Roger Cotterrell - The Politics of Jurisprudence-Butterworth (1989)
Roger Cotterrell - The Politics of Jurisprudence-Butterworth (1989)
Roger Cotterrell - The Politics of Jurisprudence-Butterworth (1989)
THE POLITICS OF
JURISPRUDENCE
A Critical Introduction to
Legal Philosophy
Butterworths
For Ann, David and Linda, again
The Politics of Jurisprudence
Butterworths
London and Edinburgh
1989
United Kingdom Butterworth & Co (Publishers) Ltd, 88 Kingsway, LONDON
WC2B 6AB and 4 Hill Street, EDINBURGH EH2 3JZ
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced in any material
form (including photocopying or storing it in any medium by electronic means
and whether or not transiently or incidentally to some other use of this publication)
without the written permission of the copyright holder except in accordance with
the provisions of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 or under the terms
of a licence issued by the Copyright Licensing Agency Ltd, 33-34 Alfred Place,
London, England WC1E 7DP. Applications for the copyright owner’s written
permission to reproduce any part of this publication should be addressed to the
publisher.
v
vi Preface
Roger Cotterrell
Faculty of Laws
Queen Mary College London
June 1989
Contents
ix
X Contents
References 258
Index 271
1 Legal Philosophy in Context
The internal view is that of legal ‘insiders’ who orient their thinking
in terms of legal rules treated as guides for conduct - whether
or not the rules are approved by such insiders. For Hart, however,
the internal view is certainly not restricted to lawyers. He defines
it in such broad terms that it encompasses many different kinds
of perspectives of citizens on law. The external view seems to be
restricted to those who cannot really reason with rules at all or,
for their own purposes, see no point in doing so (see Chapter 4).
Another way of looking at the internal-external dichotomy is
illustrated in the recent writings of Ronald Dworkin. Dworkin sees
legal questions as, essentially, questions of interpretation. One can
understand what the law is, in a particular community, only by
becoming involved as a participant in the ‘game’ of interpretation.
Judges and lawyers, of course, are so involved, and - according
to Dworkin - so also are legal philosophers. By contrast, on the
‘outside’ is anyone who rejects or avoids involvement in these
interpretive debates which determine the content and meaning of
law. Thus, Dworkin puts matters very differently from Hart. In
particular, because for Dworkin insiders - participants in the
interpretive exercise - actually determine the law, knowledge of
law is essentially restricted to these participants. They can and do
include ordinary citizens, as Dworkin (1977: 214-5) makes clear,
but it is hard to see that the citizen will usually be able to compete
effectively in interpretive debate with the professional community
of lawyers and judges on the meaning of laws. Consequently,
Dworkin’s image of the internal-external dichotomy seems to move
us closer to a parallel distinction between legal professional insiders
and other outsiders (see Chapter 6).
These brief remarks on areas of theory which will be considered
in later chapters at least suggest that the internal-external dichotomy
can refer to several different kinds of demarcation. It may focus
on the distinction of‘legal’ phenomena or characteristics from ‘non-
legal’ in many contexts - for example, with regard to rules, systems
of doctrine, types of reasoning, institutions or decisions. It may
focus on the idea of a distinctive Field of legal knowledge or
understanding, separable from other knowledge-fields; or on the
idea of a community of legal ‘insiders’, distinguishable from
outsiders in some consistent way; or on the idea of a distinct
professional practice of law, marking lawyers off from other
occupational groups or from lay citizens.
12 Legal Philosophy in Context
but also as behaviour (cf. Chapter 7); not just in terms of logical
structures and rational foundations of doctrine but also through
rigorous historical study of legal institutions. Thus, it might be
said that normative legal theory in general has not seriously
addressed the question ‘What is law?’. It has more typically asked
how it is possible to organise, in an intellectually satisfactory way,
the diversity of doctrinal materials associated with legal regulation.
But, in trying to answer this question it has often implied a great
deal about the nature of law in society.
This book, therefore, is a discussion of normative legal theory
which tries to adopt a broader view of what is required for an
adequate legal theory than that which normative legal theory itself
often presupposes. To remain true to that broader view the
discussion seeks consistently to read normative legal theory ‘in
context’; to suggest the wider implications of some of this literature
and what has promoted or inspired it, as well as to discuss its
major claims and arguments about law.
days upon the earth are but as a shadow in respect of the old
ancient days and times past, wherein the laws have been by the
wisdom of the most excellent men, in many successions of ages,
by long and continual experience. . . refined, which no one man
(being of so short a time) albeit he had in his head the wisdom
of all the men in the world, in any one age could ever have effected
or attained unto. And therefore. . . no man ought to take upon
him to be wiser than the laws’1.
Though such statements date from long ago they express honestly
and directly a set of assumptions which underpin the classical
conception of common law judging. According to the declaratory
doctrine of common lajw, judges do not make law2. They are, in
Blackstone’s words, ‘the depositories of the laws, the living oracles,
who .must decide in'alTcases of doubt’ (Blackstone 1809 I: 69).
The authority of law is seen as a traditional authority. The judge
expresses a part of the total, immanent wisdom of law which is
assumed to be already existent before his decision. The judge works
from within the law which is ‘the repository of the experience of
the community over the ages’ (Postema 1986:32). Thus, even though
he may reach a decision on a legal problem never before addressed
by a common law court, he does so not as an original author
of new legal ideas but as a representative of a collective wisdom
greater than his own. He interprets and applies the law but does
not create it. for the law has no individual authors. It is the product
of the community grounded in its history. Judicial decisions,
according to Matthew Hale writing in the seventeenth century, do
not make law ‘for that only the king and parliament can do’ but
are evidence of law, and ‘though such decisions are less than a
law, yet they are a greater evidence thereof than the opinion of
any private persons, as such, whosoever’ (quoted in Levy-Ullmann
1935: 56). Thus the judge is spokesman for the community about
its law, but a particularly authoritative spokesman.
Such a viewpoint could lead to apparently radical conclusions.
A judge could mistake the law (Postema 1986: 9-11; 194-5).
Blackstone (1809 I: 70) writes: ‘The doctrine of the law then is
this: that precedents and rules must be followed, unless flatly absurd
1
Calvin’s Case (1608) 7 Co Rep 1, 3.
2 See e.g. per Lord Esher MR in Willis v Baddeley [1892] 2 QB 324,
326.
26 The Theory of Common Law
common law is, above all, rational, excelling all other human laws
in rationality (Sommerville 1986: 89, 92-5). But there are probably
at least two conceptions of rationality at work here. Common law
entailed a kind of particularistic analogical reasoning making it
possible to link cases and compare precedents (Postema 1986: 31).
It could thus tolerate broad illogicalities arising out of particular
analogical linkages of ideas or cases. Equally, however, common
law is, for Blackstone, ‘a rational science’ of ‘general and extensive
principles’ (Blackstone 1809 I: 2, II: 425). Therefore, such a view
might permit illogicalities of detail within an overall framework
of broad principle5. Reason could, consequently, serve opposite
roles in linking detailed particularities or broad tendencies in legal
thought. There is, thus, no simple key to unlock the assumed
rationality of common law.
In particular, there is no key which an untrained person could
use. If the law is that of the community it is, nevertheless, inaccessible
to most members of the community, at least in detail. According
to common law thought, law is not natural reason but refined
or artificial reason which, as Coke asserted, ‘requires long study
and experience, before that a man can attain to the cognisance
of it’6. Although the law is reason, reason alone will not give mastery
of it. Experience of the practice of law (such as the common law
judge possesses) is also essential (Postema 1986: 33, interpreting
Hale), and apprenticeship is the most appropriate means of
acquiring it. Thus, obviously, actual knowledge of law is denied
to the community. This knowledge is necessarily - by its nature
- the monopoly of lawyers, who appear as the absolutely
indispensible representatives of the community in stating,
interpreting and applying the community’s law.
The point is strengthened by aspects of the linguistic history
of common law. ‘Legal ideas were transmitted largely orally, and
even the available literary sources were, as late as the seventeenth
century, written in a special and partly private language’ (Simpson
1973: 21). After the Norman conquest the language of the English
common law courts became Norman French and then a unique
‘Franco-English jargon’, long maintained as such by the lawyers
for documents, despite efforts to change the language to English
by statute (Levy-Ullmann 1935: 123-4). Only in 1731 was there
finally a conclusive enactment making English, rather than Latin
5 Cf. Lord Devlin’s remarks in Hedley Byrne & Co Ltd v Heller & Partners
Ltd [1964] AC 465, 516.
6 Prohibitions del Roy (1608) 12 Co Rep 63, 65. Cf. Pound 1921: 61 •
Sommerville 1986: 89, 93-4.
The Political and Social Environment 35
7
Statute 4 Geo. II, c. 26.
36 The Theory of Common Law
8 Dr. Bonham’s Case (1610) 8 Co Rep 114, 118 (per Coke CJ). See also
Calvin’s Case (1608) 7 Co Rep 1; Day v Savadge (1615) Hob. 85; City
of London v Wood (1701) 12 Mod 669. And see further Chapter 5,
below, pp 121-2.
The Political and Social Environment 37
law, so Savigny notes that law ‘perfects its language, takes a scientific
direction’ and ‘devolves upon the jurists, who thus, in this
department, represent the community’. Thus it becomes ‘artificial
and complex’ and leads a twofold existence as part of community
life and also as the specialised knowledge of lawyers (Savigny 1831:
28; 1867: 36-40). This idea closely parallels the uneasily ambiguous
common law view of law’s relationship with community. For
Savigny, as for the common lawyers, it is vital to affirm that the
link with community is not broken, however complex law becomes,
for where else is the source of law’s utility and authority to be
found?
As regards legislation, its task is explained by Savigny, in terms
reminiscent of Blackstone, as that of putting settled law into
systematic form and clarifying law in transitional phases where
new legal principles reflecting the developing common consciousness
are emerging but not yet crystallised (Savigny 1831: 33, 152-3; cf.
Blackstone 1809 I: 86-7). There seems to be an important difference
from classical common law ideas, however, in Savigny’s recognition
that legislation eventually becomes central to the task of developing
the law, not peripheral and supplementary as it often appears to
be in common law thought. The appropriate scope of legislative
activity seems to depend on the stage of development of culture
which has been reached. Cultures rise, flourish and then decline.
In certain late phases of cultural development conditions ‘are no
longer propitious to the creation of law by the general consciousness
of a people. In this case this activity, in all cases indispensable,
will in great measure of itself devolve upon legislation’ (Savigny
1867: 34). It seems to be implied, therefore, that the eventual
dominance of legislation as a legal form is inevitable - though
hardly to be taken as a sign of cultural vitality.
A consequence of this more definite view of the eventual
pervasiveness of legislation is that Savigny is forced to make explicit
the strange consequences of treating the authority of legislation
as deriving from the same communal and traditional sources as
other legal authority - such as, particularly, that of the law-declaring
judge. The legislator must, as Savigny puts it, stand in the centre
of the people or nation ‘so that he concentrates in himself their
spirit, feelings, needs, so that we have to regard him as the true
representative of the spirit of the people’ (1867: 32). This awkward
and unreal formulation probably points not so much to a democratic
assembly with a popular mandate as to an enlightened monarch
with the common touch. But Savigny’s need to address the legislative
role in direct terms at the dawn of the age of modern legal codes
does seem to lead him finally to a different emphasis from that
Savigny: A Theory For Common Law? 41
Codes became possible with the discovery and diffusion of the art
of writing and, in some contexts, gave rulers or communities a
means of breaking the knowledge-monopoly of juristic elites. Maine,
like Savigny, notes the generally unsystematic character and lack
of technical precision of these codes. They tended to mix ‘religious,
civil, and merely moral ordinances, without any regard to differences
in their essential character’ because the separation of law from
morality and from religion belongs ‘very distinctly to the later stages
of mental progress’ (Maine 1861: 9). But we should note that Maine
intends in writing of the era of codes merely to mark the transition
from unwritten to written law. Accordingly, English common law,
presented in the form of written reports and records, is ‘only different
from code-law because it is written in a different way’ (1861: 8).
The transition to written law in the evolution of civilisations
is fundamental. Without it, Maine suggests, there can be no further
significant legal development. Unwritten custom, arising perhaps
for good reasons, may degenerate into unreasonable and irrational
ritual and be distorted by extension through irrational analogies,
since the law exists, inseparably from numerous interpretations of
its meaning and purpose, only in collective memory. A reduction
of law to writing fixes rules in such a way that they must be changed,
if at all, deliberately. It marks the end of ‘spontaneous development’
of law and the beginning of the possibility of law’s purposive
development (Maine 1861: 13). Thus, like Savigny, Maine sees the
question of the point at which codification occurs in the evolution
of a culture as being of the utmost importance (1861: 9-10). If
custom has already degenerated by the time it is codified the result
will be very different from a codification of living custom animated
by manifest reasons intelligible from experience. But whereas
Savigny treats early codes as merely clumsy and primitive and later
systematic and comprehensive ones as of value only to preserve
legal achievements from future cultural decline, Maine treats codes
- in the sense of written compilations of customs - as the keys
to all future progress, as long as codification occurs while custom
retains its vitality.
Thus, all major civilisations reach the era of written law but,
while ‘stationary’ societies show little further legal development,
‘progressive’ societies - which for Maine certainly included those
of western Europe but not many others (1861: 13-4) - continue
to undergo substantial social and legal change. Three devices are
available to allow modification of law to follow social change. They
are legal fictions (maintenance of legal forms while concealing the
fact of their operation in new ways), equity (principles distinct from
ordinary law but claimed to be able to supersede it by virtue of
44 The Theory of Common Law
What can be said of the relevance of Maine’s work for the concerns
of lawyers as an occupational group within common law systems?
In considering the period when Maine wrote and the decades before
Ancient Law appeared, it is certainly possible to see a modern legal
‘profession’ self-consciously shaping itself and building its status,
whatever may have been the nature of the occupational group of
common lawyers in earlier times (Cocks 1983; cf. Duman 1983:
ch 7). In the nineteenth century fundamental issues about legal
education and training began to be seriously addressed9 and, with
them, difficult and controversial questions about the nature of the
lawyer’s professional knowledge and expertise, about what the
student of law should learn in order to be well equipped as a member
of a modern learned profession, about the possibility of a ‘science’
of law comparable with the other modern sciences then flourishing,
and about whether and in what ways legal knowledge could be
considered autonomous, unified and systematic.
Maine’s writings are of great importance in this context. As has
been seen, common law - as portrayed in classical common law
thought - can certainly be considered to be knowledge which is
both esoteric and of central social importance. But it cannot easily
be considered a ‘science’ in the nineteenth century sense of a rational
organisation of ideas. Such a rational science ‘could never hope
neatly to capture within its four corners the rich, living tradition
of Common Law’ (Postema 1986: 37). Equally, as noted earlier,
classical common law thought lacked grounding in any serious
historical inquiry10. It existed in substantial isolation from
knowledge of other legal systems or methods (Feaver 1969: 45;
Pocock 1957: ch 3). Finally, it lacked any rigorous intellectual
criteria separating it from other branches of learning. Its relationship
11 Report from the Select Committee on Legal Education no. 686 (1846).
Historical Jurisprudence and the Legal Profession 49
and to escape the idea that law was no more than an ‘occult science’
vastly inferior to the real sciences explaining the nature and progress
of civilisation. His work did not offer a conception of a manageable
professional knowledge.
Thus, with the eclipse of historical jurisprudence, the problem
of finding a normative legal theory compatible with common law
thought seems no nearer solution. Maine’s writings pointed not
towards normative legal theory but instead to the value of what
has been called, in the previous chapter, empirical legal theory
- theory aimed at explaining the nature of law in terms of its social
origins and effects. Maine is, to this day, treated as a significant
figure in the history of anthropology and his work exerted major
influence on the development of sociology, including sociology of
law.
Even here, however, we should keep clearly in mind that he
was, first and foremost, a jurist. To some extent, Maine is closer
to Savigny, to whom culture appeared merely as the motif which
made sense of law’s claims to doctrinal integrity, than he is to
modern social science. He was not a ‘thorough sociologist’ (Burrow
1966: 151) and many writers have commented on his unreliable
use of empirical evidence. Adherents of historical jurisprudence
distanced themselves from the writings and outlook of sociologists
(Collini, Winch and Burrow 1983: 213, 220). Equally, historical
jurisprudence in England had a different orientation from
anthropology. Whereas the latter appeared to take all mankind
as its province, the former, as Maine established it, was concerned
only with those peoples whose cultural history fed into what was
seen as the evolution of civilisation (Collini, Winch and Burrow
1983: 212). Historical jurisprudence traced a line of descent of
civilisation, validated essentially in terms of the historical
development of comparable legal ideas and institutions and
grounded in assumptions about an original Aryan family of peoples.
Maine wrote: ‘Civilisation is nothing more than a name for the
old order of the Aryan world, dissolved but perpetually re¬
constituting itself under a vast variety of solvent influences’ (1875b:
230). It is almost as though the seventeenth century appeal to an
ultimate timeless and mystical cultural foundation of common law
in the idea of the ‘ancient constitution’ is resurrected in the idea
of the timeless cultural unity of the Aryan world. The unity
underpinning Maine’s thought, like that of common law thought,
is a unity of culture.
If such a unity is hardly satisfactory to ground a normative legal
theory, where else might one look for foundations? Having followed
assumptions of classical common law thought to what may seem
The Fate of Maine’s New Science 51
Law as Government
Since the consequences of this view of law are important to many
aspects of Austin’s legal theory it is worth commenting further
on it before considering Austin’s other claims with regard to the
idea of law as a species of command. In a sense, law is, for him,
effective government. Certainly a directive relating to a particular
occasion would not be a law. Even here, however, Austin recognises
that particular commands issued by a law-making authority may,
in practice, sometimes be called laws. The lectures hardly suggest
that this incorrect usage raises an important issue of principle for
him (Austin 1832: 19; cf. Neumann 1986: 220). When, later, he
discusses civil and political liberties, the contrast with liberal theories
is made very explicit. Like Bentham, Austin has no patience with
the ideas of natural or fundamental rights. There are no rights
or laws which are somehow inherent in the human condition, in
human nature, or in the very essence of social or community life.
All laws, rights and duties are created by positing rules, the laying
down of rules as an act of government. Consequently there can
be nothing inherently sacred about civil or political liberties. To
the extent that they are valuable they are the by-product of effective
government in the common interest.
Austin’s lectures are generally dry and laden with cold, precise
definition and classification. But occasionally a fierceness breaks
through; a vehemence that reveals deep feelings normally hidden.
The discussion of liberties is one such place: ‘To the ignorant and
bawling fanatics who stun you with their pother about liberty,
political or civil liberty seems to be the principle end for which
government ought to exist’. Such liberty ‘has been erected into
an idol, and extolled with extravagant praises by doting and fanatical
worshippers’ (1832: 269). But, writes Austin, the purpose of
government is to serve the common good. The promotion and
protection of civil or political liberties is of value only insofar as
it serves that end. Limitation of liberty may in some circumstances
be more conducive to the common good than maximisation of
it. Austin obviously thinks that the word ‘liberty’ is a slogan which
can easily get out of hand.
Several things follow from this ‘governmental’ view of law. One
is that duties are more fundamental than rights. The individual’s
ability to make specific claims on others through the legal system
is derivative from the law’s commands. Austin’s command theory
of law produces this result analytically. Command and duty are
treated as correlative terms: ‘wherever a duty lies a command has
been signified, and wherever a command is signified, a duty is
62 Sovereign and Subject: Bent ham and Austin
Sanctions
Sovereignty
2 For the meaning I attach to the word ‘institution’ in this context see
p 3, above.
68 Sovereign and Subject: Bentham and Austin
right in this context (see Hart 1982: 221; Austin 1832: 277-8). The
existence of sovereignty is merely a political fact, not a matter
of right and wrong.
On one view, the ‘weak side of the “Austinian analysis” is this
transference of a legal conception to a sociological problem’
(Stephen 1900: 329) and certainly the grounding of the ultimate
authority to create law in a sociological consideration stores up
problems for normative legal theory. Nevertheless, it is easy to
see here the utilitarian attempt to be realistic, to avoid dogma and
abstract talk about arbitrarily assumed natural rights, and to avoid
sanctifying authority. Austin cannot resist speculating on why people
might habitually obey but for the moment that matter can be left
aside. Like the sociological question of how far state sanctions
induce compliance with law, it is not important to the analytical
issue of the location of sovereignty. All that is necessary for the
latter is the fact that habitual obedience by the majority of the
population exists. Where there is no such obedience there is either
anarchy (no recognised sovereign at all) or revolution (the
population is divided into groups rendering habitual obedience to
different authorities).
in the sovereign goes along with the need for extensive delegation
of sovereign powers, as has been seen. Austin praised the institutions
of local government and recognised the appropriateness of judicial
law-making and extensive rule-making in administrative contexts.
Nevertheless, in his writings on the virtues of centralisation he insists
that none of this delegation must be allowed to defeat the central
co-ordination of government by which rational utilitarian policies
can be consistently brought into effect.
In later life, Austin changed many of his political views, replacing
much of his optimism about the prospects for rationality in politics
and social organisation with a Maine-like pessimism. Centralisation
seemed less attractive to him with his fading belief in the potential
of government to direct society rationally, and with a growing fear
of its control by despots or mobs (Hamburger and Hamburger
1985: 185-6). Most fundamentally, Sarah Austin tells us that her
husband decided some time after 1832 that ‘until the ethical notions
of men were more clear and consistent, no considerable
improvement could be hoped for in legal and political science, nor,
consequently, in legal or political institutions’ (Austin 1885: 16).
Apparently, education remained the key to advance but the struggle
was now seen as a far harder one than had originally been envisaged;
perhaps, indeed, an impossible one.
Austin’s late and profound pessimism should not affect the
assessment of the ideas contained in his lectures. It should alert
us only to the fact that his ‘timeless’ concepts of ‘sovereign’,
‘command’, ‘sanction’ and ‘habitual obedience’ are not formulated
in isolation from specific political conditions. Like most elements
of normative legal theory they are conceptual reflections of a
particular time and place, transformed in a way that gives them
the potential to speak to other generations in other legal conditions.
In Austin’s case, however, these concepts are formulated with a
clear awareness of the sociological questions they entail. This
dimension of his thought has been almost totally ignored by his
critics in the field of normative legal theory.
Although Austin’s legal theory may still have much to teach, given
its serious attempt to view law realistically as an instrument of
state power, it is obvious that much has changed since he wrote.
The confident utilitarianism that emphasised social benefits to be
brought about by rational government and rational law was typically
also an unashamedly elitist view of government. It was seen in
Chapter 3 that the virtues of democracy do not enter into Austinian
calculations. The limitation of governmental power is not viewed
as an especially important concern. Liberty is seen as a by-product
of rational government, rather than as potentially threatened by
state power. The doctrines of the Rule of Law and the Rechtsstaat
- the state defined by and subject to law - are not reflected or
prefigured in Austin’s legal philosophy to any notable extent.
Constitution building and the careful legal separation of
governmental powers - matters which were of considerable
importance to Bentham - play little part in Austin’s thinking irv
his lectures. In the modern Anglo-American world, however, all
of these matters are regarded as politically of great importance.
They are also, typically, matters of serious professional concern
to lawyers. Thus, it is not necessarily only the defective logic of
earlier legal philosophy which has inspired different approaches
in the literature to be considered in this chapter. These newer
writings may also reflect different concerns from Austin’s, different
fears, different political experiences and a changed social (and legal)
environment.
This chapter is concerned with the work of two writers both
of whom can be seen, in terms of the theses of this book, as trying
to transcend - in radically contrasting ways - the approach to
legal philosophy adopted in Austin’s lectures. One of them, H.L.A.
Hart - Professor of Jurisprudence at Oxford University from 1953
to 1968 - explicitly builds his ideas in normative legal theory on
a critique of Austin’s jurisprudence. Of Hart’s work it has been
appropriately said that it ‘provides the foundations of contemporary
legal philosophy in the English-speaking world and beyond’ (Hacker
and Raz eds. 1977: v). The other major writer to be considered
84 Analytical Jurisprudence and Liberal Democracy
here is the Austrian Hans Kelsen, perhaps the most illustrious and
widely discussed figure in twentieth century legal philosophy. Kelsen
originally developed his theories in a continental European tradition
without reference to Austinian thought, but arrived at positions
which he himself recognised as having an affinity with Austin’s
analytical jurisprudence. Thus he wrote in the 1940s, three decades
after having laid the foundations of what has become known as
the ‘pure theory’ of law, that this theory ‘corresponds in important
points with Austin’s doctrine’ (Kelsen 1941b: 271). ‘Where they
differ, they do so because the pure theory of law tries to carry
on the method of analytical jurisprudence more consistently than
Austin and his followers’ (Kelsen 1945: xv).
Kelsen’s willingness to recognise these parallels is generous. His
work is far wider in intellectual scope than Austin’s and, outside
the Anglo-American world, has been much more influential. It is
based on a rigorous epistemology and a sophisticated philosophical
view of the nature of legal theory - matters which Austin never
seriously addressed in any comparable fashion. Kelsen’s writings
demonstrate his familiarity with literature in such fields as
psychoanalytic theory, political and social theory and anthropology,
as well as law and philosophy. Hart’s normative legal theory does
not show a comparable range. As will appear, it was constructed
primarily in conscious reaction to Austin’s jurisprudence, and has
since been refined and revised largely in the context of commentary
on and criticism of Bentham’s normative legal theory. Given the
contrasting intellectual contexts of Hart’s and Kelsen’s work it is
interesting that, while Kelsen draws significant parallels between
his own and Austin’s work despite fundamental philosophical
differences, Hart asserts unequivocally the need for ‘a fresh start’
and a total rejection of Austin’s jurisprudence (‘the record of a
failure’) in order to advance legal philosophy (Hart 1961: 78).
Kelsen’s legal theory was shaped in a legal and cultural
environment significantly different from that of the Anglo-American
common law world. His ideas are relevant to this book insofar
as they have had a significant impact on legal thought in the Anglo-
American context but also because they help to put Hart’s work
into a broader intellectual perspective in two ways. First, parallels
between Hart’s and Kelsen’s ideas help to show how themes in
Hart’s jurisprudence may reflect wider political concerns about
modern law which are not confined to the Anglo-American
tradition. Secondly, a consideration of Kelsen’s methods of
constructing his legal philosophy - methods which are radically
different from Hart’s - helps in evaluating ideas about the nature
and appropriate methods of normative legal theory which are often
Analytical Jurisprudence and Liberal Democracy 85
Most English legal philosophy was empiricist (in the particular sense
used above) in orientation between the time when Austin’s
jurisprudence became influential (from the 1860s) and 1953 when
Hart was elected to the Oxford chair of jurisprudence. Its dominant
approaches had come to be called analytical jurisprudence. They
adhered to Austin’s view that law and morality should be kept
analytically separate and that the appropriate subject of
jurisprudence was positive law. Analytical jurisprudence thus viewed
law as a human creation established through political power. A
primary object of analytical jurisprudence was to clarify the meaning
88 Analytical Jurisprudence and Liberal Democracy
conceptualism (see e.g. Hart 1970: 271, 274) and seeks to find its
concepts in the actual linguistic practices of lawyers, judges and
citizens.
Sociological Drift
First, the primary rules will not constitute a system but merely
a set of separate standards, so doubts as to how the rules relate
to each other or how far they extend cannot be resolved. They
suffer from the defect of uncertainty. Second, they have a static
quality since no means are available for changing them in deliberate
fashion, either generally or in their applicability to particular
individuals. Third, there is no means of establishing conclusively
when a violation of the rules has occurred or of systematically
enforcing them.
Behind this fictitious idea of what Hart terms a pre-legal society
can be sensed not only a vision of some simple changeless society
which an anthropologist might discover but also, perhaps, the image
of unguided, culturally determined legal evolution suggested in
classical common law thought, as discussed in Chapter 2. Such
an image has no conception of law as positive, deliberately created
and so subject to human interpretation and development. This
conception of doctrine as subject to positive development, which
Austin found in the idea of sovereignty. Hart finds in a further
set of rules beyond the primary duty-imposing rules. Their
introduction or evolution marks, for Hart, the transition from a
pre-legal to a legal order.
These secondary rules are generally portrayed as parasitic on
primary rules, power-conferring rather than duty-imposing, and
of three kinds which correspond with the three major defects of
a regime of primary rules alone. Thus, the secondary rule of
recognition is the simplest remedy for the uncertainty of the regime
of primary rules. It specifies what particular features a rule must
have to be recognised as a rule of the society. The rule of recognition
may be simple or complex. An example of a complex one could
be that rules are to be recognised as rules of the society if created
through a certain legislative procedure, or declared by a judge in
certain conditions, or supported by long customary practice. The
limbs of such a complex rule of recognition could be hierarchically
ordered so that the limb recognising legislative rules takes priority
over those recognising customary rules and rules declared injudicial
decisions. Secondly, rules of change remedy the static quality of
a regime of primary rules because they regulate procedures for
creating or changing other rules or altering their operation. For
example, they include rules governing the composition and
procedures of a legislative body, as well as rules allowing individuals
to alter their own legal circumstances: for example, by making
wills or contracts. Finally, rules of adjudication arenecessary to
remedy the inefficiency in operation of a regime of primary rules.
They specify means by which a final authoritative decision can
98 Analytical Jurisprudence and Liberal Democracy
Hart’s Hermeneutics
2
See Weber 1978: Part I ch 3, Part II chs 10, 11, 14, 15.
Judicial Decisions and the ‘Open Texture’ of Rules 105
Kelsen’s Conceptualism
Hart’s work has had and continues to have great influence in Anglo-
American legal philosophy. The same is true also of the prolific
writings of Hans Kelsen. Yet they have never had the same centrality
despite being among the most profound contributions to legal theory
in the present century. One reason is that Kelsen’s writings are
informed to a considerable extent by the traditions of continental
civil law thought rather than the specific experiences of Anglo-
American common law. This can be only a partial explanation,
however. After fleeing from Nazi Germany to Switzerland in the
1930s, KelsenTevenfually settled in the United States and spent the
remaining three decades of his life there (he died in 1973), holding
the position of professor of political science at the University of
California until his retirement in 1952. Thus, he worked for a
considerable period - writing prolifically - in an Anglo-American
environment. Equally, he made considerable efforts to explain and
interpret his ideas in relation to Anglo-American legal and political
institutions and the major tendencies of Anglo-American legal
philosophy.
The main reason why Kelsen has remained an outsider is that
his approach to theory is a thoroughly conceptualist one, in the
sense explained earlier in this chapter. In this respect it runs counter
to ideas rooted in the common law tradition, as well as, perhaps,
counter to broader cultural tendencies in Britain and America.
Whatever view we take of classical common law thought, it remains
the case that the Anglo-American common law tradition emphasises
piecemeal, case-by-case legal development, and what the sociologist
Max Weber termed ‘empirical law-finding’ (cf. Weber 1978: 785—
8). That is to say, concepts in common law are not imposed on
the law but are assumed to be drawn from the detail of case-by¬
case legal experience. Legal ideas are found empirically in the
Kelsen’s Conceptualism 107
3
See e.g. Kelsen 1967: 71, 221; 1945: 124, 126, 132, 198, 354.
110 Analytical Jurisprudence and Liberal Democracy
Plainly, in any realistic view of law, the machine does not run
by itself. There are, no less than in Austin’s time, people in positions
of power pulling its levers. What is the real significance, then, of
this emphasis on the self-regulating character of modern law? Its
purpose surely is to demonstrate law’s integrity as an independent
intellectual field and as a specialised field of professional practice.
The ideas of unity and system in law, which were noted in Chapter
1 as having considerable importance for the conception of law as
a field of professional knowledge and practice, are presented in
both Hart’s and Kelsen’s theories in ways which make strenuous
efforts to exclude political considerations or any explicit recognition
that law is an expression of political power. Admittedly, neither
theory is concerned to prescribe how law ought to be; both purport
only to describe (in Hart’s case) or provide the conceptual means
of interpreting (in Kelsen’s) law as it is. Thus, neither theory claims
Democracy and the Rule of Law 113
Conclusion
Why might this dispute about the relations of law and morality
bear on the question of whether any of the perspectives or concerns
of classical common law thought survive their displacement by
positivist analytical jurisprudence, from Bentham onwards? As was
seen in Chapter 2, classical common law thought assumed various
sources of law’s authority. Law was seen as rooted in immemorial
custom, or community life; in a transcendent reason, or the
accumulation of ancient wisdom greater than that of any individual.
By contrast, Bentham’s and Austin’s writings ground law’s authority
in the existence of habitual obedience to a sovereign, a purportedly
objective ‘test’ to distinguish law from non-law and identify legal
authority. Hart and Kelsen focus on the fact of social acceptance
of a rule of recognition or a basic norm as the fundamental pre¬
requisite for a determination of legal authority. Positivist theories
attempt to provide criteria of the ‘legal’ and of law’s authority
in specific formal conditions which avoid vague ideas of the nature
of the community or of social organisation, or of some transcendent
reason. Because common law thought identified the source of legal
( authority, not in the state or sovereign or in rule-governed
procedures of legal enactment but in reason or community, it
1 allowed at various times, as has been seen, for the possibility that
' - in theory, at least - some legislation or judicial decisions could
j be void either as abuses of legal authority or as misstatements
of the law.
Given this facet of classical common law thought it is unsurprising
that at times it related closely to natural law ideas (Gough 1955:
ch 3; Haines 1930: ch 2), which also claimed the possibility of
evaluating law’s authority before the tribunal of reason. The notion
of common law as something not residing in rules but in more
fundamental principles expressing a transcendent reason or ancient
wisdom had close affinities with natural law doctrines asserting
the existence of some higher (moral) law governing and providing
ultimate authority for the ordinary rules of human (positive) law.
On the other hand, natural law theory was always a two-edged
sword. In English history it was used to defend the divine right
of the monarch, as expressed in prerogatives, against the claims
of common law (Pocock 1957: 55). Equally, it could be used to
assert limits on, or a limiting interpretation of, the powers of
Parliament, as in Coke’s famous pronouncements in Calvin’s Case
(1608) (Gough 1955: 44-5). But appeals to natural law as a set
of principles which could control the substance of human law ceased
to be practically significant in England once parliamentary
122 The Appeal of Natural Law
Our concern is not with the long history of natural law theory
in Western civilization but with its particular appearances in the
modern Anglo-American legal context. In this perspective the
decline of natural law theory can be dated conveniently from
Bentham’s attack on natural law ideas in Blackstone’s
Commentaries. Bentham’s view that natural law was a ‘formidable
non-entity’, and natural law reasoning a ‘labyrinth of confusion’
(Bentham 1977: 17, 20) based on moral prejudices, or unprovable
speculations about human nature, went along with a profound
2 Although for Kelsen, it would be not the law as such but the content
of its norms which could be re-evaluated from a moral perspective:
cf. Kelsen 1945: 374-5.
Natural Law and Legal Authority 125
The key to the debate around natural law is thus the issue of the
nature of legal authority. Natural law theory seems to become
significant in debate at times when political and legal authority
are under challenge. In times of stability positivist criteria of legal
authority typically seem sufficient. In times of political turmoil
or rapid political change they frequently seem inadequate; legal
understanding seems to demand not merely technical guidance
about the nature of valid law but moral or political theory. Questions
as to what rules are valid as law become elements of ideological
struggle; a matter of winning hearts and minds for or against
established regimes. Some of the material in Chapter 4 hinted at
this dimension of the determination of legal validity. Kelsen’s efforts
to establish a pure theory of law are, in part, an attempt to protect
law from politicisation; an attempt made in full awareness of the
difficulties of doing so ‘when in great and important countries,
under the rule of party dictatorships, some of the most prominent
representatives of jurisprudence know no higher task than to serve
- with their “science” - the political power of the moment’ (Kelsen
1945: xvii). Indeed, Kelsen recognises that acceptance of a positivist
science of law, such as his own, may be possible only ‘in a period
of social equilibrium’ (1945: xvii).
Thus, it is tempting to suggest that the enduring appeal of natural
law arises precisely from its willingness to confront directly the
moral-political issues of legality which arise in times of disorder
and conflict, while positivist analytical jurisprudence presupposes
a political stability which it cannot, itself, explain or even consider
as a subject within the concerns of legal philosophy. However,
the situation is more complex than that because modern versions
of natural law theory have been developed in relatively stable
societies such as those of twentieth century Britain and the United
States. This suggests that legal positivism is seen by natural law
writers as inadequate even where political authority is not being
seriously challenged. Perhaps the best way to understand the matter
is to recognise that a degree of ‘instability’ as regards law-making
authority is actually built into the structure of stable legal systems
as portrayed by positivist analytical jurisprudence. This is because
key questions about how law changes remain apparently impossible
to address in modern positivist theory. This has been seen in Chapter
4 where it was noted that judicial law-making is, for Hart, the
exercise of ‘discretion’, which his normative legal theory cannot
really analyse, and is, for Kelsen, explicitly a matter of politics
outside the compass of the pure theory of law.
128 The Appeal of Natural Law
The historical legacy of the Nazi era has explicitly influenced modern
Anglo-American debates between legal positivists and natural
lawyers. One of the most direct confrontations, between the
positivist H. L. A. Hart and the American natural lawyer Lon
Fuller, centred in part on discussion of the way in which post¬
war German courts were apparently evaluating the legality of acts
done during the Nazi period and which were claimed to be lawful
on the basis of Nazi law (Hart 1958; Fuller 1958). More generally,
the influence of emigre scholars, who fled from Germany during
the 1930s and, in many cases, settled eventually in the United States,
helped to feed into Anglo-American legal and political
consciousness insights and dilemmas about the nature and authority
of legal regulation which experience of Nazi practices and policies
inspired (e.g. Neumann 1944; Neumann 1986; Kirchheimer 1961).
In addition, reflection on the character of war crimes trials and
their basis of legitimacy and on the ultimate foundation of the
principles applied to judge guilt in them, undoubtedly made the
issue of the nature and authority of Nazi regulation a matter of
direct concern in the Anglo-American world and, at the same time,
informed wider speculation about legal methods and reasoning (e.g.
Shklar 1964: Part 2) and the adequacy of legal positivism (Paulson
1975).
The 1958 Hart-Fuller debate is a good starting point in
considering the recent confrontation of legal positivism and modern
natural law in the Anglo-American context, and especially as an
introduction to Fuller’s influential ideas which will be the concern
of much of the remainder of this chapter. At the time of his exchange
with Hart, Fuller was professor of jurisprudence at Harvard
University, where he taught, with a break during the 1940s, for
more than thirty years until his retirement in 1972. As his biographer
notes, he is ‘unquestionably the leading secular natural lawyer of
the twentieth century in the English-speaking world’ (Summers 1984:
151).
Hart argues that the positivists’ analytical separation of law and
morality is an aid to clear thinking; it avoids confusing legal and
moral obligation. To say that a rule is a valid law (judged by such
positivist criteria as its being the sovereign’s command, authorised
by a rule of recognition or imputed from a basic norm) merely
asserts the existence of legal obligation. Whether one ought morally
to disobey an unjust law is a matter about which positivist analytical
jurisprudence can remain uncommitted, for moral issues are not
within its province. For Fuller, however, such a view is both
130 The Appeal of Natural Law
However, the important point being made from the Nazi example
is that the stable forms and procedures of law and the nature of
its authority are linked and Fuller is specific in his claims about
the consequence of disintegration of these forms and procedures
in practice in Nazi Germany. He suggests that the decline in
procedural propriety, in the internal morality of law, was so serious
that a legal system, as such, ceased to exist in Germany during
the Nazi period. Hence, post-war courts should not recognise Nazi
law. Matters of legality in the Nazi period should be clarified, where
necessary, by retroactive legislation. This claim about the non¬
existence of law in Nazi Germany is, indeed, one which other writers
had already made, and on the basis of similar arguments about
the effects of the procedural arbitrariness of the Nazi regime. Franz
Neumann, a distinguished jurist who practiced law in Germany
during the years leading to the Nazi accession to power in 1933,
wrote, observing Nazi Germany from exile in America, that ‘there
is no realm of law in Germany, although there are thousands of
technical rules that are calculable’ (Neumann 1944: 468). Another
eminent German scholar, Otto Kirchheimer, wrote to similar effect:
‘With the access to power of National Socialism the common legal
bond of a generally applicable civil law disappeared more and
more. . .’ (Kirchheimer 1941: 89).
Obviously a specific definition of the word ‘law’ is involved here
and Nazi regulation is being tested against it. But, in Fuller’s 1958
essay, no such definition is made explicit. In Kirchheimer’s and
especially Neumann’s writings, however, the concept of law
employed is elaborated. Indeed Neumann used it in major writings
of the 1930s and 1940s as the criterion for assessing general changes
in the character of twentieth century regulation and as the organising
concept for the most detailed historical analysis available in English
of the notion of the Rule of Law (Neumann 1986).
Neumann writes bluntly: ‘the National Socialist legal system is
nothing but a technique of mass manipulation by terror’ (1944:
458). If law is merely the sovereign’s command such a system must
be recognised as legal. But if law ‘must be rational either in form
or in content’ Nazi regulation definitely does not deserve the name
of law. For Neumann, law is both voluntas (the expression of
sovereign power) and ratio (the expression of reason, or rational
principle grounded in general ethical postulates) and the legal history
of Western civilization is a history of the attempt to reconcile these
typically incompatible yet essential components of legality
(Neumann 1986: 45-6; 1944: 451-2). The component of ratio insists
that law be a matter of general rules, not special individualised
commands. It requires also that these general rules be clear and
predictable in application, not vague general norms providing broad
authority for virtually free official discretion. Hence, although Nazi
regulation made considerable use of technical rules, it lacked the
character of law.
Kirchheimer elaborates similar arguments. He sees Nazi
regulation as guided wholly by policy demands. These necessitated
technically rational norms of a purely provisional character which
134 The Appeal of Natural Law
appear later, even legal positivists have realised that this might
be desirable.
Fuller’s other writings make it clear, however, that his main concerns
about law’s morality are not with such questions of legal pathology
as whether Nazi law was too evil to be law, but with constructive
issues as to how to infuse the highest legal virtues into systems,
such as those of Anglo-American law, which he would regard as
far from pathological. The internal morality of law - the procedural
criteria by which Nazi legal tyranny is measured in the 1958 essay
- are discussed in Fuller’s most influential book The Morality of
Law, first published in 1964, as criteria also of possible legal
excellence.
In The Morality of Law Fuller distinguishes between two kinds
of morality or moral judgment. The morality of duty refers to
the basic moral demands of order without which mere existence
(whether of a society or of a legal system) becomes impossible.
The morality of aspiration, by contrast, refers not to a moral
minimum, but a maximum. ‘It is the morality of the Good Life,
of excellence, of the fullest realisation of human powers’ (1969a:
5). Duty and aspiration constitute the ends of a moral scale rising
from the bare moral necessities for any human achievement, through
to the highest moral ideals. Moral demands can be pitched at various
points on this scale. For example, a judgment about the morality
of gambling could stress that extensive gambling directly harms
society, the individual and the individual’s family in economic,
psychological and other ways. These ‘duty’ considerations might
suggest that gambling should be legally prohibited. On the other
hand, gambling on a small scale and for low stakes might not
seem harmful in these basic ways but only a matter for regret that
the individual can find no better use of time and energy. The
aspiration that people should live ‘good lives’ is not something
to which they should be compelled. We assume that law should
require the moral minimum, not try to force citizens to become
saints.
This idea of a moral scale enables Fuller to pose, as a fundamental
problem of all legal regulation, that of deciding where the pressures
of duty stop and the excellences of aspiration begin. Law’s
impositions must be sufficient to sustain duty but they become
tyrannous if they seek to impose excellence. Hence one of the most
important arts of law-making is that of judging for each issue,
A Purposive View of Law 137
each law and each activity or situation, what level of moral demands
law should operate with. But the demand for legality is itself a
moral demand. Therefore, it is necessary to decide how far it relates
to the morality of duty and how far to that of aspiration. Where
on the moral scale is the internal morality of law to be located?
In The Morality of Law law’s internal morality is first presented
negatively as ‘eight ways to fail to make law’. These are (i) a failure
to achieve rules at all, so that every issue must be decided on an
ad hoc basis; (ii) a failure to publicise the rules to be observed;
(iii) the abuse of retroactive legislation ‘which not only cannot itself
guide action, but undercuts the integrity of rules prospective in
effect, since it puts them under the threat of retrospective change’;
(iv) a failure to make rules understandable; (v) enactment of
contradictory rules or (vi) rules requiring conduct beyond the powers
of the affected party; (vii) introducing such frequent changes in
the rules that those addressed cannot orient their conduct by them;
and (viii) a failure of congruence between the rules and their actual
administration (Fuller 1969a: 39). Total failure in any one of these
directions, or a pervasive general failure in them (as with Nazi
regulation) would, for Fuller, result in the non-existence of a legal
system (1969a: 39). At this basic level, therefore, the internal
morality of law provides a minimum morality of duty without which
the existence of a legal system is impossible.
Beyond such rare pathological cases, however, the internal
morality of law is primarily a morality of aspiration; the aspiration
to maximise legality, to make legal order as good an order as can
be. The internal morality can then be expressed as eight excellences
which are the reverse of the ‘eight ways to fail to make law’:
government always by rules, which are always publicised,
prospective, understandable, non-contradictory, etc. Yet Fuller
stresses that it would be counterproductive to try to realise fully
all eight excellences in a working legal system. No system of rules
could function on such a basis but would collapse in chaos or
paralysis. For example, retroactive laws are sometimes inevitable,
not all legal disputes can be solved by existing rules, and rules
cannot achieve perfect clarity in advance of all applications of them.
Thus, the achievement of legality is not merely the acceptance of
a set of moral principles. It is a matter of judging the point on
the moral scale between duty and aspiration where each component
of legality, as related to each concrete problem of legal regulation
in the particular legal system concerned, should be set. And the
point on the scale will vary with circumstance and time. The
achievement of legality is, thus, a task requiring all the skills of
138 The Appeal of Natural Law
reason and fiat or ‘order discovered and order imposed’ and ‘to
attempt to eliminate either of these aspects of the law is to denature
and falsify it’ (Fuller 1946: 382). Classical natural law theory cannot
convince us that law can actually be pure reason; it cannot supplant
the need ‘for authority, for a deciding power’ (1946: 388)5. But,
equally importantly, positivism cannot convincingly portray law
as pure fiat (that is, a formal structure of authority) because the
legal outcomes of judicial decisions cannot be understood except
in the light of reasons for the decisions. In case law, reason and
fiat are inseparably intertwined. The judicial decision is an exercise
of authority but is also a search for, and attempt to construct,
reason in legal doctrine. The common law method entails an
appreciation of both fiat and reason in case law. At its best, it
keeps these aspects of law in balance.
Thus, Fuller suggests that an extreme positivism, which sees law
only as fiat, is ‘essentially alien to the American spirit’ (1946: 394).
It cannot adequately represent the common law method of legal
development. Hence the emphasis on ‘reason’, which in Fuller’s
later writings develops into the procedural version of natural law
represented by the internal morality of law, connects with a defence
of common law methods.
There is, however, more to this defence than a device for attacking
legal positivism. In Chapter 2 the image in classical common law
thought of law’s deep roots in community life was discussed. Fuller,
also, asserts in his writings that the case law of the common law
tradition projects its roots ‘more deeply and intimately’ into the
actual patterns of human interaction than does statute law (Fuller
1969b: 26). His concern over the years to understand these social
patterns and their relationships with legal procedures and
institutions gradually led him to deeper study of sociology,
anthropology and social psychology. What resulted was a body
of writing examining the social roots and consequences of particular
forms of law and of particular kinds of legal procedures and
institutions.
The most interesting aspect of all this for the concerns of this
book is the way in which Fuller’s researches led him to a kind
of restatement of elements of classical common law theory, but
in a sophisticated form which replaces the mystical images of
5 No doubt it is this point which, several years later, makes Fuller in
The Morality of Law - now explicitly accepting the label natural law
for his own theory - address that theory primarily only to the procedural
forms by which the deciding power expresses and implements its
decisions, and not directly to the substance of the decisions (as classical
natural lawyers typically have done).
140 The Appeal of Natural Law
6 For Fuller, ‘the task of the legal philosopher is to decide how he and
his fellow lawyers may best spend their professional lives’: Fuller 1940:
2. And see generally Fuller 1940: 2-4, 12-5.
Politics and Professional Responsibility 143
ideal. But like any group, a community in this sense has definite
conditions of existence. It can be said to exist ‘wherever there is,
over an appreciable span of time, a co-ordination of activity by
a number of persons, in the form of interactions, and with a view
to a shared objective’ (1980: 153). It is enough to note here that,
like the exponents of classical common law thought, Finnis sees
the moral and rational strength of law as grounded in its purposive
contribution to the continuance and fulfilment of a complete
community. Unlike the classical common lawyers, however he also
sees the need to make some effort to elaborate rigorously what
this concept entails.
Finnis’ ideas about authority and the Rule of Law can be
considered together. Influenced here, as elsewhere, by Max Weber,
he sees the basis of the authority of rulers not, for example, in
the consent of the governed nor in a notional social contract such
as Hobbes or John Locke described, but merely in the likelihood
of compliance by those over whom authority is claimed (1980: 249).
The existence of constitutional structures and the issue of whether
the ruler has the consent of the governed are relevant in asking
whether someone guided by practical reason ought to obey the
claimed authority; but this does not derogate from Finnis’s
surprisingly Austinian position that authority depends on the ‘sheer
fact’ of likely obedience (1980: 250).
On the other hand, a Fullerian view of the Rule of Law and
its demands is built on to this positivist conception of political
authority. Acknowledging Fuller’s influence, Finnis stresses
reciprocity between rulers and ruled as the foundation of the moral
demands of legality (1980: 274). Elaborating the main features of
legal order, Finnis produces a general picture strikingly like Fuller’s.
Thus, law is a coercive structure but, more fundamentally, a system
of rules. It brings clarity and predictability to human interactions,
regulates its own creation and modification, allows individuals to
adjust their circumstances rationally within a rule governed
environment, provides reasons for future actions, and postulates
a gapless framework of regulation. Finnis’ descriptive emphasis
on these characteristics seems to reflect a recognition of the
importance of technical imperatives in the application of legal rules
which no modern legal positivist could quarrel with. The Rule of
Law, then, as in Fuller’s characterisation of legality, is the
requirement to make these elements of rule-governed reliability and
predictability as pervasive as possible in a legal order. And, like
Fuller, Finnis emphasises the reciprocal relationship between ruler
and ruled (together with the virtue of maximising the dignity of
individuals as free, responsible agents) as the foundation of the
Natural Law Tamed? 149
622). But this involves ‘new rules, then new premises, and finally
a systematic body of principles as a fresh start for juristic
development’ (1908: 612), so there is no suggestion that legislation
is restricted merely to consolidation. For Pound its role is dynamic,
not passive; to move law forward in the light of modern social
needs when other forces of legal development are failing. Reading
Pound s early essays one is made to see legislative action as a kind
of shock treatment to get the heart of common law beating regularly
again. It follows that, given this importance of legislation, lawyers
must become knowledgeable in its techniques and effective
professional advocates in debates about its content. Hence, in the
twentieth century, according to Pound, such a role demands lawyers’
attention to social science which provides important material in
these debates.
It is also clear from these essays that, for Pound, the reason
why legal doctrine as developed by the courts has reached an impasse
is that the essence of common law method has not been followed.
Courts have adopted blindly deductive reasoning - ‘mechanical
jurisprudence - antithetical to the common law concern with
precepts in relation to their ‘conditions of application’ (1980: 611-
2). The time-honoured methods of common law require in modern
conditions that lawyers make use of the sources of knowledge of
community values and needs which modern social science can
provide.
The St. Paul address, although atypical of Pound’s work in its
sharp criticism of professional practices, usefully highlights some
of his early, central, practical reformist concerns which help to
explain the direction which his normative legal theory takes. The
address notes criticism of common law methods for their
individualist emphasis in a society which attaches increasing
attention to broad social interests. It seems to follow, then, that
a theory in defence of common law methods in contemporary
conditions should direct attention systematically to these social
interests and show how they are and should be taken into account
m the adjudicative and lawmaking processes. Equally, if a cause
o dissatisfaction is the distortion of broad social issues into matters
of private dispute, it is surely necessary to show how individual
and social concerns can be kept analytically distinct, considered
on their own separate planes: individual against individual, social
against social; with disputes of broad consequences being considered
primarily in terms of the social issues raised, rather than confused
wdh private or individual concerns. Again, if litigation seems too
much like a game, perhaps what is needed is a theory of the
adjudicative process emphasising its objective character: as a
The Outlook of Sociological Jurisprudence 159
A Theory of Interests
4
Cf. Chapter 3, above, p. 80.
162 The Problem of the Creative Judge
law are significant for the interpretation of rules but deny that
the model of rules needs amendment to accept these elements as
essential components of law. In effect, much of what Pound treats
as precepts other than legal rules could be seen by positivist
analytical jurists as merely a segment of the discretionary (non-
legal) considerations which judges or other officials take into
account in making decisions in hard cases. The positivist image
of law would remain inviolate. The judge’s creative role would
remain legally inexplicable and legally unjustifiable.
Dworkin’s strategy is, therefore, to show that principles, whj^
as legal aut horities which cannot be ignored; that .they are essential
(not optional_ptL.discretlQoar,vi elements in reaching, decisions in
hard cases. Indeed, Dworkin seeks to arnue..lh.amimJili..cases a
structure of legal principles stands behind and informs the applicable
rules. The only difference, then, between a hard and simpTe~case
is that in the latter the relationship between applicable principles
and relevant rules is seen byTHe deciding court ar interpreters
of the courfs decision as clear and unproblematic.
A favourite illustration, in Dworkin s writings, of legal principles
is the American case of Riggs v Palmer6 in which the New York
State Court of Appeals refused to allow Elmer Palmer to inherit
property as a beneficiary under the will of his grandfather, whom
he had murdered by poisoning. The applicable legal rule appears
to be that legacies contained in legally valid testamentary
dispositions are to be guaranteed by law in accordance with the
wishes of the testator. Yet the court in Riggs v Palmer consciously
decides not to apply the rule and does scrby-relying” on a general
principle that a wrongdoer should not be allowed to profit from
hl$ own wrori^TTfis not judicial discretion which oaerates to defeat
TTvT^dma^juje as to legacies but an-interpretation of the rule
in the light of a governing principle. ' And the principle here is
legal since If l^not-taken Qut.oftfmmr as amurelv discretionary
invention of the court but is one which has its own legal history
as something developed, applied and interpreted in earlier cases
and,in reiationJ^iffieientJegairules and circumstances.
This is not to say that because law contains principles as well
as rules, the former are to be equated with the latter. While legal
rules mav be identifiable bv using some positivist test expressed
in terms of rules of recognition, basic norm or sovereign command,
legal principles cannot be so identified. They emerge, flourish and
decline gradually through their recognition, elaboration and perhaps
6
(1889) 115 NY 506. See Dworkin 1977: 23; 1986: 15-20.
170 The Problem of the Creative Judge
opposite views. Can law control its own destiny from its own
resources - is it morally and politically autonomous in that sense;
or is it essentially an instrument of political power, subject to control
and direction from beyond its own doctrinal resources?
In Dworkin’s recent writings it is made clear that the organicist
conception triumphs. In other words, for Dworkin, as for Pound,
the common law judge should still dominate the legal system. One
might be forgiven for thinking that as long as rules can be
distinguished from principles and understood in positivist fashion,
they import into the arena of judicial interpretation normative
material which the judge cannot but give effect to; the material
controls him. Thus, insofar as law consists of policy-shaped
legislative rules, the judge can only be an instrument of policy
without independent creativity. Yet, as has been seen, for Dworkin,
principles control the interpretation of rules. Hence, the rule-
principle distinction has lost much significance in his recent writings.
Principles are expressed through rules; rules derive their meaning
from principles. Law is entirely a matter of interpretation. In this
specific sense, no law is imposed on the judge. All law which comes
out of the judge’s decisions is the result of his creative interpretation,
whether of legislation, prior case law or ultimate constitutional
provisions (such as in the written United States Constitution).
It follows that, in a sense, principle trumps policy because the
interpretation of law derived from policy considerations must be
conducted in accordance with the judge’s obligation to fulfil the
elements of principle in law. There is no law other than that which
results from creative interpretation of existing legal materials guided
by the attempt of the interpreter to make the law the best it can
be.
Law as Interpretation
In recent writings Dworkin has used analogies with literary
int^rpretationuto^xplain the mdge’s obligation in creative legal
interpretation (e.g. 1982: 166-8; 1985: ch 6; 1986: 228-38). A judge
TsTTke a writer trying to continue a story started by earlier writers.
The writer must make the story as good as it can be. This necessitates
tfiM^lKTT^aclSsTSu^TSe^m^Knrv^rwhat went before (the
requirement of‘fit’), and must make the best of that existing material
by interpreting it irTHie most plausible and attractive way and
then adding a contribution which will further enhance it. Since
the task of the writer is to continue the story, he canoaLsitopiy
go off on his own literary troIic~but must create his own contribution
in a way that is consistent with the best interpretation of thetttSSdfing
174 The Problem of the Creative Judge
Law’s Community
But there is a price to be paid for this apparent theoretical advance.
What happens, for example, to the relationship hetweeaJaw j£d
community.wfpeh has been identified in this book as central to
classical common law thought? It becomes, for Dworkin, what it
is for classical common law thought: something wRTcFTannot be
examined empirically but only taken for granted. Thj&.is
the..theory offers no., external or
law’s relationship with community can be analysed. Here is an
176 The Problem of the Creative Judge
century failed; that it did not replace classical common law thought
but merely confirmed the inadequacy of the common law outlook.
At the same time, what might be called neo-classical common law
thought, of which Dworkin’s legal philosophy is the best example,
raises difficulties of its own, explained in Chapter 6. Above all,
it seems forced to give up any prospect of a science of law - in
the sense of a search for something more systematic and objective
than the participant perspective of a practical legal interpreter. Yet
it was precisely that search for systematic theoretical explanation
of the nature of law as a body of professional knowledge and as
a distinctive professional practice which, as has been seen, first
inspired and gave original legitimacy to modern Anglo-American
legal philosophy in Bentham’s and Austin’s work.
Is there a way out of this impasse? Suppose we were to retrace
our steps and go back to Austin’s original starting point for legal
science: the idea that a law is the result of a distinctive action
(in his theory the act of commanding), and is to be understood
in terms of those who perform the action (for Austin, the sovereign
or sovereign body) and the means available to make the action
effective (sanctions). Suppose that, without becoming embroiled
again in arguments about sovereignty or the specific form of law,
we were to treat these behavioural dimensions of law as the focus
of scientific inquiry in legal theory. And suppose further, finally,
that in order to avoid the problems encountered in Chapter 6 about
guiding values and traditions inherent in a legal system and
determining appropriate judicial innovations in doctrine, it were
to be assumed as a starting point for analysis that innovations
in legal doctrine are nothing more nor less than expressions of
the wishes, policies, or preferences of the decision-makers (for
example, judges) who create law. What would follow from such
positions?
At least initially, taken without qualification or elaboration, these
points of departure suggest a profound scepticism about normative
analysis of law. They suggest that doctrine is less important than
those who create it; that what judges do is more important than
the reasoning with which they justify their decisions; that values
are relevant to legal analysis only insofar as they represent the
particular preferences of influential decision-makers; that legal
outcomes reflect configurations of political power, not overarching
social or political values. But this approach might also be called
realistic, and seen as adopting the only starting points which make
it possible to do full justice to the original motivating assumption
of the analytical jurists - that law is a human creation, to be
understood as it is and not as it might or should be. On this view,
184 Varieties of Scepticism
1
See Chapter 3, above, pp 75-7.
Varieties of Scepticism 185
Hart (1961: 133) refers to ‘rule scepticism’ as ‘the claim that talk
of rules is a myth, cloaking the truth that law consists simply of
the decisions of courts and the prediction of them’. If, as seems
Sethis is intended to refer to Llewellyn’s theories (cf. Hart
1961: 232, 250; Twining 1968: 6), it is a serious distortion, yet
typical of the misunderstandings of realism often found, at least
Llewellyn’s Constructive Doctrinal Realism 195
3 See Llewellyn 1951: 8-10, 12; 1960: 511; Twining 1973: 148-50; cf. Hart
1977: 124.
196 Varieties of Scepticism
Period-Style
Llewellyn describes (1960: 24-5), for example, the ‘single right answer’
outlook (now strongly associated with Dworkin’s legal philosophy: see
above, p. 171) as one such matter of judicial style to be considered
sociologically.
Llewellyn’s Constructive Doctrinal Realism 201
Why has realism in this and other forms had little impact on
normative legal theory in Britain, while it received, and still receives,
much attention in the United States? It is important to note, first,
that the idea of realism’s limited impact in Britain needs to be
qualified by recognition that post-realist developments in legal
theory, to be mentioned in the remaining sections of this chapter,
are having an increasingly powerful influence on legal thought on
both sides of the Atlantic. Is it merely a matter of a long delayed
reception of realist ideas in Britain, rather than dismissal of them?
Orthodox contextual explanations of American legal realism
encourage an image of it as a product of distinctive historical and
political conditions in the United States. It is seen as a consequence
of the extraordinary historical role of courts in American
government (Hart 1977: 124), and especially of a constitutional
framework allowing judicial review of the validity of legislation.
This emphasis on courts reflects a more general view of political
power as appropriately decentralised and dispersed; institutionally
through the federal system and the doctrine of separation of powers,
and geographically and culturally through the sheer practical
impossibility of imposing uniform solutions to all governmental
problems in a nation of such size and diversity.
More detailed analyses along the same lines seek to explain why
the realist movement arose in the early decades of the twentieth
century. It was a response to a crisis of ‘overload’ in legal doctrine
and the resultant inability of courts to operate a system of judicial
precedent on the traditional common law model. ‘Toward the end
of the nineteenth century the rate of acceleration in printed case
reports became nightmarish. Digests of all reported cases decided
Irom the institution of courts in the American colonies until 1896
- a period of over two hundred years - take up three shelves in
l,nLLarW Llbrary- Di§ests of cases decided since 1896 [and up to
I960] fill more than thirty shelves’ (Gilmore 1961: 1041). As Grant
Gilmore explains, not only were many more cases being decided
The Political Context of American Legal Realism 203
from the late nineteenth century as both the population and the
number of courts and state jurisdictions grew, but a higher
proportion of cases was being reported, especially as a result of
the establishment of the West National Reporter system in the 1870s.
When the number of reported cases ‘becomes like the number of
grains of sand on the beach’ a precedent system cannot work
(Gilmore 1961: 1041). And the problem in the American context
was exacerbated by the fact that most private law problems were
left to the individual states, and were left by the states to courts.
This now familiar explanation of the crisis which produced the
origins of American realism is usually supplemented, at least in
modern American histories, with a more specific political
explanation. Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes’ famous dissenting
opinions in the United States Supreme Court8 are typically seen
as a protest against the mindlessly mechanical legal logic of the
majority of the court at a time when (at the turn of the century)
American government was faced with immense problems of
adapting to social and economic change. What Pound saw as
‘mechanical jurisprudence (see Chapter 6) to be remedied by
legislative inspiration and a renewal of the traditional evolutionary
practice of common law judging, Holmes saw as judicial frustration
of the popular will for legal change by judges who imported their
own prejudices into their decisions under cover of legal logic. But
Holmes’ view was not realist in the sense of those legal realists
who adopted him as their mentor. While he claimed9 that courts
could operate objectively and leave the expression of policy
convictions to democratically elected legislators, the legal realists
tended to see courts as inevitably involved in policy decision. The
issue became what policies they promoted and how open they were
in admitting value preferences.
Thus, the orthodox story of legal realism sees its flowering as
a dominant legal theory in the 1930s as an almost inevitable
expression in legal thought of the political demands which gave
rise to Franklin Roosevelt’s ‘New Deal’ government in the same
period. These demands were for clear policy uniting all government
agencies to attack the fundamental social and economic crises of
the Depression era beginning with the Wall Street stock market
crash of 1929. Thus, for some writers, legal realism is essentially
the jurisprudential analogue of the New Deal (White 1972; Murphy
1972: ch 4). There is, undoubtedly, much truth in this. The urgent
need for new approaches to legal scholarship which would provide
Post-Realist Policy-Science
Las-dougalism
Judicial Behaviouralism
11
Lochner v New York (1905) 198 US 45, 76.
212 Varieties of Scepticism
from legal restraints, for example on their ability to own the stock
of other corporations. In this manner doctrinal development cleared
the way for corporate economic concentration, without ever
admitting that this was what really lay behind the changes in legal
ideas and the abstract arguments used to justify them (Horwitz
1985).
Horwitz’ essay is a good example of the most productive kind
of work which has arisen from the CLS movement. Doctrine and
its development is taken very seriously, but the motor of doctrinal
development is not considered to lie in legal logic, or overarching
values or traditions of the legal system (Pound, Dworkin), or mere
judicial discretion as proposed by positivist analytical jurisprudence.
The impetus for change in doctrine comes from outside the
professional legal domain, especially in political struggle and the
economic conditions, changes or crises of capitalist society. But
these real forces are not usually revealed in doctrine itself nor in
legal reasoning. Part of CLS’ objective is to reveal ‘hidden motives
that the judges themselves would treat as illegitimate if forced to
confront them’; it ‘requires the analysis of the coherence of judicial
explanations of outcomes. . .. But the goal is neither an alternative
rationale nor a criticism of the outcome’ (Kennedy 1979: 219, 220).
Instead it is to show how a judge’s formal rationale of the decision
(which presents itself as mere legal reasoning) obscures the real
political significance of what is being decided.
Another example of this kind of analysis is found in Karl Klare’s
examination of American judges’ interpretation of the 1935 National
Labor Relations Act, ‘perhaps the most radical piece of legislation
ever enacted by the United States Congress’ (Klare 1978: 265) and
one which ostensibly gave major rights to employees as against
employers and greatly strengthened the role of collective bargaining
in American labour law. Klare shows how, in a series of decisions
widely regarded as employee victories, courts applied the Act to
shape an institutional structure of collective bargaining which gave
unions power at the expense of individual workers and helped shape
‘the modern administered, and regulated system of class relations’
(Klare 1978: 336). Again the essence of the CLS method here is
to show that what doctrine appears to say is not what it does;
the narrow ‘logic’ of the cases is exploded by revealing in detail
the economic and political context in which it is developed and
how case outcomes relate to wider tendencies in American society
and politics.
To the extent that this kind of inquiry is intended to increase
understanding of the role and character of legal doctrine it can
be seen as related to constructive doctrinal realism and certainly
Post-Realist Radical Scepticism 213
This book has argued that normative legal theory has not been
able to give a convincing explanation of judicial creativity and of
legal development generally. This theory has tried to explain law
as a structure or system of doctrine without being able to dismiss
difficult empirical questions about the behavioural conditions under
which it makes sense to think in terms of such a system or structure.
Realist and post-realist legal thought is a recognition and expression
of this continuing problem for any theory which attempts to treat
law merely as doctrine or ideas. It can be argued that, in this respect,
normative legal theory has not provided an adequate theoretical
basis for understanding the nature of Anglo-American law.
To leave that as the sole conclusion here would, however, be
unduly negative, misleading and unfair. A major claim made in
Chapter 1 was that, despite normative legal theory’s frequent
pretensions to the contrary, it should not be understood as seriously
attempting to provide general theories of the nature of law.
Typically, normative legal theory assumes that law is centrally, and
perhaps exclusively, legal doctrine. It does not address the possibility
that law as an object of inquiry might better be considered to be
Some Political and Professional Uses of Theory 217
1
See Chapter 4, pp 99-100, 112-7; and Chapter 5, pp 135, 148-9.
Some Political and Professional Uses of Theory 219
Who is Listening?
understands its limited view as a total one; the royal route to legal
understanding.
To write of the lawyer’s perspective is, of course, to gloss over
the fact that lawyers’ perspectives on law can themselves be very
varied, that judges’ perspectives may be significantly different from
those of practising lawyers, that those of appellate judges may be
significantly different from those of trial judges, and that the
viewpoints of academic lawyers may also show much diversity and
vary widely from those of practitioners. Since most normative legal
theory has been produced by academic lawyers these points are
important. Nevertheless, what unifies all of these legal professionals
of different kinds is their generally substantial interest in and
knowledge of law as doctrine; an interest which suggests a broadly
different general perspective from that of many social scientists,
for example, whose focus might be primarily on behaviour, and
patterns of social relations, associated with law as a field of
experience and practice.
Many contributors to normative legal theory have been aware,
in one way or another, of a need to transcend a perspective which
treats law as structured and systematised doctrine in order to extend
understanding of law as a social phenomenon. Normative legal
theory represents often only a part of these writers’ work in the
field of legal theory. Fuller, for example, seeking to understand
better the range of regulatory mechanisms available in Western
societies and to discover some of their inherent limitations and
potentialities, was drawn increasingly to the study of sociology and
anthropology, as noted in Chapter 5. Kelsen recognised in a clearer,
more rigorous manner than have most other writers discussed in
this book, the partial nature of normative legal theory’s perspective.
He came to accept sociology of law as a parallel but quite distinct
enterprise of inquiry about the legal field, alongside what he viewed
as legal science - the normative analysis of legal doctrine guided
by the concepts of the pure theory of law. Kelsen’s writings recognise
that normative legal theory cannot merely collect the data of law
and put it in systematic order. It must deliberately construct a
perspective on reality appropriate to its object. Hence his
conceptualism, discussed in Chapter 4, presupposes that each science
constructs its own methods and its own way of seeing reality. Indeed
its special perspective determines what that reality is, since for
Kelsen, there is no way of understanding reality except through
a structure of concepts devised for that purpose. While Kelsen’s
position suggests no way of linking different sciences or disciplines
his intellectual curiosity led him to researches in several of themi
Normative Legal Theory as a Partial Perspective 231
The claim made here that normative legal theory represents a partial
perspective on law does entail the further claim that different
perspectives can be related in some way. For something to be partial,
after all, it must relate to a larger whole of which there are other
parts. Thus we reach the extremely difficult question of how the
insights of normative legal theory can somehow be integrated with
ideas developed by viewing law from other perspectives. Indeed,
what other perspectives might these be? In Chapter 1 a broad
distinction was drawn between normative legal theory and empirical
legal theory. By empirical legal theory I mean theory which seeks
to explain the character of law in terms of historical and social
conditions and treats the doctrinal and institutional characteristics
of law emphasized in normative legal theory as explicable in terms
of their social origins and effects (Cotterrell 1983: 241-2). Empirical
legal theory is concerned with the systematic explanation of law
as a field of experience; as behaviour as well as doctrine, with
both of these being treated as components and determinants of
each other. Adopting this definition it is clear that several of the
writers whose work has been considered in this book for its relevance
to normative legal theory have also directly contributed to the
development of empirical legal theory in various ways.
Perhaps the most interesting link figure is Karl Llewellyn whose
constructive realist critique of orthodox legal doctrinal analysis was
considered in Chapter 7. Llewellyn’s commitment to the orthodox
lawyer’s quest for integrity and rationality of doctrine is clear. At
the same time, a realist perspective which refuses to accept that
legal analysis can only be analysis of doctrine frees Llewellyn to
suggest ways in which the processes of development, interpretation
and application of legal doctrine can be viewed behaviourally. The
insights of normative analysis are not to be overthrown. But it
is made clear that they represent, at best, a partial perspective on
the ‘reality’ of law. And, perhaps what is most important about
this constructive realist claim is that it makes clear that it is not
enough for the lawyer to be satisfied with the partial perspective
which a focus on doctrinal rationality represents, and to leave other
perspectives to other observers of law (for example, social scientists
or politicians). Once the partial character of the doctrinal rationality
focus is revealed, the incompleteness of the knowledge which it
232 The Uses of Theory
this book’s argument, has been its inability to explain the processes
of legal change. Yet it has been suggested in this chapter that it
is precisely legal change (change in the character of doctrine and
forms of regulation, and corresponding changes in the conditions
of legal practice and legal education) which seem to suggest the
danger of normative legal theory being marginalised insofar as it
continues to claim that law does or should exhibit something more
than what I call a piecemeal rationality. Empirical legal theory,
which has a rich and varied literature and which now flourishes
in a wide variety of forms, treats law as a social phenomenon to
be examined through systematic empirical analysis of the political,
economic and social conditions in which it exists. I have described
much of its central literature elsewhere (Cotterrell 1984).
Examination of it here would be out of place. It is enough to
say that empirical legal theory potentially offers the means of
examining legal change in systematic fashion. It recognises that
the impetus for change is not usually to be found in legal doctrine
but in the social, economic and political conditions in which that
doctrine exists. Empirical legal theory is, thus, necessary to explain
the changing situation of law (and perhaps of normative legal theory
itself) in a way that normative legal theory is unable to do.
But this is not to supersede normative legal theory. The heritage
of this theoretical literature provides a storehouse of ideas about
the nature of law viewed from a certain standpoint. That standpoint
is not rendered inappropriate by the fact that there are others which
must be taken into account in order to achieve a more adequate
understanding. Debate rages in modern philosophy and elsewhere
as to what adequate can mean in this kind of context. No answer
has been given in these pages to the general question of how, in
general terms, it is possible to confront partial perspectives ’ on
experience with others so as to extend knowledge. Some writers
doubt that this is possible because no partial perspective can
necessarily provide the means of declaring any other ‘wrong’. Can
empirical legal theory show that normative theory is wrong? I make
no claim here that it can or that there is any reason why it should
try to do so. For the purposes of this book it is enough to say
that taken on its own terms, judged in terms of what it has apparently
attempted to do in clarifying and making explicit the rational
structure or system of legal doctrine, normative legal theory has
certain strengths and weaknesses. Its weaknesses seem to open the
way to types of theory, drawing on social scientific traditions and
methods, which offer the prospect of explaining what, according
to the arguments of this book, it apparently cannot explain.
Its greatest strengths, however, have been its commitment to
The Destiny of Legal Theory 235
In the following notes sources included in the list of text references are
cited by author and date only.
The first few lectures of Austin’s course were published in expanded form
as The Province of Jurisprudence Determined in 1832. The rest remained
unpublished until after his death in 1859. In 1861 a second edition of
The Province was published by Sarah Austin and in 1863 she published
the remaining lectures insofar as they could be reconstructed from Austin’s
notes. There are three contrasting recent full-length studies of Austin’s
work. Rumble 1985 deals with Austin’s career as a whole including his
later political writings and his work as a Royal Commissioner in Malta.
It contains profound discussions of many aspects of Austin’s thought.
Hamburger and Hamburger 1985 is a more conventional biography,
providing a valuable portrait of both John and Sarah Austin. Morison
1982 is perhaps most closely geared to the interests of students of normative
legal theory, but tends to adopt a rather narrow interpretation of Austin’s
aims and methods.
elements of a defence of Austin see Moles 1987, pp. 65-70. While Moles’
approach seems to me to be, in this respect, broadly along the right lines
it does not address major criticisms which Hart and others raise and fails
to make clear the particular crucial difference of aims (reflecting different
political philosophies) as between Austin and Hart which I try to bring
out in the text of this chapter and the next. See also R. Ladenson, ‘In
Defense of a Hobbesian Conception of Law’ (1980) 9 Philosophy and
Public Affairs 134.
THE CHARACTER OF RULES: See Hart 1961, pp. 54-60 on the nature
of rules, and pp. 79-88 on obligation. On the internal aspect of rules see
also especially D. N. MacCormick, Legal Reasoning and Legal Theory 1978,
pp. 275-92.
the legal validity of principles can be tested in the same way as that of
any legislative provision or judicial rule; hence (iii) Hart’s idea of an ultimate
rule of recognition within a legal system is not rendered incoherent by
an acceptance of the analytical importance of legal principles. Finally,
(iv), principle and policy are part of, implicated in, and the basis of legal
rules; they are not separate components of a legal system: ‘to explicate
the principles is to rationalize the rules’ (p. 157).
Although MacCormick’s thesis is a valuable attempt to remedy the
absence in Hart’s legal philosophy of an analysis of judicial reasoning
in hard cases, it seems open to the objection that principles governing
coherence and consistency are not given by rules of law, as MacCormick
seems to suggest, but must be imposed on them. Thus, for Dworkin, the
process of applying and developing principles is creative and constructive;
it is not already bounded by a criterion of legal validity but is part of
the ongoing process of determining legal validity. MacCormick seeks to
retain the positivist idea of discretion, but to bound it with principle:
‘It is the interaction of arguments from principle and consequentialist
arguments which fully justifies decisions in hard cases’ (p. 194). This seems
to be to have one’s cake and eat it if, for MacCormick, discretion beyond
rules is to be controlled by principles derived from rules. If it is not so
controlled, the positivist problem of the inability legally to explain discretion
remains. On the other hand, if principles are admitted not to be derived
from rules validated by a rule of recognition, MacCormick’s positivist
defence of the centrality of this ultimate validating rule seems hard to
sustain.
of these views see references under the heading ‘Judicial Decisions and
the “Open Texture” of Rules’ in notes to Chapter 4, above.
For valuable general assessments of realism see especially L. Kalman,
Legal Realism at Yale 1927-1960 1986; Twining 1973; Rumble 1968; Stevens
1983.
The idea that normative legal theory’s professional role is made problematic
by the changing forms of Western law is discussed also in Cotterrell, ‘English
Conceptions of the Role of Theory in Legal Analysis’ (1983) 46 Modern
Law Review 681. The idea that one discourse, or one perspective on reality,
cannot necessarily provide a grounding for, invalidate or even evaluate
another originating in a different practice (in other words, that all ‘truth’
claims are specific to the discourse in which they are made) is a theme
of much modern writing in philosophy and social theory. Within recent
Anglo-American philosophy one of the clearest and most influential
statements is R. Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature 1979. See
also e. g. J.-F. Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition 1984. For a broad
view of important parts of the relevant European continental tradition
see A. Megill, Prophets of Extremity 1985.
I have tried to suggest, with reference to the disciplines of law and
sociology, some conditions under which fields of knowledge can sometimes
confront each other directly in the specific historical circumstances of
particular intellectual and professional practices: see Cotterrell 1986a.
Elsewhere I have tried to defend the view that knowledge can and does
progress by the overcoming of partial perspectives, through their
confrontation with other perspectives which come to be widely accepted
as having more explanatory power. Broader perspectives can subsume
(interpret and incorporate) narrower ones and so give rise to explanations
which seem to have greater overall plausibility, richness, range and rigour
in the light of historical experience and competing theories. See e.g.
Chapter 8: The Uses of Theory 257
258
References 259