Meita Lesmiaty Khasyar FI Ontology
Meita Lesmiaty Khasyar FI Ontology
Meita Lesmiaty Khasyar FI Ontology
220855
Philosophy of Science
Ontology
YouTube link:
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=XTsaZWzVJ4c
What is Ontology?
The word itself comes from two Greek words namely: "Onto," which means existence or being
real, and "Logia" which means science, or study. The word Ontology is used both in a
philosophical context and a non-philosophical context. Ontology in a philosophical context, well
it's basically the study of what exists, what is being real, what is real. And examples of
Philosophical Ontology questions could be - What are the fundamental parts of the world and
how are they related to each other? Are physical parts more real than immaterial concepts; for
example, are physical objects such as shoes more real than the concept of walking? And in terms
of what exists, what is the relationship between shoes and walking? And why is Ontology
important in philosophy?
Well, philosophers use this concept of Ontology to discuss questions, to build theories and
models, and to consequently better understand the Ontological status of the world. And over time
there have been two major branches: Ontological Materialism and Ontological Idealism.
Materialism from a philosophical perspective is the belief that material things are just particles,
chemical processes, and energy are more real than, for example, the human mind. So, the overall
belief within Ontological Materialism is that reality of exists regardless of a human observer.
In Ontological Idealism, on the other hand, the belief is that immaterial phenomenon, such as the
human mind and the consciousness are more real than the material things. And the belief here is
that the reality is constructed in the mind of the observer.
In a non- philosophical context, Ontology is used in a different, narrower meaning. Here
Ontology is the description of what exists specifically within a determined field. For example,
every part that exists within a specific information system and this includes the relationship and
hierarchy between these parts. And, unlike the philosophers, these researchers are not primarily
interested in discussing if these things are the true essence or core of the system. And, nor are
they discussing if the parts within the system are more real, compared to the processes that take
place within the system. Rather, they are focused on naming parts and processes and grouping
similar ones together within categories. .
Ontology is the theory of objects and their ties. It provides criteria for distinguishing different
types of objects (concrete and abstract, existent and nonexistent, real and ideal, independent and
dependent) and their ties (relations, dependencies and predication).
The former investigates the problem of truth on three basic levels: (a) Formal Apophantics, or
formal logic of judgments, where the a priori conditions for the possibility of the doxic certainty
of reason are to be sought, along with (b) the synthetic forms for the possibility of the axiological
and (c) "practical" truths. In other words it is divided into formal logic, formal axiology, and
formal praxis.
In contemporary philosophy, formal ontology has been developed in two principal ways. The
first approach has been to study formal ontology as a part of ontology, and to analyze it using the
tools and approach of formal logic: from this point of view formal ontology examines the logical
features of predication and of the various theories of universals. The use of the specific paradigm
of the set theory applied to predication, moreover, conditions its interpretation.
This approach is best exemplified by Nino Cocchiarella; according to whom "Formal Ontology
is the result of combining the intuitive, informal method of classical ontology with the formal,
mathematical method of modern symbolic logic, and ultimately of identifying them as different
aspects of one and the same science. That is, where the method of ontology is the intuitive study
of the fundamental properties, modes, and aspects of being, or of entities in general, and the
method of modern symbolic logic is the rigorous construction of formal, axiomatic systems,
formal ontology, the result of combining these two methods, is the systematic, formal, axiomatic
development of the logic of all forms of being. As such, formal ontology is a science prior to all
others in which particular forms, modes, or kinds of being are studied." (2)
The second line of development returns to its Husserlian origins and analyses the fundamental
categories of object, state of affairs, part, whole, and so forth, as well as the relations between
parts and the whole and their laws of dependence -- once all material concepts have been
replaced by their correlative form concepts relative to the pure 'something'. This kind of analysis
does not deal with the problem of the relationship between formal ontology and material
ontology." (3).
b) Descriptive ontology concerns the collection of information about the list of objects that can
be dependent or independent items (real or ideal).
Notes
(1) "To the best of my knowledge, the idea of a formal ontology makes its first literary
appearance in Volume I of my Logische Untersuchungen (1900), [Chapter 11, The Idea of Pure
Logic] in connexion with the attempt to explicate systematically the idea of a pure logic -- but
not yet does it appear there under the name of formal ontology, which was introduced by me
only later. The Logische Untersuchungen as a whole and, above all, the investigations in Volume
II ventured to take up in a new form the old idea of an a priori ontology -- so strongly interdicted
by Kantianism and empiricism -- and attempted to establish it, in respect of concretely executed
portions, as an idea necessary to philosophy." E. Husserl, Formal and Transcendental
Logic (1929), English translation: The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff 1969, p. 86.
(2) Formal Ontology, in: Barry Smith, Hans Burkhardt (eds.), Handbook of Metaphysics and
Ontology, Munich: Philosophia Verlag 1991 p. 640.
(3) Liliana Albertazzi, Formal and Material Ontology, in: Roberto Poli, Peter Simons
(eds.), Formal Ontology, Dordrecht: Kluwer 1996, p. 199 (notes omitted).