Regia, Quae de Imperio Eius Lata Est, Populus Ei Et in Eum Omne Suum Imperium Et Potestatem Conferat Vigorem
Regia, Quae de Imperio Eius Lata Est, Populus Ei Et in Eum Omne Suum Imperium Et Potestatem Conferat Vigorem
Regia, Quae de Imperio Eius Lata Est, Populus Ei Et in Eum Omne Suum Imperium Et Potestatem Conferat Vigorem
The Roman jurist Ulpian observed that:
Absolute: On this point, he said that the sovereign must be hedged in with
obligations and conditions, must be able to legislate without his (or its) subjects'
consent, must not be bound by the laws of his predecessors, and could not,
because it is illogical, be bound by his own laws.
Perpetual: Not temporarily delegated as to a strong leader in an emergency or a
state employee such as a magistrate. He held that sovereignty must be perpetual
because anyone with the power to enforce a time limit on the governing power
must be above the governing power, which would be impossible if the governing
power is absolute.
Bodin rejected the notion of transference of sovereignty from people to the ruler (also known
as the sovereign); natural law and divine law confer upon the sovereign the right to rule. And
the sovereign is not above divine law or natural law. He is above (ie. not bound by)
only positive law, that is, laws made by humans. He emphasized that a sovereign is bound to
observe certain basic rules derived from the divine law, the law of nature or reason, and the
law that is common to all nations (jus gentium), as well as the fundamental laws of the state
that determine who is the sovereign, who succeeds to sovereignty, and what limits the
sovereign power. Thus, Bodin's sovereign was restricted by the constitutional law of the state
and by the higher law that was considered as binding upon every human being.[4] The fact that
the sovereign must obey divine and natural law imposes ethical constraints on him. Bodin
also held that the lois royales, the fundamental laws of the French monarchy which regulated
matters such as succession, are natural laws and are binding on the French sovereign.
Despite his commitment to absolutism, Bodin held some moderate opinions on how
government should in practice be carried out. He held that although the sovereign is not
obliged to, it is advisable for him, as a practical expedient, to convene a senate from whom he
can obtain advice, to delegate some power to magistrates for the practical administration of
the law, and to use the Estates as a means of communicating with the people.
Bodin believed that "the most divine, most excellent, and the state form most proper to
royalty is governed partly aristocratically and partly democratically".
With his doctrine that sovereignty is conferred by divine law, Bodin predefined the scope of
the divine right of kings.
Age of Enlightenment
During the Age of Enlightenment, the idea of sovereignty gained both legal and moral force
as the main Western description of the meaning and power of a State. In particular, the
"Social contract" as a mechanism for establishing sovereignty was suggested and, by 1800,
widely accepted, especially in the new United States and France, though also in Great Britain
to a lesser extent.
Thomas Hobbes, in Leviathan (1651) put forward a conception of sovereignty similar to
Bodin's, which had just achieved legal status in the "Peace of Westphalia", but for different
reasons. He created the first modern version of the social contract (or contractarian) theory,
arguing that to overcome the "nasty, brutish and short" quality of life without the cooperation
of other human beings, people must join in a "commonwealth" and submit to a "Soveraigne
Power" that can compel them to act in the common good. This expediency argument attracted
many of the early proponents of sovereignty. Hobbes strengthened the definition of
sovereignty beyond either Westphalian or Bodin's, by saying that it must be: