Untitled
Untitled
Untitled
H E R E T IC A L T HOU G H T
Series editor: Ruth O’Brien,
The Graduate Center, City University of New York
Call Your "Mutha'": A Deliberately Dirty-Minded
Manifesto for the Earth Mother in the Anthropocene
Jane Caputi
Assembly
Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri
The Rise of Neoliberal Feminism
Catherine Rottenberg
Interior Frontiers: Essays on the Entrails of Inequality
Ann Laura Stoler
Insurgent Universality: An Alternative Legacy of
Modernity
Massimiliano Tomba
Wild Democracy
Anarchy, Courage, and Ruling the Law
A N N E N O RT O N
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers
the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education
by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University
Press in the UK and certain other countries.
Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press
198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America.
© Oxford University Press 2023
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in
a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the
prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted
by law, by license, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reproduction
rights organization. Inquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the
above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the
address above.
You must not circulate this work in any other form
and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer.
Library of Congress Control Number: 2022919036
ISBN 978–0–19–764434–8
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197644348.001.0001
1 3 5 7 9 8 6 4 2
Printed by Sheridan Books, Inc., United States of America
Contents
Forward ix
T H E SE S F O R D E M O C R AT S
There are times when a book has to be written with a precision that can
be achieved only in a technical or scholarly language. This is not that
time. This is not that book. I make no distinction between the writings
of scholars or the writings of rebels, the writings of statesmen or the
writings of dissidents. I go through terrain that is not enclosed, that
remains a commons open to all. This is the democratic wild: unfenced,
unconfined, untamed.
If we are to rule ourselves, this must be our terrain. We need to seek
anarchy. We need to find courage. We need to rule the law.
Anarchy is the nursery and the refuge of the democratic. In anarchy,
one is neither ruler nor ruled. Here people learn to rule themselves.
Here there is, if only for a moment, in a small space, no one to order
or to serve. Here people learn to provide for themselves. They learn
to work together. Anarchy is not the rejection of politics, solidarity, or
cooperation; it is the rejection of any ruler but oneself. Where no one
orders and no one serves, people grow strong. They learn the courage
to face what they must. They win the daring to do what they can.
Courage is the virtue of the democratic. People begin to rule when
they find the courage to think things could be otherwise. They find the
courage to speak freely. Courage fires their uprisings and revolutions.
These fires can fail, but they can be made to burn again. Courage
maintains the work of revolutions. Courage enables people to rule
themselves in great things and in small ones. People who rule them-
selves are steadfast. They face constant uncertainty with equanimity.
They learn when to change and when to endure. They learn to walk
among their enemies unafraid.
Law is ours to judge, to break, to make, to uphold, and to bring
down. If we are citizens, we are ruled by law, but we rule law as law’s
sovereign. If we are democrats, we are law’s rulers. If we are courageous,
x Forward
This will be the practice of the king who will rule over you. He will
take your sons and appoint them as his charioteers and horsemen,
and they will serve as outrunners for his chariots. He will appoint
them as his chiefs of thousands, and of fifties; or they will have to plow
his fields, reap his harvest, and make his weapons and the equipment
for his chariots. He will take your daughters as perfumers, cooks, and
bakers. He will seize your choice fields, vineyards, and olive groves,
and give them to his courtiers. He will take a tenth part of your grain
and vintage and give it to his eunuchs and courtiers. He will take
your male and female slaves, and your choice young men, and your
asses, and put them to work for him. He will take a tenth part of your
flocks and you shall become his slaves. The day will come when you
cry out because of the king whom you yourselves have chosen; and
the Lord will not answer you on that day. (Nevi’im I Samuel 9:11)
Wild Democracy. Anne Norton, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197644348.003.0001
4 Wild Democracy
Many great and good men sufficiently qualified for any task they
should undertake, may ever be found, whose ambition would aspire
to nothing beyond a seat in Congress, a gubernatorial or a presiden-
tial chair; but such belong not to the family of the lion, or the tribe of
the eagle. What! think you these places would satisfy an Alexander,
a Caesar, or a Napoleon?—Never! . . . Distinction will be his para-
mount object, and although he would as willingly, perhaps more so,
acquire it by doing good as harm; yet, that opportunity being past,
and nothing left to be done in the way of building up, he would set
boldly to the task of pulling down.
them to find these enemies and prevent dissent. They resort to cen-
sorship, surveillance, and networks of informants who can, perhaps,
prevent the attacks they fear, yet every piece of information they gather
feeds that fear. Fear spreads, as Arendt describes, until each person
fears everyone else. The apparatus of surveillance and punishment
becomes total, enveloping every person within reach. Surveillance
and informing become part of “a method of dealing with his neighbor
which everyone, willingly or unwillingly, is forced to follow.” No one is
free; all are fearful. This is “a system of ubiquitous spying, where eve-
rybody may be a police agent and each individual feels himself under
constant surveillance.” In the end, because everyone is an enemy to
everyone else, and the state has earned the enmity of all, victims are
“chosen completely at random.” Arendt argued that the “consistent
arbitrariness” of totalitarianism “negates human freedom more effi-
ciently than any tyranny ever could,” for willingly or unwillingly, the
subjects become the eyes and ears and hands of a tyrannical state.6
The tyrant’s fear is a contagion. Fear is the enemy of democracy.
We have every reason to fear authoritarianism, whether it comes to
us in the guise of a man or a state. We have little reason to fear anarchy,
yet the fear of anarchy shadows democracy. Where the people rule,
each person is understood to have standing and freedom. Each has
the right to leave if they choose, rebel if they choose. Each person may
participate, perhaps each person should, but no one can be compelled.
Anarchy is not only a possibility; it is a necessity. Anyone can leave, and
so it is possible that everyone might leave. Anyone can refuse, and so it
is possible that everyone might refuse. That refusal, the right to say no
to rule, is the guarantor of our freedom.
Anarchy is the shadow of democracy in a double sense. Fear of an-
archy shadows democracy. Anarchy is not to be feared; it offers shade,
a place to rest, a place to hide. The shade anarchy offers protects us.
The people who are most free are often not those who govern, but
those who refuse to be governed, not those who join in rule, but those
who refuse to be ruled at all. In America, Patrick Henry argued, the
common man did not want power, still less did he want national glory;
he simply wanted to be let alone: “He enjoys the fruits of his labor,
under his own fig tree, with his wife and children about him, in peace
and security.”7 Jefferson famously wrote that the best government was
8 Wild Democracy
Poets, philosophers, and the people have long recognized that bandits,
pirates, outlaws, and rogues are close to democracy. There are many
reasons for this. For some, this is simply another way of casting the
rule of the people as the madness of the crowd, the rule of the Great
Unwashed, the rise of starved beasts who will fatten on the wealthy.
For those who regard the rule of autocrats or elites as the natural order
of things, democracy is simply a theft of power, and people who rule
themselves are no more than criminals.
The popular imagination of bandit democrats sees it otherwise.
Pirates and bandits are admired for what they refuse and what they
choose, for the wrongs they flee and the wrongs they attempt to right.
Those who steal from the rich and give to the poor are honored and
admired. Those who rob the poor or con the elderly, who extort pro-
tection money or amass great wealth through dishonest means are
scorned. Stories of honest bandits are shadowed by stories of the rich
and disreputable. Wealth, these stories remind us, is not a sign of honor
or merit. There are inequalities to be remedied. In honoring outlaws,
people put the justice of the present order in question.
The bandit, the pirate, the outlaw, and the rogue are all outside law
and custom. All defy order for its own sake. Some, like Robin Hood, are
placed outside the law by unjust rulers. They are law’s exiles. Their out-
lawry is a rebuke to the ruler’s claim to justice. Some bandits are driven
out by poverty. They are a rebuke to a country that cannot provide for
10 Wild Democracy
its own. Other bandits, pirates, and looters defy the laws that govern
property and possessions. Where law produces radical inequality, they
refuse it. All refuse order for order’s sake.
When pirates, bandits, and outlaws band together, like the
Zapatistas, Phoolan Devi’s band, or Robin Hood’s Merry Men, they
choose to rule themselves. They consent to rule and to be ruled.
These remembered or imagined outlaws are, as Hobsbawm and
Scott have argued, primitive rebels who are learning—if they have
not yet mastered—“the art of not being governed.”10 They also point
to a central question for all people: What is one’s own? Bandits who
“steal from the rich and give to the poor” demonstrate a democratic
sensibility. In their rough redistribution of ill-gotten gains, they re-
move one of the most serious obstacles to people ruling themselves.
Woody Guthrie put it this way in his ballad of the outlaw Pretty
Boy Floyd:
Pirates too are on the way to the democratic. Pirates elected their
captains for one voyage, agreed to serve under them, and retained
the right to depose them when they chose. Pirates voted on missions
and on the division of plunder. They also instituted social welfare
programs, providing for those who were hurt or maimed or the fami-
lies of those killed in battle. They included people of all races, all sexu-
alities, “villains of all nations.” Like Hobsbawm’s bandits, the pirates
often served, directly and indirectly, in rebellions against oppressive
rule. They sailed into the unknown. They had the courage of people
who consented to ruling and to being ruled, the longing not to rule at
all.12
Anarchy, courage, democracy 11
Outlaws deserve their name and the ambivalence attached to it. They
are outside the law. Frontier outlaws are beyond law’s reach; often they
are political exiles or refugees whose rebellion precedes their outlawry.
All outlaws, of necessity, live and work outside and often in defiance of
the law. Their actions can show the limits, the fragility, or the injustice
of the law. Bands of outlaws, like those of Pancho Villa, raise the possi-
bility of other political orders, outside or against the state. Where the
state is unjust, they can move easily into revolution. All outlaws put the
commanding power of the law in question. They show the limits of the
law’s power. They show the distance between law and justice.
For Jacques Rancière, democracy belongs to the part that has no part,
to the excluded. In A Renegade History of the United States, Thaddeus
Russell “tells the story of “bad” Americans—drunkards, prostitutes,
“shiftless” slaves and white slackers, criminals, juvenile delinquents,
brazen homosexuals, and others who operated beneath American
society—and shows how they shaped our world, created new pleasures,
and expanded our freedoms.”13 This is, as Russell recognizes, an
American (though not only an American) tradition. These people, the
mad, the bad, the irrepressibly transgressive, mark the boundaries of
sane, moral, and lawful a conduct, putting those boundaries in ques-
tion. They expand dangers as well as possibilities: opening paths and
setting traps. This might be, Russell declares, “history from the gutter
up,” but any look at American culture, at any moment, in any place,
shows people ready to embrace these freedom-loving transgressors.
The antiheros of every genre—videos, novels, comic books, history—
testify to the importance of the rebel to the drive for freedom.
Russell departs from Rancière (or does he?) in seeing the excluded
as alien to democracy. The democratic revolutions turned, he argued,
from external to internal governance. People were called to discipline
themselves. Russell has a keen eye for those forms of coercion that live
in the mind and heart, governing conduct when government is silent—
as well as those formal attempts, even (perhaps especially) by the
partisans of political liberty—to regulate moral conduct. He provides
a detailed account of the “renegades”and their contributions—witting
and unwitting to freedom while recognizing that any world they would
make “would be a living hell.”14 If we are to become democrats, we need
to rule ourselves, but we do well to recognize the cost of the discipline
12 Wild Democracy
democracy demands of the people, and the ways in which it may de-
form us. We need to keep a space for anarchy not only in the world, but
in ourselves. Acts and practices that may seem, at first blush, to be dis-
tant from the political can be salutary political forces.
The rebels, the shiftless, and the transgressive who are suspicious of
power fuel the drive to freedom and the drive to greater justice. They
combat the excesses of those who want to govern too much. They
mock those who have the arrogance to tell others how to pray, how to
dress, what to eat, how to live. They open the possibility of other lives.
Drag queens and voguers changed how people saw and then how they
thought about sexuality, about race, about beauty, about who should be
welcomed when they appeared in the world. Once they were shocking
and outrageous. No more. Now they are ours.
These disobedient ones have served in other ways. Because they dis-
trust power, they may protect others among the powerless. Because
they have the courage of their own judgments, they can stand fast
when rights and the just are under attack.
There is an old poem, written by a man who was a rebel himself,
about those who keep honor safe. Vachel Lindsay’s willfully demo-
cratic and political poetry is out of step with my time but speaks to it
with a directness that pierces the heart:
The bandit, the outlaw, the rogue, the rascal, the battered, and the
shunned live at the very boundary of the country, in the nation but out-
side the state, of the people but outside the law.
When people believe the law has failed them, they may (they
should) turn to the people as a whole. They will have to ask, “Who are
my people?” They will look for guidance to the living and those yet to
Anarchy, courage, democracy 13
The Arabic word shaabi means “of the people,” but democracy is also
“shabby” in the English sense. Democracy is the regime of worn-out
shoes and old clothes, of frayed collars and thrift shops. For Plato, and
many after him, democracy was government of the poor. Democracy
accepts and belongs to those for whom shabbiness is, in Pierre
Bourdieu’s apt phrase, “the choice of necessity.” No one has to dress
up for democracy. Democracy belongs not to special occasions but to
the everyday. Democracy begins not in the halls of government but in
the streets, in bars, and at kitchen tables. You come as you are to dem-
ocratic debates. Politicians who want to signal (as they must) that they
belong to the people take off their suit jackets and roll up their sleeves.
During his 1952 run for the American presidency, Adlai Stevenson
was mocked for having a hole in his shoe. He made it the symbol of
his campaign. The worn-out shoe testified to his hard work and fru-
gality; it marked his efforts to speak to as many people as he could.
The shoe bore witness to his labor. His indifference to the worn shoe
showed an indifference to the marks of wealth and status. That is at the
heart of democratic practice. Every politician who eats a corn dog at a
county fair or sits down at a diner in jeans testifies to the importance of
appearing (at least for the moment) as an equal.
Anarchy, courage, democracy 15
There is nothing new in this. The Scottish poet Robert Burns, who
had proud disdain for show and a deep commitment to the rule of
the people, contrasted their simple dress and manners with those of a
wasteful, empty, and parasitic aristocracy:
They fill us with anxiety. We want to be free and brave, but we make
ourselves docile and fearful. We want to protect the people, but we sow
fears that divide them. We teach our people that they are prey.
The perverse effects of enhanced security are evident in other forms
of security as well.
The enhanced security procedures that followed terrorist attacks in
Europe, the United Kingdom, and the United States made us less safe
and diminished our courage and our dignity. We were taught to walk
through cattle chutes to X-ray machines and thank the people who
pat us down for the privilege. We are told to enhance surveillance by
serving as watchers ourselves. “If you see something, say something”
might at its best remind us that ordinary people have the capacity for
judgment, but it is more likely to make us see the people around us
as potential terrorists. Worse, we may be tempted, we may have been
instructed, to see some people as more dangerous than others. The
Prevent program in the United Kingdom in the early twenty-first cen-
tury required people to report Muslims in danger of radicalization.
The process of being identified as a danger, reported to the state, and
subjected to a program of deliberate reeducation is unlikely to di-
minish radicalization. At each point it reminds the targeted people that
the state sees them as present dangers and potential enemies. At each
point, it instructs them that the state is deploying its powers to sepa-
rate, censor, and instruct them. At each point, it requires them to see
themselves as apart from and feared by their own people.
Those who are targeted in such programs are not well served by
them, but neither are those considered safe. They are taught to see
themselves as prey, fearing every padded coat and backpack, shying
away from any voice speaking, singing, or praying in another language.
They are taught to see authorities not only as protection but as absolu-
tion. They cannot be wrong to report a neighbor, a friend, a child: they
are doing as they are told. They are keeping us safe, while the category
“us” grows ever smaller, ever narrower. They diminish the country they
claim to preserve. They make their people more divided, more bigoted,
more censorious, more fearful than they were.
Franklin Roosevelt was right to declare to a hungry, impoverished,
and desperate people, “We have nothing to fear but fear itself.” Without
fear, with fear mastered, people can go on to do the work they need to
18 Wild Democracy
do together. They can draw on the skills, the generosity, and the courage
of their neighbors. They find that they have no one to depend on but
themselves, and in that knowledge they find solidarity and fortitude.
Fear is not only a weapon of authoritarian rulers and intrusive
states. Fear lives in neighborhoods. Fear lives in the mind. In the
United States, white women were taught to fear Black men. They were
taught that Black men presented a special danger to them, that they
were more likely to be raped or robbed or attacked by Black men.
Those women had already been robbed by white men. They lived
under laws that gave their fathers, brothers, husbands, and guardians
the right to control how and where and with whom they lived, how or
if they earned money, and any funds they earned or inherited. They
lived under laws and the greater power of customs that permitted their
husbands to rape and beat them at will. They knew those men had
power. They knew that power did not always serve them, had some-
times hurt them, always diminished them. Yet they were taught, from
the time of their birth, to see those men as their protectors. Black men
came to recognize that few things in the world were a greater threat
than white women. A lie, a word, an ambiguous glance could outrage
a bigot and inflame a lynch mob. White women, dependent on white
men, could shift from friend to foe in an instant. White women could
not be trusted.
Those laws, that teaching, drew a sharp line between Black men and
white women. Each was taught to fear the other. Each was taught to see
the other as a site of danger. Each was taught that rescue would come,
if it came at all, from the powerful: from white men with standing and
resources. This was the logic of lynching. It made solidarity between
Black men and white women unimaginable for all but great souls.
Black women, indigenous women, Asian women, any woman
marked as different, any woman alone was prey. Such women may have
developed a sharper sense for footsteps in the dark, knowing that they
had no security in a powerful protector. Some still put their faith in
men: men of their own kind or more powerful men. There were times
when their faith was justified. There are always men, always people,
who act with justice and courage when law or custom teach them to do
otherwise. Wiser women learned to rely on themselves.
Anarchy, courage, democracy 19
You may think the time for those fears is past. I think you are wrong.
There are other fears that operate in this way. When people need
money, they may go to their friends. They may go to their parents,
feeling shame. More often they go to the boss, to the bank, to a pawn
shop or a loan shark. They go knowing that they may be denied,
knowing that they are likely to be exploited. Wherever they go, their
need makes them vulnerable. They go to those who are more powerful,
and their appeal strengthens an already present hierarchy.
In each case, in every case, those who have reason to fear are better
served by solidarity than by the protection of the powerful. If fear
drives them, it should drive them to one another. Courage would serve
them better than fear.
People who want to keep their freedom, their equality, their
courage, and their capacity to rule themselves should refuse fear and
teach themselves courage in its place. There are dangers in courage, to
be sure, but those dangers threaten our bodies, not our souls. Living
with freedom and dignity, great among equals, might require us to take
a few risks.
closed doors, to tear down fences, to go farther than they had dared to
go before in pursuit of justice.
Aristocrats wore their courage like jewels. For them, courage was an
ornament, a discreetly displayed excess of something everyone (that
is, everyone who is anyone) was expected to have. Courage, for free
people, is not a distinction; it is a necessity. People who choose to rule
themselves need courage to make themselves a people, courage to de-
bate among themselves and find their way forward ungoverned. They
will need, if they choose, courage to form a government, courage to
maintain that government when they are in the minority, courage to
refuse it when they must.
We are a wild diversity of ever-changing people. No one is wholly
visible to another. No one can be wholly known. In practice, democrats
learn that they must be ruled by the will of people alien to their cus-
toms, their preferences, even their morals. They learn that some of
their fellow citizens oppose their way of life, even their presence. They
learn that some of these people work against them, work even for their
expulsion or annihilation. They live with their enemies. They live with
those they fear. For the most part, they do so fearlessly. All decent pol-
ities endeavor to protect the frail and the fearful. A democratic politics
makes people brave.
Democratic ethics demand that one take things lightly, or, more
precisely, that one act as if one did. The opponents of abortion need not
keep silent. They may speak loudly. They may assemble; they may ag-
itate. They may vote their conscience. They may believe, they may say
as loudly as they can that the practice of abortion is routinized murder.
But while they remain among people who believe otherwise they must
discipline themselves. They will not lynch, they will not bomb, they
will not silence others.
Those who argue that the decision to bear a child belongs to the
woman whose body will hold it must also take that lightly. They know
that opponents of abortion claim power over their bodies. They know
that those who oppose the right to abortion claim to govern their
bodies as intimately and as thoroughly as if they were slaves. They
know that they are called murderers. They know that some opponents
of abortion have bombed abortion clinics and murdered doctors. Yet
they must find the courage to walk among their enemies unafraid.
Anarchy, courage, democracy 21
participated in abortion. There are many issues before us, today and
every day, which make these demands.
The costs these debates exact are not easily seen. They are clear enough
to the woman in chemotherapy whose hair falls on the page as she writes
her congressman on healthcare funding. It may be harder to see the costs
for the man in his seventies who still owes money on his student loans,
or the people who bear the weight of shame and failure because they
make too little money. (Of all things, this is the least shameful and the
most shaming.) Virtually every issue makes grave demands on someone.
Some issues make demands on us all. Every day, all around us, people
face these demands with equanimity. They know the costs of a policy
that will harm them. They know that they may be faced with the defeat of
a cause they honor or the rejection of an ideal they strive for. They know
that the people who threaten these things share their country, their state,
their town. They have the courage to stand fast.
We live with our enemies. Each party longs for the end of its rival.
Right and left, conservative and liberal, we know that the other party
wishes for our defeat. We know they hope to keep us out of power, not
only for this election but for all the elections they can foresee. Our
differences, and our enmities, go far deeper. We know, we democrats,
that there are those who would like to see us dead or exiled, who wish
that we had never been or that we will be no more. A certain kind of
conservative longs for the end, if not of history, at least of the possi-
bility of socialists and socialism, anarchism, radical democracy, and
change altogether. The socialist longs for the end of the capitalist, the
leftist longs for conservatives without power. Many long for the dis-
appearance of the alien and the queer. The Christian fundamentalist
longs for the conversion of the Jew, and the Jew who sees that conver-
sion as a death sees the Christian fundamentalist not as a redeemer but
as an enemy.
We live with our enemies. Where speech is free, they announce
their aims. They seek our annihilation. Perhaps we seek theirs as well.
Perhaps not. Perhaps we are wise enough to see the value of certain
of our enemies. Perhaps we are daring enough to take pride in their
strength. Whether they fall before us or triumph over us, we walk
among our enemies unafraid. This is the courage that belongs to people
who rule themselves.
Anarchy, courage, democracy 23
Courage is required not only to live with our enemies but to live
with one another. Where the people rule, each person lives with uncer-
tainty and change. The people are always changing. People die, people
are born, people are shaped by the people around them. They learn
and they change. People change, and the people changes with them.
Democracies are driven and desiring; they are always changing. The
democrat cannot be certain what the future will bring, cannot even be
certain of the parameters of the present. A democratic life demands
that people face the possibility of change with courage and discipline.
Those changes may compass our annihilation. The practice of democ-
racy is the practice of facing death.
In his Philosophy of History, Hegel gave us a fable. Mankind had its
birth in the East, he wrote. Humanity had its golden youth in Greece,
like the kouroi, beautiful and good, yet it was not yet fully formed.
It was in Europe, in that small center of the world, that it reached its
maturity. Here, humanity grew to wisdom and judgment, finding its
fullest political expression in the state. The fable is wrong, perhaps cor-
rupt, certainly too small to hold us.
This is a European fable. It is an error, but like many fabulous errors,
there is an unexpected, subversive truth in it. The Sun moved reso-
lutely Westward. Asia, with all its grace and antiquity, was left behind.
Africa remained in darkness, “the land of childhood, which lying be-
yond the day of self-conscious history, is enveloped in the dark mantle
of Night.” Hegel’s account of Africa owes much to European ignorance
and the imaginaries of imperialism, but even in this hostile terrain
there is something to be found. “The Negro,” Hegel writes, “as already
observed, exhibits the natural man in his completely wild and un-
tamed state.”19 In this image racialized enslavement and colonial rule
meet human freedom and are overcome. Hegel’s African promises
more for democrats than does his European. There was no place for the
Antipodes at all. But if the sun moved westward, what of the Americas?
“America is therefore the land of the future, where, in the ages that
lie before us, the burden of the World’s History shall reveal itself.” This
is “a land of desire.” The Americas, Hegel held, were the Eveningland,
the land of the unknown, “and the dreams to which it may give rise.”20
The Americas posed a problem for Hegel. Was this, as the Egyptians
held, the land of death? If it were, was that land the place of annihilation
24 Wild Democracy
acts of courage. We honor those who go to sea not knowing what land,
if any, lies ahead. We honor those who go into space, into unmapped
deserts and the deepest trenches of the ocean. Facing the unknown
is what we were born to. Those impelled by that drive answer a high
calling of humanity.
We are, perhaps unknowingly, accustomed to the demands of death.
We are the people of the Eveningland.21 We look toward our own deaths
and we are not afraid. We are Vikings. We sail off into the unknown.
Democracy is the practice of a little death, of many small
annihilations. Democracy requires that at some moment one will
cease to be. You will be ruled. You will be overruled. The people will
decide against what you will. The people will decide against you. Your
voice will be silenced, your hopes defeated, your will lost. In every
election, in each debate, in reports of public opinion, in reading
bumper stickers and yard signs you are brought face to face not only
with the possibility of defeat but with the prospect of your annihila-
tion. The will of the people will wash over your vision, your aims, your
will, your voice like a great sea. You will be lost in it. All that you love
and honor will be lost.
In the face of this devastation, more profound than death and
encountered long before it, you learn courage. You learn to stand for
your ideals when they are mocked or rejected. You learn to speak when
speech is dangerous. You learn to act when success is far away and even
hope is gone. You learn to make your own judgments about right and
wrong. You learn to doubt the wisdom of those whose opinions are
more popular. You learn to doubt your own. You are forced to a life of
choice and refusal, reflection and will. You learn to be thoughtful in the
midst of doubt, brave in the face of enemies, courageous in facing the
always present possibility of loss.
And then, perhaps you rise.
We are taken up and moved with the people as by waves on a sea.
We may will what the people will and move willingly. We may resist,
and the sea will flow over us like water over rocks. We may be moved,
changed in place and time unwillingly. Yet that sea, however great, may
also be changed in its course. We can hold fast. We can go forward on
that sea. We can learn to sail.
26 Wild Democracy
People who can rule themselves excel at taking risks. The decision
to set aside the comfort of kings or lord protectors or of leaving the
decisions to the expert few is itself a great risk. People who rule them-
selves go willingly into an uncertain future. The decision to become a
people—not the armed revolution that is so often necessary to affirm
it, not the institutions and governments the people may establish—
is the moment a people is born. They speak themselves into being.
In the long reach of time, this choice has often meant accepting the
need for revolution. People accept revolution with all the danger it
involves. They risk all, “their lives, their fortune, and their sacred
honor.” They may lose their lives or the lives of those they love. They
may be maimed. They may kill or maim others. They may take sin
upon themselves. They may fail. They may end impoverished. They
may be remembered only as traitors. They take the risk. They choose
to go together, to work together, though they know that their aims
may diverge. They know they are working not only with their friends
but with those who may have been, or may prove to be, their enemies.
They take the risk.
People who rule themselves take this risk not only at the moment of
the founding but for the entire time of their existence. They may, they
will, seek to fence risk out with laws and constitutions, with customs
and practices. They may, they will, cultivate a respect for those laws
and constitutions, for precedent, for their forebears, for the past. But
they have eaten of the Tree of Knowledge. They know they can rebel.
Day after day, they are confronted by risk. There are the ordinary
risks that nature, perhaps Nature’s God, and certainly other human
beings, pose to any people. There will be earthquakes and hurricanes,
cyclones and tsunamis. There will be forest fires. There will be floods.
The people, not the monarch, not the autocrat, not even the state
they establish, will be expected to deal with catastrophes. They know
that they must demand that the state respond. They know they are to
judge that response. They know they can respond faster than any state.
People can reach further than states or state officials, respond more
quickly and more thoughtfully. They must anticipate other disasters.
They expect themselves to learn.
Anarchy, courage, democracy 27
So it is with the threat of war. People who rule themselves must meet
the threat of war not as states but as people. When they declare war,
when they marshal their defenses, they do so not only as rulers but as
the ruled. They will make the decision and they will bear the costs. The
burden must fall not on the few but upon all.
All the threats—natural disasters, economic catastrophes, war and
the threat of war—are present to democrats, as they are to all people.
The difference is that democrats are obliged to judge, consider, and
respond. They cannot assign that responsibility to others. They are
called—each separately and in common—to judgment and to action.
For people who are ruled, the great risks of war and famine, disease,
disaster, and pogroms are something to fear. Perhaps the powerful and
wealthy can protect themselves. Perhaps states, churches, temples,
and mosques will protect the weak. Perhaps not. For people who rule
themselves, these threats, these risks, these dangers are problems to be
solved, for all, together.
There are other risks. These are risks we choose. When people are
free, their minds and hands are unbound. They will explore, invent,
take up great projects. Not all these ventures will end well. Explorers
will be lost; inventions will have dangerous consequences. Bridges will
collapse; new drugs will have unlooked-for side effects. Projects will
fail. They are worth the risk.
Democrats become good at taking risks: adept at assessing them,
clever at mitigating them, quick to respond to them, and, above all,
unafraid. Courage gives them daring; judgment gives them caution;
practice gives them power.
The greatest risk is the risk we pose to one another. This is the great
risk of a common life. As the unflinching Thomas Hobbes recognized,
“anyone can kill anyone else.” We are always dangerous to one another.
Ruling ourselves requires us to become adept at both friendship and
enmity. We learn to defeat our enemies when we can, work with them
when we cannot. We learn the joy and duties of friendship. We learn
that there will be moments of enmity in friendship. We learn that there
can be moments of friendship between enemies. We face the risks of
a common life not blindly but with our eyes open. We have courage
enough. We can work together and win through to a common life. We
can learn when to work together, when to resist, when to rebel.
II
Free people keep something wild
in them
Wild Democracy. Anne Norton, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197644348.003.0002
Free people keep something wild in them 29
The idea that one might have a duty to rebel may seem shocking or
perverse. It should not. Those who believe that governments should
be ruled by the people should recognize that any failure to meet that
standard imposes a duty. It is the people’s duty to correct a government
that they, after long endurance and reflection, determine to be irrep-
arable. It is their duty to rebel against a government whose evils they
cannot overcome.That duty requires judgment and self-discipline.
That duty belongs to us all.
We should rebel more often.
Instead shame falls on those who have no reason for shame. Those
who are not wealthy are taught, day by day, that they should want these
possessions. They are taught that they would be better if they had them,
that they are less than those who do have them. They are seduced into
shame. Lacking glory themselves, they may embrace the glory of a race
or nation. As their fear lost them their liberty, their shame costs them
their judgment and their honor.
The United States did not succeed in warding off the allure of glory
or the glamour of evil. There is, as Henry feared, a standing army,
despite constitutional efforts to prevent it.5 The need for military
appropriations to be approved by Congress every two years is a ragged
remnant, the bleached bones of the Constitution’s initial bravery. The
long history of wars of conquest against the indigenous tribes and a
growing ambition to rival the empires of Europe have been justified in
all the languages of fear and ambition. Americans are not yet free of it.
The fearful passion for imperial glory has not gone uncontested.
Washington’s Farewell Address warned against military adventurism
and condemned “overgrown military establishments which, under
any form of government, are inauspicious to liberty, and which are to
be regarded as particularly hostile to republican liberty.”6 Washington
was admirably immune to glory, rebuffing Hamilton’s monarchical
ambitions, refusing a third term, and avoiding the gold braid and
ribbons of military authority that have corrupted so many revolu-
tionary leaders in the Old World and the New. He did not succeed,
however, in preventing the hunger for imperial glory in others.
We have forgotten many of the wars we fought. The expansion of
the United States across the continent was accompanied by Indian
wars and the forced removal of many tribes. Looking back, we honor
Hin-mah-too-yah-lat-kekt, Chief Joseph, not the generals to whom
he surrendered. We have forgotten their names. We remember his
courage, his care for his people, and the hard choices he made to se-
cure them. We know, we Americans, that the Nimiipuu, the Nez Percé,
were wronged. We know they acted honorably and with courage and
judgment. We have come to honor them far more than we honor the
troops the United States set against them. The same could be said of
Tȟatȟáŋka Íyotake (Sitting Bull); Shi- ka-
She (Cochise); Goyaałé
(Geronimo); and the host of tribal leaders we honor and remember.
32 Wild Democracy
The Indian wars (fought from before 1776 into the twentieth century)
are now a source of shame and regret. Yet we are a settler colony. We
have much to learn, much to mourn, much to repent, much to repair,
much to overcome.7
Theirs was not the only blood shed in pursuit of glory.
The Mexican War gave us the porous, ever-shifting borderlands that
Trump and others have sought to divide. It would be hard for anyone
raised in the West—perhaps in any part of the United States—to im-
agine an America without the words, religion, buildings, foods, music,
clothing, and legends of Mexico. The Mormon Wars, more thoroughly
forgotten, followed the assassination of Joseph Smith. Smith’s disciples
were chased from one town to another, pursued by lynchings, harried
ever farther west. Once Mormons were outlaws; now they are senators.
The Church of Latter Day Saints is now an ordinary part of the fabric
of American life.
The pursuit of glory in the American move westward brought us
riches, but they came from the generous hands of those we defeated.
The glory generals won has turned to shame and ashes. The indigenous
people they fought gave us models of freedom and courage. They have
given us works of extraordinary craft and power and ways of seeing
beauty and finding guidance in the natural world. In the shadow of
plutocracy and climate change, the Lakota and their allies have stood
fast in defense of the idea and practice of the commons.8 They have tes-
tified that the desire for profit must give way to the welfare of the land
and the people. They rightly argue that treaties must be honored. They
testify to the sacred.
The turn of the nineteenth century saw the United States embroiled
in foreign wars. Now, when long wars in distant places are more fa-
miliar to us, we may look with more suspicion on the passion for glory.
We have learned that with these we have to bear not only the deaths of
our own soldiers but the deaths of innocents; we have to bear not only
the costs of glory but the shame that is its underside.
At the turn of the nineteenth century, the passion for glory was at
its height. Americans entered the Philippines as allies of the Filipino
rebels against Spanish colonialism. From 1898 to 1946 we served as
Spain’s successor in colonial rule. There were those, like Theodore
Roosevelt, who dreamed of empire and hoped for a people hungry for
Free people keep something wild in them 33
glory. “If we are to be a really great people we must play a great part in
the world,” he declared. He could conceive of greatness only as war. He
despised, he said, “the man of timid peace” and those “who cant about
liberty and the consent of the governed.” Americans, he hoped, would
be “stern men with empire in their eyes” and “mothers of many healthy
children.”9 In the debates over the American role in the Philippines,
senators like Henry Cabot Lodge called for the United States to “step
forward boldly and take its place at the head of nations.” This was
prompted by a naked desire for power and profit, justified by racial ar-
rogance and religious bigotry.
Conquest, declared Senator Albert Beveridge, was “the mission
of our race, trustee under God of the civilization of the world,” for
“Almighty God” has “marked us as His chosen people, henceforth to
lead in the regeneration of the world.” Indeed, God had gone farther,
determining with divine omniscience that as “most future wars will be
conflicts for commerce,” the nation’s future should be “permanently
anchored at a spot selected by the strategy of Providence” to command
the China trade, for “that power that rules the Pacific is the power that
rules the world.” The language of piety veiled blasphemy. Beveridge saw
God as the servant of merchants. The “American Republic” was treated
with no greater respect. The “world-redeeming work of our imperial
race” required nothing less than the abandonment of the Constitution
and the Declaration of Independence.10
Lodge made that explicit. He argued that that the destruction of
the western tribes had made it clear. In driving the Cherokee off their
lands, in the devastation of tribal peoples, “all questions about the con-
sent of the governed went down into nothingness as they deserved to
go.”11 He shared Roosevelt’s contempt for those “who cant about lib
erty and the consent of the governed.” For Lodge, for Beveridge, for
Roosevelt and all those who shared in the lust for glory, democracy
and republicanism were myths for children. The self-evident truths
of the Declaration were fairy tales that an older and wiser nation—an
empire—would surely reject.
We have forgotten many of those who kept faith with the
Declaration. While Lodge, Beveridge, and Roosevelt boasted of the
virtues of the “Teuton” and the “Anglo-Saxon,” Senator George Hoar
bore witness to “the God who made of one blood all the nations of the
34 Wild Democracy
the principles upon which the Nation rests; it can employ force in-
stead of reason; it can substitute might for right; it can conquer
weaker people; it can exploit their lands, appropriate their property,
and kill their people, but it cannot repeal the moral law, or escape the
punishment decreed for the violation of human rights.
The steadfast opposition of Bryan and the People’s Party speaks pow-
erfully against the contemporary confusion of populism and na-
tionalism. Bryan spoke for the consent of the governed not only in
the United States but in all the world. He spoke against empire. His
opponents spoke of Providential destiny and the nation. Bryan saw
Free people keep something wild in them 35
moral duty and the rights of all people. Bryan, Hoar, and their allies
lost. The United States did not extricate itself from war and colonial
rule in the Philippines for forty-seven years. We are still enthralled by
empire. Empire is a betrayal of democracy.
This was, this is an American story of temptation and corruption and
of courage and struggle against imperialism. There are other stories,
other histories, for this is not only an American struggle. The French
revolutionaries fell prey to glory in Napoléon. The proud nation of the
Revolution and the Commune fell into empire, with colonies across
the world. Nation after nation has fallen prey to revolutionaries who,
when the work of revolution seemed to be accomplished, lost their re-
spect for the people and their commitment to justice and claimed the
powers of a monarch. Long before and after these, predatory rulers
have sought glory by preying on the people.
Glory lies in ruling ourselves alone.
to accept rule with dignity and grace and without fear is admirable.
Their ability to accept rule without violence is necessary. Once, while
watching a presidential election, my friend went to bed before the
results were clear. When I asked how she could do that, she said, “I
know there won’t be tanks in the street in the morning.” The commit-
ment to accept being ruled without immediately taking up arms testi-
fies to the trust a people must have in one another. Yet it also testifies
to their courage, to face an uncertain future with equanimity. We can
no longer be sure about the tanks. We must stay awake through all the
watches of the night.
People who rule themselves accept the idea that they may lose, that
their ideas will sometimes be cast aside in favor of others they reject.
Though they can—and usually will—hold to their positions and prin-
ciples, they accept that they will be ruled, at least for a time, in ways
they do not approve and would not choose. They will wait and watch
and judge the outcome. They will dissent, protest, organize, educate.
They may change their minds. They may rebel. More often, they hold
fast, work, and wait. The discipline of equality is not something they
demand only from the powerful. They demand it of themselves.
The citizen is also, and most importantly, sovereign. It is not the
recognition of other states, still less the recognition of international
organizations, that makes a state. It is the people. The consent of the
governed is the only legitimate ground for state authority. The sover-
eign people stand before, behind, beneath, and above the state. The
power to make a people before that people makes a state lies in each
person’s hands.
Sovereignty belongs to the citizen not only as part of the people but
as one person. If one is to rule as well as to be ruled, one must learn
sovereignty. The citizen is required not only to submit to rule but to
rule: to hold power and use it well. Those moments when the people
come together are few and fugitive, yet the rule of the people is active
and omnipresent. The people, as Tocqueville recognized, “hover above
the entire life of the state, just as God does above the world, as the cause
and end of all things.” Though that present appears distant and invis-
ible, it is within reach. Citizens are required not merely to rule for but
to rule as the people. They have a duty to seek the common good. They
also have a duty to act for it. They have a duty to rule. They are called to
judge. They are called to make law. They are called to enforce the law.
Free people keep something wild in them 37
They are called to defy it. Sovereignty does not belong to the exception.
Sovereignty is a commonplace.
Some of the work of ruling comes formally, in the work of juries,
town halls, and elections. The greater part (in every sense) comes out-
side, below, and beyond laws and institutions. Burke’s wisdom was to
recognize that people constitute themselves in the crafting of custom
and convention. They decide what they are to be, in common and in
practice. This is, as Burke saw, a long slow process in the life of a people,
but people do that work in uncounted decisions that are usually the
work of a moment. Some of those moments change the course of the
people like a rock in a stream.
We honor individual acts of authority. We saw that strength and
power in Greta Thunberg, sitting outside her high school with a hand-
lettered sign. She held fast, and the world shifted. Acts that shift worlds
are not always noticed. The people, the democrats who walk through
the world as the eyes and hands and voice of sovereignty rule the com-
monplace unnoticed. The one who sees a wrong, who says no to a
small injustice, who raises a hand to hold back force, who acts for the
common good or the rights of one, embodies sovereignty and makes it
a force in the world.
Subjects belong to monarchs, citizens to nations and to states. In
a democracy, the distinction between citizen and person should be
slight and suspect. Citizens should value the rights given to them by
law far less than those they hold within themselves. As the Declaration
of Independence (and not only the Declaration) has affirmed, the
rights that belong to all people are inalienable.
They cannot be taken. They cannot be bought and sold. They cannot
be given away.
The rights of citizens and subjects are far more fragile. The rights of
subjects ultimately depend on the will of the monarch. Where the auto-
cratic character of monarchy is tempered, as in the United Kingdom, by
deference to an unwritten constitution, the subject’s vulnerability may
be lessened by law, long-established practice and convention. There,
the rights of citizens are dependent on law and the state. They are not
rights at all: they are gifts, privileges granted by the state and the law, as
monarchs grant them to their subjects. What law grants, law may take
away. What the state protects it may attack. When law or the state is seen
as the source of rights, citizens are encouraged to defer to law and the
38 Wild Democracy
state. They are told that they owe their rights not to “Nature and Nature’s
God” or to their own humanity but to a bureaucratic dictum. They are
not their own masters. Still less are they the masters of the state. They
have nowhere to stand against unjust laws or an abusive state.
Hannah Arendt, like too many intellectuals, believed that rights
were the gift of law and the state. She had known persecution, exile, and
statelessness. She recognized the need for rights, yet she could not bring
herself to accept that rights exist before, beyond, above, and outside the
law. She argued, therefore, for “the right to have rights.” This demand is
as contrived as it sounds. The demand leaves the question of what rights
might be granted or denied to a state or an international organization of
states. Whether one has or does not have rights is left to the judgment
of lawyers and officials. The argument that human rights are the work
of a consensus of international organizations, the gift of international
law, rests the claim to rights—even the “right to have rights”—upon this
all too fragile foundation. This view makes lawyers and legal scholars,
states and organizations the arbiters of claims to rights. Those who give
can take away. The right to have rights is no right at all.
Subjects and citizens can be exiled. They can be forced to become
refugees. Their belonging to states and nations can be given and taken
away like a passport. Yet they still carry within them their inalienable
rights: the rights that belong to all human beings. Subject, citizen,
exile, or refugee, people carry their rights within them. When they are
forced back upon themselves, their rights remain. When they move,
whether from home to work or into exile, they carry their rights with
them. They cannot lose their rights, for those rights are inalienable.
Their rights are as much a part of them as their hands or their heart.
Their rights are held in their bodies. They are right incarnate.
and their own will, do not submit easily to others: “The memory of
their ancient liberty will not and cannot allow them to rest.”16
Free people shun both obedience and authority. Yet when they
choose they can be very good at both.
Free people obey freely. When they choose to come together as a
people, they do so willfully. They make their people, their country,
their nature, even their state their own. They are transformed by this.
Rousseau saw that this decision made the consenting person “an in-
telligent being, and a man.”17 People become, in one moment, both
more than themselves and more themselves. They acquire a being—as
an American or an Indian or a Palestinian—that is larger in time and
space than the limits of a single life. Their interest suddenly extends to
all those they now see as their own. They have a presence in the past
with their dead compatriots, and a presence in the future with those
who are yet to be. This belonging, this presence in time past and time
future is the work of their will, their conviction, their love. The alle-
giance that overcomes their solitude is more profound because it is the
gift of their solitude.
Knowing that they are part of a people does not end that solitude
or overcome the differences that belong to each person. On the con-
trary, it throws their personal characters into high relief. They look
around at their countrymen and see how very alien they are. They dis-
cover they are not like all others. They don’t listen to the same music,
like the same paintings, or eat the same food. They have different
aims, different ideals. They compete for jobs. They may not share
the same gods, the same goals, the same hopes for their people. They
come to take pride in certain of their differences. They come to treas
ure others. Small differences mark out families and neighborhoods.
For those who belong freely to one people, the differences among
them become sites of greater intimacy and pleasure. They take them
to heart.
Led by these passions for the places and people they take as their
own, they follow passionately. They take pride in their obedience to
laws they make themselves. They may take pride in obedience to laws
they reject, while they struggle to change them. That is pride in their
self-discipline, pride in their capacity to rule themselves. They will
show that discipline even in disobedience.
Free people keep something wild in them 41
In many languages, the word for rights is also the word for law. Not in
mine. Rights are the name my people give to the democratic demand. It
is easier to speak of rights when the name does not call up a debt to law.
Rights are before, above, and beyond the law. Rights are demands all
people make, demands that call from the flesh. Rights make demands
on us. Rights do not merely impose obligations; they command us.
These democratic demands call us to witness, to recognize, to shelter
and to nourish, to cultivate, to do justice, and to rebel.
Rights are written in the flesh. They follow from the human condi-
tion. They are grounded in embodiment. They are demanded by body
and mind as each strives toward the fullness of the human, toward the
fullness of each particular human.
The right to life is the simplest right, but from this right many others
follow. If you have the right to protect yourself and preserve your life,
you have a right to what is necessary for that. You have a right to food.
As St. Thomas Aquinas affirmed in the Summa Theologica, it is no sin
to steal food if food is needed: “It is not theft, properly speaking, to
take secretly and use another’s property in a case of extreme need: be-
cause that which he takes for the support of his life becomes his own
property by reason of that need.”1 Indeed, the saint argued, it is no sin
to steal for others who need food. For the same reason, the right to
preserve yourself gives you a right to clothing and shelter: to what you
need to protect yourself from the elements. The idea that healthcare
is a human right is not an imaginative expansion of rights: it is simple
common sense. Healthcare is needed by all who have bodies, which is
to say, everybody. You have a right to care for your health, for without
that you cannot preserve your life. Food, shelter, and healthcare must
Wild Democracy. Anne Norton, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197644348.003.0003
44 Wild Democracy
be secured to all because these are necessary to secure the rights of all
people to preserve their lives.
There is a mind sheltered in the body. That mind, and the soul and
spirit with which it dwells, rely on the body. These too require preser-
vation. They need the protection of the body that shelters them, but
they need more. The mind requires its own food: education, tools,
training, and resources. Securing the preservation of life, liberty, and
the pursuit of happiness requires us to secure the ability of all people
to learn.
If you have a right to liberty, you have a right to move away from
oppression and exploitation. You have the right to leave. You have the
right to migrate: to flee persecution, to flee war and violent criminality,
to find work and preserve your life. You have a right to protect that
liberty which is essential to you. Without it, you are nothing but an
object in the world, the tool, problem or prey of others. The right to lib
erty enables you to become human: to protect your life, your ability to
think, worship, honor, and live as you choose.
Does this imply that other bodies bear rights? Yes, it does. The rec-
ognition that people hold their rights in their bodies, that their rights
are born and carried in their flesh, drives us to the recognition that
other bodies have claims that cannot be set aside. The idea that the dog,
the cat, the elephant, the sage grouse, and the industrially produced
chicken have rights and claims on us is both familiar and unfamiliar.
Ordinary people have the profound sense that animals expect some-
thing from us and that they are right to do so. We understand that we
have a duty to all in the natural world. Their rights are entangled with
our own. We recognize, too, that we should defer to the freedoms and
claims of cats (for example) differently than we defer to those of lions,
human beings, or dogs.
The rights of other bodies—of grass and trees, rivers and oceans—
are also familiar and unfamiliar. People recognize that it is wrong to
despoil, to waste, to dirty what has been clean. We recognize that such
acts are unjust and that they do practical harm to things in the world.
New Zealand’s courts have given a legal form to the rights indigenous
people ascribed to specific rivers and mountains. The indigenous un-
derstanding of these rivers and mountains as beings that have rights
has made its way into once alien judicial institutions. New Zealanders
Rights are born in the body 45
All rights live in the right to a life. I chose the form that belongs to
my people. Their language echoes Rainsborough’s declaration that “the
poorest he that is in England has a right to live as the greatest he.”2
Rainsborough’s statement is compelling in its simplicity. He gives
it in plain language. Anyone, the poorest man or woman in the
country, could hear and understand him. This is a revolutionary
claim. Rainsborough sees that the democratic demand for the rights
every body has by nature leads directly to the right people have to rule
themselves.
The claim leads farther than we—even we who believe in natural
rights—often recognize. Rainsborough is claiming not just life, bare
life, but a life, the whole of a human life, the life that each of us has to
live. What is this? This is the democratic demand: a demand that every
person be able to live a full life. This is an argument not only for bread
but for roses, not for bare life but for an education, the tools of a trade,
for all that is necessary to make a human life.
The right to liberty is the right to shape a self in the world and to
shape that world. People who rule themselves do as they think best,
alone and together. The right to liberty entails the right to move freely
in the world. To come and to go, to stay or to emigrate. Liberty also
embraces all the political rights: the right to consent to government
and to withdraw that consent, to judge and to act on that judgment,
to speak freely, to assemble. People with the right to rule themselves
are called to rule themselves. People who rule themselves bow before
Rights are born in the body 47
A life is at once a life apart and a life together. Democrats need to pre-
serve those anarchic spaces where people are ungoverned and so can
remain ungovernable. A full life is a life with others. That begins in
the right to assemble. People have the right to work together to make
space for themselves, in families, among their friends, in towns, wher-
ever they please. They come together to shape the world as they think
best. They gather to rule themselves willingly. They also gather to
govern, reproach, challenge, and overthrow the governments they
create, powers that rise to dominate them, threats to their freedom.
The right to assemble, to appear together in all the fragility and power
of the body, secures both their common good and their freedom to
live apart.
In the United States, but not only in the United States, the right
to assemble has been eroded. We are told that we can assemble only
with the permission of the government and under the eye of the po-
lice. We can assemble only at certain places and at certain times. When
we assemble we are fenced in and herded like cattle through the pre-
appointed route of a permitted march. There are penalties for those the
police determine are disturbing the peace or not observing the limits
of their license to demonstrate. This is not exercising the right to as-
semble. This is permitting the state to take it away.
In the wake of the March on Washington, Malik el Shabazz, Malcolm
X, recognized the limits of this iconic and redemptive assembly: “They
controlled it so tight—they told those Negroes what time to hit town,
how to come, where to stop, what signs to carry, what song to sing,
48 Wild Democracy
what speech they could make, and what speech they couldn’t make;
and then told them to get out of town by sundown.”3
It is easy and convenient to accept the restrictions on marches and
demonstrations (which is to say, on our right to assemble). There is
an implicit contract, quite often breached, that if the marchers and
demonstrators stay in their place, the police will protect them. In any
case, people know the route in advance, and they can plan, if not for an
escape in time of danger (that may be blocked by the fences and inhib-
ited by the presence of the police) at least for their trip home if things
remain orderly, and for an escape if they do not. None of this, however,
needs to be honored. Officials can suggest, and people can follow these
suggestions if they choose. Accepting the limits imposed by the state
may make revolutionary change possible. Yet it is a price, a burden,
and a constraint that we should recognize and resist when resistance
is necessary.
The right to assemble is a right. No license is necessary. No permit,
no permission is required. When people accede to licenses and
permits, it should be their choice alone and ought not to be done too
often. Governments, and the people themselves, must learn again
that the right to assemble is a right and not a privilege. Corporations,
banks, and factories must learn that rights reach farther than the state.
Assemblies of free people can be displays of great recklessness and
courage. The world has watched the people of Hong Kong rally in de-
fense of their remaining liberties. They are the people Machiavelli
described, who, having lived in freedom under their own laws, re-
member their ancient liberties even when they are lost. Sometimes the
will to rule themselves seems to come not from a remembered history
but from nowhere. We watch the people of Thailand struggle toward
a democracy they have never known. The rebellious people may have
little or no freedom to remember, but they drive toward justice all
the same.
We watched the people of Tahrir Square rise up. People all over the
world who had never been to Egypt or known an Egyptian sent one
another videos showing the courage of the Egyptian people. There
is a video of an Egyptian in London, Waseem Wagdi, that I watched
in that time (and often since). He is a middle-aged man in a camel’s
hair sports jacket and a scarf, with a composed, educated manner and
Rights are born in the body 49
One of the rights sought by those who face the naked power of the state
is the right to remain silent. Those who intend to rule themselves know
Rights are born in the body 51
that they must defend their bodies to keep their souls free. The closed
body, safe from coercion, protected from dependence on others,
shelters the open mind.
Lawyers and scholars have debated whether the right to privacy is a
right at all. They are wrong to doubt it. Privacy is a right so profound
and fundamental that it has become invisible. Without the right to pri-
vacy we lie naked before the eyes of whatever state or corporate power
can place us under surveillance. We are in their power. Without the
right to keep our bodies to ourselves we are no better than slaves the
master can violate at will. Without the right to keep our bodies whole
and healthy and in the forms we choose, we are dependent and, again,
enslaved.
Those who can reach into your body have you at their mercy. This is
the case whether it is the government, a corporation, a religious organ
ization, or a private person.
The right to remain within yourself is also the right to remain silent.
This is one of the prized rights of the Anglo-American political tradi-
tion. It was claimed by those who were asked to take oaths of loyalty
to the ruler and the established church. It is claimed by those on trial
who argue that they cannot be compelled to testify against themselves.
Though it is honored in the Anglo-American constitutions, it is not
confined there. This right belongs to all.
The right to remain silent affirms the right of every person to speak
where and when they choose. The right to freedom of speech is allied
to the right to freedom of conscience.
Freedom of speech is also intimately related to freedom of the press.
The concentration of media in a few hands means that a few control
what can be read or heard, what can be written in the papers or on
billboards, what can be heard on the radio or seen on TV, even (per-
haps especially) what can be seen or heard or read online. When only
those who have wealth can speak or make themselves heard, freedom
of speech is not fully established. When those who have wealth or
power determine what can be said or heard, speech is not free.
If we cannot yet meet as equals in the public sphere, still less can
we meet as equals at work. When we meet each other at home, we can
question, challenge, and reason with each other. At work we know
that we must be silent. It is now taken for granted in many, perhaps
52 Wild Democracy
In a time when there are those who are truly silenced—by the state,
by the media, by corporations, by bosses, and by the people around
them—it is unseemly for the privileged and the powerful to claim that
they are silenced. It is dishonorable for them to demand a hearing on
false pretenses. Honorable people will recognize their power and seek
out those who are less often heard. That will not be easy. People are held
within circles of family, friendship, work, religion, and acquaintance.
While inequality persists, approaches to those less wealthy or powerful
than themselves will be awkward, limited by distrust, anger, deference,
or despair. Those without power find that approaches to the privileged
are forestalled at every step. Inequality is the enemy of freedom.
Freedom of speech is not merely the right to speak without being
silenced by censorship. It is the right to speak freely: to say what you
choose, not a script dictated to you by another. There are still efforts to
make people speak a script written by another: to denounce terrorism,
to confess their sexuality, to refuse this or that. There are still efforts to
make people speak against their will. These violate freedom of speech
as profoundly as silencing does. They are the softer face of torture.
Torture is the effort of one person, often though not always in the
service of a state, to make another speak against their will. Those who
have studied (and those who have experienced) torture have learned
that the tortured do not speak the truth. They speak as they are com-
pelled to speak. The speech that is wrung from them through suffering
is speech to end suffering, speech that signals submission. It may or
may not disclose a hidden truth; it is no more and no less than the tri-
umph of the torturer’s will. Torture is the triumph of force over con-
sent. Free people cannot use, cannot license, torture.
Let the silent speak if they choose. Let those who speak say what
they will. Listen and judge.
Democracy begins when people seize power for themselves. The pro-
cess of making their government to suit themselves begins when they
come together, acting together, binding their aims in a common cause.
54 Wild Democracy
Those who watch and study and, above all, those who police
demonstrations look for leaders and organizers. The people who as-
semble rarely do. They look to each other. They may listen to speakers;
more often they do not. They turn from speakers and talk to each other.
They are many, yet in that crowd they retain their individuality. They
come and go as they please. They chant or refuse to chant. Sometimes
they sing. They choose to be loud or silent, joyful or somber. They
choose to stand fast or to run, to fight or to refuse the fight. Assemblies
remind us that solidarity is possible in anarchy, that an anarchic dis-
position and anarchic commitments do not foreclose the possibility of
acting with others.
The anthropologist Victor Turner wrote that assemblies can loosen
all the restraints of law and custom. People feel free and act on it. They
are unbound. In their freedom they can affirm or refuse their govern-
ment, their laws, their customs, and their people. They know that they
make and unmake governments and people. They can refuse what has
been for what could be. Turner saw this embedded in the coming-of-
age rituals of many peoples. It was, he argued, part of “the ritual pro-
cess.”5 Accepting new people into the group or tribe—or nation—alters
the boundaries of the people. Acceptance changes not only those who
are newly included but those who change with their changing people.
That change, Turner argued, was the occasion for joy.
future.” One heritage, one form of life alone can form an ethical person.
People within communities should not be permitted to venture out-
side them in thought. “Outside influences” should be bound by the
community, and people should “receive such contributions only from
its hands.”6 Though she sees the defects of her own time and place, and
of the Romans, the Hebrews, the Americans, and a host of others, she
does not appear to recognize that the power of communities to shape
people can be distorting, imprisoning, and corrupting. Uprootedness
can be liberating and enlightening.
Too much turns on the metaphor of roots. That image sees belonging
as bound to a place, disturbed by movement. That is not how people
are made. People are made to stay and to go, to dig into the earth, to
build from it and walk through it. People can leave the earth to sail or
to fly—metaphorically as well as actually. Weil recognizes that “[r]isk is
an essential need of the soul,” yet she is limited by her fear of loss: “The
destruction of the past is perhaps the greatest of all crimes.”7
You have the right to a place in the world. You have the right to move.
The right to be in the world depends in practice on the right to
leave one place for another. Frederick Douglass, who knew the need
to move, wrote of a “right to migration.”8 A slave who escaped his
masters—and the law—he found his voice grew stronger as he moved
steadily northward. There are many kinds of people on the move.
Douglass was an escaped slave, a refugee, an American intellectual
in Ireland and Britain, an American ambassador. There are refugees
fleeing war, seeking to preserve their lives and the lives of those they
call their own. There are the refugees made by natural disasters: floods
and earthquakes, hurricanes and tornados. There are refugees made
by our irresponsibility before nature: drought, dust bowls, floods, and
wildfires. There are migrants who flee hunger. All these (and more)
have a right to go out into the world because they have the right to life.
There are also people pressed by needs as imperative as, though per-
haps less visible than, escaping wars and earthquakes. Local commu-
nities are often praised for their closeness, for the trust and kinship of
the people within them. They are honored by many for their ability
to maintain themselves over time, to develop their own ways. These
communities, however warm and nurturing to some, may be stifling
to others. People who do not feel at home there have the right to leave.
Rights are born in the body 57
Perhaps they will find homes elsewhere. Perhaps they will always walk
like Kipling’s cat, by their wild lone.
A community too may decide that is does not belong. Perhaps colo-
nial rule has become indefensible to them. Perhaps they have been per-
secuted. Perhaps they have simply grown apart from those they once
regarded as their own. They should not be compelled to stay.
All people have the right to leave: to leave homes, communities,
practices, and pasts behind.
If there is no place to go, the right to leave is empty. I will not pretend
that I can decide for you, or that I can decide in principle, or indeed
that we can decide in principle all that we owe or what we can justly
deny to migrants and refugees. Rogers Smith has argued that we owe
more to immigrants and refugees we have burdened in the past: the
people who have fought our wars, the people we made war against.9
This is a compelling criterion for judgment. There are simpler duties.
People carry their rights in their bodies. Those who breach the
borders, who appear petitioning at the gate, who wash up on the shore,
carry their rights with them. The rights that belong to all belong to
them. They have a right to all that is necessary to maintain life, a right
to fundamental freedoms. Though those rights may burden us, we
cannot disregard them and maintain our honor. The migrant and the
refugee have the right to pursue their happiness. They may have more
rights among more generous people. Our practice in these and other
matters should always exceed our principles. We should give more
than we think is due. That is magnanimity, the virtue proper to people
who rule themselves.
Thomas Paine, who seeded revolutions as he moved, wrote,
“[R]eceive the fugitive, and prepare in time an asylum for mankind.”10
Open the gates to those who want to come. Open them to those who
want to leave.
Rights belong to us: they are not the gift of law. They are not given by
the state or by any transnational institution. There are civil rights, of
58 Wild Democracy
course. The right to travel under a particular passport. The right to vote
in a particular electoral system, to stand for election, to hold an office.
The right to drive a car or have a dog. These are civil rights, given by a
civil order. Some are important; some are not. They may be given by a
particular people who have already ordered their government in the
form they chose, by states whose procedures determine who will and
will not be granted civil rights, even by a state controlled by an autocrat
who confers civil standing and civil rights as he or she chooses.
Whether civil rights are, in practice, rights or privileges depends
on the actions of the people or the state that claims to grant them.
Privileges are granted; rights are demanded. Civil rights are privileges
the state extends through law or dictate. Rights are ours, and their rec-
ognition is not something to plead for but something to demand. The
civil rights movement, despite its name, demanded not privileges but
rights. Their demand was not that rights be granted but that already
present rights be recognized. The rights they demanded were two-
fold. They demanded recognition of the rights that belong by nature
to all people: to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness. They also
demanded the rights of their people: to vote, to stand for election, to
hold office. They sought their freedom, as people and as a people, as
living human beings and as Americans.
Our natural rights, grounded in the body, are fundamental and inal-
ienable. They are not the gift of law.
Rights cannot be made alien to us. They are born into the living person,
held in the warm flesh of the living body, and each of us holds rights
like a soul. Are they transcendent rights? Perhaps. On earth, we know
no soul separated from the flesh, and it is on earth that we struggle to
rule ourselves.
Rights cannot be alienated. They cannot be bought or sold, traded
or disavowed.
The slave on a plantation, picking cotton in Mississippi, cutting cane
in Louisiana or Cuba; the miner in West Virginia or Witwatersrand
Rights are born in the body 59
had the rights that belong to any and to all people, long before those
rights were acknowledged, much less honored as decency demands.
Rights are inalienable. To demand, to seize, to exercise those rights
requires extraordinary courage. That courage is visible in revolutions,
to be sure, but it is ordinary courage that enables people to live freely
and rule themselves. The courage that stands against tanks is futile if
it cannot be transformed into the common courage that enables a di-
vided people to listen, to work with one another in ruling themselves,
to speak freely, to walk among their enemies unafraid.
The duty to recognize rights, to secure them, to enforce and defend
them does not fall to the police, to judges, to governments. That duty is
ours. Our rights are grounded in our bodies. Our duty is there as well.
We bear our responsibility in our bodies.
We hold our rights in common. Rights are not a gift of law, defined and
parceled out by those in power. Rights are a commons.
The commons differs from collective property. The commons
cannot be owned at all. Holdings in common cannot be alienated. They
cannot be sold or traded. They cannot be given a monetary value. So it
is with rights. They cannot be alienated, sold, or traded. They cannot be
valued in monetary terms. As with a common field, rights must belong
to all equally.
The commons can generate private property, as a fisherman in
Wisconsin takes fish from a river or a hiker in Sweden picks berries in
a field. These may diminish the commons slightly, though often they
help the commons to prosper. Rights held in common are simultane-
ously one’s own and belonging to all. Rights are part of our common
wealth in the fullest sense. The right of one person to preserve life, to
stay healthy, makes all the commons safer and healthier. The right of
one person to pursue happiness, to cultivate talents, to seek an educa-
tion, to learn, increases the common store of learning and wisdom. The
wisdom brought to the commons in this way increases the common
store of material things as well. We learn to cultivate common wealth,
60 Wild Democracy
duty, to rebel.” That is true of all rights. They command. The right
to speak freely becomes the command to speak freely and the duty
to listen. The right to assemble becomes the duty to assemble, the
command to assemble. Rights animate the people who hold them.
They shape those people in themselves and in relation to one an-
other. People who know their rights walk proudly, act bravely. They
know no life is worth more than their life. They are commanded to
protect their own rights, and that command impels them to protect
the rights of all.
The commons is a field open to all. All take rights from it and, in
doing so, increase the rights of all, as fire spreads when it is shared.11
In making common rights their own, in using their rights to shape
the world, individuals increase the commonwealth of rights. They
strengthen themselves. They strengthen the people. They repair
the world.
This is an old lesson, continually challenged. Law can block the exer-
cise of rights. Law can hedge rights about with restrictions and limits.
There is, however, nothing in the law that can take rights away from the
people. Rights are inalienable.
Rights are the grounding and the mission of law. Rights are above,
beneath, beyond, and before the law. Governments are made and laws
established, in the words of the Declaration, to secure these rights.
When they fail to do so, they lose their legitimacy. Laws must defer
to rights if they are to be legitimate themselves. Rights are before the
law. Just laws are made to ensure that rights can be made secure and
put into practice. Rights are beneath the law, supporting it. Rights are
above the law, governing it. Rights are beyond the law, giving law a mis-
sion to accomplish, a standard to achieve, an ideal to reach. Rights re-
strain the law.
Rights also drive law forward. Knowledge of the rights people
hold drives them to secure those rights, drives them to establish
62 Wild Democracy
“The Rule of Law, Not Men” was one of the battle cries of the English
Civil War. It has an honored place in the history of republicanism and
revolution. That declaration announced the end of monarchy, of all au-
tocracy and tyranny. The word of one would no longer be enough to
rule. Arbitrary rule, in which a favored few or a favored view would
be treated differently, to rise and fall at the whim of the ruler, would be
set aside. Those who longed for the rule of law saw a system in which
no one was above the law and all people would be treated equally. They
saw a system in which law endured and could be known to all. They
saw an enduring order. Yet the rule of law is not and cannot be a good
in itself.
There is no virtue in the rule of law when the laws that rule are
unjust.
There is nothing rare or mysterious about laws that do evil. That
icon of evil, the Third Reich, was a Rechtsstaat, a constitutional state,
a state under the rule of law. The genocide of the Jews, the seizure of
their goods, the ethnic cleansing of the Roma, the imprisonment of
dissenters and those called deviants were all done under the law, with
all the propriety and paperwork that law demands. The Rule of Law
was the Rule of Evil then.
At their best, legal decisions can make a change of public sentiment
visible, give it voice, and guide its development. Yet a legal decision
can as easily (and I fear more often) stand in the way of justice and
freedom. The Supreme Court of the United States has demonstrated,
on too many occasions, its ability to affirm law against justice.
The Dred Scott decision sent Mr. Scott, who had been, by law, a
free man in the state of Illinois and the territory of Louisiana, and
a free man by right in all the world, back into slavery in the state of
Wild Democracy. Anne Norton, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197644348.003.0004
64 Wild Democracy
Missouri. The Court not only denied Mr. Scott his freedom in the
state of Missouri; it denied him and all descendants of Africans their
freedom anywhere in the United States. In doing so it made freedom
dependent on laws of ownership and residence. It made freedom the
gift of the master and the masters’ law. Slaves could not demand or
affirm the freedom that was theirs by right. In denying Dred Scott his
freedom, the Court denied Dred Scott his humanity. He was, Taney’s
opinion declared, a member of “a subordinate and inferior class of
beings, who had been subjugated by the dominant race, and, whether
emancipated or not, yet remained subject to their authority, and had
no rights or privileges but such as those who held the power and the
Government might choose to grant them.”1 Here the law served to
seal the slavery not only of one man but of many. Law served injustice,
law served evil, here.
Buck v. Bell, in which Oliver Wendell Holmes famously declared,
“[T]hree generations of imbeciles is enough,” purported to defend the
confinement and care of those who were dangerous or unable to care
for themselves and allow them to be sterilized for the common good.
According to a contemporary website:
These, we are told, are the “facts of the case.” In law, the “facts of the
case” are not what an ordinary person would understand the facts of
the case to be. They are what the judge determines them to be.3 Here,
the facts of the case—in the ordinary sense—were that Carrie Buck
was not feeble-minded at all. She had had the misfortune to be raped
by a wealthy and privileged man whose family found it convenient to
have her put away.
When the Supreme Court reviewed the case, they did not inquire
into the facts of the case but simply into whether the lower courts
had followed the law. Law can be very far indeed from justice. Law is
often, if not always, seen as a good in itself, subject to its own rules, and
Free people rule the law 65
assessed not by the standard of justice but by its internal coherence and
consistency.
Buck v. Bell legitimized eugenic sterilization. The decision came
at a time when eugenics was widely popular, with contests for “Fitter
Families” and “Better Babies.” The fitter families and better babies were
white and blond, what enthusiasts for eugenics might call “Aryan.”
Eugenics fit very well indeed with the Jim Crow laws and segregationist
practices of the United States in the late nineteenth and early twen-
tieth centuries. Like segregation, it extended beyond the Jim Crow
South. Nor was it limited to conservatives. On the contrary, the con-
viction that experts, rather than the people themselves, should decide
who should reproduce and who should not, suited the belief of many
Progressives in the rule of experts. Here too the rule of law served
injustice.
Fred Korematsu resisted the forced relocation and internment of
people of Japanese ancestry in the United States during World War II.
The U.S. Supreme Court affirmed his internment, arguing not that it
was right but that it was lawful. Law served injustice here, but there
was a voice for justice. In his dissenting opinion, Justice Frank Murphy
argued that law must bow to right: “I dissent, therefore, from this legal-
ization of racism. Racial discrimination in any form and in any degree
has no justifiable part whatever in our democratic way of life. It is unat-
tractive in any setting, but it is utterly revolting among a free people.”4
Murphy’s dissent marked the divide between legality and legitimacy,
liberalism and democracy, unjust law and the requirements of a free
people.
The rule of law secured slavery in the United States. After slavery
was abolished, Jim Crow laws kept the newly free chained. Law has
subordinated women to men, workers to employers. Law favors the
rich over the poor. A fine that is nothing to a rich man can impoverish
a poor one. Worse, the practice of increasing the most trivial fines with
time—parking meter violations for example—can lead in some states
to imprisonment for failure to pay, regardless of the poverty of the de-
fendant. In such cases, people are imprisoned not for their violations
but for their poverty. The rich have the money to sue and to defend
themselves in court. Few others do. The provision of pro bono lawyers,
as every lawyer knows, does not correct this inequity. How many have
66 Wild Democracy
change, and prevents the achievement of justice. Even the most benign
orders can be stifling.
Law can help forge a better future, one in which rights are more
secure, freedom greater, and people more able to pursue their own
happiness, but it does not, in itself, drive toward the future. In states
governed by precedent and common law, law anchors itself in the
past. Common law is the work of convention in time. At its best, the
common law captures the accumulated wisdom of generations of
practice. At its worst, it preserves unjust practices, hardens them,
and secures the yoke on the necks of the oppressed. In either case, the
common law is conservative in its forms, methods, and effects. Above
all, the notion of precedent as authoritative makes the conventional
past the limit of law. All law, all judgment must be justified according
to its adherence to the past.
The past, however, has rarely been just. The full text of Baldwin’s
quote runs:
This is why those pious calls to “respect the law,” always to be heard
from prominent citizens each time the ghetto explodes, are so ob-
scene. The law is meant to be my servant and not my master, still less
my torturer and my murderer. To respect the law, in the context in
which the American Negro finds himself, is simply to surrender his
self-respect.
be ruled by law but to rule it. The rule of law should describe not only
the rule of law over all people equally but our rule of the laws we make,
the laws we are called to obey. Any people that began in revolution, or
prides itself on the revolutions that freed it from arbitrary rule, should
honor the decision to rule law rather than merely be ruled by it.
The rule of law by the people is a far more demanding discipline
than simple submission. People are required to judge. They have to
think. They have to consider what the law does—not merely in inten-
tion but in effect. They have to consider whether the operation of a
damaging law might be repaired by interpretation. There are many
people, particularly lawyers, who believe that the interpretation of laws
is a matter for experts, that lawyers and judges should interpret the law
and the people should remain passive. If the laws are the people’s laws,
they have the right and the duty to interpret them. This is true for all
law, from the smallest regulation to constitutional laws. People may—
they should—turn to others for help in this task. They should question,
debate, think, defer to judgment they judge better than their own, but
the right to interpret belongs to them. There are times when the most
powerful interpretations belong not to the rule of experts but to the
expertise of rule.
Langston Hughes’s poem “Freedom’s Plow” provides an example of
how the texts that define a people are to be read. Hughes quotes the
words of the Declaration of Independence, and then goes on:
The slaves’ reading was closest to the letter of the text and still closer
to the spirit of that text. Their reading has an authority the founders’
reading lacked.
Free people rule the law 69
There are laws no decent person can obey. They will not obey them.
Praise of anarchy, outlaws, rebels, and rogues may trouble those who
believe in the Rule of Law, who prize order and precedent, who bow
too deeply to tradition. People who rule themselves are concerned not
only with obedience to the law, or even ruling the law. They are able
to set law aside. The demands of justice surpass the demands of law.
The protection of rights has a commanding power greater than the law.
Law does not set aside the rights people have by nature. Rights surpass
the force of law. People who rule themselves do more than obey the
law. They rule it; they make it their own.
This is no revolutionary novelty. This is an old wisdom. Aristotle
observed in the Politics that law does not always accord with justice.
Justice may require more or less than the law lays out. Plato offered that
lesson in the Euthyphro. Practical experience persuaded the British of
the same thing. If law were all that was at issue, it would be unneces-
sary, even undesirable, to have a jury of one’s peers. The verdict would
be a matter of applied expertise. The judge, an expert in the law, would
be sufficient. But knowledge of the law is not enough. The jury provides
the means to give the community a voice in the justice of the verdict
and the sentence. When people judge, in formal trials or in their ordi-
nary lives, they ask not only “Is it legal?” but “Is it just?”
There is a space between law and justice, between law and rights,
between law and the people. That space will not vanish. It is the work
of time as well as politics. In this terrain, this legal no man’s land, the
people shall judge.
They judge whether the law is just. They judge whether the law
is theirs. There are many people, every day, who look upon the laws
they know and find them unjust. They must judge if it is their duty to
rebel, to organize against the law, or to decide that this is one of those
moments in which they can accept injustice done in their name.
Law belongs to those who make it. When a law becomes alien to a
people, they should repeal it.9 That law is no longer theirs, and they
need not obey it. Perhaps once pious people, they have become less
Free people rule the law 71
persuaded of the truths of their faith. Perhaps they have become more
religious and believe they can work to approach the divine. Perhaps
people who once thought they were from a single race or tribe have
learned to welcome refugees and immigrants. People may realize that
episodes in their past are more or less honorable than they had sup-
posed. People change, they learn, they grow. Regret for past wrongs
can be written into laws that look to the future.
In making their laws more just, they change who they are as a
people. Their laws come closer to justice, and so do they.
Across the world, from the Amazon to the Antipodes, North to
South, people have recognized wrongs done to indigenous people.
The wrongs are many. Parents were stripped of their children; chil-
dren were sent to boarding schools and stripped in turn of their lan-
guages and cultures, were buried in unmarked graves. Lands once held
by people in common were seized by conquest, crime, guile—and law.
Indigenous beliefs about an obligation to the land, to beings of and on
the land, to spirits held within it were once mocked and ignored. Law
made these wrongs possible. Law licensed and drove injustice.
People have come to regret the harm they did to the indige-
nous. Those regrets are not remorse alone. New Zealand has recog-
nized Mount Taranaki and the river Whanganui as beings holding
rights. In doing so, the people of New Zealand are doing more than
amending wrongs done to the land and people who first made their
home in it. They have taken the view of the indigenous people as the
view common to all New Zealanders. They have learned. They have,
thoughtfully, made themselves different than they were, in their laws
as well as their learning. They have learned that colonialism wronged
the Maori. That, perhaps, was the easiest lesson. They are learning a
harder and more valuable one. They are learning what the land was
and is to the Maori. The recognition of wrongs done testifies to their
work to make themselves more just, more learned, more responsible.
The will to make themselves more Maori, not only to learn from but to
learn within Maori concepts, ideas, and understandings, makes New
Zealanders an altered and transcendent people.
There are more mundane changes. People change around the
world, and around the people the world changes. People who work
to rule themselves are committed to sailing in that open, unmapped
72 Wild Democracy
sea, changing course when conditions require it. They will find, from
time to time, that their laws no longer serve the people they are or the
people they wish to be. They will find that the future presents them
with problems they did not anticipate. Weaponry changes. When
navies sailed and states fought pitched battles from wooden ships,
oak was a requirement of national security. States outlawed the cut-
ting of large oak trees. Rich and poor bore the burdens of cultivating
oak for the Navy. That has long been unnecessary, and the laws have
been changed. Printing, publishing, social media all changed how
people communicate. Each required new laws. Each made other laws
unnecessary.
Ruling the law requires constant vigilance. Justice requires judg-
ment. Justice requires us to make exceptions. Justice requires mercy.
Justice requires ethics. When we see a law broken we decide if we will
enforce it or look the other way. We decide if the law is just. We decide
if justice requires an exception to a just law. We decide if justice will be
done by demanding that the law be obeyed or that it be set aside.
People who rule themselves discover that law is not enough for
them. Law does too little as well as too much. Grifters and greedy busi-
nessmen, caught in the evasion of taxes, in acts of naked nepotism or
immoral acquisition, often reply defensively “It was legal” when chal-
lenged about their conduct. When someone’s defense of their conduct
is only “It was legal,” they are likely to be acting unjustly. Obedience to
law is not enough for ethics, morality, or simple human decency.
People who rule themselves are licensed to go beyond the law in re-
bellion, in disobedience, in mercy. They have the right, they have the
duty, to rebel against unjust governments. They are required to be not
only lawful but ethical. They are required to go beyond the law in their
demands on themselves.
judged, and that twice over. Each democrat is called to judge as part
of the whole. Each is subject to the judgment of the whole. Each free
person judges and is judged by the others.
Legislating is not the only role the people take in a democracy. They
judge and they execute. They are called to see the laws they made put
into action. They are executives. Judgment, of and beyond the law, is
the work of the people, who are sovereign. Before, beneath, beyond
government is the possibility of revolution. In their sovereignty, the
people affirm or change their laws and decide the need for revolution.
The people’s judgment is made formal and institutional in the jury
and in the work of election. People decide who is innocent and who is
guilty. They decide whether the laws themselves are just, whether they
should be upheld or set aside. The right of the people to judge not only
the case but the law is acknowledged explicitly in states where jury nul-
lification is recognized.
Judgment is demanded often in the ordinary workings of a common
life. One is called to decide whom to vote for, what (if any) party to
join, what verdict to give on a jury, when to press for the making or the
repeal of laws, which laws to obey and which to ignore.
One is also called, every day and in times of the greatest crises, to
decide who and what is to be tolerated. Generations ago Marcuse
declared, “Tolerance is extended to policies, conditions, and modes of
behavior which should not be tolerated because they are impeding, if
not destroying, the chances of creating an existence without fear and
misery.” Many would agree that “what is proclaimed and practiced as
tolerance today, is in many of its most effective manifestations serving
the cause of oppression.”10 We are, however, divided over which poli-
cies serve repression and which liberation, which policies ought and
ought not to be tolerated. This is, with varying intensity, nothing more
or less than democratic politics. We have different interests. We are
differently situated. We have borne different burdens and enjoyed dif-
ferent privileges. We are moved by different fears and hopes. We work
for different ends. In confronting the fact that we do not want what all
others want, we demonstrate our capacity for unity in difference, our
common courage, and our ability to rule ourselves.
This should be, as George Washington recognized, our pride. In his
letter to the Hebrew Congregation of Newport he wrote, “It is now no
74 Wild Democracy
The claim that the people are wise is at once the most doubted and
most accepted claim for democracy. It belongs to old documents and
to the virtual. It has an honorable and bastard pedigree. The ancients
placed democracies among the ignorant cities, yet they also recog-
nized that only the wisest know that they do not know. Ignorance is the
beginning (and sometimes the end) of wisdom. Conservatives praise
the wisdom of custom and tradition, of settled people whose ances-
tral ways reflect a long learning. This is one form of the wisdom of the
many. Another has become common in our time. The wisdom of the
many is harnessed in wikis.
There is another form of the wisdom of the people that approaches
the divine. Aristotle argued for democratic wisdom in the Politics. He
wrote that “the many, of whom none individually is an excellent man,
nevertheless when joined together can be better—not as individuals,
but all together.” Combined, their varied virtues and capacities can
surpass the wisdom of a single man.14 Al-Farabi echoed and expanded
this argument in his aphorisms.
Aphorism 57 opens the possibility that the virtues and capacities
necessary for governance might not exist in a single person, as those
Free people rule the law 77
People who rule themselves depend, like all rulers, not on their wisdom
and virtue alone but also on good information. We are called upon
to judge, and to judge justly we need to know the facts. We are called
to make, to enforce, and to submit to the law. Each of these requires
knowledge. Knowledge, however, is not the only form of truth we need.
Free people rule the law 79
We need people to speak the truth as they see it. Perhaps this is neces-
sary for the trust that some see as essential to democracy. I think we
can live with our enemies and that we need not trust them too far, but
I still think we need them to speak the truth as they see it. We need to
hear that truth, certainly, but we also need the courage it takes to speak
it. Ancient philosophy saw speaking truth fearlessly as an attribute of
wisdom. We need that wisdom. Religious scriptures see speaking truth
to power as prophetic. We need the courage to chasten and correct our
rulers. When we rule, we need those who have the courage to restrain
and rebuke us. Those who rule themselves, if they are to touch the di-
vine and give it voice, must speak the truth. There are hazards enough
moving into the unknown. We must bring what light we can.21
The idea that one can describe the institutions and forms of govern-
ment in a democracy is fundamentally wrong-headed. Each democ-
racy is distinct. When the people rule themselves, they do so in the
manner they decide. They may choose to fill offices by lot or by elec-
tion, for a term or a task, or to have no offices at all. They may regard
representation as necessary or abhorrent. They will draw their bound-
aries in different ways on different dimensions: by territory, language,
religion, ethnicity, descent, or principles. Perhaps they will have no
boundaries at all.
We do not yet know what democratic peoples will become, but in
our time and, I suspect, for a long time to come, they will not be wholly
democratic. They will be, they must be, different from one another.
They will defer, perhaps wisely, to the customs of their people. They
will do things other people (and other peoples) regard as decadent,
puritanical, or silly. They will value things that others dismiss. These
differences, great and small, will set them apart from one another.
When we look at other democracies we will not see our own. We
will see other people building a common life together, another people
making themselves as they choose. Perhaps we will be astonished by
what they build. Perhaps we will want to make those things our own.
Perhaps we will regard them as shameful and degraded. Perhaps, over
time, we will change our judgments. Perhaps not.
Do not expect to see people becoming more and more alike in their
ways of life. People who are free do as they please. “Aren’t they free?”
Plato’s Socrates asks of democrats. “And isn’t the city full of freedom
and free speech? And isn’t there license in it to do whatever one
wants?”1 Free people (as Plato did not write) do as they think best.
Wild Democracy. Anne Norton, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197644348.003.0005
Democrats live with open hands 83
escape the cave seeing the light of the fire as a pale imitation, a frag-
ment, of the sun. They come to enlightenment through their own will.
Enlightenment is knowledge of the being of the things that are and the
nonbeing of the things that are not. It is stable and enduring. Gods have
little or no part in it. The divinity of truth is apart from them. Though
the wisdom of the few enlightened ones has often been presented in
mystical terms, it is in important respects technical knowledge. It is ac-
cessible only to an elite. It endures unchanging. It can be mastered, but
it cannot be easily shared. Mastery sets the few apart and gives them
the right to rule.
Al-Farabi’s commitment to Islam altered his reading of the text.
For the peoples of the book, who share a commitment to a single
divinity and truth revealed in scripture, enlightenment is quite
different. The will of God, not the work or the will of men, makes
it accessible. It cannot be mastered, and it remains mysterious.
Revelation masters even the messengers, who suffer for the message
and are overcome by it. Enlightenment through revelation is stable
and enduring, and it is fundamentally accessible to all.4 But in the
absence of a prophet or messiah, it is subject to the limits of memory
and record, preserved only through the necessarily imperfect means
of imitation.
In this world, the ignorant cities appear differently than they did to
Greek philosophers. As Socrates was once recognized for the wisdom
of knowing that he did not know, so the ignorant cities, mindful of their
ignorance, may surpass the wisdom of those who have only the echo of
prophecy in scripture, only the imitation of virtue in the sunnah.
Under this understanding, democratic cities are ignorant, but they
are also free. They are the only cities able to come to virtue and to good
governance through their own reason and reasoned will. They are the
cities that may come closest to divinely inspired prophetic direction.
Plato wrote dismissively of democracy. Yet even in his hostile
and contemptuous account, this place of pretty and desirable things
emerges as a place of danger and promise. “Aren’t they free?” Socrates
asks of democrats. “And isn’t the city full of freedom and free speech?
And isn’t there license in it to do whatever one wants?” These are
indictments for Plato, the marks of an ungoverned, perhaps ungovern-
able people, led by their passions and appetites.
Democrats live with open hands 85
I have not found a more beautiful and precise description of the demo-
cratic city. Al-Farabi recognizes not only the danger but the promise of
democracy. For him, as for Plato, diversity is characteristic of democ-
racy. The gates of the democratic city are open to all; the city attracts all,
whether they are welcome or not. Al-Farabi suggests that whatever the
conditions of their arrival, these wildly diverse people will join one an-
other. They will trade together, make and sell and eat each other’s food,
taste each other’s pleasures, and make new children of every color and
kind. Democracy does not overcome difference. Democracy attracts
and proliferates difference. Democracy breeds diversity.
It is diversity, Plato and Al-Farabi thought, that attracts people of
every race and kind to democracy. Muslims might consider how Al-
Farabi’s description of democracy echoes the Qu’ran: “Oh mankind,
indeed We have created you from male and female and made you peo-
ples and tribes that you may know one another” (49:13) and “[O]f
his signs is the creation of the heavens and the earth and the diversity
of your languages and your colors. Indeed in that are signs for those
of knowledge” (30:22). All should see, in this Qu’ranic verse, and in
Al-Farabi’s description of democracy, the power and beauty of cities
where the people rule.
This runs directly counter to the view, common in our time, that
democracy depends on trust and trust upon homogeneity. I hold
to the old wisdom. Democracy calls to all people. Homogeneity is
86 Wild Democracy
If all people are like us, we know what they need. Our best defense
against this arrogance lies in respect for the principle of the consent of
the governed. “A decent respect for the opinions of mankind” should
chasten us. Respect for the men and women we hope to help or defend
obliges us to listen and defer to their views. Without that deference, we
do not serve democracy. We betray the principle that people should
rule themselves.
The democratic disposition is cosmopolitan. Democratic princi-
ples and loyalties must be as well. Subjects give their allegiance to a
person; nationalists give their allegiance to a nation. Free people can
do neither.
for all. People in democracies talk, they debate, they chatter endlessly,
and out of that comes invention. People who rule themselves prolif-
erate things, ideas, rights. They make laws and regulations (perhaps
too many). They are striving to remake the world.
They mull things over; they carry ideas like a child in the womb.
They take the time to let policies mature, to explore ideas, to debate, to
consider, to let the plan mature among them before it is brought into
the world. The work of engendering may be slow and deliberate. The
agreement, the making, the spread of a new commitment can be like
lightning. They think fast. They make fast. They think on their feet.
Fast or slow, people who rule themselves overflow with plans, goods,
ideas, inventions, actions. They create excess.
That excess is a source of pride. Free people always struggle for
more: more freedom, more rights, more power, more inventions, more
discoveries. They go farther in their imagination and ambitions. They
do not believe that anything is closed to them. Their daring and their
courage spur them on. Because each person is valued, all understand
that they must be educated and their fundamental needs ensured. They
are free to cultivate their abilities: free to invent, free to discover. Their
achievements open opportunities to others. “Job creation” is not the
province of the few whose accidental patronage is praised to the skies,
but of the many, whose work overflows with generosity. People who
rule themselves are excessive in their ambitions, in their daring, in
their imagination of what they can become. That is how they grow.
Democracies, radical democracies, maintain within themselves
the spaces of anarchy. They are always experimenting. They prolif-
erate institutions, practices, and modes of resistance. Their capacity
for solidarity enables them to work together, to assemble, to make
committees, unions, cooperatives. Their anarchic spirit enables them
to take these down again. Their capacity for solidarity enables them
to build forms of governance. Their anarchic disposition drives them
to change governnments, escape governance, try again. They experi-
ment. They are not bound to what they have or to what has been. They
build from the ruins of the past when they choose; they refuse the past
when they choose. Their experimentation has two effects. First, they
expand the available forms of governance. They provide their people
with more places to work together and more ways in which to do it.
92 Wild Democracy
Do I contradict myself?
Very well then I contradict myself
(I am large, I contain multitudes.)7
Those who doubt and distrust the ability of people to rule themselves
hedge democracy about with requirements, as if it were a country
club with peculiar criteria for admission. Democracy is only for the
wealthy, the educated, for men, for people of a certain race or tribe or
religion, for people who have a certain level of income or a certain cul-
ture. This may describe a country club in the segregated South or a
swim club outside Beirut, but it does not describe democracy. There
are no admission fees. There are no educational requirements. Those
who restrict membership to a particular tribe or race or religion make
democracy impossible if they cannot claim to have the consent of the
governed.
A more common and quite respected position argues that democ-
racy is impossible without trust, and trust is possible only among “one’s
own,” that is, they say, among those of the same culture or ethnicity.
This is wrong many times over. People who can rule themselves are
94 Wild Democracy
brave enough to live with their enemies. They are attracted to differ-
ence, and people of all kinds are attracted to them. Moreover, it is not
so easy to determine who is alike and who is different, even when the
signs of those differences—as with race—are codified and detailed.
Difference and likeness are attributes that shift with context. We are
all alike in our mortality, in the inalienable rights that belong to our
embodied humanity. We are all different in the radical solitude of body
and mind, in how we shape ourselves and how we remake the world.
Insistence on the need for cultural (or ethnic) homogeneity for
social trust, and on the necessity of social trust for democracy, is
weakness at best and bigotry at worst. People who cannot learn to
live bravely and openly with those who are not like them are not
yet prepared to rule themselves. They are not yet fully prepared for
politics.
The complex of desire and courage that democracy calls forth in
democrats is never for one demos, one people, alone. The democrat
cannot easily tell strangers from residents. Democrats may look at
their fellow citizens as foreigners. They may know them as political
rivals, even as enemies. They learn to walk among them unafraid. They
are able then to face true enemies with courage and equanimity.
As political struggles and disputes school them, they learn to see
both enmity and friendship in their fellow citizens. They learn to see
the potential for citizenship in the stranger. If they are conscious of the
rights that belong to all people, a common humanity may teach them
to see all people as, in the most fundamental sense, their own. They
may look at foreigners as they look at citizens. They may look at them
as others, alien and intriguing, opening worlds of danger and promise.
They are prepared to walk out into the world impelled by curiosity and
desire, shielded with courage.
Fear of democracy is often no more than fear of the poor. That is a fear
that justice may someday spare us. Until then, we should ask ourselves
why the poor should seem to be at the heart of democracy.
Democrats live with open hands 95
an absolute natural right, and you must deny all civil right.”11
Rainsborough did, and he was right to do so. The right to be governed
only by governments that have our consent, to rule as well as to be
ruled, belongs to all people, rich and poor. It belongs to us in our naked
humanity.
Democratic cities, as Plato presents them, emerge from the violent
power of the poor. The poor see the weakness of the rich and doubt
their strength. Democracy “comes into being when the poor win.”12
Plato’s dialogues present this triumph of the poor as the work of an un-
lovely envy. This view predominates in the canon. Rainsborough saw it
differently. So did Ibn Khaldun.
For Ibn Khaldun power arises out of lack, on the territorial, cultural,
and economic periphery, among those who are forced to rely on them-
selves. Hardship and deprivation produce people with qualities that
enable them to win power and use it well. As individuals, they become
self-reliant. They acquire fortitude. They are forced to be disciplined,
strong, inventive, intelligent, and stoic in order to survive. Their pri-
vate strengths and virtues are not, however, enough to preserve them.
These self-reliant people also develop the strongest ties of solidarity.13
Ibn Khaldun’s account of the emergence of power on the periphery
is at once familiar and challenging. His conception of the frontier is
familiar, capturing the combination of independence and cooper-
ation that characterizes frontiersmen from the nineteenth-century
American West to Jim Scott’s Burma. Yet despite its familiarity, this
account presents a challenge to enduring prejudices in Western polit-
ical thought. Conservatives too often see the poor as lazy, lacking in
talent or morality, undisciplined. Those who see the poor in this way
will strip themselves of their own virtue, losing generosity and great-
ness of soul. They will also fail to see where the strength of the people
comes from.
Hardship produces not dependence but fortitude. Much follows
from this conception of power’s origins. For democrats, it marks the
“great unwashed,” the “teeming masses,” the shaab who are both “the
poor” and “the people” as fit—perhaps especially fit—to hold power. It
inverts the understanding that saw—that sees—power as the preserve
of the privileged, to be extended to the subordinate only insofar as edu-
cation and imitation assimilate them to their betters.
Democrats live with open hands 97
make the most of what they have and what they know: to forge alliances
with friends and family and cultivate the few resources they have. The
rich can simply spend some money. They do not need to think at all.
Plato wrote in the Symposium that desire was the child of poverty
and resource. Ibn Khaldun’s work makes that observation political. The
poor join together because they must. The poor become resourceful
because they must. They become powerful because they can. Their
poverty taught them to be clever and enterprising. They learned that
solidarity not only enabled them to survive; it made them stronger
than their enemies.
Reading democracy in light of Ibn Khaldun, affirming the capacity
of those who live under hardship to acquire self-reliance, practice sol-
idarity, and acquire power, counters the exclusionary liberalism Uday
Mehta identified.15 The two Mills, and other enlightened liberals com-
mitted to the project of empire, saw the capacity for democracy as an
achievement contingent on education, the cultivation of certain mores
and specified cultural or civilizational contexts. For many more that
capacity was dependent on financial as well as cultural capital. Ibn
Khaldun’s work reminds us that we need nothing for democracy but
humanity.
Ibn Khaldun’s account also counters the assumption that anarchy
and individualism are opposed to solidarity and social action. Ibn
Khaldun recognized that solidarity is not an alternative to individu-
alism but its necessary accompaniment. They are related as concave
is to convex. The conditions that make individualism necessary make
solidarity desirable. According to this logic of origins, the more an
individual is forced to self-reliance, the more that individual sees the
virtues of solidarity. Solidarity grows not from the weakness of the
dependent but from the recognition of limits in the strong. This rec-
ognition is not peculiar to Ibn Khaldun. It animates anarchism across
time and space. Kropotkin’s anarchism is famously allied to his recog-
nition of the necessity—and the drive—to mutual aid. For Kropotkin,
solidarity was natural, a consequence of the form of human and other
embodied beings. David Graeber, citing the work of Joanna Overing,
describes anarchic practices among the Piaroa.16 The acequias of New
Mexico are communal irrigation systems, run on the old anarchic
system of the commons.
Democrats live with open hands 99
34. Taxes are how people pay for the work they do
together.
People love to inveigh against taxes. Their taxes are too high, there are
too many taxes, too many governmental bodies. Taxes are imposed by
a government that does not understand how hard it is to run a busi-
ness, that doesn’t see that the wealthy are wealth creators. Taxes are the
government’s hand in your pocket. In America, we are reminded that
tax protests are the very foundation of the Republic. The Revolution
began in resistance to the Stamp Act. The rebels who dumped British
tea in Boston Harbor were resisting taxes. “No taxation without repre-
sentation” was a war cry of the Revolution and remains the motto of a
still disenfranchised Washington, D.C.
Libertarians charge that taxes are coercive. They steadily increase
governmental power. They make bureaucratic authoritarianism pos-
sible. They are often a covert attempt to reshape people’s behavior (the
soda tax, or “sin taxes” on alcohol and tobacco). They are often a tool,
openly used, for redistributing income: taking from the rich to give
to the poor. Critics are correct to question the use of taxes to control
behavior, especially when it serves to “nudge”—that is to say, to influ-
ence behavior covertly. They are right to cast a suspicious eye on the
state, for states possess coercive power. There are elements of truth in
these critical accounts of taxation, but there is something fundamental
that is lost. It is astonishing that libertarians, who accept the tyranny of
bosses, debt, usury, and other exactions of finance, should cavil at taxa-
tion. It is absurd that anarchists, taught as they should be by Kropotkin,
should object to a practice of mutual aid. There can be unjust taxes to
be sure, but there is nothing opposed to liberty, nothing hostile to an-
archy, in the choice of people to work together.
Wild Democracy. Anne Norton, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197644348.003.0006
Taxes are how people pay for the work 101
but what if it were true? These are their people. Such people may pride
themselves (however mistakenly) on their self-sufficiency, but they can
never claim to love their country. They regard taxation as a transaction.
They expect to be given something for it, and they are looking for a
bargain. This is a small, greedy, mean-spirited mentality. These people
have not even advanced to politics, much less self-rule. They do not
know their own people. They have no pride. They lack the greatness of
soul people need to rule themselves.
Magnanimous people glory not in what they take but in what they
can give. If others take more than they do, so what? If others feed off
them, they say with Nietzsche, “What are my parasites to me?” The
honorable take pride in generosity. They glory in giving. They smile
and say, “You are welcome.” If they love their country they say, “You are
my people and I will see you fed.”
Those who begrudge their taxes, who have no desire to share their
wealth, have no love of country. Their affection does not extend far
enough. Those who love their country take all within it as their own.
They steward their land, they build with beauty and efficiency. They
aim to “walk in beauty.”4 They are proud of their people and treasure
them—even those they count as their enemies. They feel a responsi-
bility for all within it, good and bad. They are ashamed to see any one of
their people in need.
For the subjects of a monarch, national greatness may lie in conquest
or empire, in the grandeur of the monarch’s castles or the size of the
Crown Jewels. For democrats, “the crown jewels” has become a collo-
quial term for something every man possesses. Military dictatorships
and nations governed by force take pride in the size of the military.
Military parades, aircraft carriers that might never leave the harbor,
and uniforms with a great deal of brass are the currency of national
greatness.
Economists teach us to see national greatness in the size of a nation’s
GDP or the wealth that millionaires and billionaires are able to amass.
For those who value wealth alone, who measure greatness in renminbi,
dollars, or euros, displays of private wealth may be a source of pride.
Democrats take pride only in their accomplishments and the wel-
fare and accomplishments of their people. They are proud of what they
build together. They are proud when everyone has food and shelter,
Taxes are how people pay for the work 103
when everyone learns and takes pride and pleasure in their work. They
take pride not in the wealth of the few but in the prosperity of all.
It would be unjust to say to someone “Roads will serve us all, but
since you need them for your business, you build them.” It would be
arrogant for someone to say “I am wealthy” (or “I am ambitious”).
“So I will build your roads and provide your defense.” No one should
be trusted with that power. Who is that one person to decide for the
people?5 People who rule themselves are proud: proud of their inde-
pendence, proud of their abilities. Are we too poor to build our own
roads? Are we too poor to protect ourselves? No, we can do this for
ourselves.
The idea that taxation is coercion has its origins in resistance to
monarchies and dictatorships. The dictator who taxes you does indeed
have his hand in your pocket. The elected official who builds himself a
palace with public funds is a thief. When people rule themselves they
are not taking from someone’s pocket and putting it in someone else’s.
They are spending common funds on a common project. They are
working together.
Paine, who fought for democracy on two continents, argued that
though rebellious people had opposed the taxes their rulers laid
on them, they would not end all taxation. On the contrary, Paine
thought free people—people who ruled themselves—would simply tax
themselves differently. They would be free of the expense of a mon-
archy: the pageantry that accompanies it; the expenses of a dynasty and
its hangers-on. They would fight fewer wars and spend less on armies
and navies and the machinery of combat. They would not, however,
dispense with taxes altogether. They would tax themselves willingly.
For a people who rule themselves, under laws they make and will-
ingly submit to, the greatest shame would be to neglect their duty to
one another. For a free people who live together willingly, the sight of
people who are homeless or unfed, who struggle to find work or get an
education is shaming. When we see that, we see our failures.
Our duty extends beyond those who are ours by law and custom.
There is a greeting in Arabic: ahlan wa sahlan. The late Farouk Mustafa
used to translate this as “You are among your people and your keep is
easy.” The greeting comes to strangers as much as to one’s own. To say
this, to practice this, is the mark of a people who have ears to hear the
104 Wild Democracy
democratic demand and eyes to see it, who live with great hearts and
open hands.
When I was a child and we were about to move overseas, my mother
took me aside. She explained to me that I would see beggars. This was,
she told me, a sad and terrible thing, and I should prepare myself for it.
I learned in that moment that for a country to have beggars was a cause
of great shame. I did not know then that my country’s beggars had been
hidden from me. I have learned since to long for the day when I can say,
“There are no beggars in my country.”
VII
The problem with liberalism
Al-Farabi wrote that places where the people rule are open to the
greatest evil and the greatest good. He wrote of the democratic city,
“The bigger, the more civilized, the more prevalent and the greater
are the good and the evil it possesses.”1 Democratic people are free to
shape themselves and their common life together as they see fit. They
will not always do that well. Langston Hughes writes:
People struggle. They are sailing into the unmapped, unknown future.
They may be (they will be) deceived and misled. Perhaps the people,
as the Prophet Muhammad believed, will “never be agreed upon an
error.” Perhaps “the voice of the people is the voice of God.”3 Until
that unity, people will struggle to make themselves. They will make
mistakes. They will be tempted by glory and rendered powerless by
fear. They will do wrong. They will have to govern as the Vikings sailed,
steering out of the dangers they encounter in uncharted waters. Such
mistakes can be costly, even devastating, to the people and to others.
It is necessary, therefore, that people take precautions against pos-
sible errors. There should be no loss, no error that would leave the
people vulnerable. There should be no single place or person whose
fall would end the people’s rule or damage it beyond repair. When
Wild Democracy. Anne Norton, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197644348.003.0007
106 Wild Democracy
People speak of “liberal democracy” as if one word slid easily into the
other, as if there were no space between liberalism and democracy.
They speak as if there should be no space, as if democracy were accept-
able only when accompanied—or corrected—by liberalism. Liberalism
would guarantee rights and establish the rule of law. Liberalism would
protect the rights of minorities and dissidents. Liberalism would pro-
tect democracy from demagoguery and tyranny. A liberal democracy
would have regular, transparent procedures.
The problem with liberalism is that it does both more and less than
it claims.
The most admirable of these liberal claims belongs not to liberalism
but to democracy. Liberals faced with democratic critiques of liber-
alism fall back on the claim that rights belong to liberalism. In this un-
derstanding (or lack of understanding), democracy is the brute power
of the people, indifferent to the rights of individuals and vulnerable to
the ambitions of demagogues. Liberalism is the name for the contracts,
constitutions, rules, and procedures that secure rights and limit the
people in their passions and appetites.
If rights were the gift of liberalism, liberalism would command our
allegiance. They are not. Rights follow from no contract, no covenant,
no law. They are not made by a particular set of procedures; they do
not depend for their existence on the ratification of a state or any legal
order. They are ours, born in our flesh and held from birth to death.
Rights belong to the people.
Rights are a democratic demand, not a liberal gift.
Liberalism, republicanism, and constitutionalism were once
presented as supplements to democracy in the simple sense: additions
and procedures—norms—that would protect the rights of minorities
and dissidents; protect democracy from demagoguery and the tyranny
of the majority. This line of thought gave us the Bill of Rights. It has
108 Wild Democracy
until their hands were withered with age. The French had no right to
choose who would rule Algeria, yet they defended military rule there.
Democracy, even liberal democracy, is still à venir in Algeria. Coups
in Bolivia, in Egypt, in Turkey, in Chile, and in many more embattled
places have presented themselves as necessary to save democracy. They
attack what they pretend to save.
In Catalonia, movements of the Catalan people to separate from
Spain were met with violence and the hard hand of an unrelenting state.
In responding to the movement, Spanish officials showed a telling con-
fusion of the democratic, the liberal, and the constitutional. The Catalan
secessionist movement was “undemocratic,” they argued, because it did
not follow the rules, because it set aside the Constitution. They avoided
the question of popular support for secession, that is to say, the consent
of the governed. Their objections were legitimate procedural questions,
but they did not touch the question of democracy. The proposed Catalan
referendum of November 9, 2014, may have been unconstitutional. To
be sure, it violated national norms. Yet neither of these means it was
undemocratic. On the contrary. If the Spanish government was com-
mitted to the democratic rather than the liberal, it would have let that
referendum proceed. Instead it took ever more undemocratic meas-
ures against Catalan independence. Catalan politicians were arrested,
forced into exile, and later tried. People in the streets were attacked by
police brought into the province from outside. Spain then witnessed the
absurdity of Felipe Borbón, called King Felipe, declaring to an inter-
national congress of legal experts in Madrid, “It makes no sense, it’s un-
acceptable to appeal to a so-called democracy that is above the law.”8 He
may have had a receptive audience in lawyers. Nevertheless, the state-
ment is fundamentally wrong. The rule of the people is always above
the law. Without their consent, there is no law that can justly command.
In a democracy, wherever the people rule, the law is not the final au-
thority. The people make the state, the constitution (if there is one), and
the laws. They remain the laws’ master.
The undemocratic character of the Spanish state response is still
more evident if one considers the possible outcomes of the projected
referendum. The secessionists might have lost dramatically, though
that appeared unlikely. They might have won dramatically, though that
was far from certain. The referendum might have done no more (and
The problem with liberalism 111
eighteenth centuries set forth ideals still beyond our reach. The “liberal
democratic peoples” that Rawls sees as the foundation for a just “Society
of Peoples” look far more like “decent hierarchical peoples.” They are
marred by the remnants of historical injustice. They still hold—and still
defend—structures of exploitation and inequality, not least, as many
critics noted, hierarchies of sex and sexuality, race and ethnicity.
There are many hierarchies that live in those countries Rawls saw
as liberal. They change their forms, they shift, but the hierarchies re-
main. Hierarchies of race and sex, the arbitrary raising of some bodies
over others, the belief that wealth should command deference and ex-
ercise power, are neither just nor decent. Rawls was wrong in a third
sense: there are no decent hierarchical peoples.
The limits of liberalism are shown at its foundations. Locke’s formu-
lation “life, liberty, and property” placed property at the heart of liber-
alism. There is both right and wrong in this. For Locke, property was
not simply something to be bought or sold. Property, in the first in-
stance, was the body and the rights held within it. Those rights enabled
people to make things in the world their own by hunting, gathering,
building, and making. This was, and remains, defensible. The construc-
tion of a “sacred right of property” by Locke, Rousseau, and genera-
tions of liberals moved rapidly from the person and the person’s rights
to possessions. Property lost its connection to the body and the rights
sheltered within it and became another word for possessions. This was
a degradation and set further degradations in motion. The defenders
of slavery in the antebellum United States claimed that the sacred right
of property enabled them to hold their slaves. The defenders of eco-
nomic inequality in the present claim that the sacred right of property
entitles the wealthy to power beyond the reach of others. The rich can
buy speech and silence. They can buy influence. Perhaps they can buy
elections. Power of this kind is antithetical to the democratic. No free
people can accept it, for if they do, they will be ruled by wealth.
Institutions are tools. There is no tool that can be used only for good.
The courts can protect minorities or serve the powerful, defend rights
or pervert them. The legislature can advance the rights and prosperity
of all the people or serve the interests of the powerful, protect the en-
vironmental commons or serve the interests of polluting industries.
116 Wild Democracy
The executive can seek personal glory, wealth, and power or serve the
common good. The executive can be the tribune of the people or a
corrupt demagogue. The military can hold to their oath to defend the
Constitution or become an institution that undermines democracy.
Institutions, like other tools, are breakable. They lose their sharp-
ness; they rust and decay. They are shaped by one set of needs and
conditions and may work quite differently in another. Institutions
have to be built and maintained, but they must also be continually
questioned, often corrected, and occasionally remade.
Americans are in such a moment as I write. The institutions and
practices that Americans regarded as furnishing defenses against
totalitarianism—and other forms of authoritarian domination—have
failed us. We have had confidence that the free market, modern sci-
ence, and technological innovation would protect democracy and pre-
vent the concentration of power in the hands of a few. We have had
confidence that guarantees of free speech and the power of a free press
would advance the truth upon which democracies depend. But the
concentration of media in a few hands made it the tool of oligarchs.
The role of algorithms, artificial intelligence, and machine learning in
social media installed invisible censors in a field too many saw as free
and ungoverned. Our confidence was hardly rash; it was supported
by a theoretical canon, by the disciplines of history and political sci-
ence, and by the common sense—and experience—of many genera-
tions. But it is tragically misplaced in the present. These institutions
have not only failed to defend us; they have become another form of
totalitarianism.12
Reliance on the free market to spread wealth (and power with it)
has concentrated power in private hands. The free press, under the
conditions of a market free in name only, has become gatekeeper,
censor, and agitator. Rather than serving as a vehicle for the expression
(much less the contest) of diverse ideas, the media has come to define
political views that lie outside a small range of opinion as inadmissible
and absurd. Profit seekers in social media direct their readers to ever
more extreme and violent opinions. The truly absurd is given an artifi-
cial but compelling centrality.
Science and technology, including the social sciences, which were
once thought to be ungovernable and so the means for permitting
The problem with liberalism 117
Written into the Old Norse word for “the rule of the people,”
folkestœring, is an affirmation not only of the right but of the ability of
the people to take their country into unknown and dangerous places.
The image of a single man holding the rudder of the ship of state did
not fool those who knew sailing well. A ship was a ship. A people gov-
erning themselves was another matter. Ships, sailing, and steering
capture many aspects of self-governance, but not all. Experience with
sailing did not persuade the Vikings that executive power belonged to
one alone.
Then again, perhaps it was sailing that taught the Vikings. Rudders,
like stirrups, belong to a later historical moment. Perhaps the Vikings
held an older knowledge. Long before rudders, those who went viking
had learned that people rowing together can steer a ship, changing
their course as they choose, if they work together. Perhaps that knowl
edge stayed with them. In any case, it is there for us.
120 Wild Democracy
This thesis is both true and false. It is false because people, in their
moments of greatness, can overcome themselves. They may not be
ready to rule themselves, but they may have the courage to assume
that burden in the hope that they can rise to meet it. It is false because
people are never wholly democratic. At their best, they work for de-
mocracy, work in democracy, work on democracy. They struggle to
rule themselves, constantly facing the dangers in that rule and, worse,
the forces that erode it. They find freedom, strength, and protection in
the anarchic space that is both a part of and apart from the democratic.
This thesis is true because what elements of the democratic we have
in the present, and the democracy we work for in the present and the
future, are grounded in our capacities, our virtues, and our desires.
They are made by our work.
Those who intend to rule themselves collectively must be able to
rule themselves individually. Democracy demands the discipline to
meet the unknown future and the known enemy with courage. People
who rule themselves cultivate both solidarity and self-reliance. They
The problem with liberalism 121
depend on themselves and step forward to help their people. They sac-
rifice for the common good and regard it quite correctly as no sacrifice
at all.
When Michel Foucault offered a theory of power that saw it not as con-
centrated at one central point but instead diffused throughout an order,
many readers were filled with fear. They saw themselves constantly
under the gaze of power, controlled at every point. Power surrounded
them. They had nowhere to turn. Those people who already knew
themselves hemmed in on every side found this analysis liberating,
for it enabled them to see the structures they had only sensed around
them. They could begin to find their way through, though they too
were daunted by the extent and pervasiveness of power spread so
broadly.
When people struggle to rule themselves, the more power is spread
the safer they are likely to be.
When times are hard, decentralization is to institutions—and to
rule—as guerrilla war is to conventional war. Attacked in one place,
people can regroup in another. The emergence of a would-be author-
itarian in one region need not threaten the whole. The failure of one
practice or institution need not place all at risk. Nothing depends upon
a single leader.
In more ordinary, peaceful, times, decentralization cultivates quali-
ties that make the people’s capacity to rule themselves more deft, more
sure, more adaptable, more daring. They are more willing to exper-
iment when failure is less threatening. If the experiment fails in one
venue, others are safe. They watch people in other places do things dif-
ferently and see what they might improve in their own.
The connection between local communities and the capacity of
people to rule themselves runs deep in political thought and deeper
still in the minds of people with a sense of place. Many institutions—
the practices of African villages and the Haudenosaunee longhouse,
the Russian mir, the Indian panchayat, the New England town
122 Wild Democracy
meeting—are praised for their democratic character and for their inti-
mate, organic connection to the lived experience of the people.
Intimate communities and close ties are no longer confined to living
on the land. There are many of us who have our closest ties with people
who live far from us. People have become ever more adept at creating
community. Our local communities may be manifold. We may be
close, we may work together with the people who live near us. We share
common dangers and common hopes: fear of hurricanes, perhaps, or
hope for a good fishing season or fewer wildfires. We have to learn to
live together in the ordinary aspects of life: walking and driving and
riding bicycles, keeping sidewalks clear of snow. Yet these people,
nearest to us in space, may not be nearest to our hearts or minds.
There are intimate communities on the internet, bound together by
common experiences, common passions, common aims. Political life
takes place here as well. Alliances are formed, solidarities are earned,
strategies are crafted, and people learn from long discussions and
debates with one another.
People craft still other communities. These are far from the com-
munities that grow in and from a place, far from the intense immate-
riality of the internet. These are old forms of community, cultivated in
writing and episodic meetings, in moments taken out of time. They are
common among scholars.
Those who write of the political value of community, who craft
institutions designed to create or cultivate community, who write of
democratic deliberation seem to consider only communities of place.
That is not how people live. That is not how politics is experienced.
People have been adept in creating communities in many forms. All
promise ways in which people can rule themselves. All run the risk
of becoming stifling or oppressive. Communities protect only when
they can be abandoned, only when other communities are found to
shelter the democratic, only when we leave enough ungoverned space
for anarchy.
Not all decentralizations are geographic. The same logic applies to
levels and methods of governance. What is used successfully in one
system can be adapted for use in another. It is not enough to peti-
tion the center: people who want to accomplish something need first
to consider multiple ways the problem could be resolved and decide
The problem with liberalism 123
which would be easiest and most effective. They are asked to think stra-
tegically about power and to use their own judgment constantly. They
learn multiple ways to exercise power, and they become more adept at
each. They become better at steering.
In a wilder, more anarchic democracy, decentralization ceases to be
a description of institutions and becomes an ordering principle and
an ethic. There are elements of this in my country. Who holds power?
The president? The president is bound by law. Congress can govern the
president. The Supreme Court can govern the president. No branch
has the final word, no branch—and certainly no person—has power
that cannot be countered. Their power, moreover, flows outward and
can be dammed or diverted. It depends on the judgment of all those
officials and citizens who put law, regulations, executive actions, mil-
itary commands into practice. Above all, the president, the Congress,
the Supreme Court, the judges, soldiers, and sailors are sworn to the
Constitution, and therefore to the people. This is only one dimen-
sion. There are states, counties, cities, and townships, each with its
own institutions, practices, and ways of life. There are jurors who can
decide cases and nullify law. There are citizens who have the right to
vote, to sit on juries, who judge the laws and practices of power as they
walk through the world, who make and unmake governments. There
are people, empowered by no more and no less than the rights born
in them. Sovereignty belongs to the people: to each as well as to all.
In an anarchic democracy, power moves always and inexorably to the
people.
Politics is not the same as government. The practices of a people
ruling themselves are not confined in government buildings or limited
to elections. Politics is practiced at home and on the street, in writing
and in the broad, irregular spaces of the internet. All of these have uses
and value. Any one of them may save us in hard times. Multiplying
the planes and possibilities of politics advances and protects the
democratic.
Think, for example, of people who discover that they have lead
in their water. If their water supplier is a private company, regulated
only by the market, they must appeal to the company. If the company
fails them, they may have nowhere to go but the nearest unpolluted
source—or back to the market for a water purification system. The
124 Wild Democracy
respond to Hurricanes Irma and Maria, but they showed the same en-
ergy, tenacity, and local knowledge in their responses.
Even when the attacks are expected and a central authority has
plans in place, the responses to attacks and disasters often come from
those who are there. Britain planned for the Blitz and had mobilized
to respond to it, but in doing so the British relied on a system of neigh-
borhood wardens to warn of air raids, get people to shelters, put out
fires, and rescue people from the ruins. The instruction “Keep Calm
and Carry On” became emblematic of the British. It captures an as-
pect of response that is often absent in discussions of executive energy.
In natural disasters and the most unnatural of wars, success depends
not only on decisive action but on qualities of composure, steadfast-
ness, and resilience. The Palestinians, who have lived in crisis for gen-
erations, have learned to value their own steadfastness, for it is on that
quality that their endurance depends.
Crises are addressed not only in the moment of decision or the
long endurance of hardship but in carrying out the work the crisis
makes necessary. The quick, spontaneous response, without leaders or
instructions; the steadfast courage that maintains people in crisis; the
ability to continue to build themselves—these are necessary if people
are to rule themselves.
All attacks, all disasters, all crises are local. Though they may
threaten everyone, everywhere, they will hit in a particular place and at
a particular time. They will hit particular people. The fastest response
will come from those who are present at the site. The crisis will require
not action in the abstract but action in this place, this time, among
these people. Those who share that place know it best. They will be able
to act swiftly, where people new to the place must hesitate. They can
make judgments newcomers may not be prepared to make. They can
make those judgments quickly. It is the people, spread throughout the
country, who can respond most quickly and most decisively.
They have another invaluable quality in a crisis: they are slow to
leave. The people they rescue are their people. The place they struggle
to repair is their place. They will be steadfast when another crisis draws
away the attention of central authorities. The people, unlike a single
energetic executive, can respond to more than one crisis at a time,
act in more than one place at a time. They are faster, their reach is
The problem with liberalism 129
Wild Democracy. Anne Norton, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197644348.003.0008
Force is the enemy of the free 131
People who rule themselves cannot fight wars as others do. Under
kings and dictators, liberal or authoritarian regimes, wars are declared
by the ruler or by the government and fought by some arm of the state.
That may be a standing army, a volunteer force, a militia, or merce-
naries hired by the state. When people rule themselves, they are both
ruler and ruled. They make the decision to go to war, and they must
bear its costs. The closer they are to democracy, the more costs they
must assume. When the people rule, the people bear the costs of war.
Those costs are many.
132 Wild Democracy
It is both just and prudent for the people—all the people—to bear
the costs of war. It is just because those who make the decision to go
to war should be the ones to bear war’s burdens. That is rarely the case.
The wealthy, the privileged, the powerful rarely fight the wars they pro-
pose. Those wars are likely to serve their interests best, but they are
more likely to get certified for bone spurs than to see active duty. There
are privileged people, fortunate sons in nations who struggle toward
democracy, who fight and die for their country. More often, the deci-
sion for war is made by the more powerful, the war fought by the less
powerful. That is unjust. War should weigh upon us all.
Ensuring that all bear the burdens of war is prudent because their
virtues may lead democratic people into unjust or unwise wars. People
who love their freedom want others to have it too. People who recog-
nize that rights belong to all people, that they are held in all the bodies
of the living, will defend those rights in others. They are angry when
they see rights denied and people not permitted to rule themselves.
They see the cause is just. They are brave. They are daring and they take
risks. Those who call for military intervention may get an easy hearing.
We believe, we who long to be free, that we are not for ourselves or our
people alone, but for all people.
This has an honorable origin, but it can lead to dishonorable acts.
We believe that all people have the capacity to reason and to rule them-
selves. We believe they have the right to rule themselves as they choose.
If their rights are denied, we see that is wrong and believe that the
wrong should be fought. Why not by us? There are dangers here. Too
often we fail to fully consult the people we intervene to help. Because
we all have rights, because we all have reason, we may think we do not
need to ask if our intervention is wanted. Of course they want to be
free; of course they want their rights. We are all reasonable human
beings; we can recognize their needs. When we meet objections from
those we hope to help, we may make the mistake of thinking we know
better. We fail to recognize the limits of our knowledge; we fail to im-
pose proper limits on our will. We forget that they have the right to
decide when and how and with whom they will rebel. We forget that
they have the right to choose whom they will be and how to govern
themselves together.
Force is the enemy of the free 133
fought with the French in the First World War, before the United States
joined in the alliance. The Lincoln Brigade fought with the Republicans
against fascism in Spain. They acted honorably.
Those who think that their people, their state, their army, or some
mercenaries hired for the purpose should fight in a foreign country
should think again. They cannot justly ask others to fight for them. If
they think the cause is worth a death, they should offer theirs.
There are places, many places, where people struggle to rule them-
selves. They elect representatives, propose and vote on referenda. They
hold town meetings. They make the case, among the people, for the
right of people to rule themselves. They march. They protest injustice.
They go to the streets. They resist coups. They fire revolutions. They
write constitutions. They make laws. They design institutions. They
experiment with governing. They attempt to forestall the efforts of
autocrats to take power, aristocrats and the wealthy to retain it. They
endure defeats, time after time. They win victories, small and large, and
as they do, they build the foundations for democracy. They clear away
a few more obstacles; they widen the space for the democratic. They
approach democracy, but they are not democrats yet.
There are times and places where people rule themselves. There
are countries where the people can claim that their government is
one they chose, one they choose in the present, that they make their
own laws. There are countries where people have become accustomed
to judging: where they turn their demanding gaze on the conduct of
officials, of the press, and of the laws themselves. These places can
be found on every continent. They are clustered in Scandinavia and
the Antipodes, but they can also be found in Africa, Asia, and the
Americas. Yet all of these places are, at best, imperfect democracies. In
no place are the people free to rule as they choose, unhindered by the
power of wealth and the fears of elites.
As Jacques Rancière writes, “We do not live in democracies.”
Wild Democracy. Anne Norton, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197644348.003.0009
Unfinished revolutions 139
have discipline and self-control. People who are willing to take on the
hazards of self-rule must have the courage and the strength to take risks
and see them through. Those who have the discipline to rule them-
selves have the strength to refuse to be ruled. Those who live among
the free and the self-ruled are free to refuse to rule.
Mohandas Karamchand Gandhi, who devoted himself to the proj
ect of self-rule in every sense, taught that the overcoming of foreign
rule depended on the capacity to rule oneself. If Indians were to end
British imperial rule, they had to first win through to self-control.
Gandhi knew the power of small things. He thought people who
were to rule themselves needed to prize their independence if they
were to win it. They would need to be self-sufficient. He taught his
people to make their own salt, to spin and weave their own cloth, to
grow their own food, to clean their own latrines, and to live simply.
They needed to be able to face the enemy with courage—whether that
enemy was the British Empire, someone of another faith or caste, or the
wolf in themselves. He taught them to face violence without flinching.
The core of satyagraha is not only the refusal to use violence but
the willingness to endure it. Those who practice satyagraha hold stub-
bornly to the truth. They do not give in when faced with violence.
Gandhi’s satyagraha could be achieved only by the courageous and the
steadfast. It depended on people willing to face their enemies—and the
violence of their enemies—without fear.
The idea that the people are creatures of passionate appetite, like
animals in their desires and appetites, driven by all the passions from
greed to revenge, should have fallen away long ago. It is not the people
who are driven by their passions and their appetites; it is the privileged.
The wealthy rule because they can. They have means denied to
others. They need to learn little about rule because their power depends
on force and bribery rather than politics. They can give positions to
their friends and punish their enemies. They can practice nepotism.
They can establish dynasties. They do. They can use their positions to
capture funds from the public purse. They can reward those whose
wealth and privilege support their own. They do. They can indulge
their appetites, protect their reputations by bribery, by suppression of
investigations, by financial control of the media. They do.
Unfinished revolutions 141
on the law of master and servant, and kept the hierarchies character-
istic of the feudal system. The laws that governed—that still govern—
factories, shops, corporations, understood employees to be servants.
They are not, as we so often assume, people who have signed a contract
to work in a certain place for certain wages. They are servants in the
ancient eyes of the law.
There is nothing antique about this. This is law in the present.
Law and the practices of the workplace enable employers to silence
workers. They are not permitted to speak as they please at work, even
about politics. To our shame, we take that for granted. The silencing of
workers does not stop there. They can be asked, coerced, or forced to
sign nondisclosure agreements. This is a violation of the right of people
to speak freely. There is nothing about work that can set the rights of
the people aside. They cannot be silenced. As we bring our bodies to
work, so do we bring our rights. They are inalienable. They cannot be
separated from us.
The denial of natural rights in the workplace is indefensible. Where
the body is, there rights are. While these rights are denied, people do
not rule themselves. While these rights are denied, no one who works
is free, and democracy is fenced out of the times and spaces of work.
While there are bosses, there are masters. We do not yet rule ourselves.
There are other, more intimate, and perhaps more devastating
inscriptions of feudalism that remain with us. They have taken root at
the sites we are accustomed to seeing as most our own: our bodies, our
racial and sexual identities.
Feudal titles were inscribed in blood and law. The text of entitlement
was written in blood.5 The nobility held title by descent, in the blood
of their ancestors, that most intimate inscription. The expectation of
deference shaped their bodies to the form and habitus of entitlement.
Sumptuary laws made those claims more visible, more legible, even at
a distance.
Power in the body did not pass away; it merely changed its form.
The authority written in the blood and worn on the body was more
economically inscribed on the body itself. The stigmata of race and sex
marked a new form of power in the blood, a new title to dominion in
the body. The title to command was no longer “I am your lord” but “I
am white,” “I am a man.”
144 Wild Democracy
Max Weber called politics “strong and slow boring of hard boards.”8
Politics is hard labor, but democracy is harder yet. I do not expect to
see the rule of the people accomplished in my time, but I hope to see
the work advance. In that work, I may catch sight of the greater work
to come.
There is no country in my time that can truly claim that the people
rule. In my country we have prisoners to free, prisons to close. We have
people to teach. We have wars to end. There are houses to save, people
to heal. There are reparations to be made. We must work until “justice
rolls down like waters, and righteousness like a mighty stream.” Our
house is not yet finished. Our work lies long before us, but it is work
we can do.
Americans usually understand our history in one of two ways.
First there is the history some read in John Locke and Alexis de
Tocqueville: Americans are born to freedom, born equal. In this his-
tory, God or a benign history gives freedom to us as a gift. This is
not true.
In the second history, America is on a road toward freedom. In this
history, democracy gradually overcomes obstacles. Freedom is con-
tinually expanding. Working men get the vote, the slaves are freed,
women get the vote, antisemitism and the old prejudices against
Catholics are overcome, and African Americans move steadily toward
equality and inclusion. This is Langston Hughes’s history, a history of
“promises that will come true”:
146 Wild Democracy
This is the history that won my heart as well, but I no longer believe it
to be true.
There is a third history, harder and less triumphal. In this history,
the American struggle for freedom is not a history of constant prog-
ress. In this understanding, freedom wars against the desire for do-
minion generation after generation. There is no certainty of victory.
In this history, people are not born to a predestined triumph. We are
born to struggle, to the long “slow boring of hard boards.” The rule of
the people, the achievement of justice, the protection of equality, the
preservation of the ungoverned and the ungovernable require constant
and unceasing work.
This history asks more of us and promises less. This history calls
people to take up the burden of past wrongs.
Tzvetan Todorov, writing of the early colonization of what would
become the United States of America, dedicated it to the memory of
“a Mayan woman devoured by dogs.”10 This moment of colonial cru-
elty stands for many more. People who have thrown off empire and
made themselves anew often believe that in that revolution they have
freed themselves from the sins of their past. Perhaps they will find,
like us, that they are still haunted and burdened, still facing the work
of overcoming that past. Cruelty may live in them, even against their
will. This is the history, not of America perhaps, but of American em-
pire. This is the history of the crowded holds of the Middle Passage,
of slave trading and the Klan, of the plantation and the overseer. This
is the history of conquest: of the decimation and confinement of the
First Nations, the Trail of Tears and the emergence of the reservation
system, of immigration restriction and border vigilantes, of raids on
undocumented workers and the imprisonment of children. This is the
history of the prison system. This history records Japanese internment,
the Cold War, Hiroshima and My Lai, McCarthyism, Abu Ghraib,
Guantanamo, torture, and a culture of surveillance. In this history, im-
prisonment follows in the footsteps of empire. In this history, greed
makes use of violence. This is the history of Haymarket and the Tulsa
Unfinished revolutions 147
are. This is what we have been. This is part of what we are. We are called
to bear that.
But this is not what we belong to. This is not what we will be. We
who watched were changed by that time. We saw the strength and
courage of the marchers. As we watched, we learned something about
justice and the rights of man. No one who saw this, who saw Emmett
Till’s mother beside his ruined body, who watched the marchers
cross the Edmund Pettus Bridge, can fail to remember that greatness
of soul.
There is a passage in the Republic where Plato takes up the question
of the just man. How would one know the just man? Plato proceeds
to treat the just man like Job: “he shall be stripped of everything save
justice,” and in that naked deprivation the reader is to see what jus-
tice is. Antonio Negri saw the labor of Job in his prison cell. We saw
it in the photographs from Mississippi and Alabama. The marchers,
stripped of the protections of the state, held their rights still. They be-
came rights and right incarnate, and the rights they stood for stood or
fell with them.
Americans once found their soul in those who affirmed, “We shall
overcome, someday.” The Civil Rights marchers kept open the possi-
bility of an America that is not yet. They reminded us of the meaning of
the words “We hold these truths to be self evident.” They held out to us
the possibility that we could be greater than we had been, greater than
the founders imagined, far greater than we are.
The slaves, longing for freedom, gave us a greater dream of freedom
than did the founders. The Civil Rights marchers—disenfranchised,
impoverished, brave—recalled us to that dream. I lived to see my city
dance in the streets at the election of a Black president. I lived to see
white supremacy rise up again. I lived to march with my people in the
city of brotherly love, affirming once again that Black lives matter and
that all men are created equal.
Knowing that tragic and disheartening events occur in every age, in
every time, among every people, we must reject the idea that democ-
racy progresses inevitably toward freedom. The work is not done. The
memory of hardship and shame dedicates us to the cause. Memory of
the triumphs enables us to keep our hands on the plow.
Unfinished revolutions 149
Many of those who have taught me, and those with whom I have
worked, have followed Sheldon Wolin in seeing a fugitive democ-
racy. They see democracy in those moments, great and rare, when
the people rise up and see themselves as a people: living and acting
together in the present. I see democracy growing in the crevices of the
everyday, yet I still turn to those moments. Those who have experi-
enced revolutions often write of feeling that they had been born again,
or that they were creating a novus ordo saeculorum, a new world order.
Perhaps these fleeting moments were moments of madness, perhaps
they were moments of wisdom, but whatever they were, they were
filled with a fragile joy that could not last.
These moments of democracy are fugitive, evanescent. They are
also generative and transcendent. In these moments, people recog-
nize themselves as a people. They see their fellow people as their own.
They see something beyond themselves, and they reach for it together.
For a moment, an idea is made flesh in them. That ecstatic recognition
does not remain in its immediacy or in its fullness, but the experience
of transcendence alters them. What they see, what they learn in those
moments sets them on a course to the future. This is how one becomes
what one is.
In the time since Wolin wrote, the idea of a fugitive democracy has
been deepened by the work of Black scholars and theorists. They heard
the echoes of the Fugitive Slave Act in the idea of fugitive democracy.
Surely democracy is fugitive when a government forces free people
back into slavery, when the law aligns itself with wealth against rights.
Surely democracy lives among those in flight.
Fugitive democracy is not, however, quite as fugitive as it appears.
These moments of fugitive joy shape a people, shape people, fill their
minds and fire their hopes. The practices they develop in those times
can shape their laws and institutions. The strength they hone then will
make them democrats.
Perhaps free people are always fugitive, running to ungoverned, un-
governable spaces. Perhaps democracy does fly to anarchy. Perhaps it
should.
X
Canon fodder
Wild Democracy. Anne Norton, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197644348.003.0010
Canon fodder 151
The Athenians did not. Their demos, divided into tribes, remained
closed to immigrants. They deferred to divisions of descent and family,
acknowledging their constitutive importance and retaining them as an
ordering principle.2
The memory of democratic Athens was, for much if not all of the
West, filtered through the vivid and varied imagination of the impe-
rial British. Athens proved democracy too wild, too demanding. There
were those like Bryon and Shelley who saw something of the demo-
cratic promise beyond the limits of Athens, but they died young. British
democrats fought for Greek independence, but British diplomats
would saddle Greece with an imported king and, worse, with the king’s
debts. The British, and those they educated, would not remember bur-
dening Greece with the expense of their newly installed Bavarian king
or debts to their imperial rulers. Athenian decline had proved the ne-
cessity of Roman order and Roman militarism. The British Empire saw
the need for a monarch. Athens was a rich inheritance, but a metal too
soft for tools or swords. As they hived off the friezes of the Parthenon
and carried them away as plunder, so the British would lay claim to
Athenian democracy only to enlist it in the service of aristocracy and
empire.
Athens was used thereafter to prove that democracy was a Western
inheritance. If democracy began in Athens, then it was Western and
all other peoples had it only as the gift of the West. Athens was not the
wellspring of democracy; it marked democracy’s limits. The Athenian
origin of democracy was also used to prove its fragility. If Athens, the
home of democracy, could not hold it, how could others?
Democracy has been haunted by this Athenian legacy. Democracies
must be small, because Athens was; ethnically homogeneous, be-
cause Athens was. Democracies could have slaves, because Athens
did. Democracies could not include foreigners or immigrants or those
whose ancestry was mixed or uncertain, because Athens didn’t. The
myth of Athenian democracy made the inclusion of women appear
unnecessary, perhaps absurd. That legacy has lasted into the present
and in areas where reason alone ought to have excluded it. Political
scientists enamored of taxonomies and other so-called scholars of
democracy act as if the exclusion of women from voting was, if not
natural, inevitable, and dismiss the late inclusion of women as a small
152 Wild Democracy
defending the sacred rights of the people and the earth, of ubuntu.
Whatever the place, whenever the time, whoever the people: democ-
racy can begin there. We have all that we need in ourselves.
republicans, or liberals, there are still few to be found who do not fear
the idea that people should rule themselves. Rawls, who spoke and
wrote the common sense of many liberals, concerned himself with
just outcomes and neutral procedures. His proceduralism, like that
of Habermas, still sees the people as Aristotle saw them: vulnerable
to demagogues and tyrants, lacking the intellect or education to rule
wisely. As critics noted in the wake of A Theory of Justice, Rawls’s ac-
count assumed human beings who too closely resembled white Anglo-
European men.7 Derrida sought to still the seeking for democracy by
a double strategy. Democracy was suicidal, “auto-immune,” destroying
itself (as generation after generation of theorists and philosophers
had argued) from within. The people were dangerous. Democracy
belonged to the eveningland, the land of death, and it should be left
there in the realm of the infinitely deferred. Habermas, whose early
work showed a love for as well as an anxiety concerning democracy,
grew ever more concerned with the technical requirements of commu-
nication. Where, then, does our veneration for democracy come from?
Where are those who speak for the rule of the people?
There are at least three answers to this, and all are true. The Western
canon of democracy has resources for democrats. There is truth in
that, but it is insufficient and misleading. There is no canon of democ-
racy. There are pamphlets and manifestos, court records, poetry, and
songs that record the struggles of the people for justice. The right of the
people to rule themselves has been forged not in the texts of the wise
but in the practices of the many. That is the canon we have neglected.
We might pause to wonder what the canon would look like if we
turned to the places where democracy has prospered.
Tomba’s Insurgent Universality brings some of those forgotten
democratic practices before us. Tomba looks not at the practices of
statesmen, official documents, or the memoirs of “great men” but at
how people have ruled themselves. Russian villagers adapted the mir, a
long-established, traditional form of peasant life, in which the peasants
governed their land in common. This was quite distinct from—and
ultimately in opposition to—collectivization. The mir differed both
from private possession and from collective ownership, and each suc-
cessive system had sought to eradicate it. The land was held not by a
collective but in common, which is to say it was not owned at all. Most
158 Wild Democracy
Day and night with our friends, talking, drinking, strolling, laughing,
we celebrated our liberation. And all those who celebrated it as we
did, nearby or far away, became our friends.
What an orgy of brotherhood!1
Wild Democracy. Anne Norton, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197644348.003.0011
160 Wild Democracy
Nor was he alone. He notes that the “priests, the old aristocracy, and
the people were meeting in a common sentiment.” They were not
afraid. Even for the defeated soldiers, “all other feelings seemed to
be absorbed by the pleasure of finding themselves free. They walked
without care, stepping lightly.”6
Everyone sees the joy, the festivity of the revolutionaries. This is not,
however, simply a moment of release, a kind of political Saturnalia in
which, just for a day or two, the world turns upside down and people
feel that all is possible. There is a strong note of practicality in these
popular celebrations. For one thing, people clean up after them-
selves. Anyone who watched the Egyptian Revolution unfold in Tahrir
Square, or the Lebanese uprising, could see the people organizing
themselves to pick up rubbish and the debris of demonstrations.
They went further; they scrubbed the place clean. When the Egyptian
revolutionaries were asked about their pails and scrub brushes, they
answered that it was their country now, and they would keep it clean.
The people of Tahrir Square, men and women, rich and poor, secular
and religious, organized food and medical care for themselves. The
secular protected the religious while they prayed. Revolutionaries may
be filled with an evanescent joy as they see their people around them
and know themselves as rulers together, but they also know the en-
during joy that transforms mundane acts. They are transfigured as they
come to power, and the world is transfigured for them. Their ordinary
work has become divine.
162 Wild Democracy
The rule of the people is always dangerous. The canon of every philos-
ophy warns, over and over unceasingly, of the hazards of democracy.
The people, statesmen and philosophers warn, will rob the rich to feed
the poor. (Though I will bless them if they do, I see no evidence of
this.) The people are licentious. Once they are free to rule, they will
give in to all their appetites. (Decadence seems to me to be a problem
more of the privileged than the people.) The people are passionate.
Once they are free to rule, they will do whatever they please, and do it
with a passion that no one can stand against. (Considered against the
whims of dictators, the passions of the people may seem less threat-
ening.) Except possibly for the last, none of these dangers are more
to be feared in democracy than in another form of rule. The last is
different.
When the people are free to rule, they will indeed do what they
please. Perhaps (it is my hope) they will do it with a passion that no
one can stand against. For some this is a threat. For others (I am among
them) it opens up a horizon of promise and possibility that I cannot
dream of seeing in my time (though still I hope).
What will the people do? Ask instead: What do people do? Do they
forget the past and rush headlong into utopian projects? Sometimes.
More often they look to the past for guidance. They seek to recover
goods they have lost. They try to emulate those they admire. They seek
to preserve what they love and honor in their own history and experi-
ence. They are more likely to regard the past in the rosy glow of myth
and memory than they are to abandon it. Will they then lose the drive
to exploration and invention? Some never have that. Others always
do. In the darkest times, in places of the most abject poverty, there are
thinkers, inventors, and explorers. There may be those who choose to
be comfortable, to live like Patrick Henry’s citizen and enjoy “the fruits
of his labor under his own fig tree, with his wife and children about
him, in peace and security.”7 They can live, sheltered and fed among
the people, and the people can be proud that such are safe and content
among them. People have learned that those who live peaceful lives,
cultivate their gardens and their families, can make good neighbors
and good friends. Some, like Wendell Berry, have written of them as if
Democratic times 163
One of the great contributions of the social contract theorists was their
recognition that people make the sovereign, make the state, make
themselves.
When the people rule, they build. They build in common. They
build as individuals. Free from the fear of coercion and dependence
on the powerful, they can live as they choose, think as they choose.
Their thoughts—and their ambitions—will have more range and more
focus. People who are free to speak and write as they choose can write
honestly. They can explore the past, examine the present, and plan the
future with clear eyes.
They build in common. They will debate, as they should, the virtues
of different plans and projects. Some will see the virtues of highways,
others of mass transit or the hyperloop. They will argue over sources
of energy. They will have more to argue over because the inventiveness
that independence unleashes will open unexpected possibilities. Those
with a passion for planning will be limited in their ambition to order,
and in their power, by the anarchic.
People who rule themselves, who secure freedom and equality
among themselves, open reservoirs of creativity dammed up by
autocrats, by aristocracy, by inequalities of wealth and power. They are
more just and more honorable, to be sure, but they are also more in-
ventive and more daring.
164 Wild Democracy
St. Augustine saw that sacred and secular time could exist, did exist,
in the same place, at the same moment.8 We are at once body and
soul. The time of the soul and the time of the mind are not the same
as the time of the body. The time of the body seems inexorable to the
mind: too slow for the young who long for adventures and power, too
rapid for the old who have fallen in love with the world. The mind is
not bound wholly to the time the body inhabits but wanders through
the past and into the future. Has the soul the timelessness we claim for
it? Perhaps. One who belongs to a people belongs at once to the time
the body inhabits, the time of the surrounding world, and to the time
of that people: to the past of the people and to the people’s future.
Those moments when people, knowing they are the eyes and hands
of the sovereign, bring a people into being, are sacred times. They are
moments removed from the mundane, moments out of time. The dead
call to the living and the living to the dead. Living and dead call to those
yet to come. Law and custom vanish, and the sacred enters.
And yet it is mine. This is the call that animated King’s speech the night
before he died: “I’ve seen the promised land. I may not get there with
you. But I want you to know tonight, that we, as a people, will get to the
promised land.”9 That is my country, the longed for country that is not
yet, the only country that commands my allegiance.
The promised land opened to King not because he dreamed of the
future, but because his dreaming was fired by “the fierce urgency of
now.” Democracy belongs to those who struggle to rule themselves in
the present. Democracy is made by—and in—those ordinary moments
of judgment in which people make, follow, question, critique, reject,
and disobey the laws. Democracy is made in those frustrating, seem-
ingly futile moments when people struggle to use the worn, blunt tools
they have. The vote cast for a disappointing candidate, the unsuccessful
campaign, the books and articles, the email sent to an unresponsive
senator, the unpublished letters to the editor, the marches in the sun
and the rain, the seemingly fruitless organizing, are all working toward
the people’s rule. Each testifies to the person’s commitment. Each offers
a hard training in the discipline of being ruled. Each demonstrates the
will to speak, to be heard, to rule. Each binds an uncertain future to the
fierce urgency of now.
XII
The direction of the democratic
The idea that the people rule remains a radical idea. It goes to the root.
In advancing it we “lay the axe to the root and teach governments hu-
manity.”1 Yet anyone who looks at what people do, what they ask, what
they long for, will find that they are not ready to abandon the past.
Paine’s great antagonist, Edmund Burke, is remembered as a conserva-
tive, but his conservatism had a profound respect for the wisdom of the
people. Burke’s belief that we should defer to custom and convention
has a democratic cast; it speaks to democratic history and democratic
sensibilities. At the very moment when the American Revolution
caught fire, the Declaration noted that people endure hardships and
evils for the sake of stability, that they change unwillingly. When people
decide important matters, they turn to the past. They look to history
and custom, they consult the advice, the wisdom and the dreams of the
past. They are not bound by the past, but they bear it in mind. The past
does not rule them, but they go forward mindful of those who came
before.
Many people see the rule of the people as rooted: rooted in custom,
rooted in history, rooted in their communities, rooted in the life of
people who have a shared life in a place they hold in common. Wendell
Berry wrote that the commonwealth, “household, neighborhood, and
community,” is “the foundation and practical means” of democracy.2
Those from Tocqueville to the present who admire the New England
township, those who write wistfully of the villages of England, Kenya,
and Rajasthan hold to this as well. There are left Burkeans to be sure,
and there are also conservative Gandhians: people who hold to the
virtue of the old ways of small communities and ancient crafts.
Wild Democracy. Anne Norton, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197644348.003.0012
The direction of the democratic 167
they fail to see that the limits of the present are their limits as well.
Blind to their own fallibility, indifferent to the virtues of others, they
insist that they know what is best, and their drive to a better future
becomes a forced march to an iron cage.
The belief that progress is predestined, that we shall overcome
someday, gives comfort in hard times. Those who suffer injustice rest
in the hope that better days will come. Those whose courage and virtue
are not matched by those around them move like horses running for
home, fueled by the hope that the country they call their own can still
be reached in their time. Their strength can become the strength of
their people.
Those who do not believe that progress is inevitable, who distrust
promises of either a heavenly or an earthly paradise, who have no faith
that we shall overcome one day may still take heart from those who do.
For us there is no promise but our promise, no redemption but in our
own work.
Those who believe that the people should rule themselves, who
agree to rule and to be ruled in turn, hoping for none to be ruled at
all, who are convinced that all men are created equal, that everyone
has a life to live, are radicals all. They go to the root. Everybody, every
body walking on the earth, living and breathing, hungry and thirsty,
thinking and planning, has a life to live. I ground rights in the needs
and demands of those bodies and the souls they shelter within them.
This is the ground of equality. The right to live freely, to live life apart
and in common, is rooted here.
The right of people to rule themselves is radical in another, more
common sense. Much must be changed to make that possible. There
are institutions to take down, rules to break, laws to disobey.
Praise of the conservative preservers and the progressives on
their predestined progress neglects the revolutionary power of the
uprooted and the rootless. These, exiles and refugees, dissidents and
heretics, are how newness enters the world. The world has failed them
or launched them into the unknown. Nothing holds them. They are
unbounded.
Conservative or liberal, progressive or radical, democrats are al-
ways fugitives. They are pursued on every side. Those who distrust
the people fear that they will unleash the mob. Those who want to
170 Wild Democracy
The rule of the people, Whitman saw, comes out of the ground
like grass,
It remains close to the ground. The right of the people to rule, the
power of the people to rule, is present in each of them, no matter how
poor, no matter how abject. The conviction that the people should rule
draws them upward. They stand tall, metaphorically but also in prac-
tice. When the people rule, they walk without fear. They stand firm in
the knowledge of their right to rule.
Democracy begins among the people and spreads, far too slowly,
upward, until the arrogance of the rich and privileged is shamed.
The rule of the people moves upward in another sense. The people
build. The spread of equality gives power to the creativity of the many.
Where a few once invented, discovered, explored, many do. The con-
centration of wealth in a few hands is often defended by arguing that
a fairer redistribution would stifle creativity and limit invention. The
opposite is true. The capacity for invention, research, discovery—yes,
“wealth creation”—is not concentrated in the hands of a few. When
people are given tools and education, the freedom to invent and exper-
iment, many create wealth where few did before. That wealth is spread
The direction of the democratic 171
more broadly, and as it spreads, more people are freed and inspired
to build.
The demands of self-rule raise standards of conduct. In asserting
this, I am, of course, directly contradicting the greater part of the
canon of Western political philosophy. I do so proudly. That canon was
written in the service of tyrants and for the advancement of the few.
These men claimed that free people would give themselves up to ap-
petite and license. We have seen that the closer people come to ruling
themselves, the more responsibility they assume.
When people follow tyrants, demagogues, and autocrats, they
abandon their pride, their responsibility, and their self-discipline. The
autocrat’s misconduct licenses every offense, every vulgarity, every
abandonment of responsibility. The followers abandon ethics for the
guidance of the corrupt, abandon responsibility for indolence, pride
for the pleasures of abjection.
It is otherwise with free people. The more responsibility they as-
sume, the more carefully they govern their own conduct. They learn to
judge, and they turn that judgment on themselves. Little is required of
them but much is asked. They learn to fend for themselves and to pro-
vide for others. They learn discipline, and they learn power. They learn
to stand up for themselves and for others.
They rise.
People who rule themselves reach upward to the divine.
Democrats rise, but in the common phrase they remember where they
came from. This is our common sense: the sense, held in common, that
we are all mortal, we are all fragile, we are all at risk. The rule of the
people looks to people in their simplicity: as mortals with all the needs
and frailties of embodied beings. Mindful that everyone has a life to
live, democracies direct their resources downward. Democracy has
the poor in its heart. People who rule themselves ensure that all are
fed, all are sheltered, all are cared for in times of need. Mindful that
they will not only rule but be ruled, they ensure that all are educated,
that all have the tools they need to cultivate their talents, that all have
172 Wild Democracy
the means to resist when resistance is necessary, that all have a place
to shelter in hard times, and, at all times, places where they cannot
be ruled.
The rule of the people moves downward in another sense. Power,
even the power of the ruling people, is not to be concentrated at a
single site, certainly not at the top. The decentralization that extends
democracy and shields the power of the people in hard times moves
downward. Power moves through the whole of the people, living, dead,
and yet to come, but it flows most powerfully among the living people.
Democratic rule depends on the presence and the lived experience of
power in all people. Every one of the people should know their power
and seize their right to rule. Every one of the people should be willing
to submit to rule by their own people.
Everyone must resist unjust rule, even—especially—among their
own. “The people shall judge” applies not only to the right of revolu-
tion and the need for it but to the ordinary conduct of a common life.
The people judge. They execute the laws they judge to be just in the
ways that they think best. Everyone must be ready to correct injustices,
great and small, and to call for revolution when revolution is necessary.
Each person builds their world, making it anew at every moment of
their common life.
People work to ensure that “justice rolls down like waters, and right-
eousness like a mighty stream.”6
When the people rule, they will make mistakes. They will try strat-
egies that fail. They will have plans with catastrophic consequences.
Even when they move wisely, they will encounter obstacles. They will
advance, and they will fall back. They keep the faith. They keep their
hands on the plow.
XIII
Democratic spaces
The people are never visible as a whole, for the people include in their
understanding of themselves the living, the dead, and those yet to
come. When the American people speak in the Constitution, we es-
tablish a government “for ourselves and for our posterity.” All people
move forward. When they come to know themselves as a people, they
look both to those they take as their compatriots in the past and to
their own presence, the presence of their children and their children’s
children, in the future. A people in its wholeness is thus hidden from
us. The closest we come to that vision of the whole is of the people
assembled. The sight of people stretched beyond the line of vision calls
up the vision of the people we cannot see. In that assembly we see the
people whose power and whose right to rule stands before and beyond
law and government. It is for this reason that demonstrations still serve
to call governments to account. Demonstrations remind governments,
institutions, officials that they serve at the pleasure of the people and
that they must answer to the people.
When people assemble they call up the people, but that call will
be judged by their compatriots, living and yet to come, perhaps even
by the dead. Their assembly calls people to ask: Do they stand for the
people? Do they stand for me? The answer to that question shapes the
constitution of the people.
National assemblies, congresses, and parliaments gesture visu-
ally toward the presence of the people. They are, in themselves, the
work of the people’s will in choosing their forms of governance and
the representatives themselves. The spectacle of deliberation and
debate—especially debate—makes two aspects of popular rule visible.
Representatives, and those who watch them, confront the differences
Wild Democracy. Anne Norton, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197644348.003.0013
174 Wild Democracy
and enmities among the people. They are reminded that though the
people are one people, they are also many people. We differ pro-
foundly, in practice and in principle, in our interests and in our ideals.
Only in the simultaneous presence of likeness and difference can the
people be seen.
Cities intensify. There is more art, more commerce, more crime, more
law enforcement, more politics, more scholarship, and more religion
in the cities than there is among the farms and ranches of the country
or the malls and developments of the suburbs. The weight of govern-
ance is felt more heavily. Every level of a decentralized government is
visible and active in the city. If government is centralized, it will be in
the city that its power is greatest. If it is decentralized, it will take on
myriad forms in cities. If it is liberal, the city will be hedged about with
regulations, which will be endlessly debated and modified. If it is auto-
cratic, it is in the city that the full weight of dictatorial rule will be felt.
The work of government will be visible to all: in buildings, in meetings,
in posted regulations. No one will be able to walk the streets without
seeing it. The work of the governing people is visible there and in the
contests surrounding issues and events. Sovereignty shows itself in the
city. Power shows itself in the city.
The simplest aspect of cities may be the most important. There are
more people. Cities are magnetic. They attract people who are looking
for jobs for there are many jobs, far more than are to be found in the
countryside. They attract people who want to study. There are uni-
versities in the country, to be sure, but the city has not only colleges
and universities but art schools and conservatories. People bring
their pasts, their hopes, their interests, and their ideals with them to
the city. People flee to the city from places where they felt lost, alone,
abandoned, or alien. They mix with others like and unlike themselves.
They are confronted by new ideas, new questions, new possibilities.
The pleasures and dangers of living with other people, unknown, dan-
gerous people, are familiar to them. They can acquire the common
Democratic spaces 175
courage that comes from living with difference, in and among the
unknown.
Party and the Progressives possible and fueled them with the urgency
of need.
The country is a place of solidarity and solitude. People help one an-
other. There is often nowhere else to turn. They combine, as they did in
granges, ranging themselves against the absent powers of banks, other
corporations, and the state. They learn to provide for themselves. They can
grow, hunt, fish, and forage for their own food. They learn to build. They
learn skills people in cities may never need. They strive to be free from de-
pendence on others, yet they give to their neighbors with an open hand.
The country can also be a place where anarchy spreads its branches,
where people live as they choose, and new ways of life are born and
take root.
There is a simpler way to state the preceding two theses: “In the city
the people rule” and “In the country the people rule.” One of the
shortcomings of the word “democracy” is its concealment of this
simple idea. I wrote the theses as I did because each holds a political
history within it. “Democracy belongs to the city” calls up the many
efforts to cast cities as places of sin and degradation. Many of the state
constitutions written after the American Civil War gave cities less rep-
resentation, and less power, than rural areas. Trump’s characterization
of Baltimore as “a disgusting rat and rodent infested mess” echoes a
long history of hostility to cities and their people. “Democracy belongs
to the country” counters a history of portraying rural people as igno-
rant and parochial. It recalls a neglected history of Midwestern radi-
calism in the search for justice. Both are charged with a predilection for
violence: the gangs of the city, the vigilantes of the countryside. Both
are feared as places of anarchy.
Let them be.
Political theory and political practice have divided the world again.
Statesmen and theorists have taught that there are separate realms,
public and private, ruled by different regimes. Where rights are con-
cerned, these divisions must be considered carefully, used carefully, for
they are a weapon that can turn in the hand. The distinction between
public and private can protect the people. The idea that some space
is private, that it cannot be entered by the state or by others can give
people shelter: shelter for their beliefs, for their practices, for whatever
they choose to keep to themselves. Holding that space, caring for what
lies within it, teaches them to rule. We have learned, however, that the
distinction between public and private gave some people unjust, ty-
rannical power over others. For women, for slaves, for servants, even
for children, the private realm has been made a prison. The idea of the
private, holding homes and corporations, has concealed the power of
the wealth and the persistence of feudal power in the aptly named ec-
onomic realm.
Democratic spaces 179
cases where those who work in the company own it as well, there is
nothing democratic here, nothing republican. This is alien territory for
people who intend to rule themselves. Here, the boss rules.2 This is true
for Goldman Sachs and Santander, Nando’s and McDonald’s, for the
man who owns a corner store and the man who owns Amazon. For
generations, for hundreds of years, people who believe themselves to
be democrats, who have built republics and struggled to establish at
least representative institutions have spent most of their lives under the
rule of one boss or another.
Is there anyone reading this who has not worked under a boss?
There are few, I expect, who have not worked under a bad one.
There are places, of course, liberal or striving toward the democratic
(even some totalitarian orders) where the boss is constrained. Slavery is
forbidden. Children under fourteen or fifteen or still in school are for-
bidden to work, or are allowed to work only when the work is not haz-
ardous. The hours a person can work are limited. Working conditions
are regulated for safety. Some workers are allowed to unionize. In lib-
eral places, places where people have worked to introduce elements of
democracy in their institutions, these constraints were won only after
hundreds of years of struggle and suffering. They are still evaded or
ignored.3 And though in music and art, in every medium, people rec-
ognize that the boss is a tyrant, the company’s rules foolish, and the law
powerless; though people talk, quietly and discreetly, in the corners of
the workplace, the rule of the boss is accepted, even praised, as essen-
tial to capitalism and wholly consonant with—perhaps even necessary
to—democracy. This is wrong.
Rights are held in the body, in your body, in our bodies. There is no
invisible process that strips them from you, silently and thoroughly, as
you enter the workplace. There is no boundary that that rights cannot
cross. The powers bosses claim and states license are illegitimate and
indefensible.
The idea that the workplace can be democratic may seem absurd
and unimaginable. Yet there have been many times when people not
only struggled for their natural rights in the workplace; they expected
them. The young women hired in newly established New England tex-
tile mills assumed that they carried their rights to speech and assembly
into the mills. They assumed that decisions about the mill would be
Democratic spaces 181
made democratically. After all, were they not still in a democracy? That
claim was answered with brute force, yet their question remains.
If people are to rule themselves, then they must do so everywhere,
not just outside the workplace and not for (allowing for eating and
sleeping) something less than six hours a day.
The same should be said of that amorphous zone called “the social
order.” Hannah Arendt argued, in “Reflections on Little Rock,” that
segregation was permissible in the United States because it belonged
not to the political but to the social order. Arendt believed that there
were no rights outside politics, indeed no rights for any people without
a state. The condition of the stateless thus was, for her, one of complete
abjection. They could make no demands, for they had no rights. Rights
came from laws. Rights came from states.4 She could not bring her-
self to ask for more for the stateless than “the right to have rights.” In
making the argument that the social order stood apart from politics,
Arendt made her politics smaller. She denied that politics takes place
outside law and governance. Politics observes no such boundaries. The
denial of equality and power to a slave or a wife in the home is political.
Caste and racial hierarchies are no less political because they are “so-
cial distinctions.” Hierarchies of wealth and poverty are no less political
because they are social (or economic). Arendt, Wendy Brown notes,
laid every sin of modernity at the feet of the “overtaking of everything
by the social.” Arendt praised the American Revolution for avoiding
“the social question in the form of the terrifying predicament of mass
poverty.”5 Arendt’s imaginary of an American Revolution raised above
concern for poverty conceals the revolutionary importance of the Dorr
Rebellion and the Whiskey Rebellion, the continuing pressure for vet-
erans’ pensions, and the text of the Declaration. Equality grounded the
revolution. Equality grounds democracy.
Where the people rule, each person carries the right to rule. More than
this, each person does the work of judging politics every day. They
make law together. They judge the law, they judge offenders, every day.
182 Wild Democracy
They execute the law, obeying when they think it best and ensuring
that others obey. The work of politics is thoroughly decentralized.
Responsibility belongs to every person.
The people are always present, not only in the form of an idea but in
the flesh. They do not simply “hover above the world,” as Tocqueville
wrote. They are in the world, doing the work that belongs to us all.
That presence, however, is only a partial one. Each of us is a part of the
people. Each of us stands apart from the people. We are partial to those
we love, to a place perhaps, or a party, to a particular set of sentiments
and ideas. We carry with us a particular set of experiences, of love and
loss, victories and frustrations. We carry knowledge and memory,
tastes and dispositions. We have some skills and not others. We learn
some things and make some errors. Yet it is in us, through us, and as us
that the sovereign people is present in the world.
It is in the thoughts and practices of particular people that the idea
of the people is called forth in the world. It is in and through the actions
of particular people that the people act.
Donne’s observation “Any man’s death diminishes me because I am
in involved in mankind” becomes more intimate and more political
here. There is only one way in which the people appear in the world.
The people appear in the people. My people appear in me. I am called
to act for, to act as my people in the world. There is no other way to call
a people into being. There is no other way for a people to be born, to
live, to thrive, to decay, to be lost except in its people.
There is, I have been told, a Hasidic belief that there is a person in
every generation who has the potential to become the Messiah. The
democratic call is broader than that. This is not a question of the possi-
bility of greatness in one. All are called, and all are chosen. All bear the
universal within them. Each person is a gate, and through that gate the
future comes into the world. When we belong to a people it is through
us, in us, as us that the people live or die, suffer or thrive.
XIV
Friends and enemies
Say this, as Wendy Brown has, in the clearest way: “Political equality
is democracy’s foundation.”1 When Americans declared their inde-
pendence, they began here. They addressed not their overlords but all
mankind. They began not with their grievances but with truths anyone
could hear and understand. First among these was equality: “We hold
these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal.” Those
words have returned to us from the Diné, the Muscogee, the Lenape;
from African Americans and Asian Americans; from Filipinos and
Puerto Ricans; from the interned, the deported, and the tortured. The
words are greater than we are. They set an enduring truth before us, be-
fore all. They command us.
When the great army that brought down the English monarchy saw
Charles Stuart captured, they sat down in the fields outside London
and began to debate what form of government they would have. These
debates, the Putney Debates, are one of the most heartening moments
in history, for they show us a people willing to make themselves anew.
There is much that is admirable in these debates, but one moment
has come to stand for the whole: Rainsborough’s declaration “I think
the poorest he that is in England has a life to live, as the greatest he.”2
Everyone has a life to live. Everyone is bound within the small compass
of a single body. Everyone has a need for food, for shelter. Everyone has
been born. Everyone will die. If we are born and live and die in the soli-
tude of the body, yet we know that all people do the same. Our rights to
life and liberty are grounded in the strength and fragility of the mortal
body, and the mind and soul sheltered within it.
Every person has uncertain potential; each has immeasurable
promise. Rainsborough might have said with the Talmud, “Every
Wild Democracy. Anne Norton, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197644348.003.0014
184 Wild Democracy
death is the loss of a world.” This is the equality that is proper to democ-
racy: that each person is of incalculable worth.
The British set equality aside, preserving monarchs and aristocrats,
building an empire. Nevertheless, the words remained, driving the
British beyond empire and toward justice.
Americans set equality aside when they held slaves, against the princi-
ples of the Declaration. We have not succeeded in overcoming the effects
of slavery or the other inequalities that diminish us as a people and as a
people. Nevertheless the words remain, driving us toward justice.
The struggle for freedom in Europe’s colonies, in Ghana and Algeria,
India and South Africa, fired the hearts of people far away. The demand
that the equality of each person be recognized could not be separated
from the demand that people be free to rule themselves as they chose.
The demand for freedom and independence was grounded in the rec-
ognition of equality.
They know that wealth is power and believe that in order to serve the
common good they need to court the wealthy.
Wealth divides. We do not see the very wealthy; they have set them-
selves apart from us, but we know that they are there. We know that
there are those who could not spend their wealth in many lifetimes,
but we do not see them. We see the poor. We know that there are those
who have so little that their lives are shortened, their creative abilities
stunted, their potential fenced in at every turn.
If wealth does not trouble us, poverty should. It should trouble us all
to see people begging on the streets.
Our eyes find this excess revolting. What of our minds? That excess
should appall us. Spare us the dangers posed by the poor. Consider the
greater dangers posed by the rich. The contrast revolts our eyes and our
minds; it is at once ugly and unjust. The longer it remains, the more it
is seen, the more culpable we are for failing to do our duty, for failing
to refuse this.
There is no common, no democratic life when people are divided
between rich and poor, when voice, action, and justice under law have
become commodities for purchase. A common life, a democratic life,
requires equality.
The Greeks, and the old Norse who surpassed them in democratic
ethics, both valued friendship. “In antiquity,” Nietzsche wrote of the
Greeks, “the feeling of friendship was considered the highest feeling,
even higher than the most celebrated pride of the self-sufficient sage—
somehow as the sole and sacred sibling of this pride.”4 The Hávamál
holds, “No man is whole,” and offers the practical advice:
The enemies of democracy are the fearful: those who seek glory,
autocrats, aristocrats, and all those who claim that their lives are worth
more than others’.
What is to be done with them? The fearful can be taught not to fear.
Children learn to overcome many fears: the darkness, loud noises, the
The friends and enemies of the democratic 187
new school, strange foods, and the monster under the bed. That ca-
pacity remains in all people. The fearful can learn. They can learn to see
foreigners as people who, like them, are hungry and thirsty, who need
shelter and protection. They can learn to see them as people with useful
strengths and skills. They can learn to look with interest and curiosity
at the strange appearances and practices of foreigners. Perhaps they
can do more. Perhaps the fearful can learn the courage of the explorers.
They can learn that new places, new people, new things, new ways can
be useful and pleasurable rather than threatening. They can learn that
the one they feared can be a fellow worker, a colleague, a friend.
Perhaps they can learn, as soldiers must, to face the enemy calmly.
Faced with those who truly threaten them, they can pretend to set their
fears aside and, as they do, find a courage to fill their pretense. Those
who fear change can be taught to be at home with it. Like a person who
has never sailed, they can learn to shift their weight on the deck, to
tack, to jibe, to feel pleasure rather than fear when the boat heels.
Aristocracy, Tom Paine wrote, is infantile and silly, “it talks about its
fine blue ribbon like a girl, and shows its new garter like a child”: “The
world has seen this folly fall, and it has fallen by being laughed at.”8 In
Paine’s time there were still those who held in their hands the lives of
the untitled poor, who claimed wealth and privilege and power on a
claim no stronger than that of a purebred dog. In Europe, that claim
would still hold fast, for a time.
Aristocracy fell so far and so hard in America that Paine could say,
“If I ask a man in America if he wants a King, he retorts and asks me
if I take him for an idiot?”9 That strength has held fast. No one wants a
king. Claims to the privileges or trappings of a lord would be mocked
unmercifully. Yet elements of the feudal order remain very much with
us, embedded in the law. The old law of master and servant lives dis-
guised in the laws that govern employers and employees.10 The idea of
power in the blood, preserved in hierarchies of race and sex has been
hard to dislodge. Racial and sexual claims to power over others are
among the shards of feudalism. There are still men who demand def-
erence simply for being men, with men’s bodies. There are still women
who are beaten for not accepting this. There are those who insist
people bear the bodies they were born with. There are, we have learned
to our sorrow, still people who long to claim title in their ancestry, who
188 Wild Democracy
Wild Democracy. Anne Norton, Oxford University Press. © Oxford University Press 2023.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780197644348.003.0015
Democratic divinity 191
commander who stands apart but in those who fill the trenches. We
have learned, like e. e. cummings, to see courage in the conscientious
objector, “more brave than me, more blond than you.”2
All of us who long to rule ourselves have seen that greatness and
beauty escape and exceed wealth and privilege. Beauty belongs not
only to Blenheim and the Forbidden City but to the ruins of Chaco
Canyon, the simplicity of a wooden house rising above a klong on the
outskirts of Bangkok. There is Ming pottery, and there is Acoma pot-
tery. There are the paintings of Velasquez, and those of Diego Rivera.
The wisdom of Supreme Court justices falls before the hopes of slaves
and workers.
Beauty and grace, courage and wisdom are not found only among
the great, whether the great are aristocrats or common people.
Tocqueville saw that, in the sight of the divine, beauty belonged to
masses of people who are fed, sheltered, educated and free and who
have made that world together. There is great beauty in the sight of
people studying, working, moving, speaking freely. Beauty belongs
to clean cities with clean water, unsoiled by litter; to clear rivers, filled
with healthy leaping fish; to open beaches free to all.
Divine beauty, Tocqueville saw, belongs not to the few but to the
many, not to evanescent moments but to the constant and enduring
good in ordinary lives. People who live justly, who see that rights are
honored, that people are fed and clothed, cared for and educated, who
think and act freely, build a more just world. “In its justice lies its great-
ness and beauty.”
very far from the possible. In this long struggle, belief in the people is
hard to come by. The fire is kept alive in the ashes by memory and by
forgetting.
We must forget, we democrats, that kings and priests were said to
be divinely ordained, that the order of wealth and privilege was said
to be the work of God or nature or the market. Forget those myths
that furnished—that still furnish—the license for oppression. Power
lies in anarchist refusal: “No gods, no masters.” Forget that we have
been scorned and humiliated: walk like gods. Remember those times
when the people rose up and, for a moment, gave the divine speech and
strength and hands to work in the world.
I do not know why, but I know the people sing. This will come as no
surprise to those who have heard people singing “We Shall Overcome”
in dark times. The jailers who heard them in Selma and Birmingham
knew that what they heard was not only the voices of the imprisoned
but the voice of the people, the voice of God.7 The people who heard
them heard their own voice raised. So it has been with “Bella Ciao,”
“Glory to Hong Kong,” “Solidarity Forever,” and other songs sung in
hopeful and in desperate times. The people who sang called forth the
divine.
I do not know why the people sing. I know that when they sing, their
voices join. They speak, they sing with one voice. When the people
sing, their differences are lost in the sea of sound. It does not matter if
you sing well or badly, your voice joins with the others in that ocean.
Rich and poor, old and young, people of every sex and race sing. They
sing as one. Their bodies vibrate to that singing. Their voices come out,
join with one another, and as they do the surrounding people feel the
sound of those voices near their heart. They speak and they hear in the
same moment. They sing and they feel the sound. I know that when the
people sing, their bodies carry the common, and yet each one sings.
In singing, the solitude of the body is, for a moment, affirmed and
overcome.
196 Wild Democracy
and child. We are held in it, we are fed by it, we care for it in our turn.
Because we are in this place and in this time we have a duty. We
are called to do justice in the present. That duty falls on each of us.
Everyone is called, every person living in the radical solitude of the
mortal body.
We live in the knowledge of death. As democrats, we know what it is
to face the prospect of our annihilation with courage. Because we are
before death, life is imperative for us. We have a calling. God calls, the
prophets call, the people in their divinity call to one another.
We may warm our hands before the ashes of old struggles. We may
fire our hearts with the desire for justice in the future. Yet it is only in
the present that we can rule ourselves. We are called not to endure but
to overcome. In the song of that name, it is not the refrain “We shall
overcome, someday” that we should sing; it is “We are not afraid today.”
Appendix of imperatives
Have courage. Fear is your enemy, courage your weapon and your
defense. Walk proudly among your enemies.
Keep the open spaces of anarchy.
We are all of equal worth. Act accordingly.
Every right entails a command, an obligation, a duty.
People have a right to self-preservation, to life. Therefore they have
a right to food, to shelter, and to healthcare. We are called both to
demand and to provide these.
People have the right to make themselves as they choose. They have
a right to education, to the tools for their work. They have the
right to move. They have the duty to open the world to others.
Undo empires. Decolonize.
Your rights are yours. They do not depend on legal recognition.
Seize them.
Your rights move with your body into the school, the factory, the
job site, the church, the masjid, and the synagogue, on the road,
in private and in public space. Do not ask permission to exercise
them. Obey their commands.
Assemble. In the flesh, on the internet. You need not ask permission.
Don’t begrudge taxes. Taxes are how we pay for the work we do
together.
Judge. Judge the laws, judge officials, judge others, judge yourself.
Defend the commons. Extend the commons.
Rule the law.
Support no war you will not fight in yourself. Do not ask anyone to
die for you.
200 Appendix of imperatives
I have debts to both the living and the dead. The Declaration of
Independence, the writings of the Levellers, the Swabian peasants who
gave us their Twelve Theses, Langston Hughes, Vachel Lindsay, Philip
Levine, Allen Ginsberg, e. e. cummings, Sheldon Wolin, Michael
Rogin, Christopher Hill, and Eric Hobsbawm: people I have known
in the flesh and people I have known only on paper are not among the
living, and yet they live for me. Though she is dead now, the deep dem-
ocratic sensibility of my mother lives in me, my sister, and my brother.
She was the daughter of a coal miner and farmer, granddaughter of
immigrant peasants from every corner of Europe, admirer of the Diné
way. She came out of the open prairie of Illinois and kept that intimate
immensity within her. She taught us democratic manners, a dem-
ocratic ethic, and democratic principles. My father taught me what
honor is among free people. He was a sailor who became an officer,
a captain of ships at war who came to mourn the lives he had taken.
When I saw him, I saw Hector, who took off his plumed helmet so it
would not frighten a child. I watched him live with courage and pas-
sion, love and generosity. He taught me poetry, Japanese aesthetics,
and the shape of stories, to give with an open hand, and to reach for
courage.
When I look back on what I have written I see Adolph Reed, Rogers
Smith, Asim Qureshi, Bruce Kapferer, Thorvald Sirnes, Neil Roberts,
Jane Gordon, Lewis Gordon, Drucilla Cornell, Uday Mehta, Jeff Green,
Michael Hanchard, Eve Troutt Powell, Jim Johnson, Jeffrey Tulis, Sami
al-Arian, James Scott, Joan Scott, Murad Idris, Rob Nichols, Wendy
Brown, Judith Butler, Joe Lowndes, Kevin Bruyneel, K-Sue Park,
Elizabeth Anker, Victoria Hattam, and Deborah Harrold in the pages
of this book. I know I have not done them justice or honored their
work properly. I fear there are those I have forgotten. Joan Scott, Laurie
Balfour, Aisha Ghani, Timothy Pachirat, Jeff Green, Rogers Smith, and
202 Acknowledgments
Jim Morone read versions of the book and guided me to its present
form. Ruth O’Brien and Angela Chnapko are sorcerors of publishing,
swift and daring. Didier Fassin, Bonnie Honig, Susan Buck-Morss,
and Seyla Benhabib, unsurprisingly, surprised me with wisdom at
critical moments. Massimiliano Tomba and Banu Bargu remade my
world. Together in Princeton, we shared food and thought, laughter
and struggle, work, transgression, and love for Teo. None of my work
will have their learning and scholarship, but it will carry their thinking
all the same.
Seminars at the University of California–Santa Cruz, the Graduate
Center of the City University of New York, Deakin University, the
University of Bergen, Columbia University, the University of Virginia,
the University of Calgary, and the Center for Islam and Global Studies
at Sabahattin Zaim University contributed to this work in ways that
leave me in their debt. The Institute for Advanced Study gave me time,
a home, new thinking, and new people. I have never been at a better
place. That was the year of Brood X. The rising of the cicadas sounds
like the sea. They come out of the ground en masse, they change, they
fly. They renew the world. I learned from the cicadas as Whitman
learned from the grass.
The people closest to this book have been the graduate students
I worked with in these years, especially Andrew Barnard, Yara Damaj,
Rosie DuBrin, Mackenzie Fierceton, Ashley Gorham, Archana Kaku,
Juman Kim, Gregory Koutnik, Clancy Murray, Gabriel Salgado,
Miranda Sklaroff, and Kimberly White. They will light their time in
their own ways.
Notes
II
15. Rudyard Kipling, “The Cat That Walked by Himself,” in Just-So Stories, n.d.,
http://www.boop.org/jan/justso/cat.htm. Kipling’s story is a version of the
myth of the social contract, particularly the version Carole Pateman called
“the sexual contract.” Carole Pateman, The Sexual Contract (Stanford,
CA: Stanford University Press, 1988). This appears in its clearest form in
Rousseau’s “Discourse on Political Economy.” Jean-Jacques Rousseau,
The Social Contract, with the Geneva Manuscript and Political Economy,
trans. Judith R. Master, ed. Roger Masters (New York: Bedford, St. Martin’s
Press, 1978). Freud (himself a contractarian of sorts) called these “just-
so stories.” Kipling’s version follows Rousseau’s very closely but deserves
more attention for its treatment of the ambiguities of consent and for its
recognition of the possibility of the preservation of individual freedom.
16. Niccoló Machiavelli, The Prince, trans. and ed. Mark Musa (New York: St.
Martin’s Press, 1964), 37–39.
17. Rousseau, The Social Contract, 56.
18. Walt Whitman, “Song of Myself,” in Murphy, Walt Whitman, 68.
19. Bob Marley, “Cornerstone,” on In Memoriam, 1974.
III
IV
1. Plato, The Republic of Plato, trans. Allan Bloom (New York: Basic Books,
1968), 557a.
2. Plato, The Republic, 557c. Those translations, including Bloom’s, that give
the Greek as “fair” undermine the condemnation of surface beauty by
acknowledging the presence of justice.
3. It is Thrasymachus, an aristocrat with an aggressive, even tyrannical dispo-
sition, who objects to the simple life initially proposed in the Republic. His
objection moves the dialogue from the never rejected but much disdained
“city of pigs” to the elaborate, hierarchical, and rigid constructions of the
later Republic.
4. The democratic possibilities of revealed religion are visible in Michel
Walzer, Revolution of the Saints: A Study in the Origins of Radical Politics
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982) and Exodus and
Revolution (New York: Basic Books, 1986), in the writings of Thomas
Müntzer, in the Putney Debates, and in liberation theology, among many
other places.
5. Al Farabi, “The Political Regime,” trans. Fauzi Najjar, in Medieval Political
Philosophy, ed. Ralph Lerner and Muhsin Mahdi (New York: Collier
Macmillan, 1963), 51.
6. Nietzsche, Genealogy of Morals, Second Essay: 10.
7. Walt Whitman, “Song of Myself,” in Murphy, Walt Whitman, 123.
8. Twelve Articles of the Swabian Peasantry, in The Revolution of 1525: The
German Peasants’ War from a New Perspective, ed. Peter Bickle, Thomas
A. Brady Jr., and H. C. Eric Midelfort (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins
University Press, 1982).
9. Judith Butler, Precarious Life: The Powers of Mourning and Violence
(New York: Verso, 2006).
10. Philip Baker, ed., The Putney Debates (New York: Verso, 2007), 69.
210 Notes
11. Ireton was clear. It was only those “who had a permanent and fixed
interest in this kingdom,” that is to say, those with property, wealth,
or title, who should have any “interest or share” in governance. The
Levellers and The Putney Debates, ed. Philip Baker (New York: Verso,
2007), 69–70.
12. Plato, Republic, 557a.
13. Ibn Khaldun, Muqaddimah, trans. Franz Rosenthal (Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press, 2005).
14. W. E. B. DuBois, Souls of Black Folk. See also Anne Norton, “Law
Breaker,” in A Political Companion to Frederick Douglass, ed. Neil Roberts
(Lexington: University of Kentucky Press, 2018), for an account of the role
of precarity in Douglass’s reconception of the democratic subject.
15. Uday Mehta, “Liberal Strategies of Exclusion,” Politics & Society 18, no. 4
(December 1990): 427–454. See also Uday Mehta, Liberalism and Empire
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999).
16. David Graeber, Fragments of an Anarchist Anthropology (Chicago: Prickly
Paradigm Press, University of Chicago Press, 2004), 26.
17. The autocrat, Xenophon and Arendt variously remind us, breeds fear.
See Xenophon’s “Hiero” in Leo Strauss, On Tyranny (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 2000); Hannah Arendt, Origins of Totalitarianism
(New York: Harcourt, Brace Jovanovich, 1973).
18. Plato, Republic, 463a.
VI
VII
VIII
IX
1. I am grateful to the Ghanaian student who pointed this out to his as-
tonished classmates in my seminar some years ago. I am ashamed to say
I have forgotten his last name. His first name is Justice.
2. For a fuller and more scholarly discussion, see Demetra Kasimis, The
Perpetual Immigrant: Athenian Democracy (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2018).
3. David Graeber and David Wengrow, The Dawn of Everything: A New
History of Humanity (New York: Farrar, Strauss Giroux, 2021).
4. Massimiliano Tomba, Insurgent Universalities: An Alternative Legacy of
Modernity (New York: Oxford University Press, 2019). This book gives us
hope and reason for hope. It teaches what has been built and how it might
be built again.
5. John Locke, Second Treatise on Government.
6. Locke, Second Treatise on Government.
7. Famous correctives were offered by Carole Pateman in The Sexual
Contract (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1988) and Charles
Mills in The Racial Contract (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1999).
8. Tomba, Insurgent Universality, 154– 159 on the mir, 71–119 on the
Commune.
XI
XII
1. Thomas Paine, Common Sense, The Rights of Man, and Other Essential
Writings of Thomas Paine (New York: Penguin, 1984), 142. Paine was
referring to Matthew 3:10.
2. Wendell Berry, The Art of the Commonplace: The Agrarian Essays of
Wendell Berry (Berkeley, CA: Counterpoint, 2003), 58.
3. The project was the thought and work of Gunter Demnig. It is one of the
most brilliant and thoughtful artistic works I have ever seen. This is demo-
cratic art: speaking of the many to the many, calling each passerby to judge.
4. Honor the stories and visions of the flying African. See Henry Louis
Gates and Maria Tatar, eds., The Annotated African American Folktales
(New York: W. W. Norton, 2018), 73–83; Rhiannon Giddens, “We Could
Fly,” on Freedom Highway, 2017.
5. Walt Whitman, “Song of Myself,” in Murphy, Walt Whitman, 86.
6. Martin Luther King Jr., “I Have a Dream,” speech at the Lincoln Memorial,
August 28, 1963. https://www.archives.gov/files/social-media/transcri
pts/transcript-march-pt3-of-3-2602934.pdf. King is quoting scripture.
Amos 5:24.
XIII
claim to speak to God, or claim that God has spoken to them, or that they
have knowledge open only to believers, and watched as their conduct
convicted them.
2. For an excellent discussion of the boss, see Elizabeth Anderson,
How Employers Rule Our Lives (and Why We Don’t Talk About It)
(Princeton: Princeton University Press 2017).
3. Council of Europe, Commissioner for Human Rights, “Child Labour in
Europe: A Persisting Challenge,” August 20, 2013, https://www.coe.int/
en/web/commissioner/-/child-labour-in-europe-a-persisting-challen-1.
4. Rancière refuses Arendt’s distinction between political life and what
Agamben has called “bare life” in Jacques Rancière, “Who Is the Subject of
the Rights of Man?,” South Atlantic Quarterly 103, nos. 2–3 (2004): 297–310.
5. Wendy Brown, In the Ruins of Neoliberalism, 47.
XIV
XV
For the benefit of digital users, indexed terms that span two pages (e.g., 52–53) may, on
occasion, appear on only one of those pages.