RM3 Week1-2 Anthropocentrism
RM3 Week1-2 Anthropocentrism
RM3 Week1-2 Anthropocentrism
Anthropocentrism:
Reconceptualizing the
Value of Nature within
the Framework of an
Enlightened Self-interest
Bartlomiej A. Lenart
Introduction
Many environmentalists and philosophers troubled by today’s increas-
ingly serious environmental problems have complained that the worth
and importance of the environment is being evaluated through the lens
of a “humanistic” ethic concerned with anthropocentric values and goals.
Kenneth Goodpaster worries that since “[m]odern moral philosophy has
taken ethical egoism as its principal foil for developing what can fairly
be called a humanistic perspective on value and obligation” (2005, 54),
philosophers tend to approach “questions of conservation, preservation
of the environment, and technology assessment…simply as application
Odysseus, upon returning home from the Trojan War, hangs a dozen
slave-girls, who belong to his household, merely for suspected “misbehav-
ior” during his absence. Leopold observes that “[t]he ethical structure of
that day covered wives, but had not yet been extended to human chattels”
(1993, 373). Leopold goes on to suggest that the environment is similarly
“unprotected” by the ethical structure of our day.
As a remedy to the ethical egoism Goodpaster blames for the insuffi-
cient ascription of human obligations toward the environment, Leopold
proposes his Land Ethic, which “enlarges the boundaries of the commu-
nity to include soils, waters, plants, and animals, or collectively: the land”
(1993, 374). In a similar manner, Naess’ first principle in his (and George
Sessions’) “Deep Ecological Platform” also emphasizes a non-anthropo-
centric evaluation of the environment.
The two dogmas of Environmental Ethics, then, as Andrew Light
points out, are: (1) “the assumption that axiologically anthropocentric
views are antithetical to the agenda of environmentalists, and to the devel-
opment of environmental ethics” (2002, 429); and (2) the assumption that
non-anthropocentrism should be extended beyond individualism, which
includes sentientism of the sort advocated by Peter Singer (1990, 2011)
since “individualism or sentientism is inadequate for an environmental
ethic because it fails to offer [direct] reasons for the moral consideration
of ecosystems, wilderness, and endangered species” (Light 2002, 431).
Thus, arguments for the “intrinsic value” of holistic systems (like ecosys-
tems) have become quite common in the literature.
This paper discusses Arne Naess’ and Aldo Leopold’s accounts, which
arguably constitute paradigm examples of proposals that ascribe intrinsic
value to ecosystems. Such accounts, however, are open to various objec-
tions, which can be avoided by a more anthropocentric approach to envi-
ronmental ethics. The approach I propose is one that adopts an enlightened
self-interest grounded in Christine Korsgaard’s (1996) distinctions in
Aldo Leopold
Aldo Leopold understands ethics as originating from the “tendency
of interdependent individuals or groups to evolve modes of co-operation”
(1993, 373). He is concerned with the lack of an ethic that deals with the
relation between human beings and the land, where the “land” includes
various systems, the waters, the soil, and the numerous and diverse inhab-
itants of the “land.” Leopold’s land ethic aims at enlarging the boundaries
of the “community,” which presupposes interdependency of the various
parts that constitute a given whole, to include soils, waters, plants, and
animals as fellow members of an intricately interdependent system whose
survival and “health” depends on an appropriate understanding and eval-
uation of the various interdependencies. “In short, a land ethic changes
the role of Homo sapiens from conqueror of the land-community to plain
member and citizen of it. It implies respect for his fellow-members, and
also respect for the community as such” (1993, 374).
Leopold criticizes conservation systems based solely on economic
motives; he states that such conservation systems do not assign value to
most of the members of the “land-community” because most members do
not have any economic value. However, the land ethic points to the fact that
such members, being integral parts of the biotic community, contribute to
the stability of the entire system. Therefore, a system of conservation based
solely on the economic self-interest of human beings “assumes, falsely…
that the economic parts of the biotic clock will function without the une-
conomic parts” (1993, 178). Although Leopold does not explicitly state it,
one can infer that in such a manner, short-sighted economic self-interest not
only destroys the integrity of the environment upon which the stability of
the various life-generating (as well as resource-generating) systems depends,
but also, by direct entailment, endangers the very resources it values (since
their existence is deeply intertwined with the stability of the entire system).
Leopold offers the metaphor of The Land Pyramid, which consists of
interrelated layers of energy transfer. At the bottom layer, plants absorb
energy from the sun, which continues to flow upward through a circuit
called the biota (represented by the layers of the pyramid). The bottom
layer consists of the soil with a plant layer resting on top of it and “an
insect layer [resting] on the plants, a bird and rodent layer [resting] on the
insects, and so on up through various animal groups to the apex layer,
which consists of the large carnivores” (1993, 378). Each layer depends
on the one below it for food and various other services. The lines of
The core of the land ethic, then, can be summarized as follows: “[a] thing
is right when it tends to preserve the integrity, stability, and beauty of the
biotic community. It is wrong when it tends otherwise” (Leopold 1993,
382). What emerges out of Leopold’s land ethic, then, is an axiology that
assigns intrinsic value to wholes.
J. Baird Callicott believes that human beings must have become ethi-
cal before they became rational because the evolution of reason does not
seem plausible without the pre-requisite development of complex linguis-
tic capabilities, but these, in turn, depend for their evolution on a highly
developed social matrix. “But we cannot have become social beings,”
Callicott argues, “unless we assumed limitations on freedom of action in
the struggle for existence” (1989, 79).
Callicott understands Leopold’s land ethic as implicitly assuming such
an evolutionary sequence of events and thus as embracing David Hume’s
(1751/2006) and Adam Smith’s (1759/1976) arguments that ethics rest
upon “feelings” or “sentiments.” Callicott writes:
Darwin’s account, to which Leopold unmistakenly (if elliptically) alludes
in “The Land Ethic,” begins with the parental and filial affections com-
mon, perhaps, to all mammals. Bonds of affection and sympathy between
parents and offspring permitted the formation of small, closely kin social
groups, Darwin argued. Should the parental and filial affections bond-
ing family members chance to extend to less closely related individuals,
that would permit an enlargement of the family group. And should the
newly extended community more successfully defend itself and/or more
efficiently provision itself, the inclusive fitness of its members severally
would be increased, Darwin reasoned. Thus…the “social sentiments,”
would be spread throughout a population. (1989, 79)
It is no surprise, then, that the section entitled “The Land Pyramid,” which
arguably constitutes the heart of Leopold’s monograph, opens as follows:
Callicott continues his analysis of “The Land Ethic” by outlining the con-
ceptual foundations underlying it. He states that Evolutionary Theory
provides the conceptual link between ethics, social organization, and devel-
opment. That is, it provides a sense of kinship with fellow creatures who
are at once fellow members of the biotic community as well as “‘fellow-
voyagers’ with us in the ‘odyssey of evolution’” (1989, 82). Furthermore,
Ecological Theory provides The Land Ethic with the conceptual link
between a sense of social integration of human and non-human nature by
emphasizing that “[h]uman beings, plants, animals, soils, and waters are
‘all interlocked in one humming community of cooperations and competi-
tions, one biota’” (1989, 83). Finally, Leopold also adopts the Copernican
Perspective, which reveals the Earth to be a tiny planet journeying through
an immensity of mostly empty and hostile space. Such an image of our
planet, Callicott argues, contributes to our sense of kinship, community,
and interdependence with all of Earth’s inhabitants. In Callicott’s more
elegant and poetic words: “[i]t scales the earth down to something like a
cozy island paradise in a desert ocean” (1989, 83).
A short reflection on Leopold’s text in the section entitled “The
Community Concept” makes Callicott’s analysis quite plausible. Let us
recall that Leopold writes: “[i]n short, a land ethic changes the role of
Homo sapiens from conqueror of the land-community to plain member
and citizen of it. It implies respect for his fellow-members, and also respect
for the community as such” (1993, 374). Callicott concludes that “[t]he
land ethic, thus, has a holistic as well as an individualistic cast” (1989,
83), but soon afterwards adds:
The land ethic not only provides moral considerability for the biotic
community per se, but ethical consideration of its individual members
is preempted by concern for the preservation of the integrity, stability,
and beauty of the biotic community. The land ethic, thus, not only has a
holistic aspect; it is holistic with a vengeance. (Callicott 1989, 84)
Arne Naess
Arne Naess argues that “[c]onservation strategies are more eagerly
implemented by people who love what they are conserving, and who are
convinced that what they love is intrinsically lovable…They possess a gen-
uine ethics of conservation, not merely a tactically useful instrument for
human survival” (1993, 412). This statement implies that intrinsic value
ought to be lodged in non-anthropocentric evaluations of the environ-
ment; there is something in nature itself that is “intrinsically lovable” and
it is not merely dependent on evaluations based on human needs.
Naess’ and Sessions’ Deep Ecology Platform sheds a bit more light on
the source of the intrinsic value with which Naess wishes to endow the
environment. The first postulate states:
Naess explains that “the second principle presupposes that life itself, as a
process over evolutionary time, implies an increase of diversity and rich-
ness” (1986, 413). In conjunction with the third and fourth postulates,
Naess’ formulation of Deep Ecology points to richness and diversity as a
source of intrinsic value, which are both similarly abstract and procedural
in character to Leopold’s postulation of stability and integrity as the bear-
ers of intrinsic value. The third and fourth postulates state:
Valuing that which is natural for the reason that it is natural becomes
quite tempting once the source of intrinsic value is located in the integrity
and stability of a system as a whole (especially when human interaction
with the environmental processes is viewed as interference and intru-
sion). Sober thinks that such extreme tendencies toward valuing only that
which is natural are absurd. First of all, such views suggest that since wild
organisms are not understood as having the function of serving humans,
whereas domesticated animals do serve such a function, “[c]heetahs in
zoos are crimes against what is natural; [whereas] veal calves in boxes
are not” (Sober 1995, 237). Secondly, Sober explains that human beings
cannot be viewed as existing outside of nature in some artificial realm.
Humans, just like cheetahs, are part of nature and thus everything they
do is part of nature and so all human actions are natural in that primary
sense. Sober writes:
When we domesticate organisms and bring them into a state of depend-
ence on us, this is simply an example of one species exerting a selection
pressure on another. If one calls this ‘unnatural’, one might just as well
say this of parasitism or symbiosis (compare human domestication of
animals and plants and ‘slave-making’ in the social insects). (1995, 234)
What Sober’s objection points out is that artificial systems ought to inherit
value from their natural counterparts (if natural systems are valued) since
blindly valuing one type of system, but not another is arbitrary. Sober
warns that environmentalists should look elsewhere for a defence of their
policies “lest conservation simply become a variant of uncritical conserv-
atism in which the axiom ‘Whatever is right, is right’ is modified to read
‘Whatever is (before human beings come on the scene), is right’” (1995,
235). After all, organisms transform their environments by interacting
with them. An ant-hill, according to Sober, is just as much an artefact as
is a highway (1995, 243). Furthermore, if the source of value is a holistic
one, which reduces to the maintenance of ecological balance and diver-
sity, the charge of environmental fascism soon surfaces. Sober writes: “It
is hard to know what to say to someone who would save a mosquito,
just because it is rare, rather than a human being, if there were a choice”
(1995, 241). It is difficult to see why ecosystem stability and diversity
must be the only (or an overriding) source of value.
Anthony Weston’s (1996) critique of the very notion of intrinsic value
unveils yet another difficulty for views like those of Leopold and Naess.
Weston states that the traditional requirement for intrinsic value makes
the concept too abstract. According to Weston, intrinsic value, tradition-
ally conceived, must be self-sufficient in the sense that “intrinsic values
Korsgaard understands the Kantian postulate that only the “good will”
is unconditionally good to suggest that rational beings (who are intrin-
sically valuable in virtue of their “good will”) must be capable of con-
ferring value upon the objects of their choices, desires, and the ends they
set because rational beings must regard their ends as “good.” Moreover,
since other rational beings are also intrinsically valuable, “we must regard
others as capable of conferring value by reason of their rational choices”
(Korsgaard 1996, 260). Therefore, the ends chosen by any rational being
take on the status of objective goods. “They are not intrinsically valuable,
but they are objectively valuable in the sense that every rational being has
a reason to promote them or realize them” (Korsgaard 1996, 261).
It could be objected that it is precisely the goodness of the chosen
object that makes the choice rational. Korsgaard replies that it is the rea-
soning that goes into the choice that certifies the goodness of the object
chosen. Therefore, Korsgaard claims, on Kant’s theory, “the goodness
of rationally chosen ends is a matter of the demands of practical reason
rather than a matter of ontology” (Korsgaard 1996, 261). Thus, on Kant’s
view, the goodness of most things (all but the unconditional goodness
of the “good will”) is relational (relative to the desires and interests of
rational beings). Korsgaard continues:
[However]…since it [the goodness of most things] must also be appro-
priately related to one thing that has intrinsic value [the “good will”],
it is not merely “subjective.” Value does, in Ross’s [1930/2007] extrav-
agant terms, “shine with a reflected glory,” and it is “borrowed rather
than owned” by most of the things that have it. But it does have an orig-
inal source that brings it into the world—the value-conferring power of
the good will. (1996, 262)
The things that are important to us can be good for various reasons: they
can be good because we desire them or because we love them, they can
be good because of our interests in them or “because of the physiological,
psychological, economic, historical, symbolic and other conditions under
which human beings live” (Korsgaard 1996, 273).
Conclusion
Although the hearts of environmentalists like Aldo Leopold and Arne
Naess are definitely in the right place, their views may be somewhat alienat-
ing to many prospective “nature-lovers” because of what comes across as an
uncompromising non-anthropocentrism (or even anti-anthropocentrism),
which seems ready to sacrifice the individual at the altar of holistic
intrinsic value. The account I propose, which is grounded in Korsgaard’s
distinctions in goodness, points to a less radical (and admittedly more
anthropocentric) approach to environmental ethics, but one that grants
objective value to ecosystems while grounding the conditions of such
value in the human desire to survive, human love of nature, etc. I believe
that human understanding and appreciation of the interdependencies of
human and non-human (as well as biotic and abiotic) existence is a strong
enough foundation upon which an environmental ethic can be built.
REFERENCES
Bodian, Stephan. 1995. “Simple in Means, Rich in Ends: An Interview with Arne
Naess,” in Deep Ecology for the 21st Century: Readings on the Philosophy
and Practice of the New Environmentalism, edited by George Sessions, 26–36.
Boston, MA: Shambhala Publications.
Brennan, Andrew A. 1995. “Ecological Theory and Value in Nature,” in Environ-
mental Ethics, edited by Robert Elliot, 188–214. Oxford, UK: Oxford Univer-
sity Press.
Callicott, Baird J. 1980. “Animal Liberation: A Triangular Affair,” in Environ-
mental Ethics, edited by Robert Elliot, 29–59. Oxford, UK: Oxford University
Press.
Callicott, Baird J. 1989. “The Conceptual Foundations of the Land Ethic,” in In
Defense of the Land Ethic: Essays in Environmental Philosophy, 75–100. New
York, NY: State University of New York Press.
Goodpaster, Kenneth E. 2005. “On Being Morally Considerable,” in Environmen-
tal Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, fourth edition, edited
by Michael E. Zimmermann et al., 53–66. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice
Hall.
Hume, David. 2006. An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals. New York,
NY: Cosimo Classics.
Kant, Immanuel. 1785[1993]. Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals, third
edition, translated by James W. Ellington. Indianapolis, IN: Jackett Publishing.
Katz, Eric. 1996. “Searching for Intrinsic Value: Pragmatism and Despair in Envi-
ronmental Ethics,” in Environmental Pragmatism, edited by Andrew Light and
Eric Katz, 307–18. New York, NY: Routledge.
Korsgaard, Christine. 1996. “Two Distinctions in Goodness,” in Creating the
Kingdom of Ends, 249–74. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.