Jordheim Conceptual History
Jordheim Conceptual History
Jordheim Conceptual History
Helge Jordheim
115
CONCEPTUAL HISTORY BETWEEN CHRONOS AND KAIROS ...
116
HELGE JORDHEIM
117
CONCEPTUAL HISTORY BETWEEN CHRONOS AND KAIROS ...
118
HELGE JORDHEIM
of kairos, the situations, the ruptures, the “right time” or the “wrong
time”, play or might play, explicitly or implicitly, in the works of Ko-
selleck as well as in Geschichtliche Grundbegriffe. Hence, I am not sure
if I agree with Palonen when he says, concerning the temporal and
rhetorical perspectives, that “it is hard, if not impossible, to use both
of them simultaneously” (Palonen 1999, 43). It might be hard, but in
my opinion this is exactly what we need to do.
Furthermore, in introducing into the framework of conceptual his-
tory the ancient Greek notion of kairos, traditionally defined as a deci-
sive or possibly fateful moment (Kinneavy/Eskin 1998, 837), Palonen
– I will argue here – also presents us with a possible way to proceed
if we want to combine elements of temporal and rhetorical analysis
into a theory or even a methodology of studying historical moments,
in the framework of conceptual history. Indeed, the dual reference to
both temporal and rhetorical qualities constitutes a recurring topic in
the theories of kairos, as exemplified by the definition by the American
scholar James L. Kinneavy: “right time and due measure” (Kinneavy
1986, 85f.).
Correspondingly, kairos, as a figure of thought at work in the hu-
man sciences generally, has been used and developed primarily with-
in two different traditions, on the one hand within the rhetorical, or
more precisely the new or practical rhetorical tradition, represented
among others by Kinneavy, Lloyd Bitzer and Carolyn Miller, on the
other hand within the German tradition of Geschichtsphilosophie, often
of a theological or even messianic character, as in the case of Paul Til-
lich and Walter Benjamin. In the following I shall refer to both tradi-
tions, in trying to establish kairos as an interface between rhetoric and
Geschichtsphilosophie as well as between rhetorical and temporal ap-
proaches to the study of conceptual history and conceptual change.
However, his theoretical achievements notwithstanding, one of
the main insights offered by Koselleck has to do with the impossibility
of giving a comprehensive theoretical representation of the complex-
ity and contingency of historical reality. Thus, I intend to begin this
discussion of kairos as interface between the temporal and the rhetori-
cal with an example, one which has already attracted some attention
in the fields of politics and history: the return of the concept of “em-
pire” into the debates on American foreign policy. Taking up one of
Koselleck’s main claims from the introduction to the first volume of
Geschichtliche Grundbegriffe, that conceptual history should always be
119
CONCEPTUAL HISTORY BETWEEN CHRONOS AND KAIROS ...
On July 17th 2003, the NAI (New Atlantic Initiative) and the AEI
(American Enterprise Institute for Public Policy Research), two influ-
ential neoconservative think tanks, staged a public debate between
British historian Niall Ferguson, author of the book Empire: The Rise
and Demise of the British World Order and the Lessons for Global Power
(Ferguson 2003), and US foreign policy commentator and leading
figure in the neoconservative movement, Robert Kagan, author of
Paradise and Power: America and Europe in the New World Order (Kagan
2003). The title of the debate was a fairly simple, yet controversial
claim: “The United States is, and should be, an empire”.1 By summer
2003, this claim, in spite of its controversial and rather anachronistic
ring, “had become a staple on talk shows and had spurred writers to
produce a flurry of op-eds, essays, and books”, if we are to believe
one of the main discussants, author and publicist Andrew Bacevich
(Bacevich 2003a, xi). Before we consider the debate itself, it will be
instructive to review some of the semantic and conceptual processes
and innovations that led up to it.
Already in 1999 David Rieff claimed that only a new sort of im-
perialism would be able to deal with the humanitarian crises of our
age, in Kosovo, Somalia or Rwanda. Presuming that only the United
States could fill the role of the empire, he argued that US foreign pol-
icy should adopt a “liberal imperialism” (Rieff 2003, 10). Similarly, in
2002, Deepak Lal, Professor of International Development Studies at
UCLA, gave a lecture entitled “In Defense of Empires”, arguing for the
need of a “Pax Americana” and for the United States to face up to its
imperial obligations (Lal 2003, 29). Additionally, the historical roots of
the semantics of “empire” and “imperialism” have been discussed in
several articles, proclaiming the United States to be “the New Rome”
(Bender 2003, 81; Bacevich 2003b, 93) or, on the other hand, vehement-
ly dismissing this parallel. In an essay from 2002, Bacevich points at
the “providential significance” characterizing the United States as a
120
HELGE JORDHEIM
121
CONCEPTUAL HISTORY BETWEEN CHRONOS AND KAIROS ...
122
HELGE JORDHEIM
cal and for historical reasons. Then he introduces his famous phrase
“empire in denial”. The meaning of the concept “empire”, Ferguson
argues, cannot be established solely on the basis of definitions in dic-
tionaries, but has to take into account the entire history of the British
Empire and other past empires. According to this broader definition
of “empire”, the United States is “one of the most powerful empires
in all history, and the only remarkable thing about this is that so many
Americans are unaware of the fact”. To prove his point, moving from
a more linguistic to a more historical register, Ferguson uses what he
calls his “quack like a duck” argument: “If it quacks like a duck, it
probably is a duck. If it quacks like an empire, it probably is an em-
pire”.
Robert Kagan, on the other hand, starts by warning against de-
scending “into a definitional argument”. Still, he sets off criticizing
Ferguson’s semantic distinctions. As soon as he starts formulating his
own views on United States foreign policy, however, it is not a ques-
tion of semantics anymore, but – rather emphatically – of political re-
ality: “I won’t call it ‘empire’ because I don’t believe it is an empire,
but the most successful global hegemon, the most successful global
power in history”. Thus, Kagan has no problem admitting to the fact
that after the end of the Cold War the United States is indeed the su-
preme global power, but he strongly objects to the idea that it can or
should be termed an “empire” in the old, European sense. Instead, he
prefers “hegemon”, originally a Greek term, referring to the dominant
or leading city-state, which doesn’t have the same aura of oppression
and exploitation as “empire”. On the contrary, Kagan states, signifi-
cantly quoting the second Godfather movie, “America always made
money for its partners”.
In considering the debate between Ferguson and Kagan, together
with the essays and debates that both preceded and succeeded it, the
relevant question is how we – from a conceptual history perspective
– are to understand the reappearance of the particular concept of “em-
pire” at the beginning of the twenty-first century. At first glance this
return has been made possible by at least two important conceptual
shifts: firstly and most obviously, “empire” has moved from being a
merely historical concept, used with reference to past power struc-
tures, such as the Roman and British empires, to becoming a contem-
porary name for a contemporary political situation; secondly, but no
less important, “empire” and the corresponding ideology, “imperial-
123
CONCEPTUAL HISTORY BETWEEN CHRONOS AND KAIROS ...
124
HELGE JORDHEIM
125
CONCEPTUAL HISTORY BETWEEN CHRONOS AND KAIROS ...
126
HELGE JORDHEIM
127
CONCEPTUAL HISTORY BETWEEN CHRONOS AND KAIROS ...
Now, there is no surer sign that you are an empire than the invasion of
Afghanistan. It’s something we tried, it’s something the Russians tried,
and there you go again, as Ronald Reagan used to say.
128
HELGE JORDHEIM
129
CONCEPTUAL HISTORY BETWEEN CHRONOS AND KAIROS ...
130
HELGE JORDHEIM
From what I have said so far about the two kairos traditions, the rhe-
torical and the philosophical, it follows that the attempt to develop
a theory of the historical moment needs to combine two different
concepts of kairos: on the one hand, we have to do with a rhetorical
concept, bringing with it, more or less openly, the question of tran-
131
CONCEPTUAL HISTORY BETWEEN CHRONOS AND KAIROS ...
132
HELGE JORDHEIM
133
CONCEPTUAL HISTORY BETWEEN CHRONOS AND KAIROS ...
134
HELGE JORDHEIM
135
CONCEPTUAL HISTORY BETWEEN CHRONOS AND KAIROS ...
136
HELGE JORDHEIM
137
CONCEPTUAL HISTORY BETWEEN CHRONOS AND KAIROS ...
1972, XVIII). It follows from this idea that the meanings of words
originate in specific rhetorical situations and must be studied in refer-
ence to these situations. To analyse such specific historical moments
has always been an indispensable part of historical method as well
as the method of conceptual history. At the same time, however, this
methodical approach contains an awareness of the kairos of these mo-
ments, an awareness which might be developed further as soon as it
is expanded by means of a theory of time, temporality and temporal
experience.
In his programmatic essay “Über die Theoriebedürftigkeit der Ge-
schichtswissenschaft”, Koselleck claims that conceptual history can-
not do without “a theory of historical temporalities [eine Theorie der
historischen Zeiten]” (Koselleck 2000c, 302). One of the first steps in his
development of such a theory is “the destruction of natural chronol-
ogy”. “Chronological succession”, Koselleck argues, “[…] can rela-
tively easy be exposed as fiction” (ibid., 306). Henceforth, a primary
ambition in Koselleck’s work consists in replacing this natural chro-
nology as well as the Hegelian notion of linear time, “history as such”,
Geschichte als solche, as Koselleck calls it, with the notion of Zeitschich-
ten, of multi-layered time. At the centre of this theoretical ambition is
a reflection upon different aspects of the historical moment, of kairos,
as I use it in this article. In the following I will just give three short
examples: the surprise, the contemporaneity of the non-contempora-
neous [die Gleichzeitigkeit des Ungleichzeitigen] and the conflict.
In the essay “Zeitschichten” Koselleck discusses the relationship
between uniqueness [Einmaligkeit] and repetition in historical pro-
cesses. One of the phenomena he considers is the surprise, not only as
an empirical manifestation of exactly this kind of uniqueness, but also
– and in this context more importantly – as a kairos experience:
Suddenly one finds oneself facing something new [einem Novum], in the
sense of a temporal minimum [einem zeitlichen Minimum], appearing be-
tween before and after. The continuity of previous experience and expec-
tations for the future is interrupted and must form itself anew. It is this
temporal minimum of irreversible before and after that drives the sur-
prises into our body. (Koselleck 2000d, 23)
138
HELGE JORDHEIM
139
CONCEPTUAL HISTORY BETWEEN CHRONOS AND KAIROS ...
140
HELGE JORDHEIM
NOTES
1. All quotes from this debate are taken from a transcript published on the AEI website:
http://www.aei.org/events/filter.,eventID.428/transcript.asp
141
CONCEPTUAL HISTORY BETWEEN CHRONOS AND KAIROS ...
REFERENCES
Bacevich, Andrew 2003a. Introduction. In Andrew Bacevich (ed.). The Imperial Tense.
Prospects and Problems of American Empire. Chicago: Ivan R. Dee, ix-iv.
Bacevich, Andrew 2003b. New Rome, New Jerusalem. In Andrew Bacevich (ed.). The
Imperial Tense. Prospects and Problems of American Empire. Chicago: Ivan R. Dee, 93-101.
Balibar, Francoise, Philippe Büttgen, Barbara Cassin, 2004. Moment, instant, occasion.
In Barbara Cassin (ed.), Vocabulaire européen des philosophies. Dictionnaire des intraduisi-
bles. Paris: Le Robert/Seuil, 813-818.
Bhabha, Homi K. 1997. ‘Race’, Time and the Revision of Modernity. In Bart Moore-
Gilbert, Gareth Stanton, Willy Maley (eds.), Postcolonial Criticism. London/New York:
Longman, 166-190.
Benjamin, Walter 1977. Über den Begriff der Geschichte. In Benjamin: Illuminationen.
Ausgewählte Schriften 1. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 251-261.
Bender, Peter 2003. The New Rome. In Bacevich (ed.). The Imperial Tense. Prospects and
Problems of American Empire. Chicago: Ivan R. Dee, 81-92.
Bitzer, Lloyd 1968. The Rhetorical Situation. Philosophy and Rhetoric 1, 1-14.
Cassin, Barbara 1995. L’effet sophistique. Paris: Gallimard.
Ferguson, Niall 2003. Empire: The Rise and Demise of the British World Order and the Les-
sons for Global Power. New York: Basic Books.
Fisch, Jörg, Dieter Groh, Rudolf Walther 1982. Imperialismus. In Otto Brunner, Wer-
ner Conze, Reinhart Koselleck (eds.), Geschichtliche Grundbegriffe. Historisches lexikon zur
politisch-sozialen Sprache in Deutschland. Vol. 3, Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, 171-236.
Hartog, François 2003. Régimes d’historicité. Presentisme et expériences du temps, Paris:
Seuil.
Joffe, Josef 2006. Überpower: The Imperial Temptation of America, New York: W.W. Nor-
ton.
Jordheim, Helge 2004. Philology of the Future, Futures of Philology. Interdisciplinar-
ity, Intertemporality, and Begriffsgeschichte. In Hans Lauge Hansen (ed.): Disciplines
and Interdisciplinarity in Foreign Language Studies, Copenhagen: Museum Tusculanum
Press, 35-49.
Jordheim, Helge 2005. Die ‘Gleichzeitigkeit des Ungleichzeitigen’ als Konvergenz-
punkt von Zeitlichkeit und Sprachlichkeit. Zu einem Topos aus dem Werk Reinhart
Kosellecks. In Divinatio. Studia Culturalogica Series 22, 2004, 77-89.
Kagan, Robert 2003. Paradise and Power: America and Europe in the New World Order.
London: Atlantic Books.
Kinneavy, James L. 1986. Kairos: A Neglected Concept in Classical Rhetoric. In Jean
Dietz Moss (ed.), Rhetoric and Praxis. The Contribution of Classical Rhetoric to Practical
Reasoning. Washington, D.C: The Catholic University of America Press, 76-105.
142
HELGE JORDHEIM
Kinneavy, James L., Catherine R. Eskin 1994. Kairos in Aristotle’s Rhetoric. Written Com-
munication. 11(1), 131-142.
Kinneavy, James L., Catherine R. Eskin 1998. Kairos. In Gerd Ueding (ed.), Historisches
Wörterbuch der Rhetorik. Vol. 4. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag, 836-844.
Koebner, Richard 1953. Semantics and Historiography. The Cambridge Journal 7, 131-
144.
Koebner, Richard, Helmut Dan Schmidt 1964. Imperialism. The Story and Significance of a
Political Word, 1840-1960. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Koselleck, Reinhart [1959] 1973. Kritik und Krise. Eine Studie zur Pathogenese der bürgerli-
chen Welt. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag.
Koselleck, Reinhart 1972. Einleitung. In Otto Brunner, Werner Conze, Reinhart Ko-
selleck (eds.), Geschichtliche Grundbegriffe. Historisches Lexikon zur politisch-sozialen
Sprache in Deutschland. Vol. 1, Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, XIII-XXVII.
Koselleck, Reinhart 1979a. Begriffsgeschichte und Sozialgeschichte. In Koselleck, Ver-
gangene Zukunft. Zur Semantik geschichtlicher Zeiten. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Ver-
lag, 107-129.
Koselleck, Reinhart 1979b. Zur historisch-politischen Semantik asymmetrischer Ge-
genbegriffe. In Koselleck, Vergangene Zukunft. Zur Semantik geschichtlicher Zeiten. Frank-
furt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 211-259.
Koselleck, Reinhart 1992. Vorwort. In Otto Brunner, Werner Conze, Reinhart Koselleck
(eds.), Geschichtliche Grundbegriffe. Historisches Lexikon zur politisch-sozialen Sprache in
Deutschland. Vol. 7, Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta, V-VIII.
Koselleck, Reinart 1999. Die falsche Ungeduld. Wer darf vergessen werden? Das Ho-
locaust- Denkmal hierarchisiert die Opfer. In Ute Heimrod, Günter Schluchse, Horst
Seferens (eds.), Der Denkmalstreit – das Denkmal? Die Debatte um das „Denkmal für die er-
mordeten Juden Europas“. Eine Dokumentation. Berlin: Philo Verlagsgesellschaft, 148-151.
Koselleck, Reinhart 2000a. Historik und Hermeneutik. In Koselleck, Zeitschichten. Stu-
dien zur Historik. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 97-118.
Koselleck, Reinhart 2000b. Stetigkeit und Wandel aller Zeitgeschichten. In Koselleck,
Zeitschichten. Studien zur Historik. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 246-264.
Koselleck, Reinhart 2000c. Über die Theoriebedürftigkeit der Geschichtswissenschaft.
In Koselleck, Zeitschichten. Studien zur Historik, Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag,
298-316.
Koselleck, Reinhart: 2000d. Zeitschichten. In Koselleck, Zeitschichten. Studien zur Histo-
rik. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 9-16.
Koselleck, Reinhart 2006a. Sprachwandel und Ereignisgeschichte. In Koselleck, Be-
griffsgeschichten. Studien zur Semantik und Pragmatik der politischen und sozialen Sprache.
Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 32-55.
143
CONCEPTUAL HISTORY BETWEEN CHRONOS AND KAIROS ...
Koselleck, Reinhart 2006b. Die Geschichte der Begriffe und Begriffe der Geschichte.
In Koselleck, Begriffsgeschichten. Studien zur Semantik und Pragmatik der politischen und
sozialen Sprache. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 56-76.
Koselleck, Reinhart 2006c. Hinweise auf die temporalen Strukturen begriffsgeschicht-
lichen Wandels. In Koselleck, Begriffsgeschichten. Studien zur Semantik und Pragmatik der
politischen und sozialen Sprache. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 86-98.
Koselleck, Reinhart 2006d. Einige Fragen an die Begriffsgeschichte von ‘Krise’. In Ko-
selleck, Begriffsgeschichten. Studien zur Semantik und Pragmatik der politischen und sozialen
Sprache. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag, 203-217.
Lal, Deepak. In Defense of Empires. In Andrew Bacevich (ed.), The Imperial Tense. Pros-
pects and Problems of American Empire. Chicago: Ivan R. Dee, 29-46.
Lindroos, Kia 1998. Now-Time. Image-Space. Temporalization of Politics in Walter Benja-
min’s Philosophy of History and Art. University of Jyväskylä: SoPhi.
Miller, Carolyn 1992. Kairos in the Rhetoric of Science. In Stephen P. White, Neil Na-
kadate, Roger D. Cherry (eds.), A Rhetoric of Doing. Essays on Written Discourse in Honor
of James L. Kinneavy. Carbondale/Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press, 310-
327.
Montrose, Louis A. 1989. Professing the Renaissance: The Poetics and Politics of Cul-
ture. In H. Aram Veeser (ed.), The New Historicism. New York/London: Routledge,
15–37.
Onians, Richard Broxton 1954. The Origins of European Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Palonen, Kari 1999. Rhetorical and Temporal Perspectives on Conceptual Change. In
Finnish Yearbook of Political Thought. Vol. 3, 41-59.
Pocock, J.G.A. 1975. The Machiavellian Moment. Florentine Political Thought and the Atlan-
tic Republican Tradition. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press.
Poulakos, John 1983. Toward a Sophistic Definition of Rhetoric. In Rhetoric and Philoso-
phy 16, 35-48.
Rieff, David 2003. Liberal Imperialism. In Andrew Bacevich (ed.), The Imperial Tense.
Prospects and Problems of American Empire. Chicago: Ivan R. Dee, 10-28.
Saussure, Ferdinand de 1967. Cours de lingistique générale. Edited by Charles Bally og
Albert Sechehaye in cooperation with Albert Riedlinger. Critical edition by Tullio de
Mauro. Postface by Louis-Jean Calvert, Paris: Éditions Payot & Rivages.
Skinner, Quentin 1978. Foundations of Modern Political Thought. Vol. 1: The Renaissance,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Smith, John E. Time, Times, and the ‘Right Time’: Chronos and Kairos. Monist 53, 1969,
1-13.
144
HELGE JORDHEIM
Thompson, Roger 2000. Kairos Revisited: An Interview with James Kinneavy. Rhetoric
Review 19(1-2), 73-88.
Tillich, Paul 1961. Kairos und Logos. In Tillich, Philosophie und Schicksal. Schriften zur
Erkenntnislehre und Existenzphilosophie. Gesammelte Werke. Vol. IV. Stuttgart: Evange-
lisches Verlagswerk, 43-76.
Tillich, Paul 1963a. Kairos I. In Tillich, Der Widerstreit von Raum und Zeit. Schriften zur
Geschichtsphilosophie. Gesammelte Werke. Vol VI. Stuttgart: Evangelisches Verlagswerk,
9-28.
Tillich, Paul 1963b. Kairos II. Ideen zur Geisteslage der Gegenwart. In Tillich, Der Wi-
derstreit von Raum und Zeit. Schriften zur Geschichtsphilosophie. Gesammelte Werke. Vol
VI. Stuttgart: Evangelisches Verlagswerk, 29-41.
Tillich, Paul 1963c. Kairos III. In Tillich, Der Widerstreit von Raum und Zeit. Schriften
zur Geschichtsphilosophie. Gesammelte Werke. Vol VI. Stuttgart: Evangelisches Verlags-
werk, 137-139.
Vatz, Richard E. 1973. The Myth of the Rhetorical Situation. Philosophy and Rhetoric 6,
154-61.
Védrine, Hubert 2003. Face à l’hyperpuissance. Textes et discours 1995-2003. Paris: Fa-
yard.
145