, are networks of public-private part-
nerships which are able to better cope with the complexity of governance
problems on a global scale, better than formal institutions. Let me quote
again (Reinicke and Deng 2000:XVIII):
Formal institutional arrangements may often lack the scope, speed and informa-
tional capacity to keep up with the rapidly changing global agenda. Mobilizing the
skills and other resources of diverse global actors, therefore, may increasingly involve
forming loose and temporary global public policy networks that cut across national,
institutional and disciplinary lines. The United Nations is well situated to nurture
such informal “coalitions for change” across our various areas of responsibility.
ity of resources needed to tackle the specific issue at hand. There are six func-
tions networks can perform, which Reinicke and Deng discuss in some
detail. Let me shortly mention three of them (Reinicke and Deng 2000:27):
1. Networks contribute to establish a global policy agenda and offer mecha-
nisms for developing a truly global public discourse in which to debate the
agenda. Transparency International (TI) is an example. The problem was
and still is here to crack the taboo around corruption, without alienating
the very people on whom it would rely to make inroads into the problem.
An important part of the strategy is to build “islands of integrity” with
corporations, public authorities of the country and TI as partners in coop-
erative anticorruption efforts. All relevant companies commit themselves
in their code of conduct to refrain from bribery and to develop appropri-
ate organizational structures for the implementation of the code. I think
this is a fairly good manifestation of corporate ethics. The “islands of
integrity” are provisions to overcome the well-known prisoners‘ dilemma.
2. Networks facilitate processes for negotiating and setting global standards.
Setting transnational rules and standards is becoming ever more important
as political and economic liberalization and technological change create
transnational social and economic spheres of activity whose governance
demands a global framework. More and more national and international
bureaucracies realize that negotiating and setting standards to address
transnational problems differ from agenda-setting in their need to involve
all the stakeholders, both because these stakeholders provide timely and
complex knowledge and because their involvement provides, according to
Reinicke and Deng, legitimacy to the process through inclusion of those
concerned. A good example is the “World Commission on Dams”
(www.dams.org) which deserves to be outlined in some detail. It was the
growing complexity and politicization of large-dam construction and its
social, economic, and environmental implications which made this,
according to Reinicke/Deng, one of the most conflict-ridden issues in the
development debate. In the late 1980s and early 1990s, a breakdown of dia-
logue among NGOs, dam builders, and international organizations such as
the World Bank, which had financed many large dam projects worldwide,
led to a stalemate. This stalemate imposed considerable costs on all stake-
holders: builders saw their income from dam construction decline; NGOs
had to spend considerable resources to sustain public campaigns against
large dams; and the World Bank, facing fierce public pressure, could no
longer support any loans in this area. Bringing representatives from all rel-
evant groups and sectors together in an independent trisectoral network was
imperative to break the stalemate and to start to build a consensus on stan-
dards for large-dam construction. The World Commission on Dams did
just this. The report published in 2000 gives evidence on the impressive
results as a fair normative basis for future economic activities in this field. It
18 Horst Steinmann
factually but also formally legitimate? This is what Scherer and Palazzo
(2005) seem to propose in a recent paper. But in the absence of global sover-
eign and proper institutions for democratic political action on a worldwide
scale there is no source from which private rules can derive a binding legiti-
matory character. What seems to be necessary, then, is a broader notion of
legitimacy which is no longer bound to the nation state. Its centerpiece
would be the public use of reason, and this not only as a basis of the political
system but also of the economic system.
(3) Closely related to this second point is a third one, resulting from the inter-
active and discursive character of corporate ethics. If NGOs become more
and more partners of discourses with corporations, both as providers of tech-
nical knowledge and by participating in political processes intended for estab-
lishing a legitimate basis for corporate action, then NGOs must understand
and practice the new role required by corporate ethics (Löhr 2004).
NGOs get in a role-conflict. Thus far they act as a kind of countervailing
power campaigning from the outside in the public arena in order to force
management to change its strategy in such a way that it becomes more in
line with the (perceived) interests of stakeholder groups, interests which, by
the way, are often more or less regarded as legitimate per se. Now NGOs get
involved in a strategic corporate-ethics process, based on argumentation,
from which to derive good reasons for and to commit to action programmes
which regard human rights, social standards, environmental norms and so
forth as an integral part of corporate strategy. Our experience with the
PUMA company shows that it is obviously quite difficult for representatives
of different stakeholder groups to handle this role-conflict adequately, i.e.
not to fall back during discourses on a strategy of campaigning instead of
scrutinizing arguments.
Needless to say that there are other questions arising out of this factual
discursive practice with NGOs which relate directly to the fundamental
legitimacy problem mentioned above (Bendell 2005). Who selects the resp-
resentatives of NGOs? What groups are authorized to take part in corporate
strategy discourses? Who cares for the public interest? To whom are repre-
sentatives of stakeholders accountable? What about the responsibility of
management towards shareholders as laid down in many modern company
laws, especially in anglo-american company law? How must rules look like to
coherently integrate corporate ethics processes in legitimate corporate deci-
sion processes? Where do such rules come from to be legitimate? Is it enough
that they just emerge out of factual social processes? These are all disturbing
questions pertaining to problem of legitimacy and yet to be answered.
(4) Finally I would like to mention that corporate ethics is a challenge also
for the “Theory of International Relations” (Reinicke 1998, Hellmann et al.
2003, Wolf 2005). Let me remind you that traditional theory does hold here
that international relations are relations between nation states which have
22 Horst Steinmann
established already clear-cut national interests and which contract with one
another to create an international order to overcome anarchy.
This theory presupposes that nation states are sovereign in a double sense.
External sovereignty presupposes that nation states are independent of other
states in formulating and implementing national interests concerning cus-
toms, tariffs and so forth. Internal sovereignty presupposes that the acts of
giving and implementing national law should be independent of particularis-
tic goals of societal actors and interest groups in order to find what is in the
public interest in a given situation. As we know from everyday experience
globalization is a threat to both the external and the internal sovereignty.
When corporations, financial and non-financial, split up their value chain
and distribute it to different nation states they get more and more independ-
ent from the political power and the law of their specific home country; they
get even the power to influcence national law, both at home and in host coun-
tries. Moreover, when corporations get involved in global public policy net-
works and when they help, in line with corporate ethics, to develop and
implement global rules for economic action they may also undermine the
sovereignty of nation states. So, it comes as no surprise that theorists of inter-
national relations are trying now to describe and to better understand these
phenomena emerging in the process of economic globalization.
5 Final Remarks
(1) Thus, there are many academic fields for which the globalization process
is a challenge, in general and with regard to the public role which private
actors begin to take on here. What seems to be necessary is more interdisci-
plinary research aiming at an empirical theory which allows to better under-
stand the actual economic and ethical role of the corporation as a global
player; and to allow for necessary reforms to make peace within and between
societies more stable.
(2) It was Neil Fligstein from Berkeley who outlined such an empirical theory
in his recent book “The Architecture of Markets, An Economic Sociology of
Twenty-First-Century Capitalist Societies.” Let me quote at the end of my
paper a central passage from this book which highlights the role of the pri-
vate corporation as an active player in the market, as opposed to the ortho-
dox consensus in general economic equilibrium theory which conceptualises
the corporation as a passive actor reacting merely to market forces (23):
A sociological approach to market institutions makes us understand that there is
not a single set of social and political institutions that produces the most efficient
allocation of resources. The real issue for making markets is to create political and
social conditions that produce enough stability so as to allow investments. Once
these institutions are created, there are a great many ways to organize firms and
markets that are compatible with making profits. Since the whole society is
enmeshed in market making, it is logical to argue that many possible interventions
Corporate Ethics and Globalization – Global Rules and Private Actors 23
to produce a just and equitable society are in fact compatible with profit making.
Indeed, one outcome of these interventions is to strengthen the legitimacy of mar-
ket institutions.
References
Annan K (2000) We, the Peoples: The Role of the United Nations in the 21st Century.
New York
Apel K-O (1973) Transformation der Philosophie, Band II – Das Apriori der Kom-
munikationsgemeinschaft. Frankfurt/M.
Bendell J (2005) In whose name? The accountability of corporate social responsibil-
ity. In: Development in Practice 15 (3+4):362–374
Benner T, Reinicke WH, Witte JM (2004) Multisectoral networks in global gover-
nance: Towards a pluralistic system of accountability. Global Goverance and Pub-
lic Accountability, Government and Opposition 39 (2):191–210
Benner T, Reinicke WH, Witte JM (2002) Innovating Governance: Global Public Pol-
icy Networks and Social Standards. In: Scherer AG et al. (Hrsg) Globalisierung
und Sozialstandards. München und Mering, 97–115
Braithwaite J, Drahos P (2000) Global Business Regulation. Cambridge
Crook C (2005) The good company. Economist Jan:3–18
Drucker PF (1974) Management. Tasks, Responsibilities, Practices. London
Dubbink W (2004) The Fragile Structure of Free-Market Society. The Radical Impli-
cations of Corporate Social Responsibility. Business Ethics Quarterly 14:23–46
Fligstein N (2001) The Architecture of Markets. An Economic Sociology of Twenty-
First-Century Capitalist Societies. Princeton and Oxford
Gethmann CF (1998) Reason and Cultures. Life-world as the Common Ground of
Ethics. In: Lange H, Löhr A, Steinmann H (eds) Working Across Cultures. Ethical
Perspectives for Intercultural Management. Dordrecht et.al., 213–234
Günther K (2001) Rechtspluralismus und universaler Code der Legalität: Global-
isierung als rechtstheoretisches Problem. In: Wingert L, Günther K (Hrsg) Die
Öffentlichkeit der Vernunft und die Vernunft der Öffentlichkeit. Festschrift für
Jürgen Habermas. Frankfurt/M., 539–567
Haas RD (1998) Ethics – A global business challenge. In: Kumar BN, Steinmann H
(eds) Ethics in International Management. Berlin/New York, 213–220
Habermas J (1996) Between facts and norms: Contributions to a discourse theory of
law and democracy. Cambridge, Mass.
Habermas J (2005) Vorpolitische moralische Grundlagen eines freiheitlichen Staates.
In: Zur Debatte. Themen der Katholischen Akademie Bayern, 35 (2005a) I–III
(Nachdruck zur Debatte 1/2004 über den Gesprächsabend mit Kardinal
Ratzinger am 19. Januar 2004); zugleich: ders.: Vorpolitische Grundlagen des
demokratischen Rechtsstaates? In: ders.: Zwischen Naturalismus und Religion,
Philosophische Aufsätze, Frankfurt/M. 2005, 106–118
Habermas J (2005b) Eine politische Verfassung für die pluralistische Weltge-
sellschaft? In: ders. (Hrsg) Zwischen Naturalismus und Religion. Philosophische
Aufsätze. Frankfurt/M. 2005b, 324–365
Corporate Ethics and Globalization – Global Rules and Private Actors 25
Overview
In this paper I argue that drug resistance is an important ethical issue in
virtue of (1) the severe – and potentially catastrophic – consequences of
drug resistance, (2) the fact that drug resistance largely results from the way
that medicines (and research resources) are distributed, and (3) the fact that
drug resistance is a clear example of a public goods problem. Recognition
that freedom from infectious disease in general and drug resistant disease in
particular are public goods provides additional reasons to those traditionally
appealed to by bioethicists for treating health care as something special when
making policy decisions about its distribution. The fact that freedom from
infectious disease should be recognized as a public good, that is, provides
additional (i.e. utilitarian and self-interested) reasons to standard egalitarian
and human rights reasons for removing antibiotic distribution and develop-
ment from free market mechanisms. While the problem of drug resistance
largely results from lack of access to existing antimicrobial medications and
while a primary solution to the problem of drug resistance would be the
development of new vaccines and medicines, the problem of drug resistance
intersects with debate over intellectual property rights in pharmaceuticals.
What does all this mean for business ethics? I argue that recently proposed
incentive schemes alternative to the standard patent regime reveal that con-
flict between corporate profit promotion, on the one hand, and corporate
respect of standard humanitarian ethical duties, on the other, is not in fact
inevitable. Implementation of “pull programs” such as those recently pro-
posed by Thomas Pogge and Michael Kremer et al. would better allow indus-
try to meet humanitarian obligations and serve the world’s most important
medical needs without (necessarily) sacrificing profits. I conclude that phar-
maceutical corporations have an ethical obligation to provide the political
support necessary to put such programs into place.
1
Much of this material was initially presented at the 7th World Congress of the
International Association of Bioethics (IAB), Sydney, Australia, November 2004,
and published in an article titled ‘Ethics and Drug Resistance’ in Bioethics – the
journal of the International Association of Bioethics, published by Blackwell.
28 Michael Selgelid
Background
Though infectious diseases raise some of the most important ethical issues
in the context of medicine, they have historically been neglected by med-
ical ethics disciplines in comparison with topics such as abortion, euthana-
sia, assisted reproduction, genetics, cloning, stem cell research, and so on.
The topic of infectious disease is one of the most important topics for
bioethics because (1) the historical and likely future consequences of infec-
tious diseases are almost unrivalled, (2) infectious diseases raise difficult
ethical/philosophical questions of their own, and (3) the topic of infec-
tious disease is intertwined with the topic of justice. I have elsewhere
argued this case and attempted to explain why bioethics has not paid more
attention to the topic of infectious disease in general (Selgelid 2005). In
this paper I examine drug resistance as a specific example of a neglected
ethical issue arising in the context of infectious disease and explain why the
problem of drug resistance intersects with and lends importance to exist-
ing debates over intellectual property rights (in pharmaceuticals) and
business ethics.
The development of antibiotics was one of the great successes of modern
medicine. Penicillin was discovered by Alexander Fleming in 1928. When a
method for its mass production was later developed by Howard Florey, in
1944, it was immediately hailed as a “miracle cure” and “wonder drug”. Addi-
tional antibiotic and vaccine developments, in conjunction with improved
sanitation and hygiene, revolutionised medicine, providing unprecedented
success in the fight against infectious disease. These developments were so
promising that it became common to believe that infectious disease would
soon be defeated through medical progress. In 1967, for example, U.S. Sur-
geon General William Stewart famously declared that it was time to “close
the book on infectious diseases” and shift medical attention and research
resources to chronic diseases (Garrett 1994:33). Western medicine since
shifted focus to things like heart disease and cancer. The medical industry is
also increasingly busy with “blockbuster” treatments for allergies and
depression – and lifestyle drugs for things like baldness and impotence. In
the meanwhile, almost no new classes of antibiotics have been developed
since the 1960s. This is largely because there is little market incentive for
industry to develop antimicrobial medications.
Consequences
With the emergence and spread of drug resistant pathogens, however, exist-
ing antibiotics are losing their power to fight off infections. Though not a
new phenomenon, the problem of drug resistance is increasingly being rec-
ognized as a serious, growing threat to global public health. The magnitude
of the threat is revealed by the fact that the World Health Organization
Research Priorities, Profits, and Public Goods: The Case of Drug Resistant Disease 29
The worry that drug resistant disease might have such severe conse-
quences is by no means unique to the WHO. The concern that drug resist-
ance may realistically “plunge humanity back into the conditions that existed
in the pre-antibiotic age”, for example, has also been raised by numerous
other reputable organisations such as the U.S. Congress Office of Technology
Assessment (U.S. Congress 1995).
The potential consequences of drug resistance should reveal that drug
resistance – assuming that something can be done to alleviate the problem –
is a matter of ethical urgency. The return to a “pre-antibiotic era” would be
catastrophic. In the meanwhile the costs of treating drug resistant infections
are already enormous – and estimated to be $7 billion per year in the United
States alone (Smith and Coast 2003:76).
Over-prescription
Part of the problem is thus the widespread overuse of antibiotics. In coun-
tries such as the US and Canada, for example, it is estimated that antibiotics
are overprescribed by 50% (WHO 2000). “Antibiotics are often prescribed
for viral infections, for which they have no value, and for self-limited infec-
tions that would have cleared up whether or not an antibiotic had been pre-
scribed” (U.S. Congress 1995:11). In the United States 40% of primary care
physicians prescribe antibiotics when patients present with sore throats and
ear aches without first seeking laboratory confirmation that this is indicated.
This kind of overprescription is largely due to the time required for diagnos-
tic confirmation (ibid.:13). It is also partly due to patient demand for imme-
diate treatment and physicians’ fear of litigation. Patient demand and physi-
cian prescription are increasingly also influenced by aggressive marketing of
the pharmaceutical industry (Smith et al. 2004:12).
Another cause of drug resistance is patients’ failure often fail to complete
prescribed treatment regimens. While this itself promotes resistance, matters
are made worse when leftover pills are saved and then used for “self-medica-
tion” later (Levy 1992). The fact that antibiotics are poorly understood by
the lay public comes into play both in the case of self-medication and when
patients demand inappropriate prescriptions from willing physicians.
Farming Practice
Given that drug resistance increases with antibiotic use, it is disturbing that
vast amounts of antibiotics are used in agriculture and aquaculture for pro-
phylaxis, treatment, and growth promotion. 50% (by weight) of antibiotics
are used for such purposes. Of particular concern is the common practice of
adding “subtherapeutic” levels of antibiotics to the food of healthy animals
in order to promote their growth. In the United States, “the amount of this
subtherapeutic usage is four or five times greater [by weight] than the
amount used for treatment of animal diseases” (ibid.:137). Long-term, low
level exposure like this creates especially favorable circumstances for the pro-
motion of drug resistant bacteria (ibid.). While the threat to human health
from such a practice is difficult to estimate and study, the worries are that
resulting resistant bacteria in animals will be passed on to humans – or that
resistant genes in animal bacteria will jump to bacteria which inhabit human
hosts. A growing body of evidence indicates that the dangers are real (WHO
2001). While feeding animals with subtherapeutic doses of antimicrobials
used for humans has been banned in Europe and Canada, regulations are
lacking in the US and elsewhere. The issue, unsurprisingly, has been highly
politicized.
Research Priorities, Profits, and Public Goods: The Case of Drug Resistant Disease 31
Under-consumption
As indicated above, the failure to complete a proper course of antibiotic
treatment is one of the things that promotes the emergence of drug resist-
ant pathogens. If treatment is prematurely terminated, then disease-caus-
ing mutant bacteria, which would have been killed off if treatment had
been completed, survive and become more strongly established in the
absence of microbial competitors. Treatment with the very same drugs will
then be less effective. This is one reason why physicians emphasize the
importance of completing our treatments by taking all the pills provided.
And this is why “noncompliant patients” are so often blamed for the prob-
lem of drug resistance.
The failure to complete a full course of treatment, however, is not always
the fault of the patient. “Noncompliance”, according to Paul Farmer, is usu-
ally a matter of ability rather than agency: “Throughout the world, those
least likely to comply are those least able to comply” (Farmer 1999:255;
2003). As stated before, the poor are most likely to get sick, and least likely
to afford medical care when they do. They are also least able to complete
medical treatment once they start it. Poor people in developing countries
often simply cannot afford to complete treatment – especially given the
high drug prices set by pharmaceutical companies. In addition to drug
costs, difficulty affording time off work and the cost of (often difficult)
transportation to (often faraway) clinics pose barriers to the completion of
antibiotic therapy. Sometimes, according to Farmer, it is simply a matter of
not having enough money to rent a donkey (Farmer 2003).
Additional barriers to access are posed by infrastructural constraints of
medical systems in poor countries where drug stockouts are frequent. This is
well illustrated by the prison situation in the former Soviet Union. Increased
crime and incarceration came with the collapse of the Soviet Union. “Almost
1 percent of the population of Russia is imprisoned, a higher percentage
than any other nation in the world” (Reichman and Tanne 2002:90). Of the
300,000 prisoners released every year, 10% have active tuberculosis and
more than 80% “have been infected with latent TB”. Each of the latter has a
10% chance of developing active TB later in life (ibid.:53). Of prisoners (and
those being released) with active TB, about a third have multi-drug-
resistant TB (ibid.:90). These astounding rates of tuberculosis infection and
multi-drug resistance reflect the fact that under-funded prisons are unable
to maintain a steady supply of the full range of drugs needed for the long-
term treatment of TB. The sporadic partial treatment that inevitably results
selects directly for multi-drug resistance. Those released are unlikely to
receive much better care from the wider health care system, and so the health
of their families and communities is subsequently threatened, as is global
public health in general. Tuberculosis is spread in the air. Both in this case
and others it must be remembered that (1) infectious diseases (drug-resis-
32 Michael Selgelid
tant or otherwise) have no respect for national boundaries and (2) their
spread is facilitated by increased international travel and trade.
While ordinary tuberculosis can be treated with a six month course of
treatment costing $10, drug-resistant tuberculosis treatment takes two years
and costs 100 times as much – and “[e]ven then a cure is not guaranteed.” It
is thus widely acknowledged that new TB drug development is needed, as
there are now “300,000 new cases per year of MDR-TB worldwide.” In the
meanwhile it is unfortunate that, according to the WHO, there has been “a
40 year standstill in TB drug development” (WHO 2004).
Solutions
Numerous measures for curtailing the problem of drug resistance have been
recommended. Increased education of health providers and the public, con-
trol of prescription practices, improvement of infection control in hospitals,
and reduction of antibiotic use in farming, for example, are important parts
of the solution. Given that under-consumption of drugs by the poor is a
driver of resistance, improved access to medications through price reduction
or social provision is also needed. Things like increased (global) surveillance
and impact assessment (so the extent of the problem can be better tracked –
and appreciated) and improvements in diagnostic technology are also essen-
tial.
Of paramount importance, in any case, is the development of new drugs
and vaccines. New antibiotics are needed because the power of our existing
supply has increasingly declined, while there has been a dearth of new drug
development for decades. Vaccines are important because they prevent
infection and the need for antibiotics to begin with.
The topic of drug resistance thus directly relates to the business ethics of
innovation. What ethical responsibility does the pharmaceutical industry
have to further invest in research and development of much-needed new
antibiotics and vaccines? That the profit motive has been insufficient to
motivate this kind of innovation is revealed by the current status quo.
Almost no new classes of antibiotics, recall, have been developed since the
1960s, and no new TB drugs have been developed for 40 years. The failure of
the medical industry to further invest in antimicrobial development is
symptomatic of a more general phenomenon known as the 10/90 divide in
medical research: less than 10% of medical research resources focus on 90%
of the global burden of disease, and more than 90% of medical research
resources focus on 10% of the global burden of disease. These numbers sim-
ply reflect the uncontroversial fact that medical industry research largely
aims at promotion of profits rather than addressing the world’s most impor-
tant medical needs – and that the medicines that are most profitable for
industry to develop do not necessarily coincide with those that are most
needed from the standpoint of global public health.
Research Priorities, Profits, and Public Goods: The Case of Drug Resistant Disease 33
Public Goods
The fact that free-market mechanisms have failed to provide solutions to the
problem of drug resistance is in many ways unsurprising. The phenomenon
of drug resistance reveals that freedom from infectious disease is a public
good; and the ability of free markets to provide such goods is notoriously
dubious. That drug resistance is a problem of public goods is illustrated by
the above discussion of the dynamics behind the emergence and spread of
drug resistant disease. When one individual develops a drug resistant strain
of disease because of her over- or under-consumption of drugs, this more
difficult or more expensive strain of disease poses threats to other individu-
als who may subsequently be infected. This is thus a prototypical case of neg-
ative externalities – or harms to third parties – that are a hallmark of public
goods.
The usual moral justification of free markets holds that they promote
both (negative) liberty and utility. It is claimed that they promote (negative)
liberty because outcomes are the result of individuals’ free choices about
what kinds of transactions to enter into. And it is claimed that they promote
utility because they are pareto efficient.2 A pareto efficient outcome is one
where it would be impossible to make any one person better off without
making another worse off. It can be theoretically proven that pareto efficient
outcomes would result under ideal conditions – i.e. if the parties were
rational and in possession of full information, if there were no transaction
costs, and so on. Because transaction costs include externalities, however,
there is no good theoretical reason to expect free markets to be pareto effi-
cient in contexts involving public goods. The status quo (e.g., as discussed
two paragraphs back), in the meanwhile, seems to show that there is no good
empirical reason to think that the pharmaceutical market is efficient or util-
ity-maximizing broadly speaking.
The fact that freedom from infectious disease is a public good provides
additional reasons to the egalitarian and human rights reasons traditionally
appealed to by bioethicists for treating health care as something special when
making policy decisions about its distribution. Norman Daniels (1995) and
others are right to argue that there are egalitarian and human rights reasons
to remove health care from free market mechanisms. The fact that freedom
from infectious disease is a public good, however, shows that there are
straightforward economic efficiency/utilitarian reasons for doing so as well.
This does not mean that health care provision should be removed from mar-
ket mechanisms entirely; but, as with other public goods, some kind of gov-
2
Insofar as it is plausible to think that utility-maximizing outcomes might some-
times requiring making at least someone worst off, the common idea that pareto
efficiency is a good proxy for utility is dubious. For the purpose of this paper,
however, it is safe to leave aside this legitimate objection to the common rationale
offered in favour of free markets.
34 Michael Selgelid
Holding that poverty rather than patents is the main barrier of access to
essential medications, Attaran concludes that activists should shift their
energies towards problems of poverty alleviation rather than objecting so
much to intellectual property right protection.
Research Priorities, Profits, and Public Goods: The Case of Drug Resistant Disease 35
Both of these studies are open to serious criticism which is beyond the
scope of this paper. Even if it were true that patents do not pose serious barri-
ers of access to existing medications, however, it would be wrong to conclude
that activists concerned with health in developing countries should therefore
shift attention away from intellectual property rights in pharmaceuticals (Sel-
gelid and Sepers 2006). The availability problem is an additional reason to be
concerned about patents. The fact that patents have failed to promote ade-
quate innovation is revealed by the general dearth of antimicrobial and vac-
cine development and the phenomenon of the 10/90 divide discussed above.
Patents may spur innovation in medications likely to yield the greatest
profits, but these are generally not those which are most needed from the
standpoint of global public health – especially as those in need are usually
poor people in developing countries. The irony here is that patents are them-
selves supposed to solve a public goods problem. Knowledge – in this case
knowledge about how to cure disease – is a prototypical example of a public
good, and patents are supposed to promote its growth by providing an
incentive that would otherwise be lacking because of the free-rider problem.
Without patents, the argument goes, innovating firms would lack incentive
to engage in R&D because others would be able to free-ride on their discov-
ery investment (by making copycat products). In the context of pharmaceu-
ticals, however, even with patents the lack of sufficient incentive remains.
Alternatives to the current patent regime are apparently needed if the hope is
that the drugs which are most needed will both be made available via phar-
maceutical industry innovation and be made accessible to the poor.
Business Ethics
Business ethics is, of course, concerned with questions about what busi-
nesses and those working in business should do. If Pogge is correct, then cor-
porations should support the implementation of alternative incentive
schemes like his at least partly because implementation of such schemes
Research Priorities, Profits, and Public Goods: The Case of Drug Resistant Disease 37
would open up new markets and provide additional avenues for profit mak-
ing without interfering with existing ways of making profits in pharmaceuti-
cals. If his economic arguments are technically sound, then there are
straightforward self-interested reasons for taking action.
But there is more to it than that. Implementation of such schemes, assuming
they are in fact realistic, would promote the greater good of humankind as well.
It is often said that business executives are faced with conflicting duties: fiduci-
ary duties to share-holders to maximize profits, on the one hand, are supposed
to conflict with their more general duties as human beings to promote the good
of humankind, on the other (Friedman 1970). One might argue that one
should never take on roles involving duties that conflict with one’s prior duties
as a human being. If the role of business executive would involve duties that
conflict with the prior duties of human beings in general, that is, then no
human being should take on the role of business executive to begin with. And if
share-holders have the duties of human beings to promote the good of
humankind, then they should not require/expect the companies they own or
the executives who work for such companies to do things that would compro-
mise the good of humankind. To make a long story short, if profit maximizing
endeavors preclude fulfilling our prior duties as human beings to promote the
good of humankind, then neither share holders nor business executives should
commit themselves to profit maximizing ventures to begin with.
A promising feature of the pull programs of Kremer/Glennerster and
Pogge is that if they would actually work then the conflict (between duties to
promote profits and to promote the good of humankind) so often assumed in
debates in business ethics can be avoided to begin with. If these programs
would in fact work, then making profits would go hand-in-hand with pro-
moting the good of humankind. Above I argued that human beings should
not take on roles that conflict with the prior general duties of human beings.
Whether or not that argument succeeds, my final conclusion is that busi-
nesses and/or the individuals who comprise them have compelling moral rea-
sons to support proposals like those of Kremer/Glennerster and Pogge. The
usual excuse for corporations not directing their actions toward the promo-
tion of the good of humankind is the idea that doing so would conflict with
another (arguably primary) goal of corporations – i.e. to maximize profits. If
the proposals of Kremer/Glennerster or Pogge would actually work, however,
then that excuse falls away. We might not expect corporations to sacrifice
their profitability, competitiveness, and ability to survive in order to serve
humanitarian ends – but we should, ethically- and realistically-speaking,
expect them to promote humanitarian ends insofar as this is compatible with
profit-maximization. Assuming that the alternative innovation incentive
schemes such as those we have been discussing actually would enable phar-
maceutical corporations (and the individuals which comprise them) to both
promote humanitarian ends and maximize profits, we should expect phar-
maceutical corporations to provide political support for such schemes.
38 Michael Selgelid
References
Attaran A (2004) How Do Patents and Economic Policies Affect Access to Essential
Medicines, in Developing Countries? Health Affairs 23
Attaran A, Gillespie-White L (2001) Do Patents for Antiretroviral Drugs Constrain
Access to AIDS Treatment in Africa? Journal for the American Medical Associa-
tion (JAMA) 286
Daniels N (1985) Just Health Care. New York. Cambridge University Press
Farmer P (1999) Infections and Inequalities: The Modern Plagues. Berkeley, CA.
University of California Press
Farmer P (2003) Pathologies of Power: Health, Human Rights, and the New War on
the Poor. Berkeley, CA. University of California Press
Francis LP, Battin MP, Jacobson JA, Smith CB, Botkin J (2005) How Infectious Dis-
ease Got Left Out – And What this Ommission Might Have Meant for Bioethics.
Bioethics 19, 4:307–322
Friedman M (1970) The Social Responsibility of Business is to Increase its Profits.
The New York Times Magazine. September 13:33, 122–126
Garrett L (1994) The Coming Plague: Newly Emerging Diseases in a World Out of
Balance. New York. Penguin
Knobler SL, Lemon SM, Najafi M, Burroughs T (eds) (2003) The Resistance Phe-
nomenon in Microbes and Infectious Disease Vectors: Implications for Human
Health and Strategies for Containment. Institute of Medicine, Workshop Sum-
mary. Washington DC. National Academies Press
Kremer M, Glennerster R (2004) Strong Medicine. Princeton, NJ. Princeton Univer-
sity Press
Levy SB (1992) The Antibiotic Paradox. New York. Plenum Press
Pogge TW (2005) Human Rights and Global Health: A Research Program. Metaphi-
losophy 36:182–209
Reichman LB, Tanne JH (2002) Timebomb: The Global Epidemic of Multi-Drug-
Resistant Tuberculosis. New York. McGraw Hill
U.S. Congress, Office of Technology Assessment (1995) Impacts of Antibiotic-Resis-
tant Bacteria, OTA-H-629. Washington, DC. Government Printing Office
Selgelid MJ (2005) Ethics and Infectious Disease. Bioethics 19, 3:272–289
Selgelid MJ, Sepers E (2006) Patents, Profits, and the Price of Pills: Implications for
Access and Availability. In: Illingworth P, Schuklenk U, Cohen JC (eds) The Power
of Pills. Pluto Press
Smith CB, Battin MP, Jacobson JA, Francis LP, Botkin JB, Asplund EP, Domek GJ,
Hawkins B (2004) Are there Characteristics of Infectious Diseases that Raise Spe-
cial Ethical Issues? Developing World Bioethics: 4, 1
Smith RD, Coast J (2003) Antimicrobial Drug Resistance. In: Smith R, Beaglehole R,
Woodward D, Drager N (eds) Global Public Goods for Health: Health Economic
and Public Health Perspectives. New York. Oxford University Press
World Health Organization (WHO) (2000) Report on Infectious Diseases 2000 –
Overcoming Antimicrobial Resistance. Available at http://www.who.int/infec-
tious-disease-report/2000/preface.htm
World Health Organization (WHO) (2001) WHO Global Strategy for Containment
of Antimicrobial Resistance. Available at www.who.org
World Health Organization (WHO) (2004) Drug Resistant Tuberculosis Levels Ten
Times Higher in Eastern Europe and Central Asia. Press Release, available at:
http://www.who.int/mediacentre/releases/2004/prl17/en/print.html
Ethical Issues Associated with Pharmaceutical Innovation
Margaret L. Eaton
Introduction
Corporate managers responsible for the research, development, and marketing
of pharmaceutical products inevitably encounter challenging ethical issues.
One main reason is that, to reach the market, drugs must be studied in animals
and humans, activities that have historically been plagued with ethical dilem-
mas about weighing the benefits and risks to subjects and the goal of advanc-
ing medical science and, in the case of human research, issues of free and
informed consent. The second main reason that ethics has special relevance to
the pharmaceutical industry is related to the intrinsic nature of drug products.
Drugs become intensely personal when they make the difference between life
and death, health and disability. The more grave the illness, the more patients
care about them. Drug products are also unavoidably unsafe – no drug can be
taken without some risk of harm. The diseases that have produced the need for
drug therapy also make patients more vulnerable than other consumers. Fair-
ness issues are generated by pharmaceutical products since they are often
costly and therefore create access disparities. The vital importance of these
products ensures that company research, development, and marketing will be
closely scrutinized by governments, physicians, patients, and the press. Such
scrutiny means that any lapse in corporate ethical conduct is increasingly
detected and engenders a loss of public trust in the industry.
Given the propensity with which this industry encounters ethical issues, it
is important to understand their genesis and to understand some of the his-
tory that can provide lessons for the future. This chapter will serve these
goals by identifying ethically relevant activities of the pharmaceutical indus-
try and presenting examples of how these activities have impacted compa-
nies. Awareness of where the ethical pitfalls lie can end a common practice of
addressing these issues only in times of emergency and can allow managers
to anticipate potential problems and address them proactively.
interest are common in this setting since the two entities engaged in this
activity are very different one from the other. Companies do not want com-
petitors to learn of their early drug research activity and often seek to keep
this information confidential. Confidentiality is also important to protect
intellectual property and trade secrets. The company sponsor also needs to
design the research to achieve a commercial goal. In contrast, academics
operate under conditions of openness and free discussion, and faculties are
accustomed to the freedom to research any matter regardless of its short
term practical application. Universities also pride themselves as sources of
objective knowledge and some faculty members suspect that corporate
funding influences their research focus or scientific judgment about a par-
ticular technology. Too much corporate research support, it is argued, can
undermine the credibility of faculty members and the public trust in the
university. In addition, academics have other campus obligations – teach-
ing, governance – that can be compromised if a faculty member spends too
much time on corporate sponsored projects. Sometimes, also, industry
sponsored research can be too mundane to advance science and learning. As
a consequence, even though faculty may agree to conduct corporate
research, universities often refuse to abide by corporate requests to main-
tain confidentiality, delay publication, or alter other basic academic prac-
tices (Witt 1994; Bodenheimer 2000).
Health policy researcher David Blumenthal and colleagues at Harvard Uni-
versity study these conflicts of interest and commitment and have demon-
strated that a certain level of industry sponsored academic research is benefi-
cial to both parties (Blumenthal et al. 1996a; Blumenthal et al. 1996b). Beyond
a certain point, however, the risks seem to outweigh the benefits. When aca-
demic researchers obtain more than two-thirds of their research funding from
commercial sources, they tend to be less open, lose academic credibility, and
become less productive academic citizens. Other problems include intellectual
property disputes, disagreements about study design integrity and data inter-
pretation, and conflicts over company-mandated publication delays. A certain
amount of delay to submit patent applications is usually tolerated but not
when delay is to preserve competitive advantages such as by restricting the dis-
semination of unfavorable data. On the other side of the deal, companies can
be unhappy with university researchers when, for instance, they assign the
work to junior faculty or students, cause delays, breach confidentiality, fail to
follow the study protocol, and commit research misconduct.
An example of a research collaboration that created these kinds of con-
flict occurred when Sandoz collaborated with academic physicians to study
the cardiac effects of one of its blood pressure drugs compared to another
common drug. Some of the faculty researchers alleged that Sandoz had
wielded undue influence in controlling how the research results were
reported. For this reason, these faculty researchers made public their refusal
to have their names included as authors on the publication (Applegate
Ethical Issues Associated with Pharmaceutical Innovation 41
1
See, for example, Stanford University Faculty Policy on Conflict of Commitment
and Interest. Available from URL: http://www.stanford.edu/dept/DoR/rph/
4-1.html.
2
Available from URL: http://www.aamc.org/members/coitf/start.htm.
3
Available from URL: http://www.nhmrc.gov.au/research/general/nhmrcavc.htm.
4
Available from URL: http://www.icmje.org/index.html.
42 Margaret L. Eaton
The dilemma arises because companies need to design trials to meet their
marketing needs. For instance, if the company plans to market a drug for a
severe form of a particular disease, the studies will exclude animal and human
subjects with mild disease. Whether such a study design is considered biased
hinges on intent which is often revealed by the manner in which the company
interprets and markets the data. Using the data, for instance, to claim that the
drug is useful in the disease per se is obviously misleading. The study may also
be considered irresponsible if the company knows or strongly suspects that
the drug is ineffective or toxic in mild disease and that unsuspecting physi-
cians will tend to do what they always do – use the drug in all forms of the dis-
ease. The company may respond to this situation with a range of actions:
– claim that it is someone else’s responsibility to produce study data on how
the drug behaves when used “off label”5, in this case, for patients with the
mild form of the disease;
– state in the labeling that the drug is useful in severe forms of disease;
– state that no data exists on how the drug behaves in mild disease;
– disclose the suspicion that the drug is not useful or safe in the wider spec-
trum of diseased patients;
– act on the suspicion and conduct studies to show how the drug behaves
when prescribed in the real world, in this case, for patients with the mild
form of the disease.
Disagreements are increasingly common about whether drug study
designs intentionally enhance efficacy outcomes or conceal side effects.
Merck experienced criticism of this nature after it withdrew its anti-inflam-
matory drug Vioxx® in 2004, a drug that was selling $2.5 billion per year.
After five years on the market, the drug was shown to enhance the risk for
heart attacks and strokes prompting questions about whether the company
had delayed the discovery of these risks. Leaks of internal documents
revealed comments by the company’s vice president for clinical research that
suggested she knew that Vioxx could cause cardiovascular side effects and
was contemplating designing an important clinical trial to obscure this find-
ing (Mathews 2004). In another widely publicized case, the lead researcher
responsible for ImClone’s anti-cancer drug was called to testify at a congres-
sional investigation hearing and asked to address allegations that his lucra-
tive company ties had led him to manipulate drug study data (Urancek
2002). Whether Merck or ImClone scientists had designed studies in order
to heighten efficacy or mask side effects is unknown. Yet, commentary in the
scientific literature indicates a long-held uneasiness about whether company
sponsored drug trials are skewed to produce positive data. Others say that
this conclusion is too facile – that companies sponsor only those trials where
prior data support a reasonable expectation that outcomes will be positive.
5
The term “off label” refers to the use of a drug for other than approved indica-
tions.
Ethical Issues Associated with Pharmaceutical Innovation 43
the lab. In contrast, they chafe when asked to develop a chemically related
drug that offers only minimal improvement over existing therapies, so-
called me-too drugs. The term me-too comes from the fact that, as soon as a
large market prototype drug becomes available, several other similarly active
compounds immediately follow from competing companies. This kind of
drug is attractive for companies to develop since they can capitalize on the
research and approval of the successful prototype, develop follow-ons more
efficiently, and take an easier share of a large established market. Me-too
drugs are also developed to preserve a market for a blockbuster drug, the
patent for which is about to expire. Patenting a similar drug can allow the
company to maintain premium pricing rather than watch revenues decline
when the drug losses patent its patent and becomes generic.
Most often, the follow-ons offer some benefit over the prototype, such as
lesser toxicity, improved pharmacokinetic profile, more favorable compati-
bility with co-morbid conditions, or easier use. Patients benefit when the
me-too offers significant medical benefit and generates price competition
(Dimasi 2004). The reason that many researchers dislike developing me-
toos, however, is that too many offer only a marginal benefit, so small, claim
some, that the intellectual and financial development resources expended far
outweigh any medical or social benefit. The situation worsens, claim some,
when aggressive marketing obscures the small differences between a high
priced new drug and a cheaper generic. Scientists and physicians prefer
intrinsic medical value rather than marketing to determine which drugs get
prescribed. The fact that these drugs are considered duplicative and wasteful
of resources incites consumer groups as well. Criticism of me-too drugs is
relevant even in the situation where the existence of the me-too is the result
of a development race rather than post hoc imitation. Once a strong class
breakthrough drug has been approved, some favor a system that will allow
only those follow-ons that demonstrate significant improvements over the
prototype. Currently, most regulatory systems approve drugs based on their
intrinsic merits rather than whether they offer significant benefits over exist-
ing drugs.
An example of the me-too phenomena is captopril, the prototype for
angiotensin converting enzyme (ACE) inhibitors, a class of drugs used to
control hypertension. The approval of captopril was followed by at least 15
me-too ACE inhibitors most of which have equivalent efficacy and side
effect profiles. The similarities are so close that one pharmacologist sug-
gested that physicians should routinely prescribe whatever brand was
cheaper (Garattini 1997). An example of a drug developed to preserve rev-
enues from a patented blockbuster is the acid reflux drug Nexium® by Astra
Zeneca. This drug is the S-isomer of the company’s blockbuster drug
Prilosec® which had been a major revenue producer until its U.S. patent
expired in 2001. Astra Zeneca took advantage of the fact that isomeric forms
are considered by the FDA to be different compounds and can be separately
Ethical Issues Associated with Pharmaceutical Innovation 45
The Declaration of Helsinki (section A.5) is more narrow and states that
the well being of the human subject should take precedence over the inter-
ests of science and society. Other aspects of minimizing risks to subjects
require that sufficient prior research should be performed to understand the
potential risks as much as possible. Researchers also must be qualified and
adhere to standards of good research practice so as to preserve the benefits of
the research as much as possible, thus not exposing subjects to risk for no
good purpose. Minimizing the risks and burdens to subjects in these ways
adheres to the ethical norm of non-malfeasance or doing no harm, which is
a principle obligation of any research physician.
4.2 Informed Consent
Over the years, lack of informed consent has been at the heart of most
unethical studies. Failure to fully inform subjects uses people as a means to
an end (to produce data), disrespects the right to personal autonomy, and
offends our sense of fairness. A commonly cited example occurred in a San
Antonio, Texas study in the 1970s that enrolled mostly poor Mexican-Amer-
ican women who had had multiple pregnancies and were seeking contracep-
tive advice or medication. The double blind, randomized, placebo controlled
study was intended to evaluate the cause of oral contraceptive side effects.
8
21 Code of Federal Regulations sec. 111(a)(2).
Ethical Issues Associated with Pharmaceutical Innovation 47
Subjects enrolled in the study were not told that they could receive a placebo
and, as expected, there were a high number of unplanned pregnancies in the
placebo group (Veatch 1971). Ethical lapses such as this are the reason for
mandatory requirements that subjects be provided a clear and accurate
explanation of risks, benefits, and alternatives before enrolling in any clinical
study.9 In order for consent to be meaningful, the potential subject must be
given understandable information, informed of all of the expected conse-
quences that a reasonable person would want to know about, and given an
opportunity to ask questions and an adequate time to reflect before commit-
ting. Special attention to the consent process is needed when studies are
complex or particularly risky and when subjects’ ability to understand is
compromised. Some researchers in these situations have required subjects to
pass a comprehension test before enrolling them into studies.
4.3 Free Consent
Informed consent is not the same thing as free consent. Respect for persons
requires that consent to research be truly voluntary. For various reasons,
some patients are more vulnerable than others and are therefore more sus-
ceptible to the influence of a trusted physician who asks for consent to join a
drug study. Especially when patients are desperate for any chance of treat-
ment, physician researchers need to be careful to minimize the possibility of
coercion or undue influence in the recruitment process. Vulnerable patients
also include those who are economically and medically disadvantaged and
who may volunteer simply because money is offered or the fact that research
participation offers the only access to medical care. Those who lack mental
capacity and cannot competently consent to research need a proxy who rep-
resents the patient’s best interest. In addition, many believe that patients with
mental deficits should be included in drug research only if the mental condi-
tion is a necessary characteristic of the research population. Most countries
also have provisions forbidding or controlling the use of prisoners in research
because of the difficulty in dissuading the incarcerated from the belief that
cooperation with researchers will result in favorable prison treatment.
In general, little regulation exists regarding the methods or safeguards
that should be employed to ensure that vulnerable or incapable subjects con-
sent freely. As a result, individual researchers need to tailor their recruitment
methods to minimize any coercive influences.
4.4 Privacy
The information collected in drug research is medical in nature and, as such,
must be kept confidential. Also, the fact that a subject has entered a clinical
study often reveals his or her diagnosis, so enrollment is also private infor-
9
The FDA regulations on informed consent are at 21 Code of Federal Regulations
sec. 50.20 et seq.
48 Margaret L. Eaton
mation. Every precaution should be taken to respect the privacy of the sub-
ject and the confidentiality of the patient’s information.
4.5 Research in Children
Pediatric drug research has been generally neglected because of the reluctance
to subject children to unknown risks given that they cannot protect their own
interests through informed consent. In addition, the protective instincts of
parents and guardians make them unwilling to enroll their children in
research. The resultant lack of data on how children react to drugs means that
most pediatric treatment proceeds through trial and error. Regulatory agen-
cies are trying to correct this disadvantage by offering drug companies
inducements to conduct pediatric research and by specifying the ethical
requirements necessary to enroll these subjects in research. For instance, the
FDA regulations list the safeguards that must be satisfied depending on the
risk of the research, the potential benefit to the child, the potential to produce
generalizable knowledge about the child’s disease, and the opportunity to
understand, prevent, or alleviate a serious problem affecting the health or
welfare of children. The regulations also specify the qualifications of parents
or other consent providers and require the assent of the child if feasible.10
4.6 Placebo Controls
The ethical debate about the use of placebo controls centers on the scientific
benefits of eliminating the most study variables vs the risks to subjects of for-
going standard treatment. The use of placebo controls, according to most
researchers, best satisfies the fundamental research goal of producing scien-
tifically accurate and dependable data that can distinguish the effect of the
drug from other influences, such as spontaneous change in the course of the
disease, placebo effect, biased observation, or chance. Regulatory agencies
will not approve a drug without sufficiently controlled data and the FDA
especially adheres to the belief that no control is better than placebo.11 Thus,
drug companies often rely on the use of placebo controls because the result-
ing study data are considered trustworthy by the regulatory agencies and by
physicians. Placebo controls are also desirable since, by producing fewer
confounding variables, studies can be conducted more rapidly with smaller
populations than clinical trials using active controls. Shorter clinical trials
with fewer subjects can save time and money and put effective products on
the market more quickly (Harrington 1999; Jost 2000; Temple 2000).
The problem with placebos is that human subjects must agree to random
and blind assignment to a therapeutically inert substance masked as an
active treatment. Obviously, the sicker the patient, the greater the potential
10
See 21 Code of Federal Regulation sec. 50.50-50.56.
11
In the United States, the regulations that specify the requirement for reliable study
data are found at 21Code of Federal Regulations sec. 314.126.
Ethical Issues Associated with Pharmaceutical Innovation 49
12
This company later merged with France’s Rhone-Poulenc SA to become Aventis
SA.
Ethical Issues Associated with Pharmaceutical Innovation 51
18
See http://www.phrma.org.
19
The U.S. regulations for drug marketing and advertising are found at 21 Code of
Federal Regulations Part 202.
20
See, for example, Code of Pharmaceutical Marketing Practices of the Interna-
tional Federation of Pharmaceutical Manufacturers Associations, available from
http://www.ifpma.org/.
56 Margaret L. Eaton
change occurred when drugs were found to control hair loss, male erectile
dysfunction, short stature, and menopausal and pre-menstrual symptoms.
This kind of expansion has been given a name by critics, diagnostic bracket
creep, and has come to mean that what was once considered within the range
of normal experience and behavior was now classed as illness. The introduc-
tion of new drugs is the primary reason that diagnostic bracket creep occurs.
Debates exist about whether this phenomenon generates better and more
enlightened treatment for patients or an irresponsible medicalization of
conditions that should not be considered diseases. This debate is currently
robust within the psychiatry and psychology professions when one com-
pany’s SSRI antidepressant was approved and marketed for a new disease the
company called social anxiety disorder (SAD). Since many people are often
uncomfortable in new social situations, critics accused the company of using
its ads to expand the market for its drug by blurring the distinction between
a legitimate psychiatric disorder and normal personality variation (Vedan-
tam 2001).
These criticisms of drug marketing practices have led to the question of
cost vs benefit. If the advertising (especially the DTC kind) does not improve
health awareness or provide other benefits and, worse; if the ads are harmful,
the cost of advertising becomes an issue. In 2003, U.S. companies spent $3.22
billion in DTC advertising (Hensley 2004) and it is reasonable to assume that
this amount is incorporated, at least to some extent, into the price of the
products.21 Supporters of DTC advertising believe that it can have a positive
effect, such as when the ads prompt people to seek treatment with choles-
terol lowering drugs. Advertising lipid lowering drugs, for instance, can
decrease healthcare costs from the decrease in cardiovascular morbidity in
treated patients. Critics, however, deplore the spending and wonder if the
increase in the number of prescriptions written for advertised drugs is con-
tributing significantly to patient health. In the midst of this debate, some
companies, such as Johnson & Johnson, are skewing their patient ads to
highlight the educational and safety aspects. According to the company, the
move was to reduce the animosity directed to these ads and preserve the
right to market directly to patients by educating and counseling consumers
to improve their health (Hensley 2005).
8 Post-marketing Safety Monitoring
Drug companies have increasingly understood that the commitment they
must make to a new drug is often more than the usually quoted statistic of 10
years and $800 million to get the drug to market. The post-market research
and surveillance phase of a drug’s life is now often as active as the pre-mar-
ket phase. Companies are either obliged by the regulatory agencies or volun-
21
Industry statistics indicate that the primary effect of DTC ads is to increase drug
spending by increasing the number of prescriptions written, not the prices of the
advertised drugs.
58 Margaret L. Eaton
tarily undertake these post-market programs. Reasons for doing so are usu-
ally related to the fact that clinical research can never predict precisely how a
drug will behave once prescribed in the open market. Plenty of examples
exist of drugs approved for marketing only to be withdrawn within a short
period because of unexpected side effects. Historically, the rate of drug
recalls in the U.S. is 2–3% (Kleinke 1998). Drug companies also know that
physicians will prescribe a drug for many patients who were not included on
the pre-market studies – children, pregnant patients, the elderly, patients
with co-morbid conditions, or even patients with other diseases. These cir-
cumstances give rise to two questions that have ethical relevance. How much
post-market safety monitoring should the company perform? And, to what
extent is it the company’s responsibility (as opposed to the physicians) to
collect data on or study off-label uses? The question about post-market
safety monitoring depends on the extent of pre-market research, the utility
of the drug, and the severity of potential side effects. For instance, if there
was extensive pre-market research, the drug is for an unmet medical need,
and the potential for side effects low, then the need for safety monitoring or
further study is probably on the low side of the spectrum. The question
about off-label use is more difficult to resolve. On the one hand, physicians
need to take responsibility for their prescribing. If there is little data to indi-
cate that a drug is safe for a particular use, this suggests that the physician
should use the drug under research rather than clinical conditions and the
company should not be responsible if the physician is reckless in this regard.
On the other hand, if the company knows that the drug has a high potential
for toxicity, doing nothing seems irresponsible, especially since the company
benefits from the expansion in the market attributable to off-label use. This
is exactly the view taken by critics in the Vioxx debate (described above). The
significant legal, financial, and reputational harm that resulted in that case
indicates that companies need to devote considerable attention to their
responsibilities for post-market drug safety.
References
Adams C, Harris G (2000) When NIH helps discover drugs, should taxpayers share
wealth? Wall Street Journal, B1
Angell M (1997) The ethics of clinical research in the third world. New England
Journal of Medicine 337:847–849
Applegate W, Furberg K, Byungton R et al. (1996) The multicenter isradipine
diuretic athersclerosis study (MIDAS). Journal of the American Medical Associa-
tion 277:297–298
Arzberger P, Schroeber P, Beaulieu A et al. (2004) An international framework to
promote access to data. Science 303:1777–1778
Bayer R (1998) The debate over maternal-fetal HIV transmission prevention trials in
Africa, Asia, and the Caribbean: racist exploitation or exploitation of racism?
American Journal of Public Health 88:567–570
Brown D (2004) Group says U.S. should claim AIDS drug patents. Washington Post,
May 26, 2004, A4
Blumenthal D, Campbell E, Causino N et al. (1996) Participation of life-science fac-
ulty in research relationships with industry. New England Journal of Medicine
335:1734–1739
Blumenthal D, Causino N, Campbell E et al. (1996) Relationships between academic
institutions and industry in the life sciences – an industry survey. New England
Journal of Medicine 334:368–373
Bodenheimer T (2000) Uneasy alliance – clinical investigators and the pharmaceuti-
cal industry. New England Journal of Medicine 342:1538–1544
Borger J (2001) Dying for drugs: volunteers or victims? Concern grows over control
of drug trials. The Guardian, February 14, 4
Brower V (1999) Biotechs embrace bioethics, BioSpace, June 14. Available from URL:
http://www.biospace.com/articles/061499_ethics.cfm
Cimons M, Zonana VF (1989) Manufacturer reduces price of AZT by 20%. Los
Angeles Times, September 19, 1
Couzin J (2004) Volatile chemistry: Children and antidepressants. Science 305:468–
470
DiMasi JA (2001) New drug development in the United States 1963–1999. Clinical
Pharmacology & Therapeutics 5:286–296
DiMasi JA, Paquette C (2004) The economics of follow-on drug research and devel-
opment: trends in entry rates and the timing of development. Pharmacoeconom-
ics 22:1–14
Eaton M (2004) Geron Corporation and the Role of Ethics Advice. In :Ethics and the
Business of Bioscience. Stanford University Press, 490–511
Eaton M (2005) Affymetrix, Inc., Using Corporate Ethics Advice. In: BioIndustry
Ethics. Elsevier Inc., 219–249
Food and Drug Administration FDA (2002) Notice of Opportunity for Hearing,
James Wilson MD PhD, Institute for Gene Therapy, University of Pennsylvania,
February 8. Available from URL: http://www.fda.gov/foi/nooh/Wilson.htm
Food and Drug Administration FDA (2004) FDA launches a multi-pronged strategy to
strengthen safeguards for children treated with antidepressant medications. FDA
News, October 15. Available from URL: http://www.fda.gov/bbs/topics/news/2004/
NEW01124.html
Fuhrmans V, Naik G (2002) In Europe, drug makers fight against mandatory price
cuts. Wall Street Journal, June 7, A1
Garattini S (1997) Are me-too drugs justified? Journal of Nephrology 10:283–294
Gellman B (2000) An unequal calculus of life and death; As millions perished in pan-
demic, firms debated access to drugs; Players in the debate over drug availability
and pricing. Washington Post, December 27, A1
Ethical Issues Associated with Pharmaceutical Innovation 61
Gold R (2002) Minnesota joins list of states suing firms over drug prices. Wall Street
Journal, June 19, D3
Harrington A (ed) (1999) The Placebo Effect: An Interdisciplinary Exploration. Har-
vard University Press; Cambridge, MA
Hartog R (1993) Essential and non-essential drugs marketed by the 20 largest Euro-
pean pharmaceutical companies in developing countries. Social Science & Medi-
cine 37:897–04
Hollon MF (1999) Direct-to-consumer marketing of prescription drugs: Creating
consumer demand. Journal of the American Medical Association, 281:382–384
Hensley S (2004) As drug ad spending rises, a look at four campaigns. Wall Street
Journal, February 9, R9
Hensley S (2005) In switch, J&J gives straight talk on drug risks in new ads. Wall
Street Journal, March 21, B1
Jost TS (2000) The globalization of health law: the case of permissibility of placebo-
based research. American Journal of Law and Medicine, 26:175–186
Kaiser Family Foundation (2003) Impact of direct-to-consumer advertising on pre-
scription drug spending, June. Available from URL: http://www.kff.org/rxdrugs/
6084-index.cfm
Kennedy D (2003) When the price is wrong. Science 301:895
Kennedy D (2004) The old file drawer problem. Science 305:451
Kleinke JD, Gottlieb S (1998) Is the FDA approving drugs too fast? Probably not- but
drug recalls have sparked debate. British Medical Journal 317:899
Kucukarslan S, Hakim Z, Sullivan D et al. (1993) Points to consider about prescrip-
tion drug prices: an overview of federal policy and pricing studies. Clinical Ther-
apeutics 15:726–738
Greenwood Hon. JC (2004) Letter to Bernard J. Poussot, President, Wyeth Pharma-
ceuticals, from Greenwood, Chairman, Subcommittee on Oversight and Investi-
gations, U.S. House of Representatives, February 3. Available from URL:
http://energycommerce.house.gov/108/Letters/02032004_1202.htm
Levine RJ (1988) Compensation for research-induced injury. In: Ethics and Regula-
tion of Clinical Research, Yale University Press, 155–161
Lie RK, Emanuel E, Grady C et al. (2004) The standard of care debate: the Declara-
tion of Helsinki versus the international consensus opinion. Journal of Medical
Ethics 30:190–193
Masters BA (2004) New York sues Paxil maker over studies on children. Washington
Post. June 3, E124
Mathews AW, Martinez B (2004) Warning signs, e-mails suggest Merck knew Vioxx’s
dangers at early stage. Wall Street Journal. November 1, A1
Moses H III, Braunwald E, Martin JB et al. (2002) Collaborating with industry –
Choices for the academic medical center. New England Journal of Medicine
347:1371–1375
Niiler E (2000) Company, academics argue over data. Nature Biotechnology 18:1235
Perinatal HIV intervention research in developing countries workshop participants.
Consensus statement: science, ethics, and the future of research into maternal
infant transmission of HIV-1 (1999) Lancet 353:832–835
Pines WL (1999) A history and perspective on direct-to-consumer promotion. Food
and Drug Law Journal 54:489
Rennie D (1999) Fair conduct and fair reporting of clinical trials. Journal of the
American Medical Association 282:1766–1788
24
This article stated that the FDA had not approved Paxil for use in children, but,
since physicians can prescribe drugs for non-approved uses, more than 2.1 mil-
lion Paxil prescriptions for children had been written in 2002, according to the
legal complaint.
62 Margaret L. Eaton
Summary
This paper applies the metaphor of citizenship to business-society relations
because citizenship is concerned with power and responsibility as two major
themes in the context of ethical implications of corporate innovation. After
exploring and explaining these themes, we investigate the application of the
citizenship metaphor to corporations in three ways: corporations as citizens;
corporations deploying government-like powers in relation to human citi-
zens; and corporations as arenas for stakeholders to act in citizenship-like
ways. We illustrate how citizenship status, processes and entitlements of cor-
porations themselves, of human members of societies, and stakeholders of
corporations are structured. We consider the usefulness of our approach for
understanding corporate responsibility in the context of innovation as well
as for future research.
1 Corporate Innovation and its Societal Impacts
The debate on the ethical implications of innovation, in particular the use
of new and hazardous technologies, has a rather longstanding and well
established place in the business ethics literature (di Norcia 1994). Among
the papers in this volume, in particular the work of Margaret Eaton (in this
volume) provides an exhaustive overview over the state of the art of the
debate in particular from the perspective of business ethics. While this
debate has focused in the main on applying a philosophical perspective on
the issues, other contributions in this volume (e.g. the papers by Kuhlen,
Nuettgens, Seiter, and Selgelid) clearly reflect a more broader debate on the
wider societal and, in fact, political implications of corporate innovation
and development of new technologies. Innovation and the deployment of
new technologic options by private actors, most notably corporations, is
increasingly perceived as having fundamental implications on the con-
sumption choices, living standards and quality of live of individuals and
societies globally. We will confine ourselves to illustrating these more
recent shifts with three examples based on innovation in products, innova-
tion in production technologies and innovation in product distribution
and delivery.
64 Dirk Matten, Andy Crane, Jeremy Moon
For corporations, the nature of these debates reflects social and business
contexts within firms, among firms, within countries and among countries.
Recognizing that, like its related political concepts, the metaphor of citizen-
ship for corporations is essentially contested (Gallie 1956) does not, of
course, obviate the need for closer investigation into its theoretical appropri-
ateness.3
Corporations are generally regarded as the most prominent organisations
of contemporary capitalism in part because of the employment, production,
investment and wealth that they account for. They are now generally under-
stood to be non-governmental profit-making business enterprises owned by
shareholders who control the overall firm policy but managed by the agents
of the owners. Their legal identity is distinct from that of their members and
their internal governance regimes reflect government regulation and wider
features of their national business systems. (Albert 1991; Whitley 1999)
2
See Moon, Crane and Matten 2004 (432–434) for a discussion of the use of
metaphors in the analysis of business.
3
See Moon, Crane and Matten 2004 (433–434) for a discussion of essentially con-
tested concepts.
Corporate Responsibility for Innovation – A Citizenship Framework 67
over 700, mainly large, companies are members of Business in the Commu-
nity (BITC). BITC provides a variety of services and awards in the area of
socially responsible business through its national and regional offices,
though it emphasises that membership itself should be a step to a more
reflective and proactive style of engagement with society. There are similar
association in the USA (e.g. Business and Society). Internationally there are
other business associations to encourage more responsible business. CSR
Europe, the International Business Leaders’ Forum. Membership of the UN
Global Compact entails commitment to ten principles covering human
right, labour standards, the environment and corruption.
Another important development has been the growth of social reporting,
be it within general company communications, in dedicated social responsi-
bility reports, or within their annual reports. Some go so far as to legitimise
their reports through external verification and stakeholder engagement (e.g.
British American Tobacco, Nike). Various indicators of business responsibil-
ity have also been developed and adopted in tandem. Some of these reflect
agreement among corporations about appropriate reporting norms (e.g.
Global Reporting Initiative).
A new burgeoning of CSR consultants suggests that companies are pre-
pared to pay for advice about their CSR (Fernandez Young, Moon and Young
2003). There have also emerged new responsible business professional net-
works (e.g. CSR Chicks, Lifeworth, Association of Sustainability Profession-
als). A new business media on socially responsible business is also emerging.
This includes dedicated media outlets (e.g. “Ethical Corporation”, “Ethical
Performance”) as well as greater attention to these themes in the mainstream
media, illustrated by the “Financial Times”’ employment of a CSR corre-
spondent and recent special supplements of corporate social responsibility
in “The Economist” (22.I.2005), “The Independent” (23.III.2005) or the
“Financial Times Deutschland” (7.XII.2005).
So, in conclusion, there is plenty of evidence that corporations are at least
keen to be regarded as behaving more responsibly and there is also plenty of
evidence of resources being invested in organisational developments consis-
tent with this. What explains these developments?
2.2 Recent shifts in business-society relations towards the political
Having sketched something of the changing nature of business – society
relations we now turn to providing some explanation for the trends that we
have identified. This section is divided into two parts, the first addressing the
drivers of business power and the second addressing the movement for cor-
porate social responsibility.
Corporations are acquiring an increasingly conspicuous and, in some
respects, contentious profile. There are various reasons for this. Corpora-
tions have acquired a greater share of economic participation following
widespread privatisations; they have created new consumer markets; their
Corporate Responsibility for Innovation – A Citizenship Framework 71
cross border activities appear to have increased; and they have assumed
greater roles in the delivery of public goods.
First, corporations have acquired more commercial opportunities. In
many parts of the world this results from the waves of privatisations in what
were already capitalist economies witnessed over the last quarter century
(e.g. in Australia, New Zealand, the UK, the USA). Elsewhere this has
resulted from more abrupt shifts following the collapse of communist
regimes. As a result corporations have become responsible for more facets of
citizens’ lives than they used to be. In many communities, what was once
delivered, for better or for worse, by governmental organisations (e.g.
telecommunications, energy, water, mass transport) is now delivered by pri-
vate corporations. Although governments have tended to retain regulatory,
fiscal and organisational capacities, the tides of privatisation have not only
had the effect of increasing the corporate sector’s share of gross national
product and employment but also of yielding to corporations pivotal roles
in policy areas previously regarded as fundamentally political (e.g. invest-
ment in and performance of transport and utility companies; access to and
use of such natural resources as water, oil and gas).
Secondly, corporations appear more conspicuous because they have cre-
ated new consumer markets. This is most obviously true where there have
been recent increases in the range and availability of consumer goods (e.g.
China). However, it also reflects longer-term shifts in western societies from
‘the politics of production’ to ‘the politics of consumption’. The increasing
commodification of life is evident in such domestic activities as home
improvements, gardening and sports.
Thirdly, corporate cross-border activities have grown. Thus, corporations
are often more conspicuous simply because they are large and foreign rather
than small or medium and local. This is manifest in vast increases in national
foreign direct investment and international intra-and inter-company trade.
This is in turn predicated on trade liberalisation facilitated by political
reforms, increased access to developing economies, technological change,
economies of scale and scope, and cultural homogenisation. For corpora-
tions, globalisation thereby offers opportunities to increase growth, stabilise
performance, exploit new investment opportunities and increase market
power.
Fourthly, there is evidence of wider changes in patterns of societal gover-
nance such that governments have reduced some modes of exercising their
authority (see Moon 2002). In addition to the effect of the privatisation of
governmental responsibilities in creating new market opportunities for busi-
ness (see above), another corollary is that governments have actually encour-
aged corporations to contribute to wider governance activities. Similarly,
many western companies operating in developing countries undertake such
responsibilities in lieu of governmental provision be it in the provision of
pensions, education, worker rights and opportunities and environmental
72 Dirk Matten, Andy Crane, Jeremy Moon
Governments
Citizens Corporations
Governments Corporations
Citizens
Political community as
the arena of citizenship
the ways citizens can claim status by their participation in labour and
product markets and in down-sizing industries where governments may
have taken responsibility. Similarly, civil rights of prisoners are increas-
ingly a corporate responsibility as correctional and security services are
privatized. Governmental failures in developing or transforming coun-
tries shift the focus to corporations as Shell found in Nigeria when it was
implicated in the failure of the state to maintain the protection of the
civil rights of the Ogoni people. It is now suggested that corporations
should ‘step in’ when the status of citizens is threatened in such circum-
stances.
In terms of citizenship processes, corporate roles appear more indirect in
that they can help facilitate, enable, or block certain political processes in
society, rather than directly taking over formerly governmental preroga-
tives. Thus many political issues are now directed at corporations rather
than at governments (e.g. anti-corporate protests, consumer boycotts).
Hence, rather than replacing governments, corporations here could be said
to have provided an additional conduit through which citizens could
engage in the process of participation.
Second, corporations become active in the citizenship arena where
government has not as yet assumed the task of governing. Historically,
this was the situation that gave rise to paternalistic employee welfare pro-
grammes by wealthy industrialists in the nineteenth century. More
recently, exposure to this situation for multinationals is particularly a
result of globalization, where lack of local governance in developing
countries presents corporations with a choice as to whether to step in as
‘surrogate’ governments. Corporations such as Nike, Levi Strauss and oth-
ers which have ensured employees a living wage, and finance the school-
ing of child laborers have entered into relationships concerning entitle-
ments with citizens of developing countries. This possibility may be
extended by TRIPPS agreement in which large pharmaceutical companies
undertake obligations to provide free or discounted drugs where govern-
ments are unable to provide them.
In the case of citizenship status, there is evidence that corporations can
encourage or discourage oppressive regimes extending citizenship status as
under the apartheid period of South Africa and more recently in Burma,
Chad, Uganda and Sudan. More widely a new range of civil rights and
other status issues are emerging, in particular, issues of privacy and protec-
tions of basic freedoms, surrounding new IT and biotechnology industries.
These responsibilities often emerge because governments have not worked
out their preferred regulatory regime but nevertheless, can have massive
implications on life choices of citizens. Similarly, in processes of citizen par-
ticipation, corporations can act as a default option in the absence of gov-
ernment responsibility as in Burma where citizens dispossessed of rights to
vote might turn to lobby corporations.
Corporate Responsibility for Innovation – A Citizenship Framework 81
Governing body of
the corporation
Corporation as the
arena of citizenship
ment of corporate roles, for better or for worse. These roles can bring differ-
ent citizen status, process and entitlements for corporations, citizens, and
business stakeholders.
With regard to the topic of this volume the proposed framework actually
opens up a couple of implications not only for better understanding public
perceptions of corporate responsibility for innovation but also for develop-
ing approaches to tackle the issues.
– Thinking of corporations as citizens, they are participating in societal gov-
ernance chiefly by providing and using certain technological options. The
use of stem cell research, genetically modified organisms or genetic data
for insurance purposes has severe implications on entitlements of fellow
citizens. Key solutions from a citizenship perspective lie in the increased
provision of arenas of deliberation with other citizens and offering degrees
of participation to other citizens concerned by the technologies (Rennet
al. 1995). With regard to the development of new drugs for neglected dis-
eases (mostly of the global poor) a recent study (LSE and Wellcome Trust
2005) suggest that a key solution to approach this contested topic is the use
of public-private-partnerships in order to develop these drugs. In a citi-
zenship perspective this does not only reflect the participative nature of
the governance of (global) health politics but it also highlights the neces-
sity of protecting corporate entitlements, in particular the entitlements of
shareholders on securing viable economic returns while at the same time
assuming responsibility for major societal concerns.
– The perspective of corporations as governments exposes in particular those
situations where corporate innovation has put companies in a situation
where they directly or indirectly can either protect or violate fundamental
citizenship rights of individuals. This gets immediately visible in the case
of big pharmaceutical companies who, unlike governments, actually dis-
pose of theoretical option of providing drugs for treating diseases such as
HIV/AIDS, malaria or yellow fever. The companies in fact have a funda-
mental impact on how of basic social, political and civil rights of individ-
uals are shaped. It would occur then that companies discharge accounta-
bility in a similar way governments discharge accountability to their citi-
zens. This would in particular include accountability about their actual
cost-benefit situation with regard to the provision of these drugs or pro-
viding transparency about the way they shape global trade agreements
and influence political decisions pertinent to their business interests.
This becomes particularly evident in cases where governments do not
protect the status and entitlements of their citizens. In the Chinese exam-
ple cited earlier then a company such as Yahoo, rather than becoming
complicit in infringing fundamental citizen entitlements such as freedom
of speech and expression would assume responsibility in protecting these
rights through its policies.
Corporate Responsibility for Innovation – A Citizenship Framework 85
Bibliography
Albert M (1991) Capitalisme contre capitalisme. Paris: LeSeuil
Attaran A (2004) How do patents and economic policies affect access to essential
medicines in developing countries? Health Affairs 23(3):155–166
Barton JH (2004) TRIPS and the global pharmaceutical market. Health Affairs
23(3):146–154
BBC (2005a) Safety urged for child web users. www.bbc.co.uk/news, 18 April 2005
BBC (2005b) Yahoo ‘helped jail China writer’. www.bbc.co.uk/news, 9 July 2005
Bendell J (2000) Civil regulation: A new form of democratic governance for the
global economy? In: Terms for endearment: Business, NGOs and sustainable
development, Jem Bendell, Ed. Sheffield: Greenleaf
Bondy K, Matten D, Moon J (2006) Codes of conduct as a tool for sustainable gover-
nance in multinational corporations. In: Benn S, Dunphy D (eds) Corporate gov-
ernance and sustainability – Challenges for theory and practice. London: Rout-
ledge, 165–185
Crane A, Matten D, Moon J (2004) Stakeholders as citizens? Rethinking rights, par-
ticipation, and democracy. Journal of Business Ethics 53(1):107–122
Crane A, Matten D, Moon J (forthcoming) Corporations and Citizenship. Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press
Crane A, Matten D (2007) Business ethics. Managing corporate citizenship and sus-
tainability in the age of globalization. 2nd ed., Oxford: Oxford University Press
Crook C (2005)‘The good company. The Economist 22.I.2005, 9
Dahl R (1972) A Prelude to Corporate Reform. Business and Society Review, 17–21
di Norcia V (1994) Ethics, technology development, and innovation. Business Ethics
Quarterly 4(3):235–252
Donaldson T, Preston LE (1995) The stakeholder theory of the corporation: con-
cepts, evidence, and implications. Academy of Management Review 20(1):65–91
Elkington J (1999) Cannibals with Forks: Triple Bottom Line of 21st Century Busi-
ness. London: Capstone Publishing
Freeman RE (1984) Strategic management. A stakeholder approach. Boston: Pitman
Friedman M (1970) The Social Responsibility of Business is to make Profits. New
York Times Magazine, September 13
Galbraith JK (1974) The new industrial state (2nd ed.). Harmondsworth: Penguin
Gallie WE (1956) Essentially Contested Concepts. Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society 56(2):187–198
Harris J (1994) Biotechnology, friend or foe? Ethics and controls. In: Dyson A, Har-
ris J (eds) Ethics and Biotechnology. London: Routledge, 216–229
Häyry M (1994) Categorical objections to genetic engineering – A critique. In:
Dyson A, Harris J (eds) Ethics and biotechnology. London: Routledge, 202–271
Hertz N (2001) The Silent Takeover. London: Heinemann
Korten DC (2001) When corporations rule the world, 2nd ed. Bloomfield, CT
Langford D (ed) (2000) Internet ethics. New York: St. Martin‘s Press
LSE, Wellcome Trust (2005) The new landscape of neglected disease drug develop-
ment (A report from the Pharmaceutical R&D Policy Project). London: London
School of Economics/Health and Social Care
Manville B, Ober J (2003) Beyond empowerment: building a company of citizens.
Harvard Business Review (January), 48–53
Marshall TH (1965) Class, Citizenship and Social Development. New York: Anchor
Books
Matten D, Crane A (2005) Corporate Citizenship: Toward an Extended Theoretical
Conceptualisation. Academy of Management Review 30(1)166–179
Monbiot G (2000) Captive State: The Corporate Takeover of Britain. London: Pan
Moon J (1995) The Firm as Citizen: Corporate Responsibility in Australia. Aus-
tralian Journal of Political Science 30(1):1–17
Corporate Responsibility for Innovation – A Citizenship Framework 87
Introduction
Pharmaceuticals are a key input in health care systems. For many diseases,
they provide the basis of treatment or even the entire treatment. In OECD
countries, pharmaceuticals account on average for 10–15% of total health
expenditure1. In developing countries, the share of pharmaceuticals is usu-
ally higher (up to 50% and more), partly because there is only a limited
range of other, more sophisticated services available.
Patients in developing countries rate the performance of health care sys-
tems to a large extent based on the availability of pharmaceuticals. Atten-
dance rates in African clinics fluctuate based on the availability of drugs –
people show up for treatment if they know that there are supplies, and they
stay away when they hear from others that the clinic has run out of drugs.
Unfortunately, in today’s world we are far away from being able to secure
access to safe and affordable medicines for all people on this globe. This is
partially a problem of resources – there is not enough money to buy drugs in
many poor countries. But even if the resource gap could be closed by
increasing wealth or external donor funding, there are additional hurdles
that prevent access for poor people, such as corruption and fraud, distribu-
tion problems, lack of regulatory oversight leading to counterfeit and sub-
standard drugs being marketed as well as cultural and knowledge barriers.
Institutions like the World Bank work with governments to address the
systemic weaknesses in many countries. They provide funding not only for
the procurement of drugs, but also for system improvements, training and
capacity building. However, one characteristic of the pharmaceutical sector
is that most of the activities are private for profit. Not only are all major
global or regional manufacturers privately owned and run as for-profit busi-
nesses, also the trade and distribution is largely in private hands. Most devel-
opment country governments run their own public delivery systems which
1
OECD Health Data, 2005, http://www.oecd.org.
90 Andreas Seiter
Access Framework
Determinants Determinants
Drug Supply
User -Type Determinants
Location -Quantity
Determinants
Drug Supply Drug Demand
Location Accessibility Availability -Type
Quality of -Quantity
Products
User's Attitudes/ & Services
Determinants Expectations Prices of Drug
Acceptability Affordability
of Products Products and
and Services Services
Characteristics Determinants
User's Income
of Products and Ability to Pay
Services
Acceptability Affordability
Determinants Determinants
30% lower than the original, which is enough to generate significant sales with
relatively limited marketing expenses (the product is already well known, cus-
tomers are waiting for the first generic because they want to utilize the savings
potential). At such a price level, a generic product is usually very profitable, as
the manufacturer does not have to amortize large R&D expenses. This explains
why in competitive and prize sensitive markets generic prices keep dropping
until they reach a trough which is defined by the manufacturing costs plus
general overheads and a profit margin. This can be 10% of the original price or
even lower. At this stage, manufacturers that can make large volumes have an
advantage: economies of scale drive manufacturing costs further down – one
of the reasons why the Indian pharmaceutical industry is so competitive even
compared to other countries with similarly low labor costs.
Both innovative and generics manufacturers, assuming that they do busi-
ness in developed countries, must have strong capacities in general manage-
ment, marketing, manufacturing and quality assurance. The pharmaceutical
industry in developed countries is highly regulated and under significant
competitive pressure. Neglecting quality standards or mismanagement in
economic terms can lead to serious consequences including loss of share-
holder confidence and takeover by another company. For R&D based com-
panies, the shareholder value is defined by the “pipeline” of new drugs in
development and the expected revenue growth based on this pipeline. Many
companies that were household names a few years ago meanwhile lost their
independence and were “digested” in a merger or takeover after falling
behind in a less forgiving market environment. These dynamics must be
taken into consideration when thinking of pharmaceutical companies as
potential partners in development. On the one hand, a good corporate
image is important to create a positive business climate and secure customer
loyalty in developed markets. On the other hand, companies will only have
limited resources available for development related projects that do not
directly contribute to their present or future bottom line.
In developing countries, the managerial and quality standards in the
national drug industry vary. Several countries do not have the regulatory
capacity to enforce strict GMP (Good Manufacturing Practices) guidelines.
Economic ties between political and administrative decision makers and the
companies sometimes lead to favoritism and double standards. Another
problem is lack of capital to invest into modern technology and attract qual-
ified technical personnel for the operations of a state-of-the-art pharmaceu-
tical manufacturing plant. As a result, there is a significant quantity of sub-
standard medicines in circulation in developing countries. WHO, USP
(United States Pharmacopeia) and others regularly publish data on substan-
dard and counterfeit drugs2. This issue is at the very basis of Corporate
2
Matrix of Drug Quality Reports on USAID-assisted Countries, United States Phar-
macopeia, March 2005, http://www.uspdqi.org/pubs/other/GHC-DrugQuality
Matrix.pdf.
Access to Medicines and the Innovation Dilemma 93
3
2001: Drug firms withdraw from AIDS case, BBC News, On This Day, 19 April
2001, http://news.bbc.co.uk/onthisday/hi/dates/stories/april/19/newsid_2488000/
2488509.stm.
4
Accelerating Access Initiative, http://www.ifpma.org/Health/hiv/health_aai_hiv.aspx.
94 Andreas Seiter
5
Introducing Advance Purchase Commitments, DFID consultation note, 2005,
http://www.bvgh.org/documents/DFIDAPC2-pager.pdf.
Access to Medicines and the Innovation Dilemma 95
7
IMS Health, Global Insights, World Markets, July 2005: Looking to China and
Cancer as Cost Containment Slows Growth, www.imshealth.com/globalinsights.
8
Glivec® International Patient Assistance Program (GIPAP),
https://www.maxaid.org/.
Access to Medicines and the Innovation Dilemma 97
teria are defined based on insurance coverage, personal assets and income.
The program is administered by an independent third party; the application
has to be made through a physician who is registered with the administrat-
ing entity. So far, more than 11,000 patients in 80 countries are covered by
this program (outside the US; within the US Novartis runs a separate patient
assistance program). However, such an approach is only possible if the num-
ber of patients is small, like in the case of CML (chronic myeloid leukemia).
For more common diseases, other models need to be developed in order to
address the conflict between economically rational behavior of a profit seek-
ing entity and the equity goals of public health policy.
Table 2: Potential for collaboration between the public sector and multi-
national pharmaceutical companies in various policy areas
Policy Area Industry Expertise Alignment of Goals
Regulatory process High Medium
Good Manufacturing Practices High High
Forecasting and planning High High
Procurement Medium Medium
Pharmacovigilance, quality Medium High
assurance in the supply chain
Pricing High Low
Reimbursement Medium Low
Rational use of drugs Medium Low
Advertising and promotion High Low
Consumer education High Medium
98 Andreas Seiter
Markus Nüttgens
most used web servers (Apache 2006). From about 76 million web server
installations world wide, in February 2006, the Apache web server had a
market share of around 68 percent (Netcraft 2006).
Even governments begin to think about the usage of Open Source soft-
ware for public service purposes more often. One driver of such thoughts
might be the suspicion that sensitive data could be accessible for third
parties, if commercial software is used. A famous example that impres-
sively underlines that the publication of a software’s source code is no
security risk at all is given by the encryption software “Pretty Good Pri-
vacy” (PGP) (PGP 2006). In this case, the accessibility of the source code
greatly improves the security level of the software by offering third parties
the possibility to take an insight into the software to look for possible
problems.
These developments won’t leave the consulting business unaffected. To
give customers strategic advices for the design of information systems and to
consult a customer on the operative level during the rollout of solutions, the
competence portfolio must be extended accordingly. Thereby the consulting
companies decrease their dependence from single software vendors. Above
this, the possibility to proactively develop specific solutions arises. If this
development is performed together with the customer, a new dimension of
customer loyalty emerges.
In the following section the concept of Open Source will be explained
shortly (for a detailed introduction see Nüttgens and Tesei 2000). After that,
upcoming action options for software companies and consultants are intro-
duced and discussed with respect to the Open Source concept.
but generally not for licensing issues. Proprietary software can be consid-
ered as the opposite of the Open Source concept. The usage, distribution
or modification of proprietary software generally requires an approval by
the copyright owner.
2.1 The Genesis of Open Source
Ever since the very beginning of software development in the 1960s and
1970s, programs were shared among development teams for reading, chang-
ing or reusing purposes (software sharing communities). In 1982 the com-
panies IBM, HP and DEC released commercial versions of the UNIX opera-
tion system for their own hardware. Members of various research teams
(from universities or even other companies) were recruited and they worked
on commercial software to a greater extent from then on. The simple com-
munication infrastructure started to become increasingly insufficient and so
the software sharing communities slowly started to dissolve. A vacuum orig-
inated within the software production area that motivated companies to fill
it with commercial software. This development resulted in the decrease of so
called free software. Companies and research institutions decided so use
proprietary software to a greater extent. The technological development sup-
ported this trend as operating systems were often directly dependent to
hardware so that all processors needed their own proprietary operating sys-
tem very soon.
For reanimating the cooperative spirit of the software sharing commu-
nities, the former MIT employee Richard Stallman initiated the GNU
(GNU’s not UNIX) project and founded the Free Software Foundation
(FSF) (see Stallman 2006; FSF 2006). At that time, the project goal was to
104 Markus Nüttgens
10. If you treat your beta-testers as if they’re your most valuable resource,
they will respond by becoming your most valuable resource.
11. The next best thing to having good ideas is recognizing good ideas from
your users. Sometimes the latter is better.
12. Often, the most striking and innovative solutions come from realizing
that your concept of the problem was wrong.
13. “Perfection (in design) is achieved not when there is nothing more to
add, but rather when there is nothing more to take away.” (Antoine de
Saint-Exupéry)
14. Any tool should be useful in the expected way, but a truly great tool lends
itself to uses you never expected.
15. Provided the development coordinator has a communications medium
at least as good as the internet and knows how to lead without coercion,
many heads are inevitably better than one.
On the basis of this development model, a complementary distribution
model for open source products was established. Developers provide their
software on the internet. Interested users can search for software on their
own, test and use it. Also users can get into direct email contact with the
developers and thereby participate in the development of the software.
Another possibility is given by the distribution of software bundles. Con-
trary to proprietary software, where customers have to pay license fees, fees
for free software only arise for the service of providing. This means that free
software that is acquired once can be freely passed down to others. The most
common distribution types are (1) the download from the internet, (2) the
ordering and shipping of CDs or DVDs and (3) the free give away of CDs or
DVDs as attachments to magazines.
Consulting
focus
Industrial
Orientation 3 D 4
A
Software
Orientation 1 A 2
Development
Closed Source Open Source approach
Field 1
Description: Introduction and customizing of proprietary software systems.
Providers: IT consultancies in the area of office and ERP systems.
Field 2
Description: Introduction and customizing of Open Source systems.
Providers: Companies that emerged from the Open Source community.
These companies test, document and distribute Open Source
software. Consulting services offered include introduction,
user training and technical support.
Field 3
Description: Development of technical-organizational solutions by the
usage of proprietary software systems.
Providers: Process consultancies with high industrial sector compe-
tences that implement proprietary software systems on the
basis of business process analysis.
Field 4
Description: Development of technical-organizational solutions by the
usage of Open Source systems.
Providers: Consultancies that develop and implement solutions by
using specific Open Source systems that may have been self-
developed or extended.
If one reflects the described potentials of Open Source systems and then
assesses them superior to proprietary solutions, the conclusion is that posi-
tions within field 1 and 3 will lead to competitive disadvantages in the
108 Markus Nüttgens
In the short- and mid-term, pure Open Source providers also have the
possibility to move from field 2 to field 1 to link successful proprietary sys-
tems with Open Source systems or to transform proprietary software into
Open Source projects. This reveals that the adaptation strategies of the pres-
ent software vendors must be considered as well.
4 Outlook
The concept of Open Source offers an alternative way for developing and
distributing software. It combines already existing knowledge about software
development and software distribution and effects of the internet economy.
Due to the increasing standardization level of royalty-free software interfaces
and formats, the importance of proprietary software solutions is assumed to
decrease accordingly. If the service levels are comparable, customers feel
more attracted to Open Source distributors to avoid strategic dependencies
on vendors of proprietary software solutions. Present software costs will
remain existent to some extent, but in the context of Open Source, these
costs are no longer software license fees but service royalties. Opened and
linked collaborations appear to produce more sophisticated solutions for
company problems. The potentials arising offer consultancies the possibility
to realign their strategic focuses. Today companies no longer ask the ques-
tion “Why should we use products whose quality and enhancement is not
guaranteed by any company?” but rather “Why should we buy software
whose quality is no subject to public discussions?” and “Why should the con-
trol of central systems be given into the hands of another company?”
In the field of operating systems, the Open Source concept is already
highly established – mainly because of the engagement of distributors like
Redhat and SuSE. Time will show if a similar development will take part in
the field of application software. The consulting business can play a key role
therein.
110 Markus Nüttgens
References
Apache Software Foundation (ed) (2006) The Apache HTTP Server Project. URL:
http://httpd.apache.org
DiBona C, Ockman S, Stone M (eds) (1996) Open Sources: Voices from the Open Source
Revolution. URL: http://www.oreilly.com/catalog/opensources/book/toc.html
Feller J, Fitzgerald B, Hissam SA, Lakhani KR (eds) (2005) Perspectives on Free and
Open Source Software. Cambridge et al., The MIT Press
Free Software Foundation (FSE) (ed) (2006) The Free Software Foundation. URL:
http://www.fsf.org
Müller M (1999) Die Philosophie des GNU und die Pragmatik des Open Source. In:
Open Source – kurz & gut, Cologne et al., O’Reilly & Associates, Inc., 17–19
Netcraft Ltd. (ed) (2006) Web Server Survey 2006. URL: http://news.netcraft.com/
archives/web_server_survey.html
Nüttgens M, Tesei E (2000) Open Source. In: Scheer A-W (ed) Veröffentlichungen
des Instituts für Wirtschaftsinformatik Saarbrücken, 2000, No. 156, 157, 158
Open Source Initiative (ed) (2006a) The Open Source Definition. URL: http://
www.opensource.org/docs/definition.php
Open Source Initiative (ed) (2006b) Certification Mark and Process. URL: http://
www.opensource.org/docs/certification_mark.php
Open Source Initiative (ed) (2006c) Licensing. URL: http://www.opensource.org/
licenses/index.html
PGP Corporation (ed) (2006) PGP Source Code Downloads. URL: http://
www.pgp.com/downloads/sourcecode/index.html
Raymond ES (ed) (2000) The Cathedral and the Bazaar. URL: http://www.catb.org/
~esr/writings/cathedral-bazaar
Stallman R (2006) About the GNU project. URL: http://www.gnu.org/gnu/theg-
nuproject.html
St. Laurent AM (2004) Understanding Open Source and Free Software Licensing.
Beijing et al., O´Reilly Media Inc.
Further volumes of the series Ethics of Science and Technology Assessment
(Wissenschaftsethik und Technikfolgenbeurteilung):