Introduction To Scholastic Theology (PDFDrive) PDF
Introduction To Scholastic Theology (PDFDrive) PDF
Introduction To Scholastic Theology (PDFDrive) PDF
Introduction to
Scholastic
Theology
•
Ulrich G. Leinsle
Translated by Michael J. Miller
Copyright © 2010
The Catholic University of America Press
All rights reserved
Abbreviations ix
v
vi Contents
Bibliography 361
Index of Names 387
Abbreviations
ix
x Abbreviations
1
2 What Is Scholastic Theology?
for the first time in a philosophical context in the Politics of Aristotle (384–
322 BC). It signifies a freely chosen activity which is performed for its own
sake, and ultimately θεωρία as an expression of σχολή, the pursuit of what
is essential unencumbered by the immediate requirements of living.3 Ar-
istotle’s disciple Theophrast (372/369–288/285 BC) uses “σχολαστικός” in
this sense to describe himself: he is someone who lives for θεωρία.4 “Βίος
θηωρητικός” for Chrysippus (281/277–208/204 BC) is synonymous with
“βίος σχολαστικός” as a term for the way of life proper to the philosopher
alone.5 Through the organization of “schools of philosophers,” “σχολή” or
“schola” becomes in Cicero’s time (106–43 BC) a term for everything con-
cerned with the business of schooling: the place, the instruction, but also
the [ideological] alignment of the school.6 A scholasticus, accordingly, is
anyone who has to do with the school, and in a broader sense an educated
man (eruditus, literatus, sapiens), but especially the rhetorician (rhetor, first
century BC) and the learned legal counselor (third century AD).7
This linguistic usage is essentially preserved in Christian antiquity also.
We find “scholasticus” (sometimes in the superlative) especially as a mark of
distinguished learning and erudition and as a term for rhetoricians, advo-
cates and officials.8 As late as the Merovingian period it is the customary title
for a civil servant, whereas from the Carolingian period on it also designates
the head of a cathedral, municipal, or monastic school.9 In any case scholas-
ticus is not found in the early and High Middle Ages as a (self-) description
of a particular kind of theology, but rather as a description of persons, books,
or a manner of speaking or teaching (scholastice loquentes, scholasticae disputa-
tiones), whereby “scholastic” can simply mean “learned,” but also “academic”
[schulmässig, sometimes implying dependence on a school of thought]. With
reference to the education of his day, Haimo of Auxerre († ca. 855) defines
“scholastice” as “philosophice sive dialectice.”10 In the twelfth century scholasti-
cus serves in monastic circles (admittedly in very few instances) to character-
3. Aristotle, Politics 1313 b, 2–3; 1322 b, 38–39; 1341 a, 18–19; see also Nicomachaean Ethics 1177 b, 22.
4. Diogenes Laertios, Vitae philosophorum V, 37, ed. H. S. Long, vol. 1 (Oxford, 1965), 215.
5. Plutarch, Moralia 1033 c, ed. M. Pohlenz and R. Westmann (Leipzig, 1959), 6:2–3.
6. Cicero, Tusculanae disputationes 1.7–8, ed. K. Büchner (Zürich-Stuttgart, 1966), 8–9; 1.113
(114–15); 2.6 (146–47); 3.81 (270–71); 5.25 (278–79).
7. See Du Cange, Glossarium mediae et infimae latinitatis (Paris, 1883–1887), 6:350 (Papias);
Sueton, De grammaticis et rhetoribus 30, ed. G. Burgudi (Leipzig, 1963), 4. Theodosiani Libri XVI,
8.10.2, ed. Th. Mommsen—P. M. Meyer (Berlin, 1905), 405. Claus, Ho Scholastikós, 20ff., 150ff.
8. See Manser, “Die mittelalterliche Scholastik”; Claus, Scholastikós, 95–125.
9. See Schmidinger, “Scholastik,” 1334.
10. See Landgraf, “Zum Begriff der Scholastik,” 488.
What Is Scholastic Theology? 3
ize the methods and persons of the municipal or cathedral schools.11 Even
the title Historia scholastica by Petrus Comestor (ca. 1100–ca. 1179) indicates
nothing more than the fact that the work was a popular medieval textbook.
“Scholastic” as a description of medieval philosophy and theology is a
modern term. Erasmus of Rotterdam (1466–1536) and Martin Luther (1483–
1546) explicitly contrast their positions with those of “scholastic” theology
and philosophy, which they see embodied in the three late medieval schools
(sectae) of the Thomists, the Scotists, and the Nominalists. “Scholasticism”
takes on negative connotations and implies reverence for Aristotle, barbaric
Latin, hair-splitting, sophistry, useless logical disputations and pastoral bar-
renness.12 Luther’s Disputatio contra scholasticam theologiam (1517) distances
itself from a particular sort of theology, which besides the aforementioned
evils is characterized by its Aristotelianism (especially the Metaphysics) and
the overemphasis on man’s capability as opposed to the grace of God which
alone is effective (sola gratia).13 In view of this clear dissociation of Luther
and the humanist disdain for Scholastic “barbarism,” the early Protestant
school cannot be described as Scholasticism. Moreover the initial Protes-
tant altercations with Aristotelian metaphysics are conducted in a human-
istic and not a Scholastic spirit. Thus in 1598 Rudolf Goclenius (1547–1628)
publishes an Isagoge in Peripateticorum et Scholasticorum Primam Philoso-
phiam, quae dici consuevit Metaphysica.14 Later Christoph Scheibler (1589–
1655) describes “Theologia scholastica” as a “strange sort of theology, as it is
pursued by the noble professors at the great schools and other schools. In
which nothing else is to be found but what they had to discuss most inge-
niously pro and contra.” In contrast, correct theology is entirely “directed ad
praxin [toward practical formation] or at training.”15
The rejection of Scholastic theology expounded here, however, could
not prevent the establishment, influenced by the newly incorporated meta-
physics of Catholic (and especially Spanish) Scholasticism, of a sort of
Scholasticism in the Protestant schools as well, although it soon met with
resistance from within those ranks.16 The undifferentiated use of scholasticus
11. See Chenu, La théologie au douzième siècle, 325; Leclercq, Wissenschaft und Gottverlangen, 11.
12. See Dalfen, Erasmus von Rotterdam; Quinto, Scholastica, 133–41; Schmidinger, “‘Scholastik’
und ‘Neuscholastik,’” 36–38.
13. WA 1, 224–28; see also the Römerbrief-Vorlesungen [Lectures on the Letter to the Romans]
dated 1515–1516: WA 56, 273, 296, 312, 337, 354; Quinto, Scholastica, 208–15.
14. Frankfurt, 1598; see also Leinsle, Ding, 175–88.
15. Ch. Scheibler, Aurifodina theologica (Leipzig, 17272), A3ff. ; Leinsle, Ding, 324.
16. Especially Jakob Thomasius, “Historia variae fortunae, quam Metaphysica experta est,” in
Thomasius, Erotemata Metaphysica (Leipzig, 1670); see also Leinsle, Reformversuche, 141–46.
4 What Is Scholastic Theology?
even as late as the seventeenth century is illustrated by the early Aristotelian
scholar Christian Dreier (1610–1688), who contrasted his own philosophy
with the interpretation of Aristotle proposed by “Scholastici et Jesuitae,” call-
ing the former “scholastica speculatio” as opposed to “praxis civica.”17 The
term “Scholasticism” is fraught with even more negative connotations in
Enlightenment philosophy, which since the days of Christian Thomasius
(1655–1728) saw in the “pedantic philosophy” of the “Papist monks and
friars” nothing but a prejudiced doctrine beholden to the authority of the
“dark,” unenlightened centuries of yore.18
In contrast, the so-called Second Scholasticism or Baroque Scholasti-
cism at the Catholic universities and religious houses of study at the turn of
the eighteenth century consciously regarded itself as the continuation and
renewal of medieval philosophy and theology.19 Precisely in the expression
“theologia scholastica,” however, “scholastic” acquires a new meaning. As dis-
tinguished from so-called positive theology (exegesis, casuistry, canon law),
it designates “theologia speculativa” (systematic theology), which is carried
out methodically first in the Commentary on The Sentences of Peter Lombard,
and later in the Summa Theologiae of Thomas Aquinas or in the treatises of
a cursus theologicus.20
“Scholasticism” thus signifies, from both the outsider’s and the insider’s
perspective in the sixteenth to eighteenth centuries, medieval, and early
modern philosophy and theology, especially at Catholic (but sometimes
also at Protestant) universities and upper schools until the Enlighten-
ment.21 The Enlightenment claimed to have prevailed over it. The Catholic
renewal of Scholastic (especially Thomistic) philosophy and theology in
direct opposition to the Enlightenment in the nineteenth century is there-
fore described as Neoscholasticism. Although the term “Neo-Scholastic”
originally had a political emphasis within the context of the Ultramontane
movement, it eventually appears, thanks to the legitimacy bestowed on it by
the encyclical Aeterni Patris dated August 4, 1879, as the name selected by
philosophers, theologians, and periodicals themselves to make clear their
17. Ch. Dreier, Sapientia seu Philosophia prima (Königsberg, 1644), a2v; see also Leinsle, Reform-
versuche, 128–34.
18. Ch. Thomasius, Einleitung zur Hof-Philosophie (Frankfurt/Leipzig, 1710), 39f. ; see also
Leinsle, Reformversuche, 162–67. This theme continued to be influential down to the time of Hegel,
see Schmidinger, “‘Scholastik’ und ‘Neuscholastik,’” 42–43.
19. See Giacon, La seconda scolastica; Leinsle, “Scholastik,” 54–69.
20. See Quinto, Scholastica, 238–95; Schmidinger, “‘Scholastik’ und ‘Neuscholastik,’” 44; Lang,
Loci theologici, 28; Tshibangu, Théologie positive.
21. See Leinsle, “Scholastik,” 54–56.
What Is Scholastic Theology? 5
ecclesiastical alignment.22 Yet Neoscholasticism, like Baroque Scholasti-
cism, is not just a repetition of the Middle Ages, but at least partially an ap-
plication of Scholastic methods and teachings to new questions, which are
nevertheless treated along the same lines as the old authorities and meth-
odologies. Scholasticism (in most cases restricted to Thomism) thereby be-
comes a normative standard of philosophy and theology.
2 Attempts at a definition
“What-is-it” questions are not uncommonly understood to be ques-
tions calling for a definition. So it happened that in Neoscholasticism there
were attempts to define the essence of the normative standard “Scholasti-
cism” and thus to delineate a theoretical paradigm for the academic disci-
pline.23 These attempts at a definition should be critiqued in terms of their
presuppositions and their historical suitability.
As early as 1909 the historian Martin Grabmann advocated a concept of
Scholasticism informed by the Scholastic method: “The Scholastic method
intends to gain as much insight as possible into the contents of the faith
through the application of reason and philosophy to the truths of revelation,
so as [1] to bring supernatural truth closer to the human mind which re-
flects on it, [2] to make possible a systematic, organically structured general
presentation of the truth about salvation, and [3] to be able answer reason-
ably the objections raised against the contents of revelation.”24 This influ-
ential definition of the term, nevertheless, is both too broad and too nar-
row. It restricts Scholasticism to theology. However, since specialists have
demonstrated that the methods of decisive importance for medieval theol-
ogy were developed in jurisprudence and medicine, in some cases within
Islam, “Scholasticism” can no longer be restricted to theology alone.25 To
explain and defend the rationality of the contents of revelation, moreover,
is not an independent method but rather a concern that can be pursued by
different methods. The narrowing of the Scholastic method to this concern
leads Grabmann to conclude that theologians who apply the technique of
38. Bonaventure, Collationes in Hexaemeron II.3, in Opera omnia, ed. Quaracchi (1882–1902),
5:337a; see also Quinto, Scholastica, 81–87.
39. See, for example, Die Matrikel der Universität Innsbruck, vol. 2, Matricula theologica, part 1,
ed. J. Kollmann (Innsbruck, 1965), lvi; see also Leinsle, Studium im Kloster, 95–97.
40. Kluxen, “Thomas,” 181.
41. See Schönberger, Scholastik, 45: “Scholastik [. . . ] läßt sich wohl nur durch eine Kombina-
tion von einzelnen Beschreibungen, aber nicht durch eine definitorische Formel fassen.” [“Scholasticism
. . . can probably be understood only through a combination of individual descriptions but not
through a formulaic definition.”]
42. De Rijk, La philosophie au moyen âge, 20–21. Concerning the critique, see Schönberger,
Scholastik, 49–50.
What Is Scholastic Theology? 9
commonly found until the sixteenth century, and again these treatises on
logic typically apply generally to the scientific method that must be used in
all disciplines if they intend to be considered sciences.43 Thus the statement
that Scholasticism is a “method without a ‘discourse’” can hold true only for
parts of medieval Scholasticism but not for the modern offshoots.44 It’s just
that this “discours de la méthode” [methodological discourse] is treated not
in the specialized discipline in question but rather generally in the study of
Logic for all the disciplines. Here of course we should distinguish the sci-
entific method, as it is established for instance in the Posterior Analytics of
Aristotle, from the form of presentation and the teaching technique, so that
even within this methodological concept of “Scholasticism” differentiations
again take effect, which show that the Scholastic method, too, is not a uni-
form construct but rather a complex methodological paradigm with shift-
ing techniques, presuppositions, manners of representation and standards
of rationality. Common to them all, however, is their orientation to a stan-
dard of scientific rigor (which in each case is determined by the times). If
we want to understand what Scholastic theology means in a particular era,
we must therefore above all study the underlying concept of science.45 For
that concept determines the methods to be applied, and these in turn deter-
mine the form in which the related discipline is handed down orally and in
writing. Therefore the characterization of a discipline as Scholastic can be
made comprehensible only in terms of the scientific criteria and techniques
of the Middle Ages and of the early modern period.
3 Characteristics
If a definition of the essence of Scholasticism is not possible, then at
least a few characteristics should be listed to make the object in question—
Scholastic theology in the Middle Ages and the early modern period—
more accessible. An initial characteristic is its academic character [Schulmäs-
sigkeit, a term that sometimes implies dependence on a school of thought],
in contrast to forms of free, spiritual or monastic theologizing. Thus Jean
Leclercq has suggested speaking about a “theology of the schools” instead
of about “Scholastic theology.”46 But new problems crop up here. In the me-
43. See Ashworth, Language and Logic; Leinsle, Ding, 452–59.
44. Schönberger, Scholastik, 50. The general discourse, however, should be expected after the
general acceptance of the Posterior Analytics in logic.
45. This has been carried out in an exemplary way by Schrimpf, “Bausteine.”
46. Leclercq, “Renewal of Theology,” 72.
10 What Is Scholastic Theology?
dieval school system there were various types of schools at which theology
was taught: monastic schools, cathedral and municipal schools, and later re-
ligious houses of studies, general houses of study, and universities.47 Among
the monastic schools a further distinction must be made between internal
schools for the choir monks and the schools for the externs (people living
in the world). One suspects that these different schools with their different
students represent in each case a different theology. Thus Anselm of Can-
terbury, who since Grabmann has been considered “the father of Scholasti-
cism,” was a monk in Bec at the time when he wrote his most important
works. If one restricts “Scholastic theology” to the nonmonastic schools,
then Anselm is not a Scholastic. On the other hand, a typical Scholastic like
Abelard was from time to time a monk and an abbot and was conversant
with the forms of monastic theology.48 Moreover in the twelfth century
we are dealing with a strongly person-centered scholarly education, which
was acquainted not only with a school in Laon but with a school of Laon, a
school of Abelard or a Porretan school (at various locations). Here, at the
latest, Scholastic theology in the sense of “the theology of the schools” dis-
solves into more than one.49
Likewise a definition of Scholastic theology by means of a standard of
scientific rigor or rationality, as Wolfgang Kluxen and Gangolf Schrimpf
have suggested, seems to be insufficiently precise as a uniform criterion.50
For even in the patristic period we find rational proof of the faith and sci-
entific theology with methods that are basically Scholastic (quaestiones et
responsiones, commentary),51 since even Grabmann can speak about the
“Scholasticism of the late Greek patristic era.”52 However the concept of sci-
ence and the standard of rationality change, as Schrimpf demonstrates in
an exemplary fashion, not only between the ninth and the twelfth century
(Scotus Eriugena and Abelard) but even more with the reception of the Pos-
terior Analytics of Aristotle and in the early modern debate on method. Yet
presumably the factor that characterizes the Scholastic form of theology as
an academic, scientific and rational penetration of the deposit of faith, with
a special technique and form of presentation that distinguish it from other
4 Scholastic theology
If we are to define “Scholasticism” or “theology” in the Middle Ages, we
cannot start from today’s concepts. In the patristic era the concept of theol-
ogy covered a broad spectrum of themes and approaches, including Chris-
tian doctrine as a whole but also and especially “theologia triparta” made up
of poetic, political, and philosophical theology.66 The semantic fixation of
theologia upon the present understanding of the term came about together
with the development of a professional, academic, “scholastic” theology in
the twelfth century.67 Yet besides this term, other much more widely-used
lastik kann man geradezu als eine fast totale Herrschaft des Sprachsystems über alle anderen Orientier-
ungs-, Reaktions- und Interaktionssysteme ansehen. Das dialektisch nach allen Seiten hin abgesicherte
Argument, das jeweils beweist, was nur sein kann und was jedenfalls nicht sein darf, reicht aus, um Wahr-
heit und Wissen zu garantieren.” [“Medieval Scholasticism can be regarded as an almost total do-
minion of the linguistic system over all other systems of orientation, reaction, and interaction. The
argument that has been tested and proved on every side proving in each instance what must be and
what cannot be, is sufficient to guarantee truth and knowledge.”]
74. Schönberger, Scholastik, 63.
75. For further discussion see Flasch, Einführung, 38; Schönberger, Scholastik, 64–68.
76. See esp. Fichtenau, Ketzer und Professoren.
77. Ibid., 254–55.
78. Ibid., 245–57.
What Is Scholastic Theology? 15
defining, univocal term, but rather as a collective name for the theology that
was developed along various lines in medieval schools and universities and
to some extent was still pursued or renewed in the early modern period.
The characteristics that distinguish it from contemporary forms of theol-
ogy (epistolary literature, monastic treatises, spirituality, mysticism) are the
methods accepted in these schools for use in theology: commentary on an
authoritative text, lectio, disputatio, and praedicatio, taking into account the
changing standards of rationality and concept of science in the individual
eras. But since these standards and concepts, like the methods themselves,
are part of a development, Scholastic theology should not be understood
either as a uniform structure, the essence of which can be summed up in
a definition. Instead its history can only be reconstructed genetically. Nor
should this lead to a genetic definition but rather, within the framework of
an introduction, merely to an independent understanding of the inquiries,
methods, and results of Scholastic theology in the Middle Ages and the ear-
ly modern period. This will be accomplished by alternating survey chapters
with the description of central problems in the respective historical peri-
ods. In these contexts the individual theologians will be introduced along
with their solutions. Therefore this volume does not offer a comprehensive
presentation of the history of theology or dogma. Nor can it evaluate the
individual theologians in terms of their achievements.79 An appropriate
understanding of Scholastic theology could, though, also help to overcome
many prejudices against “ivory-tower Scholasticism,” for example, the idea
that a Scholastic is nothing but a theologian who “under pressure from a
past that is deemed authoritative vainly attempts with outdated methods to
illuminate an outdated matter, without any lively understanding of present-
day problems.”80
79. For that purpose we refer the reader to the well-known standard works, especially the
Handbuch der Dogmengeschichte (HDG) and Handbuch der Dogmen- und Theologiegeschichte
(HDThG). Good surveys are offered in Evans, ed., Medieval Theologians; Köpf, ed., Theologen des
Mittelalters; Leppin, Theologie im Mittelalter.
80. G. Krüger, Das Dogma von der Dreieinigkeit und Gottmenschheit (Tübingen, 1905), 259;
cited in Grabmann, Methode 1:1.
1 How Did Scholastic Theology Come About?
1. See, among other studies, Stockmeier, Glaube und Kultur, 120–37; Studer, Schola Christiana,
170–94; Kobusch, Christliche Philosophie, 26–57.
16
How Did Scholastic Theology Come About? 17
losophy” of Christianity and the richly differentiated Hellenistic culture of
its day. Greek philosophy is not necessary for salvation, but it is for a deeper
understanding of what is believed: “However, just as we declare it possible to
be a believer without any knowledge of the art of writing, so too we agree that
one cannot possibly understand the teachings contained in the faith without
learning. For the ability to accept correct teachings and to reject the others
comes not simply from faith, but only from faith that is based on knowledge.”2
Faith, then, needs rational justification of its content (fides quae) and of the
assent given by the believer (fides qua). Now this rational justification, which
is supposed to lead to an understanding of the content of the faith, takes place
with the help of the intellectual methods and philosophical precedents of the
era in question. For Christianity in late antiquity, this implies philosophy. The
philosophy of the Greeks, however, seemed to Clement [of Alexandria] to
have been surpassed by Christ. “Since the Word Himself has come to us from
heaven, we need not, I reckon, go any more in search of human learning to
Athens and the rest of Greece. . . . For if we have as our teacher Him that filled
the universe, . . . the whole world, with Athens and Greece, has already be-
come the domain of the Word.”3 This priority of the Christian message over
pagan philosophy is a constituent element of every Christian theology, if it is
not to be relativized as an arbitrary philosophy of religion or worldview. What
is relativized instead is philosophy: it becomes a propaedeutic or preparatory
instruction for the faith insight and for theology as well, and thus its claim to
be the independent way of salvation for the educated men of late antiquity is
denied.
Yet this optimistic equilibrium between pagan philosophy and Chris-
tian revelation in a scientific theology is not shared by all. Tertullian († after
213) speaks in a different language: “What indeed has Athens to do with Je-
rusalem? What concord is there between the Academy and the Church? . . .
Our instruction comes from ‘the porch of Solomon,’ who had himself
taught that ‘the Lord should be sought in simplicity of heart.’ . . . We want
no [wise sophistry] after possessing Christ Jesus, no inquisition after en-
joying the Gospel! With our faith, we desire no further belief. For this is
our primary faith, that there is nothing which we ought to believe besides.”4
27. Augustinus, div. quaest. 48 (CCh SL 44A, 75); C. epist. fund. 12, 15 (CSEL 51, 1, 208–9).
28. Augustinus, div. quaest. 48 (CCh SL 44A, 75, 7–10).
29. Augustinus, ag. christ. 15 (CSEL 41, 118, 17–21).
30. Augustinus, quant. an. 76 (CSEL 89, 224, 11–12).
31. Augustinus, vera rel. 45 (CCh SL 32, 215, 4–8).
32. Augustinus, ep. 120, 3 (CSEL 34, 707, 2–5).
33. Augustinus, En. in Ps. 118, 18, 3 (CCh SL 40, 1720–1); see Duchrow, Sprachverständnis, 106–7.
How Did Scholastic Theology Come About? 23
For Augustine, this auctoritas is now, after Christ’s divine authority, the
continuation thereof par excellence in the “auctoritas scripturae” [“author-
ity of Scripture”], as he repeatedly emphasized from 392 on.34 Yet here
too, being personally affected by the word of God is contrasted with the
hermeneutic-theological approach to Scripture, which defuses scandalous
passages by means of contemporary allegorizing and thus responds to the
“verbi auctoritas” [“authority of the word”] with its own interpretation: that
it is only a matter of a “figurata locutio” [“figurative speech”].35 On the other
hand the correct exegesis is actually a part of the authoritative character of
Scripture; for Augustine it is a true book in terms of (natural) science as
well. One proviso: If a sentence in the Bible were clearly false in the literal
sense, it would have to be interpreted in some other way. All sources of er-
rors in the codex or in the translation should be assessed in advance.36 The
problem of possible contradictions in the Bible itself, which was a major
concern of the patristic authors and a favorite point of attack on the part of
the “unbelievers,” prompted Augustine to resolve these alleged contradic-
tions in an exemplary way in De consensus evangelistarum. Agreement and
harmonization are the order of the day here, since there must not be any
contradictions in a book having divine authority, neither within the book
itself nor in comparison to extra-biblical truths.
If ratio is at the service of biblical auctoritas as a matter of principle,
then the Church’s teaching authority in the service of the truth also appears
as an “external hermeneutic principle” and “guardian of true exegesis.”37
Consequently for people today the Church’s authority is sufficient cause
to believe the authority of Scripture, as Augustine put it in the famous say-
ing: “Ego vero evangelio non crederem, nisi me catholicae ecclesiae commoveret
auctoritas” [“Indeed, I would not believe the Gospel if the authority of the
Catholic Church did not move me to do so.”]38 Justifying this authority of
the Church is again the task of ratio, especially in debating with pagans and
heretics—a task that is admirably taken up in De moribus Ecclesiae Cath-
olicae et de moribus Manichaeorum. The ratio auctoritatis attempts to prove
that acceptance of the authority and obedience to it is an act of reason or
at least a reasonable activity. Augustine sums up this program of theologi-
34. Augustinus, duab. anim. 9 (CSEL 25, 1, 61, 20); see Lütcke, Auctoritas, 128–36.
35. Augustinus, doct. chr. III, 15 (CCh SL 32, 87, 19–22).
36. Augustinus, ep. 82, 3 (CSEL 34, 354, 2–22); see ep. 143, 7 (CSEL 44, 258, 2–9).
37. Lütcke, Auctoritas, 144.
38. Augustinus, c. ep. fund. 5 (CSEL 25, 1, 197, 22–23); see util. cred. 31 (ibid., 38–40).
24 How Did Scholastic Theology Come About?
cal investigation in the alternative: proof of the truth of the contents of the
faith or proof of the authoritative position of the one who demands that we
believe this content.39 Despite this basically harmonizing tendency, it must
not be overlooked that ratio has a critical potential as well, which in certain
circumstances can endanger the position of the auctoritas. Therefore theol-
ogy is always an adventure of critical reason in the presence of the claim of
divine, biblical and ecclesiastical authority.
39. Augustinus, c. ep. fund. 14 (211–12). Listed as possible arguments: the professional and
moral qualifications of the person invested with authority, miracles, the fulfillment of prophecies,
and more generally: the success, age, and continuous tradition of the authority, recognition of the
authority even among opponents. See Lütcke, Auctoritas, 166–76.
40. See esp. Marrou, Augustinus, 163–392; Studer, Schola Christiana, 102–3, 149.
41. On the varying divisions of the artes in Augustine’s writings, see Ferrarino, “Quadruvium,”
359–64.
42. Augustinus, de ord. I, 2, 3 (CCh SL 29, 90, 1–17); see Leinsle, “Weltordnung,” 369–77.
43. Augustinus, conf. I, 15, 24 (CCh SL 27, 23, 7–8).
44. Ibid., X, 35, 54–57 (ibid., 184–86); see Marrou, Augustinus, 296–97.
How Did Scholastic Theology Come About? 25
man’s eternal destiny, an education in the liberal arts contributes nothing
unless it is used as a path to God. Therefore caution is required also when
themes from pagan education are placed at the service of Christian theol-
ogy, so that “the demon of art” does not thereby insinuate itself again into
Christian education.45
The philosophical outline of a “studium sapientiae” [“study of wisdom”],
as set forth in Cassiciacum in De ordine, is less decisive for medieval theol-
ogy than the theological purpose to which profane education is put in De
doctrina christiana. On the one hand the bishop of Hippo adheres to phi-
losophy as a path to God, yet he places it in the Christian context of faith, so
that it becomes “sapientia christiana.”46 An indispensable condition for this,
however, is the study of the artes; besides this education there is no other
way by which one can reach sapientia.47 If the way of sapientia were the only
way, then only a few would arrive at theology. Augustine himself traveled
that path. The bishop of Hippo now realizes that in addition to this sapien-
tial type of theology another type is necessary, which makes it possible to
employ the arts and sciences directly in the service of the faith. Augustine
now terms this latter type scientia:
not indeed so as to attribute to this knowledge [scientia] everything whatever that
can be known by man about things human, wherein there is exceeding much of
empty vanity and mischievous curiosity, but only those things by which that most
wholesome faith, which leads to true blessedness, is begotten, nourished, defended,
strengthened; and in this knowledge most of the faithful are not strong, however
exceeding strong in the faith itself. For it is one thing to know only what man ought
to believe in order to attain to a blessed life, which must needs be an eternal one;
but another to know in what way this belief itself may both help the pious, and be
defended against the impious, which last the apostle [1 Cor 12:8] seems to call by
the special name of knowledge.48
45. See Augustinus, conf. V, 3, 4 (CCh SL 27, 59, 26–38); doct. chr. IV, 14, 30–31 (CCh SL 32,
137–39); Marrou, Augustinus, 296–97.
46. See Augustinus, ep. 218 (CSEL 57, 426); ep. 155 (CSEL 44, 430–34).
47. Augustinus, de ord. 2, 18, 47 (CCh SL 29, 132–33).
48. Augustinus, de trin. 14, 3 (CCh SL 50A, 424, 56–67); see Augustinus, doct. chr. 2, 7, 9–11
(CCh SL 32, 36–38).
26 How Did Scholastic Theology Come About?
basis for this program of theology is therefore the study of sacred Scripture:
The “divinarum scripturarum studiosus” undertakes the study of this scientia.49
Yet even as early as Augustine, theology cannot be reduced to exegesis: be-
sides plainly exegetical works, which in any case are repeatedly interrupted
by speculative questions, there are dogmatic and polemical treatments and
elementary summaries of the substance of the faith.50 This corresponds ex-
actly to the stated ecclesiastical aims of the theological scientia.
Within this framework, the old pagan education can be justified in an
officially Christian society only by reasons from the Bible and in the service
thereof. Whatever useful things can be found in it are either to be found
in the Bible also or else to be used in interpreting it. The value of profane
education is thereby drastically relativized: only as a resource or auxiliary
discipline to theology does it have any justification in the Christian world of
education.51 Augustine thereby aligns himself with the conciliatory tenden-
cy among the Church Fathers in the debate about παιδεία. His achievement
consists of De doctrina christiana but above all in the fact that he outlined a
plan of studies and an examination of theological methods for the “divina-
rum scripturarum tractator et doctor” [“one who commented on and taught
the sacred Scriptures”].52 Naturally the linguistic subjects of the Trivium,
especially grammar and rhetoric, seemed particularly important for the
theologian. To Latin grammar was added the knowledge of foreign languag-
es, primarily Greek and Hebrew. Yet Augustine associates with grammar
the exact sciences: history, geography, natural history, and the mechanical
arts. These are followed by rhetoric and dialectic (logic) as instruction in
the formal laws of right thinking and science. The so-called Quadrivium
of mathematical arts (arithmetic, geometry, music, and astronomy, which
Augustine sometimes calls celestial mechanics) make the transition to phi-
losophy, which is pursued here essentially as doxography: a selective over-
view of the teachings of the pagan philosophers, insofar as they agree with
the Christian faith.53 Augustine adopts to a great extent the curriculum
of the schools of his day and now places it as a whole at the service of the
interpretation of divine revelation. He modifies several subjects, however,
and thereby gives rise to those problematic areas that then led to debates
67. Boethius, De fide cath. (ed. Elsässer 46, 8–10; 48, 31).
68. Ibid. (46, 29–48, 30).
69. Ibid. (62, 258–63).
70. Boethius, Contra Eut. (ibid., 66, 30.41–42).
71. See Häring, “Commentary of Gilbert of Poitiers”; Häring, Commentaries on Boethius;
Green-Pedersen, Topics.
72. See Schrimpf, Axiomenschrift, 148–49.
How Did Scholastic Theology Come About? 31
less, precisely as a scientific method for theology, prescribes an unmistak-
able standard of rationality.
104. See especially with regard to scriptural commentary Rouse & Rouse, “Statim invenire.”
105. Concerning the following “characteristics of Scholastic inquiry,” see Schönberger, Scho-
lastik, 53–80.
106. Grabmann, Methode, 2:26.
How Did Scholastic Theology Come About? 41
quaestiones et responsiones or in a modern question-and-answer session.107
The simplest answers, naturally, are references to authorities with whom the
master agrees.
The results of the quaestiones are summarized in literary form at first in
similarly miscellaneous collections of questions, which quite often contain
material by different and sometimes anonymous authors.108 Sometimes
scholars looked through the scriptural commentaries of the magistri for
quaestiones and excerpted them, for example, in the case of Robert of Melun
(† 1167) and Richard of St. Victor († 1173). The place of many questions in
the outline of systematic theology became clear in this way.
Already in the patristic era there was theological questioning, precisely
about biblical passages. Often perplexed confreres or preachers are the ones
posing the questions; we have vivid examples of this in Augustine’s expla-
nation of several questions about the Letter to the Romans.109 This mode
of instruction has its source in the dialogical, dialectical questions of antiq-
uity. We are well acquainted with medieval disputation of questions in con-
nection with the lectio from the ninth century on. At first it does not seem
to have been a disputation with assigned roles, but rather a simple inquiry,
especially in the case of contradictory authorities, which were perhaps fol-
lowed by an equally simple answer by the teacher. Probably that was how it
was usually done in the school of Anselm of Laon († 1117). We then encoun-
ter fully developed quaestiones with pro and contra around the mid-twelfth
century in the works of Odo of Ourscamp, who was a student of Anselm of
Laon and Abelard. Even in these early examples some of the more difficult
passages from Scripture are explained by extended questions. The logical
methods for this are provided initially within the framework of the dialec-
tica in the artes liberales; Haimo of Halberstadt († 853), too, distinguishes
between a simple, random disputation and liberaliter disputare, which pre-
supposes the methods of the artes liberales.110 A strictly logical disputatio
in forma (in syllogistic form) is possible only after the general acceptance
of the Logica nova (especially the Topica and the Sophistici elenchi): John of
Salisbury († 1180) maintains that without these, one does not dispute “ar-
tistically” but haphazardly.111 The great disputations became a field of intel-
125. Robert of Melun, Sententiae, “praefatio,” in Œuvres de Robert de Melun, ed. R. M. Martin,
vol. III, 1 (Louvain, 1947), 11, 28–12, 1; see Grabmann, Methode, 2:342–46.
126. Robert of Melun, Sent. praef., vol. III, 1: 24, 17–29; see Grabmann, Methode, 2:348–49.
127. For an indispensable inventory of medieval scriptural commentaries, see Stegmüller, Rep-
ertorium Biblicum, 11 volumes in all.
128. Robert de Melun, Questiones de Epistolis Pauli, in Œuvres, ed. R. M. Martin, vol. II (Lou-
vain, 1938); see Smalley, Study, 66–82.
129. Robert de Melun, Questiones de divina pagina, in Œuvres, ed. R. M. Martin, vol. I (Lou-
vain, 1932).
How Did Scholastic Theology Come About? 47
script version as well—and be replaced by a systematic arrangement of the
questions. The transition from biblical lectio to systematic theology should
be seen precisely in this gradual detachment of the quaestiones and the sen-
tentia arrived at therein from the biblical text.130 Biblical exegesis (divina
pagina) and systematic presentation (fides catholica) are nevertheless still
united in one work.131 It was not always a commentary directly on the bibli-
cal text, though: Zacharias Chrysopolitanus bases his In unum ex quatuor
(written between 1140 and 1145) on the harmony of the Gospels by Am-
monios of Alexandria, which he uses as an outline for what is essentially a
catena of passages from the Church Fathers and contemporary magistri.132
Many Scholastic scriptural commentaries are extant not in a copy (or-
dinatio) composed by the magister himself, but only in transcripts (reporta-
tiones) written down by students; these versions may or may not have been
revised and therefore not infrequently contain discrepancies or disagree-
ments; because of these errors and misunderstandings they should be used
with caution.133 Not all the books of the Bible were annotated in the schools
with the same zeal and partiality. The Psalms, the Pauline Letters and Gen-
esis 1 were among the biblical texts most commented on in the early twelfth
century. In contrast, there was essentially nothing written about the rest of
the Pentateuch and the historical books of the OT, the prophets, or even the
Gospels and the Acts of the Apostles.134 In 1121 or 1123, when Abelard tried
to hold a lectio on Ezekiel in Laon, this was forbidden as something unusu-
al.135 Soon scholars noticed also the errors and uncertainties in the biblical
text [i.e., the Vulgate] on which the commentary was based. Hebrew was for
the most part unknown. Stephen Harding (1059–1134) and the early Cister-
cians, especially Nikolaus Manjacoria († ca. 1145), however, with the help of
Jews, worked on a corrected version of the [Latin] OT text so as to restore
the “hebraica veritas.”136
Scriptural interpretation flourished in a particular way in the school of
the Canons Regular of St. Victor in Paris, where the tradition of monastic
spirituality (lectio divina) was combined with that of Scholastic exegesis.
137. PL 175.
138. MS Paris, BN lat. 13432, f.65–83. See Häring, “Commentary,” 193.
139. See Smalley, Study, 145–56; Berndt, André de Saint Victor.
140. Catalogus virorum illustrium 27, ed. N. Häring, “Two Catalogues of Medieval Authors,” in
Franciscan Studies 26 (1966): 201; see Quinto, Stefano Langton, 1–42.
How Did Scholastic Theology Come About? 49
lexicon of possibilities for exegesis, grouped under individual headings (be-
ginning with Abel). The theory of exegesis is investigated in writings such as
De difficultatibus Sacr[a]e Scripture and De Tropis loquendi.
The Scholastic interpretation of the Bible, which includes a variety of
approaches, presupposes the theory that Scripture has more than one mean-
ing or sense. Very important proponents of this theory of the fourfold sense
of Scripture were Hugh of St. Victor with his Didascalicon, Petrus Cantor,
and last but not least in the thirteenth century Bonvanture’s prologue to the
Breviloquium; the latter two are also in the Victorine tradition.141 The senses
of Scripture are not just exegetical methods; for Hugh they are disciplines
which together produce the sacra doctrina. Therefore the theologian in the
Middle Ages had to be well versed in all these areas, from literal exegesis
to the mystical-spiritual interpretation. Although the emphasis may depend
on the individual author and the field in which he worked (school, mon-
astery, parish), the literal sense usually predominates. The doctrine of the
fourfold sense of Scripture was practically canonized and handed down in
the oft-cited mnemonic verse by Augustine of Dacia († 1281):
Littera gesta docet, quid credas allegoria,
moralis quid agas, quo tendas anagogia.142
The foundation for the spiritual interpretation is the littera or the histo-
ria. Without it a spiritual interpretation goes astray as a matter of principle.
There is no question about the historicity of divine revelation in the bibli-
cal books. Thus Hugh recommends beginning with a careful lectio of the
historical books of the Bible. The littera is, so to speak, the alphabet that the
theologian has to learn first. He who proceeds otherwise acquires knowl-
edge like that of a donkey.143 For an understanding of the historical sense,
history and geography should be applied, besides the linguistic disciplines.
Upon this foundation, then, the building of the spiritual interpretation
is constructed; allegory is the first step. Allegorical interpretation, which
was already common in reading classical authors in the schools of antiq-
uity, found a home especially in Alexandrian exegesis. It concerns initially
141. See esp. de Lubac, Exégèse médiévale [Medieval Exegesis]; Chenu, “Théologie symbolique”;
Smalley, Study, 242–63.
142. “The literal sense teaches what happened; what you should believe—the allegorical; the
moral (= tropological) sense—what you ought to do; what you should strive for—the anagogical.”
See Châtillon, “Vocabulaire,” 17–18.
143. See Hugh of St. Victor, Didascalicon VI, 3, ed. Ch. H. Buttimer (Washington, 1939), 114,
9–10: “quorum scientia formae asini similis est. noli huiusmodi imitari.”
50 How Did Scholastic Theology Come About?
an overall interpretation of Scripture in relating the OT to the NT as the
“prophetic prefiguration” or “type” of the latter.144 In OT words, figures and
events, components of the NT event involving Christ and the Church are
discerned. Allegory occurs as verbal allegory (words that have a meaning
other than the literal sense), but also as “allegoria facti”: events and figures
“mean” something else above and beyond the historical context. There are
many methods, some of which are handed down in fixed patterns; the imag-
es and metaphors used are generally intended to reveal something hidden,
to open up a new dimension of understanding.145 This is true also for bibli-
cal numbers, for which precise rules were handed down from the days of
Augustine. Unfamiliarity with numbers is an obstacle to the allegorical and
mystical understanding of many scriptural passages, he maintains explicitly
in De doctrina christiana.146 The technique of number allegory is developed
in the twelfth century in precise rules: for example, the analogy between
number and what is numbered, the interpretation of numbers as sums of
terms or products of factors, affinities, and types of numbers based on their
composition, but also the meaning of the symbolic numbers themselves (4,
7, 12, etc.).147
The moral or tropological sense derives from Scripture rules for Chris-
tian living and its virtues, either for the Church as a whole or for the in-
dividual person. This kind of interpretation, which passes from “factum” to
“faciendum” [from what has been done to what should be done], reaches its
apogee in the moral-pastoral scriptural exegesis of Petrus Cantor and Ste-
phen Langton, sometimes mixed with clear criticism of conditions in the
Church. The basic models for this interpretation are the pastoral rules and
the Moralia in Job by Gregory the Great († 604).148
The mystical or anagogical sense is by no means the exclusive prov-
ince of contemplative circles; rather it is one of the forms of exegesis even
in non-monastic schools. The anagogical sense points on the one hand to
the Second Coming of Christ at the end of the ages, but on the other hand
to the mystical anticipation thereof in the individual soul and its ascent to
heavenly glory. Anagogy as the goal of the spiritual interpretation of Scrip-
ture can be more or less closely connected with allegory or tropology; it
144. Dohmen, “Schriftsinn.”
145. See esp. Spitz, Metaphorik and the discussion there of individual images and metaphors.
146. Augustinus, doct. chr. II, 16, 25 (Cch SL 32, 50, 52–53).
147. Basic presentation in Meyer / Suntrup, Lexikon der mittelalterlichen Zahlenbedeutungen;
see also Hellgardt, Zahlenkomposition; idem, “Zahlenallegorese.”
148. See Smalley, Study, 242–63; Baldwin, Masters.
How Did Scholastic Theology Come About? 51
usually cannot do without a foundation in the allegorical interpretation of
Scripture.149
In works entitled Distinctiones and Allegoriae the possibile interpreta-
tions of individual words or objects are then set down as though in a lexicon,
whereby types are developed: “Jerusalem” means literally the city in Israel,
allegorically the Church, tropologically the human soul, and anagogically the
heavenly Jerusalem in glory.150 Individual Scripture passages for a particular
interpretation can also be listed under a keyword: for example, it is possible
to interpret “bed” allegorically as sacred Scripture (Song of Songs 1:16), tro-
pologically as contemplation (Luke 17:34), conscience (Psalm 6:6) or car-
nal desire (Amos 6:4), anagogically for eternal punishment ( Job 17:13) and
eternal happiness (Luke 11:7).151 The danger of such allegorical-symbolic
interpretation lay in neglect of the text itself in its literal sense, even for the
“doctrina fidei.” Thomas Aquinas clear-sightedly insists instead on the pri-
macy of the littera: Only from the literal sense can a valid theological argu-
ment be obtained, not from an allegorical interpretation.152
Nevertheless it would not do justice to medieval biblical studies if one
were to see only the symbolic-spiritual interpretation. Indeed in St. Victor
and in the Parisian schools flourishing centers of literal exegesis developed
under Andrew of St. Victor († 1175), Herbert of Bosham († 1186), Petrus
Comestor, and others. 153 Andrew of St. Victor limits himself exclusively to
the historia. The other senses of Scripture are of as little interest to him as
Scholastic theological questions, insofar as they are not immediately related
to an understanding of the littera. He consults Jewish exegetes and com-
pares the text of the Vulgate with the Hebrew wording. The interpretation
of the Church Fathers is measured accordingly and quite often criticized.154
Strongly influenced by Andrew was Herbert of Bosham, who claimed to be
the first to expound the Hebraica [Hebrew version] after the example of Je-
rome.155 He does not venture to soar on the pinions of a difficult spiritual
interpretation but rather is determined to keep his feet on the ground and
elaborate only the meaning of the littera.
149. See Adamus Scotus, Ad viros religiosos: quatorze sermons d’Adam Scot, ed. F. Petit (Tonger-
lo, 1934), 28 and 94.
150. See Dohmen, “Schriftsinn,” 20.
151. See Smalley, Study, 247; Bataillon, “Instruments de travail”; Bataillon, “Intermédiaires.”
152. Thomas Aquinas, S.Th. I q.1 a.10 ad 1 (I,9).
153. See Smalley, Study, 112–242. For the works of Andrew of St. Victor, see: CCh CM 53.
154. See Berndt, André de Saint Victor.
155. See Smalley, Study, 186–95; see also by the same author “Commentary.”
52 How Did Scholastic Theology Come About?
This study of the littera broadens theologically through the influence
of the Historia scholastica by Petrus Comestor, which Stephen Langton
deemed as influential as the Liber Sententiarum of Peter Lombard. Tak-
ing it as his model, Peter of Poitiers (ca. 1130–1205) wrote his Compendium
Historiae in Genealogia Christi, in which he gives an outline of biblical his-
tory from Adam to Christ in the form of a genealogical tree of Christ.156
These works were the basic bibliography for the “Introduction to the Bible”
course that the baccalaurei biblici at a thirteenth-century university had to
teach. The format of this instruction has come down to us in several manu-
scripts from the turn of the thirteenth century: in the prologue the purpose
of the lectio was formulated; then Jerome’s prologue to the book in ques-
tion was read. The text was read through line by line; in a later development,
students would bring their own copies and annotate them. In addition the
glosses were always read. They were named after their initial words and
ranked according to the weight of the authority: Augustine, Bede, etc.; next
difficulties from the glosses were presented.157 Once the littera cum glosis
of a passage had been read through, the lecturer went back to the begin-
ning and started the allegorical interpretation. For that purpose, howev-
er, the text as such had to be established first and, if necessary, corrected,
since punctuation marks were not used in the manuscripts; consequently
individual words could belong to either the previous or the following sen-
tence. Furthermore there was no standard division into chapters, much less
a numbering of the verses. Instead the book was usually divided into tituli
(meaning units), which were listed at the beginning like a table of contents.
In Paris, at least, no standard division of the Bible into chapters and verses
developed until the thirteenth century. The divisions, punctuations, and
corrections were compiled, especially in the thirteenth century, in so-called
correctoria. Stephen Langton’s corrections and divisions of the biblical text
became influential. But even an obviously faulty text could provide support
for a particular spiritual interpretation.158 Around this time likewise the first
concordances appear; unlike the reference works that we have today, these
contained parallel passages compiled by Stephen Langton, among others,
based on the glosses.159
Preaching flourished in the thirteenth century, thanks in part to the ar-
160. “And each finds fault with what he does not know.” Hugh of St. Cher, Postilla in Bibliam
(Paris, 1530–1545), VI f. 86; see Smalley, Study, 269. Supplementary remarks at ibid., XIII.
54 How Did Scholastic Theology Come About?
the business of the instructor is no longer sacram paginam glossare [to gloss
the sacred text] but rather Scripturam postillare [to comment on Scripture].
For examples of the latter we should mention the scriptural commentaries
of Thomas Aquinas and Bonaventure. In Paris (unlike at Oxford) the pos-
tilla generally presents only a few questions concerning systematic theology
and mostly quaestiones that refer only to the text.161
179. See esp. Weisweiler, “Sententiae Anselmi,” Weisweiler, “Sententiae Berolinenses”; Weis-
weiler, “Arbeitsmethode.”
180. See Leinsle, Vivianus, 55–90.
181. Weisweiler, “Sententiae Anselmi,” 232.
182. See Weisweiler, “Sententiae Berolinenses,” 356.
58 How Did Scholastic Theology Come About?
at length and summarizes. His own editorial activity here is minimal; it is
evident occasionally in a change of “ergo” to “igitur” on in supplements to
individual words. Not infrequently with his summarization technique, the
long discussions of the source are cited only as theses or sententiae, whereas
the biblical foundation and all the rhetorical trimmings are left out.183 Nat-
urally, the function of a citation is changed most often in passages where
only the gist is quoted. Texts are regrouped in a new systematic framework
and acquire new functions: What was an answer in the source becomes a
question; what was a premise there becomes a thesis; cautious formulations
are adopted apodictically; the logical structure of the source text is some-
times completely unraveled; occasionally texts from several sources are so
interwoven that a hybrid text results. Sentences by contemporaries are usu-
ally introduced by a “quidam” [“a certain person”] who then has to be iden-
tified. Passages by the compiler himself connect the quotations, hold the
text together through cross references (which may themselves be quoted
again) and not insignificantly deal with the sources by thematically classify-
ing, explaining, modifying, accepting, or rejecting the sentence under con-
sideration.
Since collections of sentences in early Scholasticism are still understood
to be at the service of scriptural interpretation but at the same time are re-
garded as systematic works, we should pay special attention to the function
of citations from Scripture in this incipient “systematic theology.” By way of
example the following functions should be mentioned:
1. Foundation of thematic exegesis.
2. A stylistic device resulting from spiritual exegesis (especially in
monastic circles and treatises).184
3. Biblical introduction of a theological term, for example, “libertas a
peccato” by referring to 2 Cor 3:7 and Rom 6:20–22.
4.Biblical characterization of persons, things and times, for example,
“sancti homines” supported by Rom 6:14 and Luke 10:42.
5. A type of argument (“auctoritas”).185
Already in the school of Anselm of Laon, “authentica” and “magistralia,”
patristic authority and the master’s sentence (“definitiones magistrales” and
195. Petrus Lombardus, Sententiae in IV libris distinctae, 2 vols., numbered 4 and 5 in the series
Spicilegium Bonaventurianum (Grottaferrata 1971/81), l.2 prol. (4:329.6), l.2 d.16 c.1 (4:406.3–5).
196. Ibid., l.3 prol. (5:1, 3–15).
197. Ibid., l.4 prol. (5:231, 3–5); on the Augustinian tradition see Fuchs, Zeichen und Wissen,
33–45, 75–77.
198. Abelard’s early “theologies” (Theologia “Summi boni” and Theologia christiana) do not
come into consideration here, since they only offer treatises on God and the Trinity.
199. Abaelard, Theologia Scholarium I, 1 (CCh CM 13, 318, 1–2).
200. Ibid., I, 17 (326, 206–10).
62 How Did Scholastic Theology Come About?
“ordinationes” of God. In his Sic et Non Abelard modifies this schema so that
the sequence runs “fides—sacramentum—caritas”; consequently the treatise
on the sacraments immediately follows the one on faith, and moral theol-
ogy is not dealt with until part 3 under the heading of “caritas.” This now be-
comes the decisive structure for most collections of sentences by the school
of Abelard. The Epitome Hermanni and the Sententiae Florianenses still follow
the first schema, while the Sententiae Parisienses, Magister Roland († 1181)
and Omnebene († 1185) follow the second. The Epitome clearly places the
transition from the Incarnation to the Sacraments under the heading of the
“beneficia”: the Incarnation is the “summum beneficium” [“supreme benefit”],
as is generally taught; but the sacraments too are God’s “beneficia” and ac-
cordingly should really be part of book 1 on the faith, or at least be closely
connected with it.201 Thus “caritas” as “moral theology” seems even more
distinctly separated from “dogmatic theology.”
The structure typical for Abelard can be presented schematically as fol-
lows, according to his Sic et Non:
1. Fides
1.1 Treatise on God
1.1.1 The Trinity
1.1.2 The Attributes of God
1.2 Beneficia Dei
1.2.1 Treatise on Creation
1.2.1.1 The Angels
1.2.1.2 Man
1.2.2 The Incarnation
1.2.3 Mary and the Apostles (the Church)
2. Sacramentum
2.1 Baptism
2.2 Eucharist
2.3 Matrimony
3. Caritas
3.1 Love
3.2 Good Works
3.3 Sin
201. See Epitome theologiae christianae c. 38 (PL 178, 1738 C); contrast Sententiae Florianenses,
ed. Ostlender, 14.
How Did Scholastic Theology Come About? 63
Whereas there had already been logical problems of classification in the
schemata organized along the lines of salvation history, and historical ar-
rangements of material within the conceptual schemata, in the mid-twelfth
century several influential mixed forms developed. One such schema is pre-
sented by the Summa Sententiarum, which was compiled around 1135–40
under the influence of Hugh of St. Victor.202 The first part, as with Abelard,
is devoted to a presentation of the faith; indeed, it even uses Abelard’s “sum-
ma formula”: “Tria sunt in quibus humanae salutis summa consistit,” [“There
are three things in which the perfection of human salvation consists,”] but
now according to the schema “mysterium divinitatis—sacramentum incarna-
tionis,” in which we can see again Hugh’s influence. The editor of the Summa
Sententiarum deals with Abelard much as Peter Lombard had dealt with the
Augustinian schema. He steers the plan toward salvation history: After the
treatise on God he regards the part on “fides” as being already concluded
and then turns to creation, man, the fall, and the restoration (redemption),
down to the “remedia sacramentorum” after the model of Hugh of St. Vic-
tor.203 The sacraments themselves are treated according to the schema of
the three eras or “Laws” in salvation history.
A different sort of mixed form is found in the Sententiae divinitatis from
the Porretan school.204 These sentences begin immediately with the doc-
trine of creation and then proceed to the creation of man, “praetermisso an-
gelorum tractatu” [“omitting the treatise on the angels”]. Man is considered
(1) in his creation according to the image and likeness of God, (2) in the
state of freedom from sin, (3) in his fall, and (4) in his restoration. Here
again there is tangible evidence of the influence of Laon and St. Victor.205
In part 4 the Incarnation and the treatise on the sacraments (means of the
“reparatio”) are presented. Only then does the Tractatus de divinitate et Trin-
itate follow. The transition indicates the overall connection: “Diximus, quali-
ter ipse homo factus est, vidimus etiam quomodo per peccatum cecidit a cogni-
tione divinitatis, et qualiter reparatus. Modo videamus de ipsa divinitate et
Trinitate.” [“We have said how man himself was made, and we also saw how
he fell through sin from the knowledge of Divinity, and how he was restored.
202. PL 176, 41–154; as to the dating, see Leinsle, Vivianus, 37–39; see also A. Grillmeier, “Ful-
gentius von Ruspe.”
203. Summa Sententiarum tr. 2 c.1 (PL 176, 79 C); tr.3 c.2 (91 A); tr.4 c.1 (117 A).
204. Ed. B. Geyer, Die “Sententiae divinitatis”: Ein Sentenzenbuch der Gilbertischen Schule (BG-
PhMA 7, 2–3) (Münster, 1909).
205. Sent. div., tr.1 (ed. Geyer 8*); tr.2 (ibid., 18).
64 How Did Scholastic Theology Come About?
Now let us see about Divinity itself and the Trinity.”]206 This would be, then,
a schema that ascends by way of salvation history (creation, fall, redemp-
tion) to the knowledge of God (cognitio divinitatis) as the goal of man and of
theology. Right knowledge of God, however, is possibly only after the res-
toration of fallen man. Hence the position of the treatise on God and the
Trinity at the conclusion of the Sententiae divinitatis.
The compiler of the Ysagoge in theologiam, from the broader school of
Abelard, bases his work on a different schema of ascent.207 He divides his
collection into treatises on “natura humana,” “natura angelica” and “natura
divina.” Human nature is presented in books 1 and 2 in terms of creation,
body, and soul (including the faculties and virtues). The treatise on virtues
is followed by the treatise on merit, grace and freedom, Paradise, and the
prelapsarian state. The doctrine of the fall is likewise developed strictly in
conceptual terms in the questions, “quid sit malum, quid peccatum, quid vi-
cium.” [“What is evil? What is sin? What is vice?”] The treatise on redemp-
tion adheres to the schema “bona—mala—remedia malorum” [“goods—
evils—remedies of evils”], whereby the means of salvation are subdivided
again according to the eras in salvation history.208 The means of salvation
in the era of grace consist partly of the Incarnation and sufferings of Christ,
partly of the acraments. The author then attempts to develop his angelology
(book 3) exactly in parallel to the first two books. Therefore with regard to
the angels as well he follows the schema of creation, fall, and restoration
(in this case: confirmatio bonorum, confirmation of the good angels [in their
allegiance]). The discussions, however, are substantially shorter.209 The
treatise on God has a strongly epistemological accent: the ways of knowing
God are presented, then the three divine attributes (power, wisdom, will),
and finally the testimonies of the prophets and philosophers are considered.
The Sentences of Magister Roland (Bandinelli), composed around 1150,
owe more to Abelard.210 He adopts the schema “fides—sacramentum—cari-
tas,” only to house within it much material from salvation history. The sub-
206. Sent. div. tr.4 (ibid., 155*); Cloes merely traces the schema of the Sent. div. back to a sim-
ple thematic arrangement.
207. Écrits théologiques de l’école d’Abélard: Textes inédits, ed. A. Langraf (SSL 14) (Louvain,
1934), 63–285.
208. Ibid., 130.
209. Ibid., 220: “Brevem igitur de homine disputacionem brevior de arcana spirituum natura et
summo Deo sequatur distinctio.” [“Let this brief argumentation about man, therefore, be followed
by a briefer distinction between the secret nature of the spirits and the Supreme God.”]
210. Die Sentenzen Rolands nachmals Papstes Alexander III., ed. A. Gietl (Freiburg, 1891).
How Did Scholastic Theology Come About? 65
division of the treatise on fides into the doctrine about God and his “benefi-
cia,” however, is replaced by the division into the doctrine on Divinity and
an exposition of His works. The latter, however, include the angels, the cre-
ation of the world and of man, his fall, and the restoration, which is accom-
plished during the three eras of salvation history. Thus Roland clearly shows
that he, like the Summa Sententiarum, is dependent on Hugh of St. Victor.
In Roland’s presentation, however, the third era of salvation history (tempus
gratiae) overlaps with Abelard’s second topic: “sacramentum.” Thus he now
wishes to treat that part of the faith (topic 1, fides) that pertains to the libera-
tion and redemption of man, “cuius quidem in sacramentis consistit redemp-
tio” [“whose redemption, indeed, is established in the sacraments”].211 The
difficulties of striking an equilibrium between the salvation-history schema
and a conceptual organization are clear here, as they often are in the treat-
ment of the sacraments, which on the one hand are means of redemption
and on the other hand objects of faith.
222. Concerning Richard of St. Victor’s “excerptiones” see, for example, Ott, Briefliteratur, 651–57.
223. See Leinsle, Vivianus, 55–103.
68 How Did Scholastic Theology Come About?
Such formulaic modesty is a stylistic device and should be evaluated ac-
cordingly. Soon we find entire collections of letters by individual or various
authors in which the attribution is often dubious and therefore should be
tested in each case. Last but not least, such collections of letters can serve in
turn, stylistically and thematically, as an influential source of further episto-
lary literature.
224. Petrus Cantor, Verbum abbreviatum c.1 (PL 205, 25); see Smalley, Study, 208.
225. See Davy, Sermons univeritaires; Bataillon, “Crises”; Zier, “Sermons”; Bériou, “Sermons
latins.”
226. A basic reference is Charland, Artes Praedicandi.
227. See Roth, Predigttheorie.
228. See Leclercq, Wissenschaft, 189–201.
229. Guibert von Nogent, Quo ordine sermo fieri debeat (PL 156, 26 C).
How Did Scholastic Theology Come About? 69
vestigation of Scripture, consulting a more learned scholar, and the exposi-
tion of Scripture].230 It should have the following structure: (1) Auctoritas
(scriptural text), (2) Captatio benevolentiae [plea for the listeners’ benevo-
lence], (3) Interpretation of the text while citing further Scripture passages
and authorities in support of one’s arguments and thus “producing consid-
erable excitement in the public and then calming it,” (4) Exemplification.231
Whereas this schema is still essentially bound up with the rhetoric of
antiquity, as it was handed down within the framework of the artes, the
structure of the learned sermon changes significantly in the thirteenth cen-
tury. Then, too, there was a new audience for the Latin sermon, which was
zealously cultivated in the university cities especially by the mendicant or-
ders that had just taken up residence there. The Artes Praedicandi list de-
tailed rules for the learned sermo.232 The university sermo, unlike the freer
popular sermon, has the following structure:
e thema of the sermon is announced. This is a sentence (dictum aliquod
1. Th
authenticum) from sacred Scripture (e.g., taken from the readings for the
day) that serves as the thematic foundation for the sermon.233 Besides
this there is also the custom, especially in the popular sermon, of explain-
ing the whole Gospel (without stating a theme) in the form of a homily
or a postilla.234
2. N ext comes the prothema, another Scripture passage, the subject of an in-
troductory discourse, which may be long or short and which is supposed
to prepare the listeners to hear aright; the prothema is concluded with a
prayer. Since the prothema leads the listener to the sermon, it should be
regarded as something of a preached “popular homily,” as J. B. Schneyer
has concluded from his exemplary study of such prothemata.235
nce the listener is well disposed, the introitus follows, the introduction
3. O
of the theme, which is mentioned again (also for the sake of latecom-
ers). The inventio of the theme usually applies sacred Scripture and the
Church Fathers, but on the other hand the Aristotelian rules of “ars
inveniendi,” of thematic arrangements, quotations from philosophers or
230. Alanus ab Insulis, Summa de Arte Praedicatoria (PL 210, 111 B).
231. Roth, Predigttheorie, 40.
232. Ibid., 32–86; Charland, Artes Praedicandi, 109–226, including a detailed description of the
structure of a sermon.
233. E.g., Thomas Waleys, De modo componendi sermones, c.2, in ed. Charland, Artes Praedi-
candi, 341.
234. See Charland, Artes Praedicandi, 112–13.
235. Schneyer, Unterweisung.
70 How Did Scholastic Theology Come About?
common proverbs, which are now supposed to lead the listener to the
theme itself. But the theme can be introduced through a logical argu-
ment also, whereby the truth thereof and the necessity of discussing it
can be demonstrated expressly.
4. The theme must then be subdivided in the divisio. Usually the words
of the theme that are relevant to the further division of the sermon are
emphasized. Here we should distinguish between the division of the text
(divisio) that is usually done in the lectio also, and the distinctio, the subdi-
vision of a theme according to its various aspects (e.g., love: love of God
and love of neighbor). A multiplicity of meanings in one or more of the
senses of Scripture can also be decisive for the division. The preacher has
a wealth of material available, some of it already arranged alphabetically,
in the Distinctiones and Allegoriae.236 The art of structuring a Scholastic
sermo is evident precisely in the correct division of the theme.
5. The division of the theme results in the division of the sermon in the
partium declaratio, called clavis for short. This offers the key to under-
standing the sermo and proves the sufficiency of the division with regard
to the various points. Naturally, for this proof one again uses concurring
authorities, which may provide points for further subdivisiones. Usually a
repeated threefold pattern develops, which is elaborated in divisiones and
subdivisiones and gives the sermon the appearance of a tree that branches
out extensively.237
6. Now, at last, the preacher can start the exposition of his theme, the dila-
tatio. Not all the parts of the division are always elaborated with the same
thoroughness. In typical university sermons we find here, too, auctori-
tas, ratio, and exempla combined in each section. The use of authorities
follows fixed rules of allegatio or citation [Verbindung]. They serve, for
example, to elucidate an analogy, to mediate a difference, to define, inter-
pret, describe, specify, modify, corroborate, subdivide, or supplement.238
The ratio is required when explaining terms, but also when independent-
ly compiling and evaluating authorities, when including an etymology
or the various hermeneutical possibilities in the fourfold interpretation
of Scripture, when proving the truth of the articles of faith symbolically
contained in the Scripture passage and stating the conditions and quali-
ties of such an interpretation. Finally, the exemplum is chiefly supposed
1. For the history of dogma and theology, see esp. HDG and HDThG; for a detailed study see
Landgraf, Dogmengeschichte der Frühscholastik; for the theology of the human act and ethics, see
Lottin, Psychologie; for an overview see also Evans, ed., Medieval Theologians and Leppin, Theologie.
2. Concerning the problem of an historical “self-concept,” see, for example, Borgolte, “Selbst-
verständnis.”
74
The Self-Concept of Early Scholastic Theologies 75
individual human being is determined before birth. Hence redemption
in Christ did not take place for all men. Baptism and membership in the
Church are prerequisites for election, but not all the baptized are chosen.
Moreover man’s will is not free but wicked; grace alone working in the elect
ensures that they do not give in or agree to evil and concupiscence. The
good that man does, however, is not his work, but the work of God’s grace.3
Gottschalk’s teaching, inspired by Augustine’s doctrine of predestination
and based on God’s immutability, is logically consistent and well thought
out. Yet it has dangerous consequences: man cannot change his eternal des-
tiny by his own action. In the opinion of some contemporaries, this aided
and abetted fatalism or immorality.
Gottschalk’s scientific method still followed what his Abbot Hrabanus
Maurus had taught in the Carolingian schools. This essentially consisted
of a catena technique of noncontradictory sentences from the Church Fa-
thers, underpinning a definite doctrine.4 With the proof from authority and
consistent definition, however, the apparatus of theology had already been
exhausted. Therefore the standard of rationality was essentially considered
to be the dialectica of the artes liberales and the proper use of the proof from
authority. In Gottschalk’s judgment, his teaching on predestination satisfied
this criterion, whereas the Church’s did not.
The official Church reaction to Gottschalk’s teaching in the condemna-
tions by the Synods of Mainz (848) and Quierzy (849) is less important
to us here than the theological grappling with “the Gottschalk case.”5 In
the judgments requested by Bishop Hinkmar of Rheims († 882) and King
Charles the Bald (823–877), Prudentius of Troyes († 861), Lupus of Ferri-
ères († 862), and Ratramnus of Corbie († after 868) unanimously indicate
that Gottschalk’s teaching on predestination agrees with that of Augustine
and consequently should be a good Catholic position. In doing so the judg-
es follow precisely the conventional scientific method that Gottschalk him-
self employs: logical consistency and the proof from authority ensure the
truth of a theological teaching. In this case, therefore, methodically prov-
en truth is opposed to an official ecclesiastical condemnation of the same
teaching that is based mainly on practical religious considerations.
A further judgment that Hinkmar of Rheims ordered Duns Scotus Eri-
These ideas, which essentially rely on the early Augustine, clearly set
a task for theology: it must explain scientifically the rules of true religion.
Therefore there can be no contradiction between true religion and true phi-
losophy/science. Religion, too, is defined as a bit of reasonable praxis: in it
knowledge about God is pursued in a reasonable manner; but only in theol-
ogy are the rules of this praxis examined with respect to their truth. “Regula”
16. Prudentius, De praedestinatione contra Joannem Scotum (PL 115.1009–1336), Florus, Adver-
sus Joannis Scotti erroneas definitiones liber (PL 119.101–250).
17. The “normative” view is taken especially by Grabmann, Methode, 258–340.
18. See Holopainen, Dialectic, 44–118; Gibson, “Berengar of Tours,” 61–68; Cantin, “La ‘raison’”;
Schrimpf, “Bausteine,” 9–16.
19. Berengar, Purgatoria epistola contra Almannum, in Lanfranc et Bérenger: La controverse eu-
charistique du XIe siècle, J. de Montclos (Leuven, 1971), 531–38; Berengar, De sacra coena adversus
Lanfrancum, ed. W. H. Beekenkamp (Den Haag, 1941).
20. Berengar, Sacr. coen. 35.47–48, 52.
21. Ibid., 13; see also Hödl, “Confessio Berengarii.”
The Self-Concept of Early Scholastic Theologies 79
Moreover according to Berengar it is not up to synods but rather to the
theologian, the “eruditus fidelis” to present clearly (i.e., by means of logic),
to the extent possible for our knowledge in this [earthly] condition, what a
“regula fidei” [“rule of faith”] implies and what it excludes. Logical compre-
hension is by no means a profanation of the sacrament.22 In the debate with
his opponents Berengar makes it clear that theology cannot and must not
do without the laws of logic: “As thinking beings we cannot renounce the
laws of thought. One does not honor God by disowning the human mind,
the rules of which are formulated in logic and grammar. Man as a thinking
being is the image of God. He must not relinquish this dignity. Respect for
the laws of thought has its own religious significance.”23
Among the many writings in the controversy over Berengar, the con-
trary interpretation by Lanfranc of Bec deserves special attention with re-
gard to its concept of theology and its method.24 Lanfranc, the most impor-
tant logician of his day, advocates in theology the unequivocal primacy of
auctoritas over ratio; for faith, too, precedes rational comprehension. Faith is
meritorious, while reason is not. Even Paul rejected logical endeavors where
the faith is concerned (1 Timothy 6:20). Lanfranc himself tries to conceal
as much as possible the involvement of logic in theology by presenting the
consensus of authorities and grouping them according to their importance.
The consensus and unanimity of the teaching are assumed, however, and
must be preserved. The debate about the Eucharist thereby becomes at the
same time a debate about the correct method for theology. Thus in 1059
there are discussions in Rome not only about the Eucharist, but also “de
eminentia rationis” [“on the excellence of reason”] and “de immunitate auc-
toritatis” [“on the immunity, i.e., incontrovertible character of authority”].25
Anselm of Canterbury’s fundamental answer concerning the task and
method of theology should be viewed against the background of the Beren-
gar controversy. His formula, “fides quaerens intellectum” [“faith seeking un-
derstanding”] caused him to become the “Father of Scholasticism.”26 The
arguments that he developed in his influential works, Monologion, Proslo-
gion, and Cur Deus homo are methodically presented in his Epistola de in-
27. Anselmi Cantuariensis Opera Omnia, ed. F. S. Schmitt, vol. 2 (Rome, 1940; reprinted Stutt-
gart, 1968), 3–35; see also Schrimpf, “Bausteine,” 16–19; Kienzler, Glauben, 25–157; Holopainen,
Dialectic, 119–55; Gemeinhardt, “Theologische Methode.”
28. Anselm, Ep. de inc. verb. (ed. Schmitt II, 5–8).
29. Anselm, Monol. prooem (ed. Schmitt I, 8.18–20); Anselm, Prosl. prooem (ed. Schmitt I,
93.2–4); in this passage, however, he writes “sola cogitatione”; Kienzler, Glauben, 28–33, argues that
the expression is always “sola ratione.”
The Self-Concept of Early Scholastic Theologies 81
omnium esse quae sunt in homine.” [“Reason . . . must be the ruler and judge
of everything that there is in man.”]30 This ratio, however, is no longer just
logic that is to be used purely as an instrument; in Anselm’s writings it is ex-
panded by an analysis, inspired mainly by Augustine and Boethius, of philo-
sophical and in particular metaphysical concepts: substance, person, liber-
tas, veritas, rectitudo [righteousness]. It is not logical consistency alone that
now decides as to the correctness of one’s understanding of the faith; one
now strives for such an understanding with metaphysical methods. Only
such an understanding offers the “rationes necessariae” [“necessary reasons”]
that should enable theology to make the mystery of the Trinity intelligible
in a binding way even to human understanding. This insight is never so
complete as to eliminate faith; Anselm describes it instead as “aliquatenus”
[“to a certain degree”]. Yet reason can arrive in just this way at insights that
can be recognized as true without the foundation of the faith and therefore
are to be accepted by the unbeliever as well, for example, it can arrive at the
knowledge of God’s existence, as the famous argument from the Proslogion
is supposed to show. On the other hand, the inability to grasp something
with the understanding or to make it intelligible is no reason for faith to
reject it also. In this case ratio is by no means the judge of fides. Instead such
an arrangement is morally ruled out as “praesumptio.”31
If reason tried to debate in theology whether something in the Church’s
doctrine of the faith was not true (quomodo non sit), that demand of reason
would be unjustified; the best remedy against such presumption is to refer
to the humility with which one must first accept what the Church believes
and professes. Only then can a Christian ask (quaerere, not disputare), “quo-
modo sit” [“how it is”]. Therefore theology can only offer insight into the
How of what is believed, but can neither call into question nor substanti-
ate the faith as a whole. Within the framework of his monastic, Augustinian
understanding of theology, Anselm also points out that the prerequisite for
a correct understanding of the faith is “soliditas fidei” [“firmness of faith”],
acquired through “sapientiae et morum gravitas” [“wisdom and serious com-
portment”].32 Theology without the practice of the faith is therefore not
possible. Theology is necessary, however, because reference to the author-
ity of the Church Fathers alone cannot suffice. With that, Anselm clearly
distances himself from all those who think that the recitation of patristic
30. Anselm, Ep. de inc. verb. 1 (II, 10.1–2). 31. Ibid., 1 (II, 4.5; 6.6).
32. Ibid., 1 (II, 6.5–7.4).
82 The Self-Concept of Early Scholastic Theologies
sentences is already theology. In particular Anselm gives five reasons for the
need to probe the faith personally and rationally, but at the same time he
marks out the insuperable limits of this endeavor:
1. Life is short, and the Fathers could not say everything about the truths of
the faith.
e “veritatis ratio” can never be fully exhausted by the human mind.
2. Th
3. C hrist bestows his gifts of grace on his Church until the end of time, and
therefore he also grants progress in knowing these things.
4. Scripture itself invites us to investigate the faith, while clearly giving pre-
cedence to faith: “Nisi credideritis, non intelligetis” (Isaiah 7:9, Vulgate).
[“Unless you believe, you shall not understand.”]
5. U nderstanding the faith is a path leading from faith to the beatific vision
of God as the goal of our life.33
Anyone who approaches sacred Scripture with this attitude sees in it the
perfection and surpassing of all worldly knowledge. The interpretation of
sacred Scripture is gained by way of lectio and meditatio, the independent
and also spiritual assimilation of the scriptural passage according to what
Hugh regards as its threefold sense: historical, allegorical, and tropological.
History and allegory promote man’s knowledge; tropology his “mores” or
morals; both sides must come to an agreement again in “sapientia” [“wis-
dom”].59 For Hugh, too, theology consists essentially in the right manner
and order of reading sacred Scripture, and therefore everything depends on
64. Abaelard, Hist. cal., ed. J. Monfrin (Paris, 1967), 82, 690–83, 701.
65. Abaelard, Dialogus inter Philosophum, Judaeum et Christianum, ed. R. Thomas (Stuttgart–
Bad Cannstatt, 1970), 97.1478–85.
66. Abaelard, Theologia Scholarium, praef. 1 (CCh CM 13.313.1–3).
67. Ibid., II, 18 (414.243–44): “saltem aliquid verisimile atque humanae rationi vicinum, nec sacrae
fidei contrarium proponere.”
68. Ibid., II, 56 (435.885–436.894).
92 The Self-Concept of Early Scholastic Theologies
Theologiam). The works of commentary, first and foremost the Commen-
tary on the Letter to the Romans, work their way through the scriptum to
the sententia, whereas the systematic works start with the logical, rational
explication of the sententia itself.69
This becomes very clear in Abelard’s first systematic presentation of
theology, which however includes only the doctrine on the Trinity: in the
Theologia Summi Boni (so named after its initial words; it is also called the
Tractatus de unitate et trinitate divina [Treatise on the divine unity and trin-
ity]), written in 1120.70 Here Abelard makes the widest use thus far of the
philosophy that consists mainly of Boethius and the logica vetus. He relates
the philosophical concept of the highest good (summum bonum) to the
Christian, Trinitarian God. In Abelard’s view this is justified by Christ him-
self, the “Lord of the faith,” who gave three different names to this same god
of philosophy. Accordingly it is clear also that to a great extent the argumen-
tation proceeds philosophically and that philosophical studies, especially
of dialectic, are expressly demanded of the reader.71 Whereas in exegetical
and later systematic works the quotation of Scripture passages has the final
probative force, that is not the case in this context; here further justifica-
tion by ratio is required. Even here, however, Abelard remains faithful to the
linguistic component of theology: the Theologia Summi Boni is intended as
a rational investigation of what Christ accomplished in giving the god of
philosophy the names Father, Son, and Spirit. The fact that this theology
nevertheless does not lack a foundation in practical living (Abelard wrote
the treatise as a monk) explains the repeated reference to the praise of God,
which corresponds to the monastic tradition. In the teaching about the
Holy Spirit, Plato’s doctrine of the world soul (which is familiar from Mac-
robius and Boethius) is discussed extensively. The decisive feature in either
case, however, is the explanation in terms of the philosophical categories of
substance and accidents, person, etc.
Abelard clearly distinguishes his position, however, from that of the
pseudo-dialecticians as well; they do not use their knowledge to interpret
Scripture correctly but rather place it at the service of attacks against the
faith and thus of the Antichrist.72 That is no reason, however, to condemn
69. Editions: CCh CM 11–13; Expositio in Epistolam ad Romanos: Römerbriefkommentar, trans.
and intro. by Rolf Peppermüller (Fontes Christiani 26/1–3) (Freiburg, 2000).
70. CCh CM 13.1–201: Abaelard, Theologia Summi Boni, trans. and ed. by U. Niggli (PhB 395)
(Hamburg, 1989), with an extensive introduction; see also Nielsen, “Peter Abelard,” 107–14.
71. Abaelard, Theol. Summi Boni III, 5.100 (CCh CM 13.201.1360–63).
72. Ibid., II, 1–4 (114.1–115.35).
The Self-Concept of Early Scholastic Theologies 93
dialectic and its application in theology; only its misuse leads to sophistry.
What is bad is not the science but its misuse. Abelard decisively opposes
“those untrammeled and wild combatants” who “through the one horn
of their pride fight even against the Creator” and have “raised their voice
against heaven.”73 Yet he himself makes very extensive use of dialectic and
philosophy, on the basis of the faith, of course; at the beginning he pres-
ents briefly the content of the faith as “totius disputationis thema et summa
fidei” [“the subject of all disputation and summary of the faith”], so as then
to discuss the individual questions in a strictly rational way and to answer
objections.74 To a great extent the procedure here too is linguistic criticism
and metaphysical analysis, as the questions and distinctions of the second
book make clear: Why the divine substance is simple and formless; the dis-
tinction of Divine Persons, six meanings of “idem” and “diversum” [“same”
and “different”]; meanings of “person,” etc. In this way Abelard develops the
fundamental question of theology: whether and how it is possible to apply
human expressions to God. Nor does it do any good for the opponent in
the disputation to say that he does not want to go into words and meanings
but rather to keep to the truth of the meaning. He must nevertheless make
clear what “genitus” [“begotten”] means, so as then to see that “genitus” and
“ingenitus” [“unbegotten”] are designations of Persons in the Trinity. For
Abelard, “verba catholica” [“Catholic words”] must be added to “sana intel-
ligentia” [“sound understanding”].75 The basis for this is chapter 1 of Peri
hermeneias on the correspondence of word, concept, and thing.
This apparatus of semantic and logical analysis is used aptly so as to
answer the objections of opponents; there are many of them, however, es-
pecially in Trinitarian matters. For Abelard too, nevertheless, theological
questions are not verbal battles but rather objective inquiries [Sachfragen].
One must speak correctly about the object, however, with words that are
employed “ad placitum hominum” [“for human purposes”]. There can be
agreement about objective inquiries, therefore, only through agreement
about the generally accepted meanings of the terms being used.76 In this
way one can reply for example to objections to the concept of substance
with reference to the Trinity, to the status of the Divine Persons or to the
81. See esp. Van Elswijk, Gilbert Porreta; Nielsen, Theology; on the authenticity of his works,
40–46; for his concept of theology: Gilbert Porreta, Commentarius in Boethii Opuscula sacra, ed.
N. M. Häring (ST 13) (Toronto, 1966). On his literary output and school: Landgraf, Einführung,
79–92.
82. Gilbert, Comm. Boeth., 85.1–6, 86.10.
83. Gilbert, Comm. in Ep. Pauli (British Museum, London Cod.) add. 11.853–54.151r (cited by
Nielsen, Theology, 116): “doceo non, ut cognoscentes credant, sed ut credentes cognoscant de praedictis
veritatem.” [“I teach not so that those who know might believe, but rather so that believers might
know the truth of what is proclaimed.”] See ibid., f.47v (Nielsen, Theology, 119).
84. Ibid., f.57r (Nielsen, Theology, 124). 85. Ibid., f.170r.85r (Nielsen, Theology, 125).
86. Ibid., f. 55r.63v (Nielsen, Theology, 126).
96 The Self-Concept of Early Scholastic Theologies
other hand produces the gift of theological knowledge, no conflict can arise
here in the first place between faith and dialectic, as one finds in Berengar
and Abelard. Theology has a “veritas secundum pietatem” [“truth in keeping
with piety/devotion”], unlike the truth of grammar and dialectic. It is de-
posited in sacred Scripture and is useful for eternal salvation, whereas the
secular sciences are useful only for temporal pleasures.87 The task of theolo-
gy, therefore, consists of the explicit knowledge of the faith so as to help in-
struct simple believers. They must also and particularly be enlightened as to
the invalidity of the authority of heretics. Especially useful for this purpose
is the logical analysis of the heretics’ arguments, which often draw false con-
clusions from true premises. If the heretics say something right about God,
it is only by chance.88 Some pagan philosophers, in contrast, have attained
a knowledge of God “per naturalem rationem” [“by natural reason”], but still
not without God’s help. They did not arrive at a knowledge of the Trinity
and the Incarnation, though.89 A knowledge that is used “praeter rationem,”
however, in other words, not for the praise of God, which is the goal of the-
ology, is useless.90
Philosophical knowledge of the world, moreover, cannot arrive at the
ultimate necessity of its reasons and regulae, but can only support them by
habit. Philosophical sentences have only a “consuetudini accommodata neces-
sitas” [“necessity that befits custom”]. Only theology can make clear (meta-
physically) the real causal connection, even where those philosophers who
attribute absolute truth to their own sentences discover contradictions, for
example, in the virgin birth.91 An absolute truth of philosophical knowl-
edge separated from theology is thus denied in principle. Knowledge of na-
ture relies on the path from custom and induction and in its very methods
cannot come into conflict with theology.92 Theologically correct knowl-
edge of nature, in contrast, must proceed from faith and from that point of
departure arrive at theology, where, unlike philosophy, “veri nominis atque
absoluta necessitas” [“a necessity truly so called and absolute”] rules: “In his
enim non cognoscentes credimus, sed credentes cognoscimus.” [“For we do not
believe in these things by knowing them, but rather know by believing.”]93
Accordingly, however, the correct knowledge of nature, like theology as a
100. Ibid., 57; Gilbert, Comm. in Ep. Pauli f.164v (Nielsen, Theology, 135, n. 77).
101. Gilbert, Comm. Boeth. 342.
102. See Häring, Zwettler Summe, 7; Sturlese, Philosophie, 143–56.
103. Critical edition: Petrus Lombardus, Sententiae in IV libris distinctae (Spicilegium Bonaven-
turianum 4/5) (Grottaferrata 1971/81). On the work and its influence see esp. I, 1 Prolegomena.
Concerning Peter Lombard’s theology as a whole: Colish, Peter Lombard.
104. See Lottin, “Premier commentaire,” 64–71; Landgraf, “Drei Zweige”; Landgraf, “Sentenz-
englossen”; for an overview, see Landgraf, Einführung, 93–109.
The Self-Concept of Early Scholastic Theologies 99
excerpts and abridgments are produced for use in school.105 Thanks to the
organization of the universities, a two-year lecture on Lombard, who is
called the Magister for short, became obligatory for every baccalaureus sen-
tentiarius if he wanted to complete a master’s degree. From then on com-
mentaries on the Sentences were the most important sources of systematic
theology, and this remained the case well into the sixteenth century. Then
Alexander of Hales († 1245), even while functioning as Magister actu regens
(1223–1227) still based his ordinary lectures not on a biblical text, as was the
custom, but on the Sentences of Peter Lombard: a procedure that would set
an academic precedent.106 Yet initially the prospects of this theology were
by no means that splendid; for like Gilbert and Abelard, Peter Lombard too
had to endure the accusation of heresy.107 However, the later bishop of Paris
was expressly named by the Fourth Lateran Council (1215) as the source
of orthodox teaching.108 Besides the Sentences the most important extant
works by Lombard are remarkable glosses on the Psalms and the Letters of
St. Paul.
If we look at the work of the “Magister Sententiarum,” his great influence
on future generations may at first seem surprising. It is by no means a very
original or stylistically impressive work. It is very much in keeping with the
summas of sentences compiled by followers of the school of Abelard and
St. Victor. In the prologue the Lombard clearly states that he intended his
work, written 1155–1158, to continue in the line of the early Scholastic collec-
tions of sentences. It is composed “ex testimoniis veritatis in aeternum fundatis”
[“of testimonies of truth that are well-founded for all eternity”] and contains
“majorum exempla doctrinamque” [“the examples and teachings of our ances-
tors”], in other words, it is not so much his own teaching as that of the Fa-
thers that the reader finds in this supposedly little work. This should make
it unnecessary to consult the numerous works of the Fathers individually:
abbreviation and substitution as an encyclopedic principle for theology are
clearly evident here.109 But that also states precisely the purpose of this fu-
ture textbook: to become the sole foundation for theology and to replace all
other books (eventually even the Bible in coursework). The material, how-
8 Axiomatic theology
The attempts to establish theology as a science in the strict sense lead
to the adoption of general scientific procedures in theology. This develop-
ment is advanced the farthest in the thoroughgoing axiomatic approach to
theology in the works of Alan of Lille [Alanus ab Insulis] (ca. 1120–1202)
and Nicholas of Amiens. The two scholars take different models of the axi-
omatic method, however: Alan follows Boethius, De hebdomadibus, while
Nicholas bases his work on Euclid.120
118. Concerning this medieval reading of 1 Peter 3:15 as a program for theology, see de
Ghellinck, Mouvement, 279–84.
119. Ibid., 267–77.
120. See Evans, “Axiomatic Method,” 36–52; Dreyer, More mathematicorum, 142–70.
The Self-Concept of Early Scholastic Theologies 103
The Regulae de sacra theologia by Alan of Lille highlight from the very
start the connection with the secular sciences: All sciences have at their own
foundation certain regulae [rules], which also indicate the limits of the sci-
ence in question; the regulae go by different names: in logic they are maximae
(namely, sententiae), in rhetoric—loci communes, in ethics—general prin-
ciples, in physics—aphorisms, in arithmetic—porismata, etc. Like all other
sciences, theology too as the “supercaelestis scientia” has its foundational rules
or axioms.121 These are per se of higher rank than those of all the other sci-
ences, but they are also more difficult to discover. With Gilbert Porreta, Alan
attributes absolute and irrefutable necessity (necessitas absoluta et irrefraga-
bilis) to the theological axioms in contrast to the foundations of the natural
sciences, which are based only upon the customary course of nature.122 It is
not easy, however, to find theological axioms or to formulate them correct-
ly. Someone who follows only the natural sciences will necessarily perceive
them as riddles (aenigmata) or paradoxes, which seem to be illogical and are
difficult to grasp. In fact Alan’s regulae include quite paradoxical formulas,
for example, “Only the monad [monas] is Alpha and Omega without Alpha
and Omega” (rule 5), “God is the intelligible sphere whose midpoint is ev-
erywhere and whose circumference is nowhere” (rule 7). They are also de-
scribed as emblemata (e.g., the image of the sphere) or entymemata, whereas
Boethius calls them hebdomades (according to Alan equal in dignitas to the
axioma). Because of their difficulty, however, they are not to be expected of
beginners, but rather demand an audience that is already experienced in the-
ology.123 The axiomatic presentation of theology, therefore, is not a didactic
method of handing it on, but rather the scientific proof of logical consistency
and necessity, and incidentally also the proof of the scientific character of
theology.
The axioms of theology, however, are for Alan unambiguously meta-
physical propositions, the most general and fundamental of which reads:
“Monas est, qua quaelibet res est una,” [“A monad is that by which any thing
is one,”] whereby the “supercaelestis unitas” by definition means God and
at the same time the strongly Neoplatonic provenance of this (Boethian)
metaphysics is made clear. It is required that these first propositions be un-
provable and self-evident, so that everyone agrees with them immediately
121. Alanus ab Insulis, Regulae de sacra theologia, prol. (PL 210.621 AB); see also Chenu, “Un
essai”; see also Glorieux, “Somme”; Dreyer, More mathematicorum, 142–62.
122. Alanus ab Insulis, Regulae, prol. (621 C–622 A).
123. Ibid. (623 B).
104 The Self-Concept of Early Scholastic Theologies
upon hearing them. Yet the decisive thing is not people’s agreement, since
many theological axioms are widely known (e.g., that there must be one
single principle for all things), while other strictly metaphysical proposi-
tions (e.g., that for everything that is utterly simple, being and essence are
identical) are known only to a few. The foundational axioms of the Regulae,
however, are of the latter sort. The Trinity is brought in at the third rule,
“The Monad begets a Monad and turns the ardor (of love) back upon itself ”
(rule 3).124 Even the abovecited rules show that in Alan’s system not all the
rules are unprovable axioms of the same order; instead the later ones are
supposed to be derived from the earlier ones, which he does accomplish in
the first steps. On the other hand, the constant logical deduction becomes
difficult in the case of facts from salvation history such as the Incarnation. It
is “substantiated” in rule 99 based on the threefold status of man, his thesis
(original natural and rational state), from which he can “stand out” (exsta-
sis) in two directions: upward to God in his apotheosis and downward to the
beasts in his hypothesis. Now since the latter occurs, God leaves his status
of apotheosis and empties himself to the point of hypothesis.125 Finally, rela-
tively simple dogmatic statements, for example, concerning Christ’s agony
(rule 105) are quoted and explained as axioms too.126 Precisely in this sec-
tion and in his teaching on the sacraments, where his approach is more like
that of a conventional summa, Alan’s attempt shows how difficult it is to
harmonize a metaphysical system of axioms and a biblical “fact” from salva-
tion history or the historical institutions of the Church in such a way as to
construct a thoroughly demonstrative science from those elements.
That is exactly what Nicholas of Amiens claims to do in the title of his
work Ars fidei Catholicae, which was written between 1187 and 1197: give a
technically correct presentation of the Catholic faith.127 Here technically
correct means according to Euclid’s rules for the axiomatic method, which
were originally laid down for geometry. Already in the twelfth century, then,
we are dealing with a Theologia more geometrico demonstrata, at least accord-
132. Sententiae Petri Pictaviensis, ed. Philip S. Moore and Marthe Doulong, vol. 1 (Publications
in Medieval Studies 7) (Notre Dame, Ind., 1961); vol. 2 (Publications in Medieval Studies 11) (Notre
Dame, Ind., 1950). See Moore, Works. This Petrus Pictaviensis should be distinguished from the
Porretan who taught in Vienna, Magister Petrus, who is sometimes identified as the author of the
“Zwettler Summa,” and from a canon regular of St. Victor by the same name; see also Häring, Zwet-
tler Summe, 3; Landgraf, Einführung, 105–9. Sturlese, Philosophie, 145–56.
133. See Petrus Pictaviensis, Sent. prol. (I, 1.15–2.35).
134. Ibid., Introduction XII*.
108 The Self-Concept of Early Scholastic Theologies
“Distingue, distinguenda est h[a]ec, non est danda sine distinctione,” etc., we
read again and again, especially where conflicting authorities must be har-
monized. The first thing that a theologian has to learn, therefore, before
tackling sacred Scripture, is a precise theological terminology, a standard
theological language one might say, for without it one cannot understand
anything at all about theological questions, in Peter’s opinion. “Nam ignora-
ta virtute nominum et verborum, necesse est nihil eorum intelligi, quae hoc inqui-
rantur.” [“For if one has overlooked the force of the nouns and verbs, then
one will inevitably understand nothing of what is being sought thereby.”]135
Thus immediately in the second chapter of book 1 he distinguishes nine
word types or ways of using terms with reference to God:136
1. Designations of essence: essentia, divinitas [essence, divinity];
esignations of essence but sometimes also of Persons: potentia, sapien-
2. D
tia, bonitas [power, wisdom, goodness];
3. Expressions of relation without reference: simile, aequale [like, equal];
4. Expressions of relation with reference: pater, filius [Father, Son];
5. Collective expressions for all the Persons together: Trinitas.
6. Expressions of relations involving all the Persons with respect to crea-
tures: Creator, Dominus [Lord].
7. E
xpressions of temporal relations involving individual Persons with
respect to creatures: missus [the One sent];
emporal expressions of a non-relational sort: Incarnatus, humanatus
8. T
[the One who was made flesh, became man];
9. Metaphorical expressions: agnus, leo, character [Lamb, Lion, character or
spiritual mark (in sacramental theology)].
Making linguistic and terminological distinctions is combined in Peter’s
work with a didactic method that attaches great importance to precision
and transparency. All nine word types are illustrated. Furthermore he has
his students prepare schematic drawings (figura) that are also included in
his work.137
A similar concept of theology forms the basis of the summa “Qui pro-
ducit ventos” by Praepositinus of Cremona, who taught in Paris at the same
135. Ibid., PL 211.981 C.
136. Ibid., I, 2 (I, 11.25–43).
137. Ibid., I, 15 (I, 153) concerning predestination and reprobation; I, 22 (I, 193) on distinguish-
ing among the Persons of the Trinity; I, 30 (I, 240) on the relation of the procession of the Holy
Spirit from the Father and the Son; Alberich of Trois-Fontaines testifies that this didactic method
was apparently an exceptional phenomenon: Introduction, xxi.
The Self-Concept of Early Scholastic Theologies 109
time as Peter of Poitiers and Alan of Lille and succeeded the former as chan-
cellor of Paris. His approach is even closer than Peter’s to the axiomatic
method of Alan and the linguistic logic of the Porretan school; he begins
the first book of his summa fully aware of the necessity for neat terminol-
ogy: “E vocabulis igitur qu[a]e de Deo dicuntur incipiamus.” [“Let us begin
therefore with the terms that are predicated of God.”]138 In contrast to
Peter, Praepositinus now presents in detail the grammatical and syntacti-
cal rules that are supposed to make precise discourse about the relations
in God possible. We are dealing therefore with the sketch of a theological
grammar. First the required or available words are classified:
ords that are spoken without reference to time (“ab aeterno,” e.g.,
1. W
Deus bonus, Deus justus),
2. W ords that are spoken with a temporal connotation (“ex tempore,” e.g.,
Creator, refugium, Dominus),
3. W
ords that are spoke about all three Persons and each one individually
(e.g., Deus),
4. W ords that are spoken about all three Persons together, but not about
each individually (e.g., Trinitas),
ords that are spoken only about two Persons (e.g., principium Spiritus
5. W
Sancti [the principle from which the Holy Spirit proceeds]),
6. Words that are spoken about only one Person (e.g., Pater, Filius,
Spiritus Sanctus),
7. As for their grammatical classification, they are nomina (“names”
= nouns and adjectives), verbs and participles.
8. I n the case of the adjectives, it should also be considered whether they
connote a division (e.g., unus [one]) or not (e.g., bonus [good]), whether
they are single predicates (e.g., aeternus) or relational expressions (e.g.,
coaeternus, coaequalis) with reference to another Person or a third party
(e.g., prescius [prescient]).139
Detailed rules for this vocabulary are now stated that define the mean-
ing of a given term in theological usage:
1. A
ll words that are spoken referentially about all three Persons and each
one individually designate the divine essence, except for adjectives that
connote a division.
138. Präpositinus, Summa “Qui producit ventos” I, 1 (ed. Angelini, Ortodossia, 197.1).
139. Ibid., (199.2–16).
110 The Self-Concept of Early Scholastic Theologies
2. Verbs, participles, and adjectives that connote a relation of Persons to
one another are predicated in the plural of the three Persons together
(e.g., potentes omnia [able to do all things], coaeterni).
3. Nouns that designate the divine essence are predicated in the singular of
the three Persons (e.g., Deus).
4. Adjectives that express no relation of one Person to another have the
same meaning when they are predicated in the plural of the three Persons
(e.g., “Pater et Filius et Spiritus Sanctus sunt aeterni” [“. . . are eternal”]).
5. In connection with Persons, adjectives that connote a division (e.g., unus,
aliquis, distinctus [one, someone, distinct]) connote (in the [Latin] mascu-
line or feminine gender) a distinction (e.g., “Pater est unus, Filius est alius,
Pater et Filius sunt duo” [“The Father is one, the Son is another, the Father
and the Son are two”]). In connection with nouns that designate the
divine essence, they also designate the essence (e.g., “Pater est unus Deus,
Pater et Filius sunt una essentia” [“The Father is one God; the Father and
the Son are one essence”]); in the neuter gender they likewise designate
the essence (e.g., “Pater et Filius sunt unum” [“The Father and the Son
are one”]).
6. The noun “persona” designates the distinction, answers the question
“quid tres?” [“three what?”] and in the plural is used collectively for all
three Persons.140
The rules are not laid down here according to the axiomatic method,
however, but rather emerge from a sometimes tedious disputation of the
pro and con of patristic authorities and contemporary opinions, whereby
the author is clearly aware of the constant possibility of false conclusions
based on imprecise word usage (fallaciae).141 Such terminological work
presupposes, however, a previous knowledge about the contents of the faith
as it is proposed by the Church. The object of discussion for theology is not
that but rather the adequacy of human discourse in explaining it. A logical
analysis of Praepositinus’ procedure shows that the contents of the faith as
formulated by the Church (whenever possible in standard language) can be
expressed as axioms and in that form are the precondition for the whole
discussion about the adequacy of the formulation. For example, the funda-
mental axioms for the doctrine of the Trinity are:142
149. Bernard of Clairvaux, Super Cant. 74.2 (S. Bernardi Opera. II, Roma, 1958, 240.16–22).
150. Bernard of Clairvaux, De consid. V, 32 (III, 493.24–25): “at orando forte quam disputando
dignius quaeritur et invenitur facilius.” [“But He is sought more worthily and found more easily by
praying hard than by debating.”]
151. See Leclercq, Wissenschaft, 260–75.
152. See esp. Chenu, Théologie au XII, 159–209.
153. Hugh of St. Victor, De arca Noe mystica (PL 176, 681–684); Adamus Scotus, De tripartito
tabernaculo p. 2 (PL 198, 683–744); see also Sicard, Diagrammes. A remarkable reaction to Hugh is
expressed in Smalley, Study, 96: “Oh yes! we think of the Kindergarten.”
114 The Self-Concept of Early Scholastic Theologies
partito tabernaculo by the Premonstratensian Adamus Scotus in response
to an extremely detailed inquiry from John of Kelso (ca. 1175) concerning
Exodus 25–27, for example about the location and significance of the sixth
tent curtain (Exodus 26:9) or of the bronze grating or network at the altar
(Exodus 27:4).154
Remarkably, the historical sense that appears here is strongly connected
with monastic theology. Whereas the theologians of the cathedral and state
schools generally do not develop much of a sense of history, the historical
foundations of the way of life in a specific cloister always provide an incen-
tive to grapple with one’s own past.155 Out of historiography (e.g., monastic
chronicles), however, develops an interpretation of history or a theology of
history, as is evident in Otto of Freising († 1153), for instance. Historiogra-
phy, too, becomes a means of theological edification and self-examination;
this is clearly the case with the Cluniac abbot Petrus Venerabilis († 1156),
who in the prologue to De miraculis becomes angry “about the indifference
of many people who distinguish themselves by their knowledge, love of
literature and eloquence yet are too lazy to leave to their posterity written
records of the wonderful works that the Almighty accomplishes again and
again on earth to strengthen his Church.”156 Thus historiography is ordered
to the Church, the praise of God and mutual edification, whether in the
form of hagiography (which sometimes assumes the form of an ascetical
sermon on the subject of a saintly figure),157 or in the form of a monastic,
ecclesiastical, or secular chronicle. Such documents exhibit all possible
combinations of theological intention, critical sense and belief in miracles,
sometimes even in the defense of manifestly material interests.158 Replace-
able parts, like the sentences of the magistri, are carried over from one saint’s
life to the next, which in some instances is composed for a definite purpose,
for instance to achieve the exaltation of the relics or canonization.159
Monastic theology most often regards itself in its existential setting as
superior to Scholastic theology. Authors, including Bernard of Clairvaux,
are fond of differentiating their work from Scholasticism by citing Jerome’s
remark that the monk has the “officium lugendi” [“duty of mourning”] and
154. PL 198.609–792; see also Chenu, Théologie au XII, 192–96; Leinsle, “Charitati militare,” 9–10.
155. See Leclercq, Wissenschaft, 174–89.
156. Petrus Venerabilis, De miraculis, prol. (PL 189.907).
157. See, for example, the Vita Siardi (ed. Lamboij and Mol, Vitae Abbatum, 242–349; 43–51).
158. Examples in Leclercq, Wissenschaft, 179–82.
159. Examples in Leclercq, Wissenschaft, 186–87; Heffernan, Sacred Biography.
The Self-Concept of Early Scholastic Theologies 115
not the “officium docendi” [“duty of teaching”].160 The excesses of the Scho-
lastic enterprise and the personal conduct of magistri and scholares could
provide welcome grounds for pious aloofness, as when Stephen of Tour-
nai (1135–1203) wrote to the Pope: “The students are no longer interested
in anything but what is new. The magistri, who loved their reputation above
all else, compose new summas every day and new theological works that
please the listeners and deceive them, as though the writings of the Fathers
who explained sacred Scripture were not enough.”161 If one must pursue
theology, then it should not be as a science with the methods of dialectic
terminology (“profanae vocum novitates,” 1 Tim 6:20), for that does not ed-
ify but only leads to pride (“scientia inflat,” 1 Cor 8:1). With such passages
from the Bible people in many circles believed that they were armed against
the Scholastic enterprise.162 Yet the rejection of all Scholastic, academic
theology is neither a universal nor a necessary characteristic of “monas-
tic” or cloistered theology. The addition of religious community life, how-
ever, makes the theology advocated here an existential-experiential theol-
ogy, a kind of wisdom (e.g., in the school of St. Victor) that can then be
contrasted with mere science, as Bernard of Clairvaux programmatically
maintains: “There (in the schools) we hear what wisdom teaches; here we
receive it into ourselves. There we are taught, here—deeply moved. Instruc-
tion produces knowledgeable men, whereas association [in religious life]
produces wise men. . . . There one arrives at wisdom; here one penetrates
into it.”163
160. Hieronymus, Contra Vigilantium 15 (PL 23.351); Bernard of Clairvaux, Sup. Cant. 64.3 (II,
168.3–4); Ep. 89 (VII, 236.3–4).
161. Stephen of Tournai, Ep. 251 (PL 211.517).
162. See, for example, Petrus Damiani, De sancta simplicitate scientiae inflanti anteponenda (PL
145.695).
163. Bernard of Clairvaux, Sup. Cant. 23.14 (I, 147.22–148.13).
116 The Self-Concept of Early Scholastic Theologies
doctrine.164 Proceedings against teachers are therefore different from those
against popular heresies. The mistrust with which ecclesiastical and clois-
tered circles viewed the free schools and the theology pursued in them pro-
vided a fertile soil for the suspicion of heresy: “Contrary to hallowed pre-
cepts, they debate about the incomprehensible Godhead; flesh and blood
argue with many words and without reverence about the Incarnation of the
Word. They divide up the indivisible Trinity and demonstrate the differenc-
es within it. There are already as many errors as doctors, as many teachings
as listeners, as many blasphemies as public places.” So Stephen of Tournai,
Abbot of Mont Ste. Geneviève in Paris, to Pope Innocent III (1198–1216).165
On the other hand, the learned heresies (e.g., of Abelard and Gilbert Por-
reta) are not uncommonly accused of being esoteric doctrines.166 A lack of
understanding of Scholastic terminology or of the Porretan “standard lan-
guage” and methods in broad sectors of the Church further contributed to
the suspicion of heresy.
As this early Scholastic theology was taking shape, we observe at the
same time the development of a formal and juridically exact concept of her-
esy.167 The background for this was the Gregorian reform along with the de-
velopment of the papal primacy of jurisdiction. In this trend the concept of
heresy, as found for instance in Gerhoh of Reichersberg and Peter Damian,
applies only in a very restricted way to the learned heresy; above all it is a
disciplinary measure aimed at departures from the “Romana ecclesia”: “here-
ticum esse constat qui Romane ecclesie non concordat,” [“Anyone who does not
agree with the Roman Church is recognized as a heretic,”] as Gregory VII
put it (1073–1085).168 This formula can then be applied to doctrinal devia-
tions if one assumes that the Roman Church has always preserved the true
faith; for unlike schism, heresy does not rend Church unity but rather the
truth.169 Only in this version can the reforming papacy’s concept of heresy
be applied to deviations in speculative theology, as Gerhoh’s battle against
Abelard and Gilbert’s students proves. For him as a reformed canon regular,
164. See Fichtenau, Ketzer; Grundmann, Religiöse Bewegungen; Lambert, Medieval Heresy; An-
genendt, Religiosität, 192–201.
165. CUP I, 48 n. 48.
166. See Abaelard, Confessio fidei, ed. Ch. S. Burnett, Medieval Studies 48 (1986): 132; Gaufred
of Auxerre, Contra Capitula Gilberti c.1 (PL 185.595).
167. See esp. Lourdeaux and Verhelst, eds., Concept of Hersesy; Hageneder, Häresiebegriff.
168. Register of Gregory VIII (MGH Epist/4, VII, 25); see also Classen, Häresiebegriff, 31–32.
169. Thus Gerhoch von Reichersberg, Liber de laude fidei, (Opera inedita, Rom 1955/56, 1.254);
von Reichersberg, De investigatione Antichristi I, 53 (MGH lib 3, 359–60); see also Beinert, Kirche,
368–80.
The Self-Concept of Early Scholastic Theologies 117
Scholasticism (scholastice) is the antithesis of ecclesiastical discipline (eccle-
siastice), with which doctrine is bound up. The “scholae in Francia” are the
cradles of heresy and therefore contrary to the “ecclesia Romana.”170
Bernard uses a substantially more interesting argument, from a formal
perspective, in his polemic against Abelard and Gilbert.171 On the one hand
Bernard accuses Abelard of innovating in matters of faith: he says that a new
faith is being set forth, that Abelard regards his “novitates” as superior to the
faith and the doctrine of the Catholic Fathers; in short, that he is proclaim-
ing a “nova haeresis.”172 This innovation is unmasked, however, as an old er-
ror, which goes back to the well-known heresies of the patristic era: Arian-
ism in the doctrine on the Trinity, Pelagianism in the doctrine on grace, and
Nestorianism in Christology.173 This makes clear also the final judgment
with which Bernard intervenes with Pope Innocent II (1130–1143) against
Abelard: Whatever he says, deep down he is a heretic.174 Heresy, though,
is not simply an error in matters of faith that fallible human beings might
make, but rather the adherence to error and the defense of it, after it has
been pointed out that it is an error. Heresy therefore is not just a matter of
the intellect but above all a matter of the will.175 In Bernard’s view this is
precisely the case with Abelard, who despite the condemnation in Soissons
in 1121 has not desisted from his errors but keeps producing new ones and
arousing those that were sleeping concealed among the general public and
thus is endangering the faith of the simple people.176 Gilbert too is accused
of innovation in the form of a distorted and obscure interpretation of the
Trinity with which the Catholic Church cannot possibly agree.177
It is also typical of the twelfth century that the attacks against real and
alleged heresies of the magistri originate with individual ecclesiastics. The
papacy, at this stage in the development of its claim to universal jurisdic-
1. On the history of the university see esp. Rashdall, Universities; Leff, Paris; Weijers, Termi-
nologie.
120
Theology as a Science at the University 121
this process included: the granting to the magister of authorization to teach
(licentia docendi), dealing with the chancellor as the official ecclesiastical au-
thority and with the city government of Paris as the municipal authority,
the royal privilege of Philip II (1180–1233) dating back to 1200, and finally
the university statutes of Chancellor Robert of Courson/Courçon (†1219)
from the year 1215. Disputes, unrest, and strikes marked the development
of the university in Paris in its struggle for independence from ecclesiasti-
cal oversight. For the University of Paris was still strongly influenced by the
tradition of the cathedral school of Notre Dame, which (unlike Oxford)
was ruled by a Church-appointed chancellor.2 In contrast, at the end of the
twelfth century in Oxford, located at a considerable distance from the see
of the bishop of Lincoln who had jurisdiction, the various abbey schools
gave rise to a studium generale, which in 1214 received papal approval from
Innocent III.3
The university now defined the educational career of the future theolo-
gian also.4 The student who enrolled in one of the “nations” [nationes] (in
Paris there were four, in Oxford—three) at around the age of fifteen had to
complete first the philosophical education institutionalized in the facultas
artium [faculty of the arts] before he could be promoted to the “higher”
faculties (theology, law, medicine). The relation between philosophy and
theology was thus fixed also by the university: without philosophy no the-
ology. After six years the scholar could become a baccalaureus artium [Bach-
elor of Arts]. As such he lectured on the classical texts under the direction
of the magister, and upon concluding this practicum he obtained the licen-
tia docendi, provided that he had reached the age of twenty-one. After what
was usually a very short stint of teaching in philosophy he could then begin
the study of theology (minimum age seventeen), and it took seven (later
six) years to earn the baccalaureate.5 The baccalaureus biblicus (minimum
age twenty-five), after a solemn principium or introitus, lectured cursorily on
the books of the Bible for one or more years as a cursor. Then as a bacca-
laureus sententiarius he spent two years under the supervision of a magister
explaining the Sentences of Peter Lombard. With that he was a baccalaureus
formatus. As such he had to participate in lectures and disputations and give
The university’s reacion was now unequivocal: “And the universitas mag-
istrorum bowed its head, accepted the apostolic blessing and went home.”17
In contrast, the matter developed more harmoniously at first in Oxford.
Here, though, with the appointment of Thomas of York († ca. 1260) as Ma-
gister in 1253, there were difficulties because of the fact that the Franciscans
normally dispensed with the study of the artes. On the other hand, major
conflicts arose in Oxford in the years 1311–1317 with regard to the obligation
to lecture on the Sentences for a year before studying the Bible, which con-
tradicted the custom of the mendicant orders in Oxford.18
16. CUP I n. 200 (I, 226–27). 17. See Miethke, “Papst, Ortsbischof.”
18. See Leff, Paris, 103–6.
Theology as a Science at the University 127
should have priority in university theology, the Sentences or the Bible? The
mendicants advocated a clear preference for the Bible from the very start.
Once again, therefore, it was a question of the precedence of biblical or sys-
tematic theology. Thanks to the teaching of Robert Grosseteste, among oth-
ers, theology at Oxford had an unmistakably biblical emphasis. Grosseteste
plainly stands in the same tradition of moral-pastoral exegesis as Stephen
Langton, for instance, since Thomas Eccleston describes his teaching with
the Franciscans as “tam in quaestionibus quam praedicationi congruis subtili-
bus moralitatibus” [“both in questions and in subtle matters of morality suit-
able for preaching”].19 Grosseteste is not part of the Parisian tradition of
systematic theology, but rather applies himself to the Bible and the Church
Fathers from a background of philosophy and natural science. Tellingly, the
only twelfth-century “Scholastic” on his “reading list” was Hugh of St. Vic-
tor.20 Grosseteste draws his theology mainly from Augustine and Gregory
the Great, and was influenced philosophically by Seneca in particular, which
only underscores the tropological-moral character of his scriptural exege-
sis.21 For Grosseteste the Bible and theology (as sacra pagina) are still one.
Later as bishop of Lincoln and chancellor of the University he still addresses
the magistri of Oxford in clear terms and warns them against departing from
this tradition. The books of the OT and the NT must remain the founda-
tion for the edifice of theology. The morning hours are devoted to explaining
them in the lectiones ordinariae, as was also the custom among the magistri in
Paris.22
The staunch representative of the Oxford biblical tradition in Oxford,
however, was the Franciscan Roger Bacon (ca. 1220–after 1292).23 Even in
his Compendium studii theologiae (after 1290) he still emphasized that the
real concern of theologians is “circa textum sacrum sciendum” [“understand-
ing the sacred text”]. Yet for fifty years scholars had been dealing chiefly
with questions, as was evident from their treatises and enormous summas.
In his view, however, these questions were really of a philosophical nature
“tam in substantia quam in modo” [“both in substance and in method”].24
19. Tractatus Fr. Thomae Eccleston De adventu Fratrum Minorum in Anglia, ed. A. G. Little (Par-
is, 1909), 60; see also Little, “Franciscan School,” 807.
20. See Southern, Robert Grosseteste, 187.
21. Ibid., 195, see the list: 3,000 citations from Augustine, 1,257 from Gregory the Great; Seneca
leads the philosophers with 333 as opposed to Aristotle with only 68.
22. Roberti Grosseteste Epistolae, ed. H. R. Lund (Rolls Series, 1861), 346–47; see also Smalley,
Study, 276–77.
23. On his life and work, see Hackett, “Roger Bacon.”
24. Roger Bacon, Compendium of the Study of Theology, edition and translation with introduc-
128 Theology as a Science at the University
Therefore compiling theological questions was in principle a betrayal of
theology as scriptural exegesis. In his Opus Minus (1266/67) he had already
severely attacked as “peccatum” [“a sin”] the usual Parisian practice of theo-
logical study, namely that a single summa of a magister, the Lombard’s Liber
Sententiarum, was preferred to the text that really should be interpreted in
the theological faculty, sacred Scripture. The whole reputation of a theo-
logian consisted then of his interpretation of the Lombard, and everyone
thought that he had to write a commentary weighing as much as a horse.
Once someone had lectured on the Sentences he felt that he was already a
master of theology, although he had scarcely heard anything of his real tex-
tus yet. The baccalaureus biblicus, however, is subordinate to the sententia-
rius. The sententiarius has the best hours for his lectures, an assistant and a
lecture hall at the religious house. The biblical scholar, however, has nothing
and must go to the sententiarius to beg for his hours. The sententiarius even
debates and is already considered to be a magister. The biblical scholar can-
not debate. So it has been in Bologna and elsewhere. Bottom line: “quod est
absurdum” [“this is absurd,” i.e., a reductio ad absurdum, proving the falsity
of the premises from the logical conclusion]. Subordinating sacred Scripture
to the Sentences, moreover, contradicts an old faculty regulation. Every other
faculty interprets only the authentic text. For if you really know and have un-
derstood the text exactly, you have learned everything that there is to learn
in that faculty. Indeed, that is what the authentic text was made for. All the
more reason that this should be the case in theology, for here the authentic
text comes from the mouth of God and of the saints. The Church Fathers in-
terpreted only the biblical text. That was the practice of the early teachers of
theology, namely Robert Grosseteste and Adam Marsh († ca. 1259), the first
teachers of the Franciscans at Oxford. Alexander of Hales, however, Bacon’s
Parisian confrere, was the first to lecture on the Sentences instead of the Bible,
and from then on this abuse became established in the Franciscan Order as
well. It would have been much better to lecture on the Historia scholastica by
Petrus Comestor, as had been the custom earlier, for the latter work is essen-
tially closer to theology (as sacra pagina) than the Liber Sententiarum. That
is why Bacon advocated reinstating the Historia scholastica and abandoning
the many questions that no longer have any relation to the sacred text. In-
stead, text-related questions should be posed. Now it is true, however, that
tion and notes by Thomas S. Maloney, [Studien und Texte zur Geistesgeschichte des Mittelalters
20], (Leiden, 1988), part 2, prologue, page 48; see also Bérubé, “Dialog,” 111–12.
Theology as a Science at the University 129
while the biblical scholars lecture on the text in a cursory fashion, they do
not explain it, since they don’t debate questions, whereas the theologians in
their questions are really just pursuing philosophy. Yet the theological ques-
tions in the summas and sentences must be verified by the biblical text.25
Then, too, the text commonly used in Paris is corrupted, the literal sense is
often understood incorrectly and therefore the spiritual sense of Scripture
is likewise wrong or dubious. Furthermore jurists, even if they don’t have
the faintest idea of canon law, are more highly esteemed in the Church than
biblical scholars and attain ecclesiastical honors more quickly.26 This bibli-
cal reaction to the situation in Paris and Bologna came too late, however, to
do anything about the decline in biblical theology and the rise of the ques-
tions and commentaries on the Sentences.
Biblical and systematic theology, scriptural commentary and commen-
tary on the Sentences, parted ways not only in Paris but also in Oxford. The
Dominican magister Richard Fishacre († 1248) in the prologue to his com-
mentary on the Sentences clearly distinguishes between the moral-tropo-
logical scriptural exegesis of a Grosseteste and speculative theology with its
questions taken from sacred Scripture but collected in the book of sentences.
The questions are still referred back to sacred Scripture, but the indepen-
dent value of the sentences as a systematic work of theology is recognized.
Therefore reading the Sentences should by no means be neglected, since this
study deals “de questionibus circa fidem difficilibus” [“with difficult questions
about the faith”].27 Even such a thorough Scripture commentator as Bacon’s
contemporary and confrere Thomas Docking († after 1269), who taught be-
tween 1260 and 1265, lectured on the Sentences.28
In Paris it was in fact the mendicants who, unlike the magistri from the
secular clergy, followed the Victorine school and first revived lecturing on
sacred Scripture, which led to the scriptural commentaries of Thomas Aqui-
nas and Bonaventure. We should mention here especially the postilla to the
Gospels by the Dominican Hugh of St. Cher (ca. 1235). He clearly distances
himself from the mutual critiques of the “moralistae” and the “quaestionistae”
and combines the best of both traditions: for him theology is both scrip-
25. Corrected text: Little, “Franciscan School,” 808–9; see also Tshibangu, Théologie, 122–36;
Bérubé, “Dialog,” 100–110; Antolić-Piper, “Begründung.”
26. Roger Bacon, Opus Minus, ed. J. S. Brewer (London, 1859), 330, 349; Bacon, Opus Tertium, 84.
27. Richard Fishacre, In Sent., prol., ed. Long, in “Science,” 96–97; see also Niederbacher and
Leibold, Theologie, 131–87.
28. See Little, “Franciscan School,” 846–50.
130 Theology as a Science at the University
tural interpretation and also systematic theology, as represented by his con-
frere Richard Fishacre.29 The symbolic interpretation of sacred Scripture
gained new impetus, especially in the Franciscan tradition. On the other
hand the general acceptance of the pagan, Aristotelian worldview in the fac-
ulty of arts posed serious problems for the theologian, too, who looked to
the actual wording of Scripture. Aristotelian categories (esp. the doctrine of
the four causes) make their way into exegesis.30
The attempt to strike a balance between theology as scriptural interpre-
tation and as a systematic science is evident also at an influential position in
the works of Thomas Aquinas, in the first question of his Summa Theologiae.
After discussing theology as “sacra doctrina” along the lines of the Aristote-
lian concept of science, in articles 9 and 10 he poses apparently unmediated
questions about the character of “sacra Scriptura” and about the validity of
its metaphorical language and of the manifold sense of Scripture.31 Yet the
relation between Scripture and systematic theology has plainly changed.
Whereas Roger Bacon claims that systematic questions must be traced back
to the text of Scripture, Thomas attempts a systematic justification of the
language and interpretation of sacred Scripture. He succeeds by assuming
that God is generally the Auctor of Scripture, who determines that the res
[things] designated by the words are also supposed to function in turn as
signs for a further meaning. Thus for Thomas the words or sentences do not
have various meanings, but rather the res are read as signs.32 The spiritual
sense of Scripture is therefore not just the product of interpretation but is
rather built into the literal sense (in una littera) thanks to God’s comprehen-
sive knowledge, although the intentio auctoris (i.e., God’s intention) initially
concerns the literal sense.33 This accomplishes three things:
1. Scripture and theology remain interrelated. Scriptural exegesis must al-
low itself to be justified systematically, however.
2. Literal exegesis is clearly restricted in its significance (e.g., as opposed to
the Victorine school).
3. Spiritual exegesis (probably also as a result of the experience of the con-
fusion surrounding Joachim of Fiore [ca. 1130–1202]) is deprived of its
arbitrariness and acquires a certain ontological character. The res [things]
29. See Smalley, Study, 269–70: Niederbacher and Leibold, Theologie, 37–78.
30. On Hugh of St. Cher and Guerricus of St. Quentin: Smalley, Study, 295–98.
31. Thomas Aquinas, S.Th. I q.1 a.9 f., ed. Marietti (Turin-Rome, 1952), 8–9.
32. For Bonaventure’s similar position, see also Leinsle, Res et signum.
33. S.Th. I q1 a10 i.c. (9).
Theology as a Science at the University 131
as such in Scripture have further meanings that are determined by the
author (God), not by the exegete.
34. See Van Steenberghen, Philosophie, 149–66; Grabmann, Forschungen; Van Steenberghen
“Aristoteles.”
35. See esp. Köpf, Anfänge; Dreyer, More mathematicorum; Langer, “Aristoteles.”
36. See Aristoteles, Analytica Posteriora; English translation in The Basic Works of Aristotle, ed.
Richard McKeon (New York: Modern Library, 2001), 110–86.
132 Theology as a Science at the University
and therefore has for Aristotle a theoretical and not a poietic character like
τέχνη (ars).37
The following elements of the Aristotelian concept of science are of
decisive importance to thirteenth- and fourteenth-century theology for its
self-understanding as a science in the context of the university:
1. The object of science (subjectum scientiae). Every science is concerned
with a class of things as its object; it presupposes the existence and defini-
tion of this object and inquires into its qualities, which should be proved
to the extent possible from the definition. If theology wants to show that
it is a science, it has to explain what its central object is (e.g., God), how
its existence can be established (the theoretical problem of the “proofs of
God’s existence”) and how its qualities can be identified.
2. The proof as a logical method. A proof is a “syllogism that produces
knowledge.”38 Theology as a science that proves is therefore subject to the
logical testing of the validity of its proofs. Such a syllogism proves some-
thing, however, only if it is obtained from necessary and true premises.
3. The problem of [ first] principles therefore becomes just as central for
theology as the problem of its object. The principles of the proof should
be prior to and more evident than the conclusions derived from them.39
In twelfth-century theology, metaphysical or theological axioms were
sometimes assumed as principles of theology, but usually articles of
faith served that purpose. The latter, however, are grasped only by faith
and therefore do not satisfy the conditions for Aristotelian principles
of proof.40 Since Aristotle assigns the understanding of principles to
another cognitive faculty, the νοῦς (intellectus), the object of knowledge
(scientia) is ultimately the conclusion that is proved.
4. The requirement that the principles of the proof be necessary. The
conclusion is based on necessary premises.41 Theology, considered as
the exposition of God’s historical salvific acts, as they are recorded in its
central textus, sacred Scripture, was hitherto unfamiliar with such strict
necessity, which on the other hand could jeopardize God’s freedom.
5. The requirement that the principles and the known propositions be
general. Our modern understanding of the humanities and social sciences
notwithstanding, in Aristotle’s view individual historical facts are not the
37. See Aristoteles, An. post. B 19, 100 a 6; Met. A 1, 891 a 28.
38. Aristoteles, An. post. A 2, 71 b 17. 39. Ibid., 71 b 19.
40. See Lang, Prinzipienlehre. 41. Aristoteles, An. post. A 4, 73 a 24.
Theology as a Science at the University 133
object of knowledge and science: de singulari non est scientia.42 Theology,
however, deals with historical, free, unique acts of God. If it is to be a sci-
ence in the Aristotelian sense, it must demonstrate that its object and its
propositions are general.
6. The distinction between theoretical and practical science. If one argues
for the scientific character of theology, one must explain whether it is
a theoretical science in the Aristotelian sense, that is, restricted to the
knowledge of the object’s essence and the proof of its attributes, or a
practical science, and therefore related to human activity and its goal.
With reference to precisely this question, various authors, orders, and
schools will manifest profoundly different concepts of theology and its
status: for at this juncture is decided also the significance of theology
beyond the university for religious, ecclesial, and political life.43
7. The certainty of theological statements. Proven knowledge in the most
strict sense is attained when any further question about what is known
has been ruled out.44 Theological truths do not appear to have this objec-
tive certainty, independently of their subjective certainty, that is, the
believer’s degree of conviction. For they, like their premises, are based
on faith. Moreover, God’s freedom must be taken into account, since
theological topics ultimately depend on it.
42. Ibid., B 21, 67 a 27. 43. See Krebs, Theologie und Wissenschaft.
44. See Heim, Gewissheitsproblem.
134 Theology as a Science at the University
posed a philosophy restricted to instrumental logical disciplines. Could this
formula still be applied to an independent, comprehensive pagan interpre-
tation of the world, as found in Aristotle’s works, or did scholars have to
redefine the relationship [between theology and philosophy]?
The theologians in Paris and Oxford only gradually became aware of the
problems posed by Aristotle’s works on natural philosophy. In particular the
following teachings of the Stagirite had to be viewed as incompatible with
Christianity:
1. The eternity of the world. Calcidius and Boethius were acquainted with
this as an opinion of Plato (Timaeus 28 A–38 C); the question as to the
truth of this thesis became pressing, however, partly because Aristotle’s
interpretation of the world in his works of natural science proved to be
far superior to the previous explanation, even in the view of thirteenth-
century theologians. If the thesis of the eternity of the world, time and
movement is a necessary component of this natural science, then from
the theological perspective it is false because it contradicts revelation.45
If one were to attribute to it a truth in the sphere of natural explana-
tion (philosophy) but not in the sphere of theology, this would give the
impression of a double truth: what is true in philosophy can be false in
theology.46 Philip the Chancellor († 1236) already dealt with this express-
ly in his influential Summa de bono. For him creation implies a temporal
beginning. Therefore Aristotle cannot teach a strict eternity (aeternum)
but only an unlimited temporal duration (perpetuum) of the world.47
Alexander of Hales, on the other hand, sees no contradiction between
the Stagirite’s thesis, which is to be interpreted purely in terms of natural
science, and the wording of the Bible, since Aristotle only means to say
that space, time, and movement came into being at the same time.48 For
Robert Grosseteste, who adheres strictly to the text of the Stagirite, this
conciliatory attitude of Alexander is mere nonsense and an attempt to
make a Catholic out of the heretic Aristotle. The real compromise was
achieved by Thomas Aquinas, who managed to show that an eternal
creation is theologically and philosophically possible.49
58–61; Thomas Aquinas, De aeternitate mundi contra murmurantes, in Opuscula philosophica (Turin:
Marietti, 1954), 103–8.
50. Bonaventura, Collationes in Hexaemeron, vis. I coll.3, 2–5, ed. F. Delorme (Quaracchi,
1934), 91–92; see also Leinsle, Res et signum, 74.
51. See Van Steenberghen, Philosophie, 339–50, 154; Bazán, “Conception.”
52. Thomas Aquinas, De unitate intellectus in Opuscula philosophica (Turin: Marietti, 1954),
59–90.
136 Theology as a Science at the University
The three problematic areas mentioned above were not just incidental
skirmishes. They were central to the conflict between an independent, pure-
ly natural interpretation of the world that knows nothing of revelation, and a
theology based on the authority of revelation and its doctrinal tradition. At
stake was the correct (= true) interpretation of the world, man and knowl-
edge from the perspective of Christian truth. On the other hand, scholars
also saw the great advantages of Aristotelian physics and especially meta-
physics for the interpretation of theological truths (e.g., the teaching about
the matter and form of the sacraments). The new paradigm of science as a
way of explaining the world prevailed in sacra doctrina as well, despite resis-
tance and obvious difficulties in harmonizing it with the truths of revelation.
53. Concerning the background of Islamic-Christian relations see esp. Southern, Western Views;
Daniel, Arabs.
54. See Gilson, “Avicenne.”
Theology as a Science at the University 137
tonic implications could also be harmonized with Augustine’s doctrine of
the ideas, as attempted for instance by Henry of Ghent.55 Finally, Avicenna
had a decisive influence on Duns Scotus (ca. 1265–1308), so that E. Gilson
prefers to speak of the time after 1277 as a second aetas Avicenniana [age of
Avicenna], following the first one which lasted until the massive influx of
commentaries by Averroës. Avicenna supplied valuable elements for the-
ology: his teaching about intellects can be combined with the doctrine on
the angels; God as the “dator formarum” seems closer to the Christian un-
derstanding of God than the “unmoved mover” of Aristotle; yet Avicenna
makes God subject to a strict necessity to diffuse himself, which is difficult
to reconcile with God’s freedom in creation. Moreover, even William of Au-
vergne saw the incompatibility of the Islamic notion of blessedness with the
Christian idea, whereas he plainly accepted the independent existence of
the intellectus agens [agent intellect] along with Avicenna.56
Integrating Averroës into the Christian intellectual heritage proved to
be more difficult, if not impossible. For he is by design a strict Aristotelian,
so that in his case all the difficulties in accepting the Stagirite are increased.
Tellingly, his treatise on the agreement between religion and philosophy
was not translated into Latin. It taught a priority of philosophy, even in mat-
ters of faith, which led in the Islamic world to a conflict that can be viewed
as a parallel to the twelfth- and thirteenth-century disputes in Christian
lands.57 For Thomas Aquinas, nevertheless, Averroës became the Commen-
tator pure and simple, even though he did not follow him at every point.58
Instead Thomas would be concerned, especially in the critical point about
the individuality or generic unity of the human intellect as a whole, with
establishing an Aristotelianism that would be compatible with the Chris-
tian faith and opposed to the influence of the Averroës commentary on De
anima and its recipients in the faculty of arts.
Accepting Jewish sources must have seemed easier to the medieval theo-
logian than integrating Islamic thought. We have already observed the influ-
ence of Jewish exegesis, for instance in the work of Andrew of St. Victor. Loris
Sturlese has pointed out a possible mutual influence of Jewish and Christian
55. Heinrich von Gent, Summa quaestionum ordinariarum a.22 q.5 (printed edition Paris, 1520;
reprinted New York: St. Bonaventure, 1953), f.134v D; a.25 q.3 (f.156r S); see also Emery, “Image of
God.”
56. See Roger Bacon, Opus maius II, 5, ed. J. H. Bridges (reprinted Frankfurt 1964), II, 45–48;
Gilson, “Avicenne,” 98–103; and for a list of discrepancies between William and Avicenna (119).
57. Averroës, Traité décisif sur l’accord de la religion et de la philosophie (Paris: L. Gauthier, 1983).
58. See Vansteenkiste, “Tommaso d’Aquino.”
138 Theology as a Science at the University
schools in the Rhineland.59 Especially significant for the thirteenth century
was the philosophical-theological synthesis of Moses Maimonides (1138–
1204), who like Averroës was originally from Córdoba. His program, pre-
sented in the Guide for the Doubtful (Dux dubitantium, ca. 1190), corresponds
to a thirteenth-century need resulting from the separation of philosophy and
theology. In it Rabbi Moses tries to show not only that is there no contradic-
tion between them but on the contrary that the Bible itself contains the true
(Aristotelian-Arabic) philosophy. This can be discovered through allegorical
interpretation, which is customary in the Latin-speaking world as well. In the
Jewish world itself, Maimonides’ teaching led initially to a bitter controversy
over the correctness of this interpretation of the Bible as opposed to the pre-
vious literal exegesis.60 For Maimonides’ synthesis can be read in two ways,
and both have the force to disrupt Jewish as well as Christian theology: in
this synthesis philosophy is substantiated by the Bible (a position taken again
by the strict biblicism of seventeenth-century Calvinism),61 but on the other
hand the Word of revelation is measured against the truth of Arabic-Aristote-
lian philosophy, which is assumed. Thus even the individual practical precepts
of the Old Testament Law are now set on a rational, philosophical founda-
tion. The controversy surrounding Maimonides therefore becomes a concern
of Christian theology and the Church as well. The study of Maimonides’
books, which was sometimes banned by the Jewish authorities, could become
a danger for Christianity also. Thus the intervention of the tribunal of the In-
quisition in 1232 led to a book-burning in Montpellier. This was followed in
1242 by a burning of the Talmud in Paris. The equation of Arabic-Aristotelian
philosophy with the Bible (or the biblical substantiation thereof) resulted in
a theological legitimation, from a Christian perspective, of the fundamental
errors of Aristotelianism; according to William of Auvergne, the Jews became
heretics because after their dispersal in the Arab world they accepted Arabic
philosophy, including the doctrine that the world is eternal.62
71. See the letter of Gregory IX dated April 23, 1231: CUP I n.87 (I, 143–44): quaedam utilia et
inutilia.
72. CUP I n. 79 (I, 138); see also Grabmann, Divieti, 95–101.
73. CUP I n. 149 (I, 185–86).
74. CUP I n. 384 (I, 427–28).
75. See Van Steenberghen, Philosophie, 110–16.
76. CUP I n. 201, 246 (I, 227–30, 277–79).
77. Roger Bacon, Opus Minus, 327–28.
142 Theology as a Science at the University
sive discussion of Aristotle’s philosophy: to make this new understanding
of the world and man compatible with Christian revelation and thus to pre-
vent the break up of philosophy and theology and the danger of a heterodox
Aristotelianism.78
At the faculty of the arts, where scholars did not have to have these
theological misgivings, a heterodox Aristotelianism took shape principally
in the figures of Siger of Brabant and Boethius of Dacia. At first there were
the familiar difficulties with regard to the eternity of the world and the
species-wide unity of the human intellect, which were theologically offen-
sive.79 Yet more was at stake: The question about a philosophical (= natu-
ral scientific) truth that was independent of revelation and theology had
yet to be resolved. To theologians it could appear that an independent
truth of philosophy was being set up in opposition to the truth of revela-
tion, “quasi sint due contrarie veritates” [“as though there were two contrary
truths”].80 At any rate, the methods used by the masters of arts to explain
the relation between philosophical and theological truth claims had been
developed by the theologians themselves. Alexander of Hales had already
conceded that Aristotle settled questions only according to the principles
of natural science and knew nothing about creation as a supernatural divine
intervention. His philosophical doctrine, therefore, is not absolutely true
(non simpliciter), but rather should be interpreted in terms of the state of
the author’s knowledge.81 One could fall back on this position and derive
Aristotle’s opinion from his sources and presuppositions. As a philosopher
one can dispense with the question about the relation between Aristotle’s
and Averroës’ teaching and the truth of revelation, but the theologian can-
not.82 Significantly, Alexander’s distinction was not derived from Averroës,
who recognizes only one truth, philosophical truth, but rather from Moses
Maimonides, who uses it as Catholic theology does to reconcile the biblical
and83 Aristotelian worldviews.
84. Boethius of Dacia, De aeternitate mundi, ed. Géza Sajó (Berlin, 1964), 45–62; see also
Dales, “Origins,” 177–78.
144 Theology as a Science at the University
this-worldly happiness in the philosopher’s ideal way of life, which is clearly
set apart from the eternal happiness “quam in futura vita per fidem expecta-
mus” [“which we look for in the next life by faith”].85 The “god of the phi-
losophers” who is loved and honored here is the “primum principium” [“first
principle”] and “summum bonum” [“supreme good”]. Love for this God is
manifested “secundum rectam rationem naturae et secundum rectam rationem
intellectualem” [“according to the right reason of nature (i.e., as required by
natural law) and according to intellectual right reason”].86 All of this is elab-
orated as a purely philosophical ideal, along with the “sola recta delectatio”
[“sole proper delight”] in contemplating the Supreme Good: “Haec est vita
philosophi, quam quicumque non habuerit, non habet rectam vitam.” [“This is
the philosopher’s life; anyone who does not have it does not have an up-
right life.”]87 Faith and knowledge, theological hope for the afterlife and the
philosophical formation of this world have plainly diverged.
98. Alexander of Hales, Summa theologica, p. 1 inq. 1 tr. 4 q. 1 c. 2 (I, 207); q. 2 c. 2–3 (I, 219–22);
q. 3 c. 2 a. 1 (I, 233–34); see also William J. Courtenay, art. “Potentia absoluta / ordinata” HWP VII,
cols. 1157–62; Courtenay, Capacity, 68–74.
99. See Köpf, Anfänge, 67–69; Grabmann, Erkenntnislehre; Chenu, Théologie comme science;
Kraml, Rede von Gott; Niederbacher and Leibold, eds., Theologie.
100. Magistri Guillelmi Altissiodorensis Summa Aurea, ed. J. Ribaillier, vol. 1 (Spicilegium Bo-
naventurianum 16) (Paris-Grottaferrata, 1980); see in the same series Introduction générale (Spicile-
gium Bonaventurianum 20) (Paris-Grottaferrata, 1987), 3–16; see also Niederbacher and Leibold,
eds., Theologie, 13–35.
148 Theology as a Science at the University
mental attack on theology. Starting from the “definition of faith” in Hebrews
11:1, where faith itself is described as an “argumentum,” it must seem per-
verse that the magistri try to support the faith with arguments from reason.
For faith itself is “probans non probatum” [something that proves but is not
proved], an argument, not a conclusion that would require proof. A science
of faith in the strict sense would thus be an oxymoron.101 The solution of-
fered by William follows the earlier teaching of Praepositinus. Faith relies
in three ways on ratio: among believers faith is strengthened and increased
by it; it defends the faith against heretics; finally, simple folk may be moved
to believe by rational arguments. William by no means subscribes to an Ar-
istotelian explanation of theological science; instead he adheres to the tra-
ditional understanding of faith and theology exemplified by Augustine and
Anselm of Canterbury. Faith is an illumination by God and therefore affects
intellegere [understanding]: The more enlightened a soul is, the more clearly
she sees also that the matter in question is in fact as she believes it to be, but
also how and why it is so: “quod est intelligere” [“which is to understand”].102
Therefore William also agrees with Simon of Tournai (ca. 1130–1201), who
considers the connotation of “argumentum” in Aristotle to be incompatible
with the linguistic usage of the Bible: in Aristotle the argument is a reason
(ratio) for believing a dubious thing; for Christians, on the other hand, the
argument is faith itself, which creates its own reasons (ratio).103 Theological
progress (in persons) is therefore, as Augustine says, possible only as prog-
ress in faith, not as a deductive extension of knowledge from a first princi-
ple. Instead the first principle and the first truth is God himself, upon whom
one must rely in making the ascent of faith.104
In the second quaestio William emphasizes, as Peter Lombard had done,
that arguments drawn from reason must be suitable; this is not the case
with reasons that are related only to “res naturales” [“natural things”]. The
heretics’ blunder consists precisely of the fact that they simply applied such
arguments to God and thereby arrived at their errors (Arius and Sabellius
being the prime examples).105 William generally agrees with this: all her-
esies ultimately can be traced back to a hasty transference of purely natu-
ral circumstances to God, that is, to an unwarranted natural-philosophical
101. William of Auxerre, Summa aurea, l.1 prol.1 (15, 1–10); see also Beumer, “Theologie als in-
tellectus fidei.”
102. William of Auxerre, Summa aurea, l.1 prol.1 (16.35–37).
103. Ibid., (16.39–41). 104. Ibid., (18.80–84).
105. Ibid., prol. 2 (18.1–19, 37).
Theology as a Science at the University 149
or metaphysical line of argument in theology. Therefore in his own theol-
ogy he tries to do entirely without the “propriae rationes rerum naturalium”
[“proper reasons of natural things”]. Instead in his theological pursuit he
intends to stick exclusively with reasons that are theological or suited to the
matter at hand.106 By design, therefore, William is already practicing that
sort of abstinence with regard to teachings from other disciplines, namely,
Aristotelian natural philosophy, which Gregory IX so urgently recommend-
ed to the theologians of Paris in 1228. From the perspective of William’s un-
derstanding of faith, in any case, theology cannot become an Aristotelian
science.
112. Roland of Cremona, Summa, prol. q.2, cited in Köpf, Anfänge, 100–1, n. 93.
113. Ibid., cited in Köpf, Anfänge, 141, n. 60–62; see also Summa l.3, CIV, 5, ed. A. Cortesi (Ber-
gamo, 1962), 321; CV, 1.322.
114. Ibid., prol. q.2, cited in Köpf, Anfänge, 198–99, n. 220.
115. See Pelster, “Richard Fishacre”; Long and O’Carroll, Fishacre, 15–48; Niederbacher and
Leibold, Theologie, 131–87.
116. Long, ed., “Science,” 79–98; see the more detailed discussion in: Grabmann, Erkennt-
nislehre, 205–15; Niederbacher and Leibold, Theologie, 165–84.
Theology as a Science at the University 151
about them so as not to awaken the suspicion of an adulterous relationship
with a hired maid.117 Clearly we see here the aftereffects of the warning by
Gregory IX to theologians not to busy themselves with (natural) philoso-
phy. The efficient cause of sacred Scripture and theology is God. There-
fore it is “verissima, ordinatissima et certissima” [“most true, highly ordered
and quite certain”]. Its truth, method and certainty, then, are dependent
in principle, not on the Aristotelian theory of science and a procedure of
demonstration, but rather on the truth and veracity of God.118 Therefore
“scientia vel scriptura” (= theology) knows no syllogistic method of proof;
it is based in principle not on human arguments from reason but rather on
the authority of the author, that is, God. This very argument demonstrates
the equation of sacred Scripture and theology, which is not yet regarded as
problematic. In this discipline, moreover, there is no transition from what
is known to what is less known; instead, everything that is taught is equally
certain, since God’s authority guarantees the entire contents of Scripture.
This is immediately turned into an appeal to the moral sense of the theolo-
gians: “Quod si tantus est huius sapientiae auctor, quales debent esse auditores!”
[“Now if the Author of this wisdom is so great, what should the students be
like!”]119 The materia of theology is initially described very comprehensive-
ly and skillfully in the three simple elements of “natura suprema, media et in-
fima” [“highest, middle and lowest nature”], namely God, rational creatures
and bodies, and the structures compose of those elements, the Church and
man, which are both incorporated again into Christ. The object of theol-
ogy, therefore, cannot be so easily defined as Roland does. The indivisible
fundamental element is God himself; the “maxime compositum” [“most
composite element”], in contrast, is Christ, whereas the actual subjectum is
the union of the two higher elements: God and the rational creature, that
is, the Church or God’s salvific history with mankind.120 In man, however,
there are two powers: the virtus motiva and the virtus apprehensiva, the affec-
tive faculty of will and theoretical understanding. Theology, being aligned
with both, is neither a purely theoretical nor a purely practical discipline,
but necessarily concerns the knowledge of God as the highest truth, insofar
as that is possible on earth, and union with the highest good. Now the theo-
retical part is reserved for the discussion of more difficult questions about
117. Fishacre, In Sent., prol., ed. Long, “Science,” 85–87; see also CUP I n.59 (I, 114–16).
118. Fishacre, In Sent., prol., ed. Long, “Science,” 87–89.
119. Ibid., 89–90.
120. Ibid., 91–96; see also Köpf, Anfänge, 101–2; Niederbacher and Leibold, Theolgie, 175–77.
152 Theology as a Science at the University
the articles of faith, that is, in the historical context of lectures on the Sen-
tences. The moral, practical part, on the other hand, is treated in the inter-
pretation of sacred Scripture. Both parts refer, nevertheless, to Scripture as
the foundation of theology as a whole; for speculative theology, too, is pres-
ent “indistinctly” in Scripture, but is elaborated by the “magistri moderni” in
disputations for methodological reasons. The questions in the Lombard’s
Sentences are expressly declared to be excerpts from the Bible; this legiti-
mizes systematic theology biblically.121 Along the lines of the Augustinian
moral preparation for the speculative investigation of the faith, the moral in-
terpretation of sacred Scripture must precede the lectures on the Sentences.
Neither one is an Aristotelian science, however; instead, the two together
convey a knowledge that, according to the self-understanding of the theolo-
gian, surpasses all Aristotelian scientific theory.
Clearly dependent on Richard Fishacre is Robert Kilwardby († 1279),
whose commentary on the Sentences dates to the 1250s (after 1256).122 Tak-
ing Proverbs 9:1 as his point of departure, he develops his introdution to
theology in several questions; the basic understanding of theology as wis-
dom is present, while at the same time it is investigated again according to
the four causes. In the very first sentence, however, Kilwardby distinguishes
more clearly than Fishacre between theological teaching and sacra scrip-
tura.123 The problematic relation between the Sentences and the Bible is
resolved in such a way that God naturally remains the auctor of Scripture,
while the Lombard is only the “compilator vel promulgator” of the sacred
text. The fact that the Sentences are derived from Scripture is already taken
for granted.124 Question 12, which is decisive for the question of scientific
character, lists all the reasons why the Aristotelian concept of science ap-
pears to be inapplicable to theology (viewed here as scriptura): generality,
necessity, knowledge of causes, evidence. In order to resolve the question,
Kilwardby distinguishes in principle between two kinds of knowledge: the
one comes from divine inspiration and is obtained through the study of a
book; the other comes from human ingenuity and is conveyed “viva voce.”
125. Ibid., q. 12, 30.45–49; see also Kraml, Rede von Gott, 93–103.
126. Kilwardby, I Sent q. 12.30.31–44. 127. Ibid., 30.50–31.73.
128. Ibid., q. 13.33.1–34.34.
154 Theology as a Science at the University
129. Alexander of Hales, Glossa in quatuor libros Sententiarum Petri Lombardi I, Introitus (Bib-
liotheca Franciscana Scholastica Medii Aevi 12) (Quaracchi, 1951), 1–4; see also Osborne, “Alexan-
der of Hales,” 9.
130. See Kraml, Rede von Gott, 90–92.
131. (Summa Halensis =) Alexander of Hales, Summa theologica, I (Quaracchi, 1924). On the
question of authenticity and sources, see Summa theologica, IV, Prolegomena; Pergamo, De Quaes-
tionibus; Osborne, “Alexander of Hales,” 5–18; Niederbacher and Leibold, Theologie, 110–12.
132. Summa Hal. I Tr. int. q.1 c.1 (I, 1–4); see also Gössmann, Metaphysik, 15–36; Niederbacher
and Leibold, Theologie, 77–130.
133. See Aristoteles, Met. I, 1–2.
134. Summa Hal. Tr. int. q.1 c.1 (I, 1); see also Supra 1.1.4.
Theology as a Science at the University 155
it is nevertheless rendered more specific by the affective and practical orien-
tation that distinguishes it from pure metaphysics. This affective, practical
orientation constitutes the real sapiential (“relishing, tasting”) character of
theology, whereas metaphysics (as theologia philosophorum, the theology of
the philosophers) is only wisdom as the perfection of knowledge and thus
of the habit of knowing. The other sciences, however, which deal only with
subordinate causes, are only scientiae, not sapientia.135
It is remarkable that the answer given by the Summa does not go at all
into the foundation of theology in sacred Scripture. Only in the response
to the objections against applying the Aristotelian concept of science (now
from the Posterior Analytics) to theology does it bother to mention Scrip-
ture. The insufficient generality of the contents of sacred Scripture is imme-
diately rejected as a reason for the inapplicability of the concept of science.
Whereas secular history recounts the individual fact only as such, in Scrip-
ture the individual historical fact has a universal meaning. Through his-
torical facts, general acts and conditions are indicated for the instruction of
men and the contemplation of the divine mysteries. Since what is singular
in Scripture designates something universal, the concept of science is there-
fore applicable to it. The universalization of what is manifested in salvation
history ought therefore to guarantee the scientific character of theology in
its biblical foundation as well.136 Moreover, the Summa now demonstrates
(just as desperately) that Scripture contains not only singular but general
propositions (of a moral kind), for example, Proverbs 1:7 or 1 Timothy 1:5,
so that the “universale in praedicando” [“the universal in preaching”] is pres-
ent here just like the “universale in exemplando” [“. . . in providing examples”]
on the basis of its prophetic meaning, while the “universale in significando”
[“. . . in giving signs, i.e., warning”] is found in the general meaning of salva-
tion history. Through the metaphysical attribution of the facts of salvation
history to God, who is the universal cause of creation, or to Christ who is
the universal cause of redemption, theology can furthermore lay claim to
the “universale in causando” [“the universal in causing”], so that in its biblical
foundation, too, theology can now claim to be an Aristotelian science par
excellence, as sapientia in the sense explained in the Metaphysics I,1.137
135. Ibid., q.1 c.1 sol. (I, 2a). For a further development of the teaching about the practical or sa-
piential character of theology, see Amorós, “Teologia”; Niederbacher and Leibold, Theologie, 116–20.
136. Summa Hal. Tr. int. q.1 c.1 ad 1 (I, 2–3); see also Gössmann, Metaphysik, 18–19; Nieder-
bacher and Leibold, Theologie, 128.
137. Summa Hal. Tr. int. q.1 c.1 ad 2 (I, 3).
156 Theology as a Science at the University
The discussion of the object and method of theology shows how difficult
it is to balance this concept of theology as a science with biblical thinking
about salvation history. Depending on the perspective, the object of theol-
ogy is considered to be the work of redemption, Christ or God (divina sub-
stantia), so that theology can then be defined in a handy formula as “scien-
tia de substantia divina cognoscenda per Christum in opere reparationis” [“the
science of the divine substance which is to be known through Christ in the
work of reparation”].138 The Summa strikes a balance here between the defi-
nition of theology as sapientia as understood in the Metaphysics (substantia
divina), the Christocentrism of a Roland of Cremona and the definition of
theology in terms of salvation history along the lines of Hugh of St. Victor.
In the methodological treatise, finally, the current schemata from the theory
of science must be entirely abandoned. The “modus sacrae Scripturae” [the
“method of sacred Scripture”] does not follow the rules of an art or a sci-
ence. The reason for this, however, lies in the divine wisdom, which through
the Scriptures informs man about what is important for his salvation. Ulti-
mately theology is defined as knowledge about salvation on the basis of divine
instruction and thus exempt from the laws of methodology.139 It is moreover
an affective, practical discipline, to which the methods of the theoretical
sciences—namely definition, division, and syllogism—are not applicable.
Instead we find methods that are suited to the “affectus pietatis” [“devotion
of piety”], namely precept, example, admonition, revelation, prayer. The “pi-
etas” in question here, however, is “cultus Dei” [“the worship of God”].140 In a
Franciscan way, therefore, theology appears to be related here again to piety
and reverence for God, thus embedded in Franciscan religious life.
This affective element is expressed also in the discussion of the specifi-
cally theological certainty in comparison with the other sciences. Weighty
objections arise to a certainty that would be equivalent to that of the scienc-
es: the certainty of mere belief as opposed to intellectus [understanding], in-
sufficient perspicuity of the principles, the metaphorical and equivocal style
of Scripture. The Summa makes a fundamental distinction between affective
and intellectual certainty. Theology leads to greater affective [i.e., subjec-
tive] certainty than experience; on the other hand it lags behind empirical
138. Ibid., q.1 c.3 sol. (I, 6); see also Gössmann, Metaphysik, 25–26; Niederbacher and Leibold,
Theologie, 120–22.
139. Summa Hal. q.1 c.4 a.1 sol. (I, 8a); see also Gössmann, Metaphysik, 27–31; Niederbacher
and Leibold, Theologie, 122–27.
140. Summa Hal. q.1 c.4 a.1 ad 2 (I, 8b).
Theology as a Science at the University 157
evidence [Anschauungs-Evidenz] in intellectual certainty, since it is based
on faith alone.141 Therefore even in its principles theology is different from
the other sciences, namely the theoretical sciences. The latter are founded
on self-evident, true principles; theological principles, in contrast, have two
components: truth and goodness, and thus a theoretical and a practical ele-
ment. They are “principia veritatis ut bonitatis” [“principles of Truth consid-
ered as the Good”]. With regard to theoretical [speculative] truth they are
less evident than the principles of other sciences. With regard to practical
goodness, however, they are acknowledged to have the status of “principia
per se nota” [“self-evident principles”], namely, for moral conduct.142
Theology is described here with an unmistakably practical emphasis,
yet it is not just a moral philosophy; its supernatural element becomes ap-
parent in its divine origin: It is “a Deo et de Deo et ductiva ad Deum” [“from
God and about God and leads to God”].143 Now the other sciences come
from God (a Deo), too, but they are not conveyed in the same manner,
through divine inspiration as a gift of grace, which is why it is possible to
say formulaically that theology (doctrina sacra) comes from the Holy Spirit.
The truth in it is therefore a “bonum gratuitum” [“a gratuitous good,” i.e., a
grace], and this is precisely the basis for its practical certainty also, which
consequently should not be measured according to the standards of human
science. It is not concerned about God (de Deo) only in the metaphysical
sense, but rather in terms of the Triune God in his salvific work. It leads to
God (ad Deum) through the principles of fear and love, based on faith in
God’s mercy and justice.
Since theology (again in the sense of sacred Scripture) thus conveys a
practical certainty based on inspiration and a knowledge of the same sort,
the question arises as to the validity and necessity of theoretical attention to
the scientific status of theology itself. A certain discrepancy in the Summa
Halensis cannot be overlooked: the scientific character of theology is ini-
tially proved along Boethian lines with a concept of theology as understood
in the Metaphysics, while the Christian character of this theology and its
unique status and independence from all other sciences is supposed to be
explained then by a markedly affective, practical concept of theology found-
ed on sacred Scripture. The latter sort of theology, however, hardly corre-
sponds to the scientific concept from the Metaphysics and is largely exempt
141. Ibid., a.2 sol., ad 1 (I, 9). 142. Ibid., ad 2 (I, 9b).
143. Ibid., q.1 c.2 ad ob. (I, 5b).
158 Theology as a Science at the University
from the methodological claims of the theory of science. This “immunity”
is not so difficult to defend, inasmuch as the Franciscan theologians hark
back to the sapiential theology of the monastic and Victorine circles and
understand theology as sapientia [wisdom] and thus as something which in
principle surpasses every scientia [science, knowledge]. The fault lines in the
attempted equilibrium are all too plain.
158. Ibid., q.3 sol. (I, 13). 159. Ibid., q.2 sol. (I, 10–11).
160. See Köpf, Anfänge, 145–46.
161. Bonaventura, I Sent. prooem. q.2 ad 4 (I, 11); for the concept of theology as distinct from
sacra scriptura see also Donneaud, “Sens.”
162. Edition by Russo, Metodologia, 99–133.
164 Theology as a Science at the University
takes his program for theology from Hugh of St. Victor and is thus in good
Franciscan company. Theology is geared on the one hand to the human ef-
fort for certain knowledge (cognitio certitudinalis) but on the other hand to
living the faith in the three-step process of pietas, ratio, and veritas.163 Pietas
corresponds to faith, ratio to proof and consequently science, whereas truth
corresponds to contemplation. As a science, therefore, theology as a whole
has a mediating function; it is only a part—albeit an important one—of the
path leading from faith to the comprehension of the truth. Scientific knowl-
edge is ordered to the spiritual gift of understanding; faith, however, is or-
dered to virtue, and contemplation to blessedness. The knowledge sought
in scientific theology is a “cognitio collativa” [“comparative knowledge”]
and consists therefore increasingly in the compilation and comparison of
authorities and arguments.164 The theology which in the Augustinian tradi-
tion is viewed as insight into the faith is based on revelation and author-
ity, mediated or confirmed by Christ. Without enlightenment by Christ,
no one can penetrate the “sacramenta fidei” [“mysteries of faith”] (as Hugh
of St. Victor understands that expression), and thus be a theologian in the
true sense of the word.165 The nonbelieving theologian, as we find later
in the case of Ockham, is for Bonaventure still unthinkable. Christ, how-
ever, is also the center of Scripture, “fundamentum totius fidei christianae”
[“the foundation of all Christian faith”], of the teaching of the apostles and
prophets, of the Old and New Testaments.166
Bonaventure now significantly incorporates Aristotelian material into
his elaboration of the second step, the knowledge of reason, without deviat-
ing from his basic perspective. He lists the following requirements for scien-
tific knowledge: unchanging truth on the part of what is known, infallible
certainty on the part of the knower. According to the Posterior Analytics I,2,
however, necessity and certainty are found in the knowledge of causes. Nev-
ertheless, even in this Aristotelian interpretation of science, Christ is still
the “magister cognitionis” [“Master of knowledge”], for unchangeable truth
cannot be found in the realm of created truth. That is also why the Aristo-
telian interpretation is immediately supplemented and rendered harmless
by Augustine’s doctrine of the eternal truth about us. Indeed, according
to Augustine only the being of things “in ratione aeterna” [“in their eternal
form/aspect”] is unchangeable, that is, in the Word, in Christ. He alone is
163. Bonaventura, Serm. theol. IV, 1 (ed. Russo 100.8–12).
164. Ibid., (100.12–19). 165. Ibid., n.2–3 (100.21–102.44).
166. Ibid., n.5 (102.65–72).
Theology as a Science at the University 165
the medium of knowledge that makes things “perfecte scibiles” [“perfectly
knowable”].167 Natural, Aristotelian knowledge is therefore never a com-
plete, perfect knowledge of things. It is just as incapable of leading to the
certainty that is required for science. Certainty can be found only in the
“sapientia increata” [“Uncreated Wisdom”], Christ. Thereby Bonaventure
manages also to introduce long passages from the Augustinian theory of il-
lumination into his teaching about science. For without enlightenment by
Christ, the created intellect does not even arrive at sure knowledge of any
thing; how then could it ever attain certainty about theological truths?168
Natural knowledge is therefore deficient knowledge. It must in principle be
surpassed and requires a theological foundation. Theology proves therefore
to be the authority that legitimizes the “natural” sciences as well.169
Scientific theology in turn, however, is only one part of the way to wis-
dom, which is to be attained in contemplation. This too is at all points con-
nected with Christ in his divinity and humanity.170 The way to wisdom,
however, has only one order and one author who must be “read” here. The
order leads from faith via ratio to contemplation; the sancti (the saints, but
in the technical sense the Church Fathers), who are contrasted with the
philosophi (the pagan philosophers), knew this way. The latter are accused
of ignorance of the correct method, since they disregarded the foundation
of faith, relied on reason alone and thus were completely unable to attain
contemplation. Philosophy is therefore in principle a deficient mode of
knowledge. This is already a denial of a philosophy that is emancipated from
theology; it was later formulated even more forcefully starting in 1267 in the
fight against the heterodox currents within the faculty of the arts, in several
series of lectures: Collationes de decem praeceptis (1267), Collationes de donis
Spiritus sancti (1268) and so on until the Collationes in Hexaemeron (1273).
For philosophy does not know the “doctor et auctor” Christ, the “director et
adjutor nostrae intelligentiae” [“guide and help of our intellect”], whose spe-
cific direction is necessary for knowledge of the truth.171 God’s cooperation
in the knowledge of reason involves on the one hand the effort to know and
on the other hand the certainty of the object. Natural, a posteriori knowl-
edge retains its rights, though; it must however be combined in an Augus-
195. For the sources of this interpretation see Sileo, Teoria della scienza teologica II, 131–64.
196. William de la Mare, I Sent. q.1 sol. (13.39–64).
Theology as a Science at the University 173
er. Only from faith does understanding then follow. In the other sciences,
however, belief follows understanding. William maintains that both can
be admitted, that theology is therefore a law and also a science; his conclu-
sion should be interpreted in this sense: its scientific character should be
viewed only within the framework of its legal character. It does not produce
a new or a natural wisdom that is independent of the act of faith—not even
when it proceeds syllogistically.197 In clear contrast to the Summa Halensis,
the universality of the science is seen now in the moral application of indi-
vidual events as examples, and furthermore William denies that universal-
ity is necessary in order for theology to have a scientific character. For it is
precisely the business of the law to incite people to do good by presenting
individual good deeds and to discourage them from doing evil by decreeing
singular punishments. If theology is understood in this moral, prescriptive
sense, then universality is not required of its statements.198
The limited scientific character of theology within the framework of its
legal character results also in a solution to the question of whether it is a
theoretical or a practical science. Here Thomas is referred to directly, and
his solution is immediately rejected as null and void: “Sed hoc nihil est.” For
here Thomas is arguing not in terms of the immediate goal of science, but
rather from its more remote final end, the contemplation of God’s truth in
beatitude. Since our whole life and quest for knowledge is aimed at that,
however, this would make all sciences theoretical, so that there would be no
practical sciences at all. In any case one cannot define the meaning and task
of theology as Thomas tried to do.199 Science as a human activity must be
defined in terms of its immediate goal, not from the final end of human life
as a whole. Now William is unequivocally taking the legal character of the-
ology as his point of departure. Law, however, is a collection of precepts of
a practical nature, concerned with man’s conduct. Therefore if we can speak
about a scientific character of theology, then it must be within the frame-
work of this understanding. Consequently theology should be addressed
unequivocally as a practical science. Only in a subordinate clause does Wil-
liam mention the possible difference between the legal character of sacred
Scripture and the allegedly systematic, theoretical scientific character of the
book of Sentences. The Sentences are justified in principle only as an explana-
tion of sacred Scripture (expositoria) and thus of the law: systematic theol-
203. Ibid., q.3 a.1 sol. (24.258–25.280); concerning the discussion of the object of theology, see
de la Mare, “Einleitung” [Introduction], 51*–66*.
204. Ibid., q.3 a.2 sol. (27.344–28.364).
205. See Beumer, “Erleuchteter Glaube”; Kann, “Skepsis”; Speer, “Sapientia nostra,” 260–66.
206. Henry of Ghent, Summa quaestionum ordinariarum, P.I a.1 q.2 (facsimile reprint of the
1520 Paris edition, New York: St. Bonaventure, 1953), I f. 7r I.
207. Ibid. (I f. 7v M). 208. Ibid., I a.1 q.3 (I f. 8v–10v).
209. Ibid., I a.3 q.4 ad 2 (I f. 29v R).
176 Theology as a Science at the University
Anselm had defined it, but in a scientific manner: it should become “intel-
ligentia fidei” and therefore presupposes the faith at all points.210 It unfolds
in a three-step process:
1. The believing theologian assents to the truths that he derives immediate-
ly from sacred Scripture. These serve as premises of the further scientific
development.
2. F rom these premises he deduces further truths that are hidden in them
“sub primis scibilibus” [“beneath the first knowable truths”] and are not
explained immediately by the wording of Scripture.
3. As a theologian he tries to examine rationally all the truths that he previ-
ously adhered to only in faith.211
A definition of theology as a science on the basis of its method alone
therefore falls short, because it does not include the decisive step (3). This
step cannot be taken with faith and natural reason alone, but rather presup-
poses a special enlightenment in which the revealed truths of the faith be-
come intelligible [einsichtig]. The light of faith allows one to recognize only
the fact that the truths of the faith are true and it corresponds therefore to
knowledge of a given; the step to real insight into the coherence of what is
believed presupposes an illumination by grace that is somewhere between
faith and the beatific vision.212 Moreover, the syllogistic derivation of fur-
ther articles of faith from the initial truths of the faith is likewise possible
only on the basis of this supernatural, gratuitous enlightenment.213 The
work of theology is properly speaking an activity that owes its existence to
a twofold grace: the grace of faith and the special illumination that enables
one to understand the faith. The mere application of the Aristotelian, meth-
odological concept of science to theology therefore falls too short.
The solution proposed by Henry [of Ghent] with regard to the scientific
character of theology harks back to Bonaventure’s principle of the transi-
tion from credibilia [believable things] to intelligibilia [intelligible things].
At the same time Henry distinguishes between a broad concept of science
and a narrow one. In the broader sense every certain knowledge of a truth
should be treated as scientia.214 In this sense also the objects grasped by
218. Henry of Ghent, Summa I a.8 q.3 sol. (I f. 65v); see also Leone, “Zum Status.”
219. Ibid., ad 2 (I f. 65v); see also IST, ch. 1.1.4 and 2.8.
220. See Köpf, Anfänge, 207–8.
221. Henry of Ghent, Summa I a.7 q.13 (I f. 62r–63r).
Theology as a Science at the University 179
theological truth and the truth of natural knowledge is ruled out as a mat-
ter of principle. It is possible, of course, for a theological truth to be false
according to the personal judgment of a philosopher. In that case, never-
theless, the underlying problem is only an error of the philosopher, who
considers false anything that surpasses his ability to know. In themselves,
however, philosophical and theological truth cannot contradict; instead
philosophical truth is claimed as a guide and preliminary step to theology.
Therefore a theologian who out of ignorance of philosophy considers to
be false many things that have in fact been proved true philosophically is
rash (temerarius). Truth that has been proved philosophically, however, in
no way diminishes the status of theology, since the latter owes its scientific
character not to any human effort but rather to divine enlightenment.
182
Theological Controversy and Church Reform 183
demnations of 1277, Oxford gained preeminence.2 Now the decisive philo-
sophical and theological innovations generally came from England, such as
those connected with the names Duns Scotus (ca. 1265–1308) and William
of Ockham (ca. 1285–1347). They were welcomed in Paris with vehement
controversy. Oxford, however, was also the source of John Wycliffe’s theses
concerning theology and church polity, which fell on more fertile soil at the
new University of Prague.
Paris, however, rose to the occasion of the ecclesiastical controversies
of the late Middle Ages and became the most important ecclesiastical advi-
sory authority; debated questions that were to be officially decided by the
pope and the Curia were referred to magistri in Paris for a provisional theo-
logical decision (doctrinalis determinatio praevia).3 Prime examples were
the Immaculate Conception of Mary (1387), the theoretical debate about
poverty and the controversy with the Franciscan groups (especially the
Fraticelli) inspired by the teachings of Joachim of Fiore.4 Luther, too, would
appeal to the university against the pope. The Western Schism (1378) at first
had a debilitating effect on theology at the University of Paris but on the
whole strengthened its position; all but a minority of the Parisian magistri
professed obedience to Avignon, while at the same time the university be-
came the seedbed of anti-papal tendencies that favored a national Church.5
Yet the decisive models for overcoming the schism were supposed to come
from Paris (of all places), where initially the “via cessionis” [“way of resigna-
tion”] without a general council was the preferred solution. However, Peter
of Ailly (1352–1420) and John Gerson (1363–1429), the leading figures in the
reform movement in Pisa and Constance, were Parisian theologians, too.6
The theological university scene, nevertheless, was drastically changed
by the founding of new universities in the fourteenth and fifteenth centu-
ries. In the territory of the Holy Roman Empire alone, nineteen university
foundations were registered between 1347 (Prague) and 1502 (Wittenberg).7
Sometimes in implementing the plan of the founder (emperor, prince, city,
bishop) there were considerable delays before instruction actually began.
During the Western Schism the obedience [i.e., confessional allegiance] in
logne (1388), Würzburg (1402), Leipzig (1409), Rostock (1419), Louvain/Leuven (1425), Trier
(1454), Greifswald (1456), Freiburg im Breisgau (1455/56), Basel (1459), Ingolstadt (1459), Mainz
(1476), Tübingen (1476/77), Frankfurt an der Oder (1500/06), Wittenberg (1502).
8. See Swanson, Universities, 216–17: List of universities approved by the popes from 1374–1418.
9. See Sturlese, Philosophie, 324–26.
10. See, for example, Uiblein, “Beziehungen”; Gabriel, “Via Antiqua.”
11. See Oediger, Bildung.
Theological Controversy and Church Reform 185
many respects however was changing. First we should distinguish between
the cursory “lectura textualis” [textual reading] of the baccaleureus [bachelor]
and the work of the magister [master], which has been preserved most often
in the form of questions pertaining to the Sentences. Both forms of instruc-
tion dispense to a large extent with the Lombard’s text. Instead an abridged
version was taken as the textual basis, sometimes even in the “lectura.”12 At
any rate, questions are already incorporated in the introductory lectures at
important passages. In contrast, the Quaestiones in Libros Sententiarum dis-
pense with all reference to the text and now systematically discuss the in-
dividual questions that are important in a given context without regard for
completeness. Thus Heinrich Totting of Oyta (ca. 1330–1397) discusses ten
questions on book 1 of the Sentences but only one apiece for the rest. That
alone shows the overemphasis given here to the philosophical problems of
the doctrine about God. In contrast to the simple form of the quaestio in
Thomas’ writings, its structure had already changed in the works of Henry
of Ghent (ca. 1217–1293) and even more markedly from Ockham on. The
general arguments pro and con carry much less weight than the extensive
discussion (sometimes subdivided into quaestiunculae) of the contemporary
opiniones, citing and sometimes refuting the arguments that support them.13
Just as scholars often were acquainted with the Lombard’s text only from
abridgments, the university teachers themselves likewise wrote abbreviations
of important commentaries on the Sentences, especially at the new universi-
ties, which were not yet endowed with libraries. So, for example, an abbrevia-
tion of the commentary on the Sentences by the Franciscan Adam Woodham
(or Goddam, ca. 1298–1358) is attributed to Heinrich Totting of Oyta.14 The
Scholastic masterpiece of Gabriel Biel (ca. 1410–1495) was his Collectorium,
which closely follows Ockham’s commentary on the Sentences, while of course
borrowing also from other authors for the purpose of revision.15
The explanation of Scripture, which was per se still the province of the
magister, was carried out in a twofold course, like the lectures on the Sentences:
first the “lectura textualis,” the cursory reading by the baccalaureus, and then
the exposition by the magister, which was usually restricted to just one book or
a few chapters; the text again became merely the occasion for an independent
12. Thus Heinrich Totting of Oyta used the abbreviation “Quoniam velut quattuor flumina para-
disi” attributed to Hugh of St. Cher; see also Lang, Heinrich Totting, 50–53.
13. See Rentsch, “Kultur der quaestio,” 88–89.
14. Lang, Heinrich Totting, 54–61.
15. Gabriel Biel, Collectorium circa quattuor libros Sententiarum, praef., ed. W. Werbeck/U. Hof-
mann (Tübingen, 1973), 1:6–7.
186 Theological Controversy and Church Reform
discussion of questions. Heinrich of Langenstein (1325–1397) during his thir-
teen years of teaching in Vienna did not get past the first three chapters of the
book of Genesis.16 Francis of Retz († 1421) took the Proverbs as his text and
within that context discussed all the current theological questions; Heinrich
Totting did the same with the Psalms (1–50). Thus, for example, at Psalm 21
Christological questions are considered (the separation of Christ’s divinity
from his body and soul at his death) as well as the permissibility of casting
lots and of praying to God for temporal goods, but also whether the priest
must refuse Communion to a sinner even if his sin is not publicly known.17
In the following period these questions were not infrequently detached from
the commentary and handed down independently in manuscripts.
This practice of abbreviating older works leads us also to the first com-
mentaries on the Summa Theologiae and the Summa contra Gentiles by Thom-
as Aquinas.18 Outside of the Dominican Order, however, the works of Aqui-
nas did not yet belong to the official literary canon in the faculty of theology.
Even in the order they served as a doctrinal plumb line rather than as the basis
for instruction. We find a collection of questions on the S.Th. for university
use in the Compendium Summae Theologiae by Heinrich of Gorkum († 1431
as a professor in Cologne).19 As Gabriel Biel does with Ockham, Heinrich of
Gorkum presents questions that correspond thematically but not textually to
the contents of the S.Th. His student Johannes Tinctoris († 1496) wrote the
first non-Dominican commentary on the S.Th., which he probably compiled
as part of a teaching assignment. From Cologne the interpretation of Thomas
by magistri traveled to Vienna, where the Dominican Leonhard Huntpichler
(† 1478) expounded the S.Th. for the first time; in 1490 we find lectures on it in
Freiburg and Rostock, while the great commentaries of Cardinal Cajetan date
from 1497 on. In Paris Peter Crockaert, O.P. († 1514) was the first to lecture
on Thomas in 1507. His student Francisco de Vitoria (1483/93–1546) brought
this practice to Salamanca and thus inaugurated the Thomist commentaries
of Spanish Scholasticism in the early modern period.20 We owe an early com-
mentary on the Summa contra Gentiles to the Viennese Dominican Johannes
Werd († 1510).21
1.2 Formation of schools and the dispute about the two ways
The opponents of Scholastic philosophy in the early modern period
were fond of characterizing it as “philosophia sectaria” because it was said
to be slavishly bound up with a particular doctrinal tendency or “school.”23
The historical phenomenon of the formation of more or less fixed doctri-
nal traditions, often independent of localities but usually connected with
religious communities, takes us back to the condemnations of 1277. Since
both Avicenna and Averroës, both Aristotle and Thomas Aquinas were af-
fected by them, now the Franciscans especially sought to consolidate their
position by turning decidedly to Augustine.24 This was already becoming
clear in William de la Mare’s concept of theology, but also in the works of
the secular priest Henry of Ghent and the Augustinian friar Ægidius Roma-
nus. Besides the antagonism between religious orders [Ordensgegensatz],
another important factor in the development of the late Scholastic schools
was the difference between the doctrinal traditions at Paris and Oxford, as
we encounter it in the critique by Roger Bacon. Thus it was the Dominican
Robert Kilwardby who in 1277 as Archbishop of Canterbury pronounced
the first ruling that pertained to Oxford, condemning sixteen propositions
of Thomistic philosophy; his arguments were taken up again by the Francis-
can John Peckham (ca. 1230–1291) in 1284 and 1286.25 The decisive moment
for the first phase in the formation of schools, however, was the so-called
43. See the detailed discussion in Oberman, Werden und Wertung, 4–140.
44. See Oberman, Spätscholastik.
45. See Gabriel, “Via antiqua,” 476–81; Knuuttila, “Trutfetter.”
Theological Controversy and Church Reform 193
to the via antiqua in 1425. In Heidelberg it appeared quite plainly as a re-
form movement in opposition to the via moderna, and the students demon-
strated against it because they wanted to stay with the old doctrinal habits
of the moderni.46 These facts clearly testify that the “dispute about the ways”
had nothing to do with modernity or conservatism above and beyond the
contrasting doctrines about universals.
A decisive catalyst for fifteenth-century theology, however, was the reviv-
al of Augustinian theology, in particular of its anti-Pelagian doctrine of grace;
in the fourteenth century Thomas Bradwardine († 1349) and Gregory of
Rimini provided important impetus to this development. Bradwardine’s re-
turn to Augustine to argue against the Pelagiani moderni went on to influence
Wycliffe, although we can hardly speak about a special “via Bradwardini.”47
In a way typical of theology on the eve of the Reformation, both theologians
interpreted Augustine’s anti-Pelagianism so as to counteract the late Medi-
eval pious practices that suggested justification by works, but also to refute
the speculation of “Nominalist” theology about power [Macht] and grace in
terms of an “assurance of salvation” or, in the writings of Johann von Staupitz,
even of a “claim to salvation.” The edition of Augustine’s works (Basel 1506)
organized by Johannes Amerbach (ca. 1443–1513) then made the thought of
this Father of the Church accessible almost in its entirety.48
49. See Leff, Heresy, 2:494–558; Robson, Wyclif; Lambert, Heresy, 225–42.
50. Concerning the treatise De Ydeis, see Robson, Wyclif, 171–95.
51. Ibid., 164.
52. See Leff, Bradwardine; Leppin, Theologie, 148–51.
53. See Leff, Heresy, 516–46.
Theological Controversy and Church Reform 195
positions of grace. Taken together, however, these theoretical-Scholastic
elements of Wycliffe’s theology did not yet necessarily result in that thrust
which later led to his condemnation (1377; 1381/82; 1407 and 1411) and his
association with the revolutionary social movement of the Lollards. His con-
demnation and departure from Oxford in 1381 also had another immediately
theological, Scholastic cause: his rejection of the doctrine of transubstantia-
tion as a contradiction to the teaching of the early Church.54
The combination of the scriptural principle and the Augustinian under-
standing of the Church, however, produced those teachings that brought
Wycliffe into conflict with Church teaching and practice. Once again it
was actually a conservative program of reform that incorporated Francis-
can initiatives and a vision of life in the early Church, especially in its re-
jection of worldly property and secular power (De civili dominio). His spiri-
tual understanding of the Church led him to reject the hierarchy, precisely
with respect to the Western Schism: God alone elects the pope from the
Church of the predestined and for it; who that is cannot be known with-
out a special revelation. In the Schism, ultimately, both popes appeared as
Antichrist.55 In this understanding of the Church, of course, the power to
bind and loose belongs to God alone, and not to the pope or the priests.
Whereas the Nominalists had guaranteed some role for secondary causes in
the work of salvation (albeit one that could be dispensed with at any time),
they are completely ruled out here: just as God’s knowledge is absolutely
necessary, so too is his action; anything above and beyond the revelation in
sacred Scripture must be dismissed, even if a precept or an article of faith
were pronounced by an angel.56 It is quite a different matter, though, with
the office of the king, which is divinely established. Yet even the king, who
by virtue of his office is “vicarius dei” [“God’s vicar”], is in principle “frater
noster” [“our brother”].57 Although it is not very consistent with his theo-
logical approach, Wycliffe also concedes to the king far-reaching rights over
the visible Church, including the right to confiscate Church property and to
convert church buildings into fortresses.
His step from the professorial chair at Oxford to the heretical move-
54. Wycliffe, De eucharistia, ed. J. Loshert (1886), in John Wyclif, Latin Works (New York, re-
printed 1966), vol. 12; see also Leff, Heresy, 549–57; Lambert, Heresy, 243–83.
55. Wyclif, De potestate pape, ed. J. Loshert (1907), in Latin Works, 19:185; see also Leff, Heresy,
530–33.
56. Wyclif, De potestate, in Latin Works, 19:259.
57. Wyclif, De officio regis, ed. A. W. Pollard/C. Sayle (1887), in Latin Works, 4:4.
196 Theological Controversy and Church Reform
ment of the Lollards was based on the fact that both rejected papal author-
ity and the contemporary Church with its secular power and property. The
transformation of Wycliffe’s theology into political agitation was manifested
for the first time in the Farmers’ Uprising of 1381; consequently, of course,
one could now suspect that Wycliffe’s influence was behind all disturban-
ces.58 The controversies of the Lollards at Oxford (Blackfriars 1382) con-
cerned what was still in part a university movement, which was supposed to
be quelled once again according to academic custom by the condemnation
of Wycliffe’s followers and their expulsion from the university. The popu-
larization of Wycliffe’s teachings in Lollard circles led on the one hand to
their reformulation as brief theses for the purpose of easier comprehensi-
bility and on the other hand to the production of works ascribed to their
theological forefather.59
Less genuinely philosophical in his mindset yet in agreement with
Wycliffe’s realism was the magister from Prague, Jan Hus, whose condemna-
tion and burning at the stake by the Council of Constance would lead to the
most radical disturbances of the fifteenth century.60 Hus’s influential teacher
Stanislaus of Znaim († 1413) had already tried to reconcile Wycliffe with of-
ficial Church doctrine.61 In his academic theology, Hus himself presents the
picture of a none-too-independent theologian of the via antiqua, especially
in his Commentary on the Sentences (1407–1409).62 Typical here of the
later Wycliffe, of course, is his concept of Church as “universitas praedestina-
torum” [“the company of the predestined”]. A predestined soul, however, is
someone who really lives a Christian life; therefore the true Church is the
communion of real Christians, of good Christians. As in Wycliffe, the cata-
lyst of the Hussite movement was found here in its spiritualized concept of
Church. Furthermore Hus, too, had an understanding of the Eucharist that
was rather unclear yet deviated from the doctrine of transubstantiation.63
Wycliffe had had a much greater influence on Hus’s teachers, Stanislaus of
58. Concerning the Lollards, see: Leff, Heresy, 559–605; Lambert, Heresy, 243–83.
59. See Leff, Heresy, 574–77; especially the 25 articles of 1388.
60. See Herold, Pražká Univerzita; for a critical review of the ideological interpretations of
Wycliffe’s influence on the “early bourgeois revolution” in the case of Hus and afterwards, see:
Sousedík, “Wyclif und Böhmen,” with bibliography. On Hus and the situation in Bohemia, see also
Lambert, Heresy, 284–348; Seibt, ed., Jan Hus.
61. Stanislaus de Znoyma, De gracia et peccato, ed. Zuzanna Silagiová (Fontes Latini Bohemo-
rum 1) (Prague, 1997), Introduction xxvi–xxvii.
62. Magistri Joannis Hus, Super IV libros Sententiarum in Opera omnia, ed. W. Flajšhans/M.
Komínková (Prague, 1903–1907), vol. II. See esp. De Vooght, Hérésie, 60–84.
63. See Sousedík, “Huss”; Kolesnyk, “Hussens Eucharistiebegriff.”
Theological Controversy and Church Reform 197
Znaim and Stephan Páleč (ca. 1370–1424), who were therefore accused in
Rome in 1407/08 and forced to recant.64 While the university theologian
Jan Hus was to a great extent orthodox in his teaching, above all what mat-
tered for the Hussite Reformation was his preaching, but also the tensions
between the German majority and the Czech minority at the university. Af-
ter the attempt by King Wenceslaus to crush the German majority, these
tensions led in 1409 to the departure of the German professors and students
for Leipzig. This left Jan Hus and Jerome of Prague († 1416) as the represen-
tatives of the now-Czech faculty of theology.65
In his preaching ministry at “Bethlehem” (as opposed to his university
sermons, even in the vernacular), Hus aligned himself with the moralizing
reformer’s theology of Konrad of Waldhausen (ca. 1325–1369, in Prague from
1360 on) and Jan Milič of Kremsier (ca. 1325–1374), both of whom were not
so much theologians as clergymen concerned about practical reform in the
Church.66 It was precisely their abandonment of the Scholastic distinctions
in their teaching about sin and grace and their black-and-white depiction of
issues, for example, with regard to God’s judgment of sinners, which pro-
duced the effect that a reform sermon ought to have. The luxury, greed, and
simony of Church rulers were standard themes. Hus’s spiritualist concept
of the Church was evident here especially in the contrast between the real
Church (universitas of good Christians = the predestined) and the existing,
corrupt institutional Church, with a marked devaluation of ecclesiastical in-
stitutions and human laws in favor of immediate contact with Christ, who
is Life, by his grace and by obedience to God’s Word. Thus the established
Church during the Great Schism necessarily appeared not as a way of salva-
tion but as an obstacle to it.
Hus’s conflict with the Church was, after all, of a more practical than
genuinely theological nature. This is clearly evident in his treatise De Eccle-
sia from the year 1413 and the polemical works that followed, aimed now
directly at the practices of the antipope John XXIII (reigned 1410–1415).67
Here too his theology, insofar as it concerns the forgiveness of sins and ec-
clesial obedience, is still thoroughly Catholic. Given the contemporary situ-
ation, however, even such a theology must have seemed provocative when
This excerpt shows that Hus is taking aim at Scholastically trained cler-
ics, who have mastered the technique of glossing uncomfortable passages of
Scripture as well as logic; for the devil, “sophista pessimus” [“the worst Soph-
ist”] leads them astray to this false conclusion: that Christ gave this authority
(the power of the keys) to Peter and the other Apostles; therefore to us; con-
sequently we can do what we want. They erroneously consider it equally self-
evident that they will attain blessedness and rule with Christ when he comes
again. These “powers of darkness” are contrasted with the true believers who
possess the “potestas predestinacionis” [“power of predestination”]; therefore
the “veraces christicole” [“true worshippers of Christ”] must, if need be, resist
the power of the institutional Church when it tries to keep them by force or
deceit from imitating Christ.69 Resistance is not offered here to God’s com-
mand but only to the abuse of authority, especially by simoniac priests; Hus
goes on to prove in great detail that they are the real heretics. In doing so
Hus also expressly vindicates the opinion of Stephan Páleč and Stanislaus of
Znaim “de clero pestifero” [“concerning the pestilential clergy”].70 The very
fact that the treatise De ecclesia proceeds by the logical argumentation of a
formal debate shows that Hus’s plea for a reform of the Church cannot be
separated from his academic activity; on the contrary, Church reform has
become here the object of academic theology, which of course has left the
narrow confines of the lecture hall; for this treatise was read aloud not at the
68. Ibid. (91); see also Liguš, “Schriftbegriff.”
69. Ibid. (92).
70. Ibid. (95).
Theological Controversy and Church Reform 199
university but rather in “Bethlehem.” This combination of academic and ref-
ormational activity anticipates Luther, who in 1520 after reading De ecclesia
declared: “Breviter: sumus omnes Hussitae. Denique Paulus et Augustinus ad
verbum sunt Hussitae.” [“In short: we are all Hussites. Finally Paul and Augus-
tine, read literally, are Hussites.”]71
76. Ibid., 2:26–27; see also Contra curiositatem studentium II (Glorieux, 3:242).
77. Ed. Glorieux, 2:28.
78. Ed. Glorieux, 3:333–40.
Theological Controversy and Church Reform 201
5. A theological proposition that is correct in the logical sense must be
disavowed if it is false in the literal sense, offensive or morally doubtful.
6. Th
e literal sense was first revealed through Christ and the Apostles, il-
lustrated by miracles, corroborated by martyrs, explained and defended
(along with the conclusions drawn from it) by the Church Fathers and
defined by the Councils. Appropriate punishments have been prescribed
by the ecclesiastical authorities for transgressions of these norms.
7. If the literal sense is attacked when it has already been defined by the
Church, one should therefore proceed against the challengers not with
academic disputations (curiosis ratiocinationibus) but rather with the ap-
propriate punishments.
8. If the literal sense has been defined by decrees, decretals or at councils, it is
just as much a part of theology and sacred Scripture as the Apostles Creed.
9. Although the literal sense is sufficiently clear in Scripture itself or has
been explained by the work of scholars, it can be proclaimed “compen-
diose” [“summarily”] in a few articles separately (e.g., as a profession of
faith), especially in view of the uneducated and differences of opinion.
10. The literal sense is interpreted reasonably in theological houses of
study [affiliated with Generalates of religious orders], in other dioceses
or by means of consultation with a concilium [advisory council] of
local theologians.
11. A nyone who denies an interpretation that has been defined as biblical by
the bishop (or the bishop together with a concilium doctorum) should be
punished and obliged to recant.
12. If someone maintains that the literal sense is not true and proceeds to
oppose it in word and deed, this gives rise to the urgent suspicion of
heresy, more precisely, of incorrigibility and obstinacy in an error of
intellect and will.
The impression of purely positive ecclesiality given by this list should be
viewed within the context of the goal that Gerson is trying to attain with this
decidedly biblical and ecclesial alignment of theology as a whole.79 Theol-
ogy should again serve the purpose of human life, eternal salvation, for man
aspires to God as his natural center and place of rest. This is where certainty
can be found with regard to Scholastic disputes and the insecurity of theo-
logical knowledge.80 Therefore theology must immediately become a bib-
90. Clm 18364; cited by Lang, Wege der Glaubensbegründung, 231–35; on its influence, see 225–37.
Theological Controversy and Church Reform 205
taught in Vienna in 1383/84.91 Besides his activities at the university and in
ecclesiastical politics during the Western Schism, there is a decidedly pas-
toral emphasis in his writings. The biblical foundation for his theology is
evident in his Viennese Commentary on Genesis (chapters 1–3 only) and his
work De idiomate hebraico, which underscores the importance of the biblical
languages for the study of theology. Heinrich himself had learned Hebrew
in Paris and Vienna from baptized Jews. In his theology Heinrich brings to
bear an eclectic variation of the via moderna which borrows especially from
Gregory of Rimini and thereby, like Heinrich Totting, avoids objectionable
or radical theses.92
Heinrich’s pastoral and ascetical writings, however, were the most wide-
ly circulated.93 He gave the secular priests in his benefice of Grossrussbach
precise instructions about how to teach catechism to the children in the
parish. Above all they should teach them the correct wording and under-
standing of the Our Father, the Hail Mary, and the Creed (in German).94
Earlier in 1380, Langenstein himself had given a “Lectura super Pater noster”
in Paris.95 Other works by Heinrich that were translated into German in-
cluded his treatise “On the discernment of spirits” (the Latin text of which
has been lost) and his “Quaestio on the temptations of the devil and helps
against them.” The latter had a long and influential textual tradition.96 This
very quaestio is well suited to illustrate the step from university to pastoral
theology and from the Latin original to the German translation. The ques-
tion is situated, moreover, within the context of the late Medieval belief in
the devil and demons, although it by no means supports it. The main source
for the quaestio on temptations is De virtutibus by William of Auvergne,
whose outline is still applied here. Quantifying the temptations and rem-
edies was a favorite schema of the period. Thus Gerson describes fifty-eight
temptations of the devil in De diversis diaboli tentationibus alone.97 Lan-
genstein’s quaestio, however, proves to be a university lesson, not pastoral
91. About his life see Kreuzer, Heinrich von Langenstein.—Heinrich von Langenstein, Der Sen-
tenzenkommentar, ed. R. Damerau (Studien zu den Grundlagen der Reformation 15–18) (Marburg,
1979/80).
92. See Lang, Christologie.
93. Heinrich von Langenstein, Erchantnuzz der sund, ed. R. Rudolf. (Texte des späten Mittelal-
ters und der frühen Neuzeit 22) (Berlin, 1969). The authenticity of this work is disputed because of
its vocabulary by Wiesinger, “Autorschaft.”
94. Clm 17645, fol. 125va–126r; see also Kreuzer, Heinrich von Langenstein, 146.
95. See Kreuzer, Heinrich von Langenstein, 105.
96. Synoptic edition: Hohmann, Langenstein; see also Hämmerl, Welt, 151–62.
97. Ed. Glorieux, 7:343–60; see also Grosse, Heilsungewissheit, 8–44.
206 Theological Controversy and Church Reform
instruction: “Quaestio magistralis de temptatione diaboli.”98 The translation,
which presumably was done by a clerical courtier for a lady at the ducal
court,99 already deviates from the original Latin quaestio in the fact that it
does not adopt its precise formulation of the question or the main argu-
ments. The questions are still framed in a purely scientific, theological man-
ner: Can a man on the earthly pilgrimage be led astray by the devil through
deceit and cunning? Even the general distinctions among temptations
(temptatio probativa/pulsativa, [i.e., a temptation that tests/impels one] to
perform or omit an action) and their subdivisions are missing. On the other
hand the translation expands on the text, sometimes with citations from
Augustine, but also with rather colorful comparisons that have no place in
a Scholastic quaestio.100 The translation begins immediately with the four
aims of the devil’s temptations: mortal sin, schism and heresy, error in hu-
man sciences, superstition. The quantifying continues: The devil, presented
as magister of antitheology, tries to prove his conclusions contrary to ours,
and he opposes the Ten Commandments with the seven capital sins and
the twelve (or fourteen) articles of faith with his own theses, resulting in
either nineteen or twenty-one conclusions.101 The basic framework of the
quaestio is provided however by the seven temptations of the devil accord-
ing to William of Auvergne:
1. Wearing the sinner down or tormenting him with a [particular] sin,
2. The unusual or marvelous character of the object,
3. Temptation to change one’s state of life,
4. Counsel to seek goods that are unattainable for human weakness,
5. Counsel to run a risk for the sake of a supposed good,
6. Recommendation of a vice under the guise of virtue,
7. Complete peace and the cessation of temptations 1 through 6.102
98. Vienna, Schottenstift Codex 128 fol. 204va; Cod. 326, 300v; on the question of authorship,
see also Hohmann, Langenstein, 151–57.
99. Cf., Hohmann, 157–58; inferred from Schottenstift Codex III, 4–7 (181/183): “dye ich hye
durich dye sunder lieb, dye ich hab zu ewrem ewigen hayll, wirdigew fraw, vmb dye lieb, dy ir mir habt
erczaigt, yn dewczsch hab geschriben, das ir euch dester pas chündt halten gegen dem selbem.” [“which
(instruction), for the love of sinners that I have unto your eternal salvation, Honorable Lady, and
for the sake of the love that you have shown me, I have written in German, so that you may all the
more suitably be informed and armed against it (i.e., temptation).”]
100. For example, Schottenstift Codex III, 45–85 (185–87): Just as the fisherman lures the fish
from their spawning place so as to catch them in his net, so the Devil lures men from their state in
life (laymen, priests, bishops).
101. Hohmann, Langenstein, 178.17–20.
102. Ibid., 180–94.
Theological Controversy and Church Reform 207
Finally, besides the threefold remedy that every virtue offers against
temptations, namely in considering the value of the virtue itself (proprio
gladio), in contrasting it with the vice (gladio alieno) and in fleeing from the
missiles of the Evil One, sixteen remedies taken from William of Auvergne
are listed.103 This produces an impressive and easily remembered outline of
good and evil with which to apply Scholastic teaching to the needs of prac-
tical spiritual direction.
114. Duns Scotus, In I Sent., prol. q.1 (edition consulted: Johannes Duns Scotus, Über die
Erkennbarkeit Gottes. Texte zur Philosophie und Theologie, lateinisch-deutsch, hg. u. übers. von
Hans Kraml, Gerhard Leibold, Vladimir Richter, Hamburg 2000, 4–20; as interpreted by Richter,
“Textstudien,” 439–45; see also Leibold, “Kontroverse.”
212 Theological Controversy and Church Reform
beatitude (fruitio Dei, the enjoyment of God) is after all the end of activity,
not of theoretical knowledge.115
Our theological knowledge therefore is subject to a twofold arrange-
ment, the individual elements of which would not infrequently be played
off against each other in subsequent periods:
1. This knowledge is partial and not comprehensive, obscure and not clear,
in accordance with the free, contingent revelation of God.
2. I t is nevertheless sufficient for practical action with regard to man’s
supernatural end.
The question of theological certainty and truth is therefore, to Duns
Scotus’ way of thinking, an immediately practical and existential question:
How can theology provide the certainty that I must presuppose if my life is
to be meaningful with respect to its ultimate success or failure? Duns Scotus
still succeeds in considering both partial aspects at the same time. This is
evident especially in the question about the object (subjectum) of theology.
The central object of a science is that which cannot be attributed to some-
thing else, the thing in terms of which virtually all the propositions of that
science can be asserted. Perfect theological knowledge, by its very nature,
is possessed by God alone, for only God knows himself perfectly. In this
knowledge of God all theological truths are virtually contained and verified.
Theological knowledge therefore has as its central object God, not in some
relation or other to his work (e.g., as Creator or Redeemer), but not in the
philosophical-metaphysical definition of him as ens [Being] or ens infinitum,
either, but rather in his nature [Wesen], in which all of these relations are
included (as theological truths).116
If theological knowledge is to attain the certainty required for action
and at the same time declare in accordance with the truth what it is possible
for us to say about God, then it must be proved in the first place that an un-
equivocal discourse about God is possible. God’s existence and action must
be recognizable for us and describable in precise language.117 This is the
theoretical-scientific background for the doctrine of the univocal charac-
ter of being, which is inseparably connected with Scotus’ name. It is aimed
115. Duns Scotus, In I Sent., prol. q.3 (Scotus, Erkennbarkeit, 28–43); see also the interpretation
by Richter, “Duns Scotus’ Text zur Theologie,” 465–75.
116. Duns Scotus, prol. q.2 (Scotus, Erkennbarkeit, 20–28); see also the interpretation by Rich-
ter, “Textstudien,” 445–49.
117. On the problem of proving the existence of God, see Richter, Studien, 30–78.
Theological Controversy and Church Reform 213
especially against Henry of Ghent, whose opinion Scotus summarizes in
three conclusions:118
1. God cannot be known “per se” but only “per accidens,” that is, only his
attributes can be known.
2. G od can be known “in universali,” that is, in a general concept that can be
predicated about several things, but only by an analogous concept, not
by strict, univocal predication.
3. God cannot be known “in particulari,” in his proper individuality,
because a creature is only a “peregrina similitudo” [“passing, distant like-
ness”] of God and allows us to infer only some of God’s attributes.
Duns Scotus sees that as an invalidation of any precise theological
knowledge and of its claim to truth. His critique takes language, the propo-
sition, as its point of departure. Attributes (e.g., “sapiens”) are predicated of
a subject and therefore presuppose some knowledge about what the subject
is (quidditative, “with respect to its what-ness”). This is true also for knowl-
edge about God, if theological discourse is to obey the rules of grammar.
As Henry of Ghent correctly observes, our knowledge does not arrive at an
understanding of God’s nature, of how he is in himself, but for other reasons
than Henry supposes. God is knowable in this way for himself alone; for all
others he is knowable only as a freely chosen object of cognition. Here, at
any rate, the creature’s likeness to God is no reason to assume that it pro-
vides particularly accurate or inaccurate knowledge about him.
That requires, rather, that a concept be constituted in such a way that
one can predicate univocally with it, so that it becomes possible to formu-
late propositions with truth value and thus to construct correct syllogisms
(without quaternio terminorum, a set of four terms yielding no real conclu-
sion).119 This is not the case, however, with a merely analogous concept, but
only with a univocal concept. In order to form such a concept about God it
suffices that the predication be unambiguous and that it be possible to as-
118. See Richter, “Univozität”; about Henry of Ghent, see also Aertsen, “Von Gott kann man
nichts erkennen,” 30–36.
119. Duns Scotus, In I Sent. dist.3 q. 1 (Duns Scotus, Erkennbarkeit, 98, 5–10): “Conceptum uni-
vocum dico qui ita est unus quod eius unitas sufficit ad contradictionem, affirmando et negando ipsum de
eodem. Sufficit etiam pro medio syllogistico ut extrema unita in medio sic uno sine fallacia aequivocationis
concludantur inter se uniri.” [“I call univocal a concept which is ‘one’ is such a way that its unity suf-
fices to formulate a contradiction by affirming and denying it about the same thing. It suffices also
as a syllogistic middle term or mean, so that we may conclude that the extremes which are united
in the mean that is ‘one’ in this way are united to each other without any fallacy of equivocation.”]
214 Theological Controversy and Church Reform
sign a precise content to the concept, although that by no means solves all
further questions. Of course, the predication as such (and consequently the
concept) cannot be certain and dubious at the same time. It suffices, there-
fore, to speak about God as ens [being], without yet having determined
whether this ens is finite or infinite. Only on this basis will a philosophical
discussion about God be meaningful, because there is a common object of
discourse, whereas the analogy of concepts in Henry of Ghent eliminates
precise, common discourse and consequently abolishes theology as a sci-
ence. Someone might just as well claim that “man” cannot be predicated
in the same way of Socrates and Plato, that there are instead two concepts
here, which appear to be one because of their great similarity. With that,
however, all univocal predication, the foundation of scientific discourse,
is abolished. We must take as the epistemological source of theology not
just any vague (ontological) similarity, but rather the successful predication
that is presupposed by human speech acts. This guarantees that our theol-
ogy, though partial, is nevertheless sufficient to make our actions ultimately
meaningful.
120. See esp. Möhle, Formalitas, 25–27; also Roth, Franz von Mayronis; in places corrected by:
Rossmann, Hierarchie.
121. Edition used: Franciscus de Mayronis, In Libros Sententiarum, Quodlibeta, Tractatus For-
malitatum, De Primo Principio, Terminorum Theologicalium Declarationes, De Univocatione (Venice,
Theological Controversy and Church Reform 215
Francis also illustrates quite clearly the debate among the Parisian schools:
Dominican Thomists against Franciscan Scotists along with eclectics and a
few independent theologians like Peter Aureol (ca. 1280–1322). This debate
can be followed literarily in the Disputatio collativa by Petrus Rogerii [Pierre
Roger], OSB (1292–1352, later Clement VI), which he conducted with Francis
of Meyronnes in 1320/21 as a baccalaureus in Paris.122 The disputed points may
seem “typically Scholastic” to the modern reader: Whether the principle of
contradiction can be established in theology; whether the divine essence de
potentia dei absoluta can be contemplated without the Divine Persons; wheth-
er a real distinction can be made between the creaturely status by which a
creature is dependent on God and the creature itself; whether in the order of
origin an angel was created by the Father earlier than by the Son; whether in
God there is only a “signum a quo” ([“sign from which”] Petrus Rogerii) or a
“signum in quo” ([“sign in which”] Francis of Meyronnes), etc. The language
and style of the disputations also produce the impression of sterile “Scholasti-
cism,” especially due to the fourfold division of all decisions and conclusions,
which is sometimes carried out quite strictly.123
The real concern and the theological importance of such controversies
becomes clear only when on reflects on the “linguistic turn” taken by theolo-
gy since Duns Scotus. It is not by chance that the Conflatus begins with a long
exposition of the principle of contradiction as a principle of ambivalence in
theology.124 With this principle Scotus had laid the foundation for univocal
predication about God. Every predication is true or false, never both at the
same time. Thus unambiguous predication and bivalent [zweiwertige] logic
are set forth as the basis for theology as a whole. Theological propositions
have definite truth value, even our statements about God; for the principle
of contradiction is equally valid for God and creatures. Our theological state-
ments can be rendered certain only if contradictions are inadmissible in God
as well. According to the underlying realistic semantics, however, univocal
predication and the validity of the principle of contradiction in statements
about God presuppose “something” (ontologically) about which contra-
dictory statements (with reference) are possible. Contradictory statements
1520; reprinted Frankfurt, 1966). Concerning the problems of literary criticism: Rossmann, “Sen-
tenzenkommentare”; Möhle, Formalitas, 29–41.
122. Ed. J. Barbet, François de Meyronnes—Pierre Roger, Disputatio (1320–1321) (Textes phi-
losophiques du moyen-âge 9) (Paris, 1961); see also Rossmann, “Sentenzenkommentare,” 140–65.
123. See Rossmann, “Sentenzenkommentare,” 220–27.
124. Franciscus de Mayronis, Conflatus, prol. q.1 (2r–4r); see also Roth, Franz von Mayronis,
297–369; Möhle, Formalitas, 42–73.
216 Theological Controversy and Church Reform
presuppose distinctions: one thing and another thing, same and different,
example and counterexample. Corresponding to our distinctions in state-
ments about God, therefore, there must be actual distinctions in the nature
of God, if theological discourse is to be assured semantically (and thus on-
tologically). This becomes especially urgent in the doctrine of the Trinity:
multiplicity of Persons—oneness of nature; communication [i.e., sharing =
Mitteilung] of the essence—non-communication of the Persons, etc. A real
distinction is ruled out, since that would imply a division in God; a mere[ly
notional] distinction on the part of man does not assure predication along
the lines of a “realistic” semantics. Consequently an additional sort of dis-
tinction must be assumed (“ex natura rei,” “resulting from the nature of the
thing”), which does not signify a real division yet does guarantee a semantic-
ontological correspondence with our distinctions and thus a univocal refer-
ence of our theological discourse. This is the origin of the so-called formal
distinction, which is already found in the writings of Duns Scotus and be-
came a point of dispute with the Thomists and Nominalists. The application
of this potential solution in Francis of Meyronnes is initially restricted to the
relation between relational statements (concerning properties or persons)
and absolute statements (about the essence or nature), and also between es-
sential attributes and the substantiality [Wesenheit] of God himself. These
signify different “formalitates,” not different things, but not just moments or
aspects of an intellectual/notional subdivision, either. Now of course it is
possible to make further statements about such “formalitates.” The attributes
ascribed to them cannot in turn signify real qualities or distinctions, but only
corresponding modifications (in disjunct pairs) of the formalities; they are
therefore only “modi intrinseci” [“inner modalities”] that do not change the
nature of the formalities: finitude—infinitude, reality—possibility, neces-
sity—contingency, existence, reality, and haecceitas (individuality).125
The importance of the principle of contradiction in theology is also evi-
dent on another level: with regard to God’s freedom and sovereignty, which
Francis staunchly defended as a good Scotist, most clearly in a quaestio from
Codex Vaticanus lat. 901 that was probably submitted as an opinion in the
Ockham trial.126 God’s sovereignty is explicitly compared to the univer-
sal sovereignty of the Pope, which Francis emphatically advocated while a
member of the Curia in Avignon, despite their divergent opinions in the
125. Conflatus l.1 d.33 q.3 (101rv); ibid. q.5 (103rv); see also Roth, Franz von Mayronis, 319–25;
detailed discussion in Möhle, Formalitas, 74–113, 286–336.
126. Text: Rossmann, Hierarchie, 251–57.
Theological Controversy and Church Reform 217
debate about poverty.127 He attributes to both a potentia absoluta [absolute
power] that is not connected with existing laws (even its own), but rather
is itself the cause of its freely willed laws.128 In view of this absolute sover-
eignty of God, the question arises concerning the validity of human theo-
logical statements, but by the same token concerning the meritoriousness
of human contingent action with respect to man’s final end. The factual or-
der of creation and redemption is contingent; it springs from a sovereign,
free-will decision of God, who consequently complies with it in his potentia
ordinata [ordered power], although in and of himself he would not be com-
pelled to do so. Finally, which statements can then derive their permanent
validity [Bestand haben] not only from God’s nature but also to his creative
and redemptive acts, independent of God’s dispositions? Thus God could
have saved mankind, for example, even without the death of Christ.129 Can
we then in theologicis [in theological matters] rely on those arguments that
are valid in our lawfully ordered reality: for example, that guilt has punish-
ment as a consequence, and merit results in reward? Francis discusses this
question explicitly in three respects: with regard to the principles of nature,
of moral action and of supernatural merit. From a purely causal perspective,
there is no necessary connection between the state of grace and acceptance
by God, in the sense that there would be no contradiction if the conse-
quence failed to materialize. From the moral perspective, the absolute sov-
ereign can determine the price of a thing with complete freedom; thus God,
who is free per se, determines what is necessary in order to obtain eternal
happiness. Therefore at any time he can also change, increase or diminish
the price: thus eternal happiness must not depend on the presence of su-
pernatural gifts of grace, much less on merits. In and of himself, God can
grant it even without these prerequisites or refuse it when they are present.
It is remarkable, in any case, that the question of whether man is accepted
or rejected in God’s sight is discussed according to the rules of a bill of sale,
albeit in order to show forth the mercy of God, who can supply eternal hap-
piness even below the agreed-upon “selling price.”130 The Conflatus accepts
as a possible “consideration” or service by man in return even a morally bad
act (actus vitiosus), which naturally would then be not only morally good
but even meritorious. Thus God in and of himself (de potentia absoluta) can
131. See Conflatus I d.17 (73rv); see also Dettloff, Entwicklung, 173.
132. See Conflatus I d.43/44 q.4 (125r): “Utrum deus possit facere quicquid non includit contra-
dictionem” [“Whether God can do whatever does not involve a contradiction”]; see also Möhle,
Formalitas, 71–73.
133. Conflatus I d.45 q.1 (129v–130r).
134. See Rossmann, Hierarchie, 259–63.
135. Introduction to his life and work: Ruh, Meister Eckhart.
136. So far only the Collatio in libros Sententiarum has been edited: Meister Eckhart, Die latein-
ischen Werke, 5:1–26.—The dating of the work to 1293 is according to Ruh, contrary to J. Koch, who
still dates it to 1297–1300, when Eckhart was already Prior in Erfurt and Vicar of Thüringen.
Theological Controversy and Church Reform 219
tion of his order.137 That scholastic tradition was at the same time impor-
tant for Eckhart’s early view of God.138 It inquires into the identity of being
and knowing in God, which leads then directly to the controversies between
Thomists and Scotists over the doctrine of distinctions [in God], and on the
other hand also underscores the Thomistic emphasis on God’s knowledge
rather than his action. Eckhart’s thesis is that the indistinguishability here is
real and possibly notional and intellectual as well; as his first argument he
immediately cites two passages from Thomas.139 In keeping with the Liber
de causis, God’s intelligere [understanding] is even depicted as the founda-
tion of his being: God does not know because he is, but rather is because
he knows, whereby “esse” is understood in principle as creaturely being.140
This is confirmed by John 1:1, which does not say, “In principio erat esse” (or
ens) [“In the beginning was being”], but rather “In principio erat verbum” [“. . .
the Word”]. “Verbum,” however, connotes truth and thus knowledge. In the
dialectical interaction with these concepts in this Neoplatonic interpretation
of being and knowing, everything that belongs to the intellect becomes non-
ens [nonbeing], of course, because in that way nothing is said about its being
realized outside of the intellect. If God is only intellect, however, and as such
the cause of all being, then in God there is neither existence nor being (that
is, considered as something created and definite).141 The game of affirmation
and negation that Eckhart is playing here is supposed to show forth the radi-
cal otherness of God even within the framework of the Thomistic analogy of
being and can consequently be interpreted as the exact antithesis of Scotist
univocality. Formally speaking (formaliter), God is not being (ens) but rather
something higher of another sort, namely, the cause of all being and “puri-
tas essendi” [“purity of being”], a being of an altogether different kind than
creaturely being.142 Compared with the linguistic, logical presuppositions
and methods of a Duns Scotus, Eckhart’s quaestiones appear quite modest.
Their importance lies rather in their Neoplatonic, dialectic development of
Thomistic metaphysics and of its thinking about the analogy of being.
The Opus tripartitum, Eckhart’s principal work in Latin, which dates at
least in part from his second stint as magister in Paris, has been preserved
143. Meister Eckhart, Expositio Sancti Evangelii secundum Iohannem, prooem. n.2 f. (Lat. Werke
3:4.4–6, 14–17); German translation, i.e., the cited work is a Latin-German edition.
144. Meister Eckhart, Prologus generalis in Opus Tripartitum n.2 (Lat. Werke 1:148.5–149.2).
145. Ibid., n.5 (1:151.2–6). 146. Ibid., n.7 (1:152.3–7).
Theological Controversy and Church Reform 221
among metaphysical axioms, quaestio and scriptural exegesis in the first arti-
cle of each part: In the Opus propositionum it is the statement, “Esse est Deus”
[“God is being”]; in the Opus quaestionum—the question “Utrum Deus sit”
[“Does God exist?”], and in the area of scriptural exegesis—Genesis 1:1.
The metaphysical foundation of scriptural exegesis is thus clearly under-
scored. The fundamental propositions of metaphysics remain the norm for
the interpretation of Scripture.147
Against the background of the first Parisian quaestio it must appear at first
to be a rupture in Meister Eckhart’s teaching when already in the prologue to
the Opus tripartitum he repeatedly and decidedly insists on the fundamental
proposition: “Esse est Deus.”148 In the first quaestio he had still used “ens” and
“esse” primarily for creaturely things and assigned preeminence to intelligere.
Yet even in that work he already speaks about God as “puritas essendi” [“purity
of being”]. Now, within the framework of Christian Neoplatonic metaphys-
ics, this becomes the prevailing point of view, without which one can neither
prove the existence of God nor carry out Eckhart’s program of a metaphysi-
cal interpretation of Scripture. Methodologically little has changed since the
first quaestiones. We no longer encounter disputations pro and con but rather
theses that are proved by multiple arguments (the shorter arguments being
enumerated). In neo-Platonic conceptual dialectics, in each case the (ab-
stract) fundamental concept is sought first, the concrete thing is then derived
from it and the negative contrary concept is formed as well: being/an existing
thing/nothingness, unity/one/many, truth/a truth/a falsehood, goodness/a
good/an evil; the pattern is not followed through consistently, however.149
The “purity of being” [or: “Pure being”] has now become “esse” [“being”] it-
self as the fundamental definition of the biblical, Christian, and metaphysical
God, whose identity is fundamental for Eckhart. “Esse” or “ens” in the abso-
lute sense should be distinguished from “ens hoc et hoc” [“this or that being”]:
with that, God’s logical otherness is just noted by means of another predicate,
as Eckhart will go on to show with the remaining transcendentals.150 Then,
through the corresponding negative concepts, everything that is not ens in the
proper sense appears as nothing: “praeter esse et sine esse omnia sunt nihil, etiam
facta.” [“Aside from and without being, all things, even those that are made,
165. Ockham, I Sent. d. 17 q.1 (3:452.6–13); see also Dettloff, Entwicklung, 263.
166. Ockham, I Sent. d.17 q.2 (3:471–72); this would then be misunderstood as “Pelagianism”;
see also Leppin, Theologie, 142–43.
Theological Controversy and Church Reform 227
The act of assenting to faith occurs with reference not to a “res” [thing]
outside the mind, but rather to a proposition whose terms, however, signify
(in personal supposition) and thus stand for the thing and do not just have
a purely grammatical or logical meaning. The truth of the proposition is for
Holcot the “res significata,” not an intentional or mental object (complexum
significatum), as Crathorn and Gregory of Rimini claim.176 The material
truth of faith statements and theological propositions is consequently as-
sured with regard to their extension. It is dependent on the use of the terms
in the proposition as signifiers, that is, they are true if the terms really do
designate what they mean, and consequently a corresponding res outside
the mind can be produced for which they stand. This is not the case, for
example, in Anselm’s proof of the existence of God; here it would be nec-
essary first to prove that “istud quo majus cogitari nequit” [“that thing than
which nothing greater can be thought”] can be used as a signifier [i.e., with
173. Ibid., a.2 (91.2–18).
174. See Hoffmann, Methode, 211–16 (with literary-critical emendations of the incunabulum
text); see also Perler, Wahrheitsbegriff.
175. Translated from the German version by Hoffmann, Methode, 216; see also Hoffmann,
“Satz,” 300.
176. See Crathorn, I Sent q.2, ed. Hoffmann, Crathorn, 152–205; Holcot, Conferentiae a.1 (67–82).
Theological Controversy and Church Reform 229
a real, objective referent].177 The verification of theological statements now
becomes the decisive problem. This cannot be accomplished by means of a
proof that immediately entails knowledge, but rather is a matter of faith and
its own logic. That is why “God is,” meaning the result of a philosophical
proof, is something different from a faith statement; the philosophical proof
does not attain the object of the Catholic faith, since the concept “god” for
the philosopher or the pagan is different from the Catholic’s concept. We
are dealing therefore with an equivocation which rules out all proof and in-
deed requires a special “logic of faith” in order to assure theological state-
ments.178
This logic is required precisely in those situations where statements
about God necessarily involve an appraisal of his freedom or man’s free-
dom, that is, with (future) contingent statements—another point disputed
by Holcot and Crathorn.179 Statements about the future have no definite
truth-value; contingent statements are not demonstrable. If we maintain
both God’s freedom and his omniscience, then statements about future
contingent matters are necessarily either true or false, as statements, but not
at the same time nor successively. Consequently, in view of the freedom of
God and of man, there must be statements which are true and yet in an-
other respect false, for example, “Socrates (or this man) will go to heaven.”
For that depends both on God’s freedom and also on the freedom of that
man. But what is true today cannot be false tomorrow, except for predic-
tions of contingent events which as future statements are falsified by the ac-
tual occurrence, for example, “The soul of the Antichrist will be created,” or
“The day of judgment will take place.” Once the event takes place, the state-
ment in its future form can no longer be made and is thus false. Now since
such contingent future statements can be the object of revelation, Holcot
accepts, for purely logical reasons, the possibility that such statements can
be falsified even when they are found in the Bible, and therefore admits the
possibility of a faith in statements that are possibly false, even in the case of
the “anima Christi.” This leads to “objectionable” theological formulations:
“God can deceive. The soul of Christ was capable of being deceived. Sacred
Scripture can be false. A false faith can be meritorious.”180
Furthermore, man by his natural powers can will that God (and not
something else) should be God.183 Thereby, however, he places an act of su-
preme benevolence toward God. Holcot agrees with Bradwardine, though,
in a purely logical way, that God can also be the efficient cause of man’s sin-
ful acts, and of the act of faith, too, which then however would no longer be
an act of assent. Holcot, in any case, restricts this causality to God’s “volun-
tas beneplaciti” [“permissive will”] and thus rejects any direct command of
sin by God (“voluntas signi”).184 The technique used in the discussion here,
as always, is propositional logic, with all its possibilities for analyzing falla-
cies, especially through the perennial distinction between the proper and
improper use of language (modus loquendi vs. forma loquendi), so as to guar-
antee theological statements in their truth value as well.185 The latter are
still dependent on Scripture but likewise on the logical proof of their truth
or credibility.
199. I Sent. d.17 q.1 a.2 (2:222, 5–10); see also Dettloff, Entwicklung, 317.
200. I Sent. d.17 q.1 a.1 (2:234.23–235.21). 201. Ibid. (245.24–31).
202. WA Br 12.387.16–20.
203. For the debates at the University of Louvain/Leuven, see Baudry, Querelle des futurs contin-
gents; for a history of the problem: Craig, Problem of Divine Foreknowing; Schwamm, Vorherwissen.
Theological Controversy and Church Reform 235
in the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries and was thoroughly debated even
in difficult university disputations, is in modern dress the question as to ab-
solute knowledge even of future and contingent things: How will the course
of the world continue? As an example of the medieval discussion, which was
carried on not only at the universities but also by every “muliercula vel etiam
laica persona” [“common woman or even lay person”],204 we present here
Marsilius of Inghen (ca. 1330–1396), a professor in Paris and Heidelberg, who
studied in Paris (theology beginning in 1366) together with Geert Groote,
the founder of devotio moderna, and kept in contact with Heinrich Totting of
Oyta. From 1386 on he taught the artes at the new University of Heidelberg,
and he held the office of rector there from 1386–1392 and in 1396. Not until
1396 was he promoted in Heidelberg to the degree of doctor of theology, but
he died that same year.205 His Quaestiones super Quattuor libros Sententiarum,
which were influenced by Ockham, Adam Woodham and Gregory of Rimi-
ni, were composed in Heidelberg in the years 1392–1394 and grapple with the
problem in a logically precise manner. Every quaestio is subdivided accord-
ing to its premises (suppositiones) and conclusions, which in turn are proved
individually with many arguments.206
Even his way of framing the questions is oriented to the propositional
understanding of truth: Can the following propositions be true simultane-
ously, or are they contradictory?
I. Divine foreknowledge infallibly knows everything beforehand.
II. There are consequences that are produced contingently and freely.207
Marsilius maintains both presuppositions in faith, both God’s compre-
hensive foreknowledge and also the contingency of future, freely willed
events. Accordingly, the first proposition is proved very briefly in article 1:208
1. God knows in advance everything in the future.
2. God’s foreknowledge is absolutely infallible with regard to future events.
3. A
lthough most contingent future events depend on a created, free will,
they are infallibly known by God in advance.
204. Marsilius of Inghen, I Sent. q. 40; ed. Hoenen, Marsilius van Inghen, 2:71.
205. See Hoenen, Marsilius of Inghen, 7–11.
206. Ibid., 19–22; on the sources see also Santos Noya, “Auctoritates theologicae.”—Published
works: Questiones Marsilii super quattuor libros sententiarum (Strasbourg, 1501; reprinted Frankfurt,
1966).
207. Marsilius van Inghen, I Sent. q. 40 (ed. Hoenen, 2:61–113).
208. Ibid., a.1 (2:73–74).
236 Theological Controversy and Church Reform
But now what is the relation between this comprehensive foreknowledge
of God and the contingency of created things and the freedom of human will
that are emphasized at all points by Ockham?209 God’s knowledge, however,
being knowledge, is propositional. It refers to circumstances as the referential
objects of propositions (complexe enuntiabile), not to things.210 There must be
contingent future circumstances, if theological discourse about sin is to retain
its meaning; for sin is in principle a free human act. The prime example is the
Antichrist (a future figure), according to Daniel 11:36–37 and 2 Thessalonians
2:4. Now given that he will demand to be worshiped as God, there are in prin-
ciple three possible ways of explaining this:
1. The Antichrist acts freely, and this action is sin.
2. The Antichrist acts out of necessity and therefore does not sin. If God
then punishes him with eternal damnation, however, he is acting unjustly.
3. The Antichrist acts out of necessity and necessarily sins; he is damned
justly “ex natura rerum” [“by the nature of things”]. This answer (given by
Robert Holcot), however, makes God the “principalis actor” of sin and is
therefore just as unacceptable as (2).
Therefore only possibility (1) is theologically acceptable, and this re-
sults in a typical formulation of contingent future statements and of divine
knowledge about them:
(a) The Antichrist will sin at a point in time a, and
(b) The Antichrist is capable of not sinning at the same time a.
These two propositions are combined as:
(a–b) The Antichrist will sin contingently at the point in time a.
(c) God knows infallibly that the Antichrist will sin at the point in
time a.211
God’s foreknowledge and the contingent future are therefore not con-
tradictory, as one might assume. God’s knowledge implies also the mode in
which circumstances come to be, and thus also the contingency of future
circumstances. Yet Marsilius goes beyond that by making this knowledge
of God to be itself a contingent knowledge, and thus declares the mode of
what is known to be a mode of the knowledge: God himself does not know
necessarily, but rather only contingently what I will do in the future; but if
209. See Perler, “Notwendigkeit und Kontingenz”; Beckmann, “Weltkontingenz.”
210. See Hoenen, Marsilius of Inghen, 217–18.
211. Marsilius van Inghen, I Sent. q.40 a.2 (ed. Hoenen 2:75–82).
Theological Controversy and Church Reform 237
he knows it contingently, then also temporally. Therefore it is possible that
at a point in time a, he did not know it. God’s knowledge is therefore not
a knowledge about eternal, unchangeable ideas and their necessary conse-
quences in the world, as Marsilius maintains, clearly criticizing the via an-
tiqua (Thomas Bradwardine). The room for human freedom is therefore
expanded, so that even God’s knowledge is thereby restricted, at least in
its mode. Truth, considered in purely logical terms, implies not necessity
but rather facticity: The proposition “God knows (from all eternity) that p
will be the case at time t” does not imply the necessary occurrence of p at t.
Consequently, p can also not occur. God, however, could never have known
this latter proposition also, that p will not occur at t. Similarly, Marsilius at-
tempts to find a way out of the dilemma between the immutability of God’s
foreknowledge and the mutability of the future, again by tranferring the
mode of what is known to the mode of the knowledge. He plainly criticizes
our temporal notions of God’s foreknowledge as a procedure that is already
concluded and past. Instead one must speak about it in the present tense:
God knows (simultaneously) that p; this is compatible, however, with the
proposition: God did not know in advance that p, since in his knowledge it
is not determined in what way God himself or the human being will freely
decide. Therefore we should not think about the truth of the future accord-
ing to the model of historical truth. Statements about the past are true or
false in a determinate way. Statements whose truth-value still depends on
the influence of other potential circumstances are true only indeterminate-
ly.212 Thus not all truth should be interpreted according to the model of fac-
tual truth.
Furthermore God’s nonknowledge with regard to futura continentia re-
fers only to the scientia visionis, the immediate, intuitive knowledge of real-
ity, not to the “notitia simplicis notitiae vel apprehensionis” [“the knowledge
of simple cognizance or apprehension”] in which God knows all possible
circumstances. Thus it goes without saying that he knows that a contingent
future circumstance is possible. Thus in God there is simultaneously [1] nec-
essary cognizance [Kenntnis] of everything that is possible and [2] contin-
gent knowledge [Erkenntnis] of individual contingent events, dependent
on the free decision of the creature.213 A causal connection between fore-
knowledge and freedom, however, is ruled out entirely. Knowledge exerts
1. One of the first to overcome this assessment, in the case of humanism, was Ritter, “Bedeu-
tung.”
2. See esp. Oberman, Werden, passim; on the concept of humanism: Oppermann, ed., Human-
ismus; Kristeller, “Humanismus und Renaissance”; also Bejczy, Erasmus, 62–103; Quinto, Scholas-
tica, 129–40.
3. For those topics see, in general, HDThG, vol. 2 and HDG; also Jung and Walter, Theologen
des 16. Jahrhunderts.
4. See IST, ch. 4.1.4–4.1.6.
243
244 Humanist and Reformation Theology
demic life in the late Scholastic period, with its established structures that
had become particularly rigid during the fifteenth-century debate about
the two ways. Possibly the Italian universities were an exception, most of all
Padua, which became a stimulating center for philosophical development,
in German-speaking regions as well.5
The contrast between the humanist movement and the prevailing Scho-
lasticism can be summarized in the following points:
1. A
departure from the Scholastic method of disputation and its foundation
in late Scholastic logic. This was said to be based less on Aristotle’s writ-
ings on logic than on the logica modernorum [logic of the moderns] with
their sophismata [sophistries, quibbles], and insolubilia [interminably
debated questions].6
2. A turn to new sources. “Ad fontes!” now no longer meant consulting only
the Scholastic authorities, but rather Plato, the authentic Aristotle, the
Stoics, Cicero and the poets, and in theology—the Church Fathers, es-
pecially Augustine and Jerome. Their thought was no longer summarized
in just a few sentences; now the art of printing books made it available in
its full context in exemplary editions.7
e promotion of language studies. The “vir trilinguis” [“trilingual man”],
3. Th
the ideal educated man (eruditus), had to master Latin, Greek, and He-
brew. The linguistic elegance of the ancient writers and humanist authors
was contrasted with the “barbaric” Latin of the Scholastics with their
wretched termini technici. Disputation was not infrequently replaced by
rhetorical declamation.
Thus the rejection of Scholasticism was for the most part based on liter-
ary and methodological reasons (especially in the writings of Lorenzo Valla
[1405/07–1457]), whereas other Italian humanists, led by Giovanni Pico
della Mirandola (1463–1494), accepted much of the medieval intellectual
heritage.8
The reception of these humanist demands in the universities met with
material and organizational difficulties north of the Alps. Often they came
into conflict with the old rights of the professors of the arts to provide the
sole authoritative preparation for study in the higher faculties and to teach
5. See esp. Kristeller, “Humanism and Scholasticism,” 553–83; Schmitt, Aristotelian Tradition.
6. See esp. Lawn, Rise and Decline, 107–26.
7. See Baron, “Der erste Druck.”
8. See Kölmel, “Scholasticus literator.”
Humanist and Reformation Theology 245
the only authoritative methodology. Accordingly, the studia humanitatis at
first did not find a proper place at the universities; they were usually situ-
ated outside the system of faculties: for example, the short-lived Collegium
poetarum et mathematicorum founded by the emperor in Vienna in 1502, but
also the more permanent Collegium trilingue in Louvain (1519), and various
humanistic lectures in Tübingen and Ingolstadt. Only in Wittenberg were
the humanist departments successfully incorporated into the faculty of the
arts, even before Melanchthon’s reform of the university.9 The widely trav-
elled humanist lecturers or poets, moreover, usually could not prove their
qualifications by an appropriate university education. This resulted in dif-
ficulties with the students’ societies and academic stipends.
University reform along humanist lines, as it was carried out in Erfurt
and Leipzig (1519), Rostock (1520), Greifswald (1521), Heidelberg (1522),
and Tübingen (1525), by its very nature affected the faculty of the arts ini-
tially.10 Precisely through this change in preparatory studies, however, it had
considerable consequences for theology. This is illustrated by the inaugu-
ral discourse of the twenty-one-year-old Melanchthon at the University of
Wittenberg, De corrigendis adolescentiae studiis [On revising secondary stud-
ies] on August 29, 1518, which is supported not so much by Reformation as
by humanist principles.11 The humanist propaedeutic, which was an educa-
tion in speaking and judging, consisted of subjects that are still called “hu-
manities,” (languages, poets, rhetoricians, history), along with a philosophy
that was restricted to natural science and ethics. The humanist “ad fontes”
[return to the sources], however, applied also to theology: the Greek and
Hebrew languages made those sources accessible. Instead of so many “cold”
(= Scholastic) glosses, concordances, and dissensions [Diskordanzen], the
res [matter] itself was supposed to become clear from a reading of the text,
so that one could “savor Christ” (Christum sapere).12 The humanist student
was to have Homer in one hand and Paul in the other, but above all the
courage to taste the subject in the ancient texts themselves: “Sapere audete!”
[“Dare to taste!”].13 In reducing the study of theology to the Bible and the
Church Fathers and eliminating lectures on the Sentences,14 Melanchthon
20. See Schubert, “Typologie,” 85–99; Boehm, “Bildungsbewegung,” 342–45: Leinsle, Dilinga-
nae Disputationes, 86–91.
21. Published together in a Latin-German edition by G. Winkler: Erasmus von Rotterdam, Aus-
gewählte Schriften, gen. ed. W. Welzig, vol. 3 (Darmstadt, 1967); see also Winkler, Erasmus von Rot-
terdam; Hoffmann, Erkenntnis; Bejczy, Erasmus, 134–50.
22. Erasmus, Paraclesis (ed. Winkler, 27).
23. Ibid., 22.
248 Humanist and Reformation Theology
e “philosophia Christi” consists first and foremost of following what
2. Th
Christ taught; it is an “illiterata philosophia” of simple people, which can
however change the world.24
3. C
hristian philosophy, in contrast to pagan philosophy, offers something
decidedly new; traces of its truth are to be found nevertheless even in the
ancient authors, who consequently ought to be read.25
4. Th
eology as “Christian philosophy” is generally related to man in his
concrete societal status and his striving for happiness, which should be
attained by putting into practice Christ’s instructions (“pie philosophari”
[“philosophizing piously”]).26
5. Th
e central object of theology is Christ, as we encounter him in the NT
writings. The study of sacred Scripture is therefore the real subject matter
of the “old and true theology.”
6. Th
e essential preparatory training for scientific theology is therefore
philological and humanistic, not dialectical and Scholastic. Nevertheless,
exegesis presupposes some knowledge of systematic (dogmatic) theol-
ogy, which cannot be derived from Scripture inductively.27
By no means does Erasmus, in his conciliatory approach, intend to con-
demn Scholastic theology and its great masters without distinction. Its fun-
damental problem, however, appears to be its overemphasis on human au-
thorities, especially those belonging to the individual schools of thought, as
opposed to the authority of Scripture. Only in the latter is Erasmus willing
to worship what he does not understand!28 Erasmus sees a further defect of
Scholastic theology in the useless questions that overrun dogmatic theol-
ogy and the casuistry that stifles moral theology, which contradicts his ideal
of simple pietas.29 Theology as such is not to blame for this, but rather the
fact that it is overloaded with Aristotelian philosophy and logic. In regard to
Scholastic quaestiones, Erasmus recommends, if need be, academic epoché,
the refusal to give a positive or negative judgment, and by way of example
he enumerates several late Scholastic quaestiones of this sort:
What sense would it make for me to torment myself over whether God could create
man to be anamárteton, that is, incapable of sin? Whether God would be one and
undivided if another God distinct from himself existed? . . . Or whether the propo-
Thus the element from the practice of theology at the university that
remained a constant in the Reformation process was not really the disputa-
tion, but rather the test of the scriptural character of theological doctrines,
the probatio. Scripture—instead of the many Scholastic authorities and
ways—was recognized as the sole authority for this test, which both reli-
gious parties could in fact agree upon.
60. RTA VI, 492, no. 107. On Spengler see Grimm, Lazarus Spengler.
61. RTA IV, 202–3.
62. G. Pfeilschifter, Acta Reformationis Catholicae Ecclesiam Germaniae Concernantia Saeculi XVI.
Die Reformverhandlungen des deutschen Episkopats von 1520 bis 1570, vol. I (Regensburg, 1959), no. 50.
63. RTA VII, 1142.14–17; see also Honnée, “Religionsverhandlungen,” 25–27.
64. Friedensburg, Reichstag zu Speyer, 557.
Humanist and Reformation Theology 255
65. WA I, 224–28; see esp. Grane, Contra Gabrielem; idem, Modus loquendi theologicus, 130–38;
Lohse, Luthers Theologie, 114–15; Quinto, Scholastica, 208–15.
66. See Karlstadt und Augustin: Der Kommentar des Andreas Bodenstein von Karlstadt zu Augus-
tins Schrift “De spiritu et littera,” introduction and text by E. Kähler (Hallische Monographien 19)
(Halle, 1952), 8*–37*.
256 Humanist and Reformation Theology
“43. It is an error to say: Without Aristotle one does not become a theo-
logian. Contrary to common opinion.
“44. Indeed, no one can become a theologian unless he becomes one
without Aristotle.”67
The rejection of Aristotle is nevertheless not limited to the Ethics, but
extends to the Logic also, whereby the “logica fidei” of Peter of Ailly is reject-
ed in particular (theses 45–49), and indeed to Aristotle’s work as a whole,
which like darkness is driven away by the light of theology—this includes
even the doctrine of universals in the Isagoge by Porphyry (theses 50–53).
Consequently, once the philosophy of Aristotle and thus the core curricu-
lum of the faculty of arts is withdrawn as a propaedeutic to theology, then
the genuine relation between grace, the law and human will can be set forth
according to Paul and Augustine and against Biel and Peter of Ailly (theses
54–98).
This formal and substantial rejection of Scholastic theology is intensi-
fied in the Heidelberg disputation (April 26, 1518). Already in the resolutio-
nes to the theses on indulgences (1518) Luther contrasts the theologus crucis
[theologian of the cross] and the theologus gloriae [. . . of glory] (thesis 58)
and sees in the latter the Scholastic theologian, who on the basis of natu-
ral, Aristotelian ethics knows about the goal of his striving, that is, about
good and evil, yet does not know the crucified and hidden God, but only
the glorified, omnipresent God who is supposed to be known from vis-
ible things (see Romans 1:19–20).68 The rejection of Scholastic theology is
therefore no longer articulated merely in terms of the theology of grace and
ethics, but also with regard to knowledge about God in general. In Heidel-
berg Luther sets out immediately from his view of the relation between the
law and grace, an approach that then allows him to critique earlier theology
precisely as a “theologia gloriae.”69 In particular Luther objects to the teach-
ing, found in the writings of Gerson and Biel, among others, of “facere quod
in se est” [“doing whatever one can”] as a prerequisite for grace. Instead, a
human being must abandon hope in himself and acknowledge his nothing-
ness so as to desire grace (thesis 18). A natural, metaphysical knowledge of
God, which tries to derive God’s attributes from creatures, does not lead to
wisdom, but rather is dismissed as foolishness according to [his reading of]
Romans 1:22 (thesis 19). Instead, the only access to knowledge of God is the
67. WA I, 226.14–16.
68. WA I, 613–14; see also Lohse, Luthers Theologie, 122–25; Lohse, “Luthers Selbstverständnis.”
69. WA I, 353–56.
Humanist and Reformation Theology 257
cross. By this way, however, God’s metaphysical attributes (power, divinity,
wisdom, justice, goodness) are not known, but rather the “posteriora et visi-
bilia Dei” [“the subsequent and visible things of God”], namely his human-
ity, weakness, and folly (thesis 20). The Scholastic theologia gloriae is there-
fore a false, mendacious theology that views what is genuinely good (bonum
crucis) as only bad, and what is really bad (malum operis, the evil of work) as
good (thesis 21). Scholastic theologians therefore appear as “enemies of the
cross of Christ” (Philippians 3:18). Only by a previous acknowledgment of
one’s own nothingness does one arrive at true theology. But one does not
learn this in the philosophy of Aristotle, which Luther here criticizes philo-
sophically as well (theses 29–40). Instead, being puffed up, blind, and rigid
are the moral consequences of Scholastic theology (thesis 22). The remedy
for this is radical: obliterating it and turning to the folly of the cross. Lu-
ther’s deliberately paradoxical formulation of this “theology of humility”70
must have struck his contemporaries as the clearest possible rejection of the
prevailing Scholastic theology: “The theology that Luther opposed consists
not only in a false doctrine, but in an approach that is false from the outset,
which cannot lead to theology but only to a pseudo-theology.”71
What, then, should theology look like—the true, correct, pure theology
that Luther has in mind—as opposed to the one devised by the “swinish
theologians” who are asleep and at best produce a “theologia diabolica” that
the devil has no cause to fear?72 Unlike the humanists Erasmus and Mel-
anchthon, Luther expressly and frequently uses the terms “theologia” and
“theologus” so as to make clear thereby his own claim: “Theology is tanta-
mount to God’s word. The theologian is the one who speaks God’s word.”73
In inquiring as to the central object of this theology (the subject of the sci-
ence), Luther plainly turns aside from all Scholastic definitions. The [prop-
er] object is not God or Christ, but rather fallen, lost man and the justifying
and saving God.74 Everything beyond this definition that is taught de facto
in theology does not belong to it but rather is error and “vanitas.” Knowl-
edge about man and knowledge about God belong together in theology,
but only in that mutual relation which is now decisive: fallen man and the
Although the list still looks like a summary of the conventional treatises
of systematic theology, because of a pronounced turn away from the Scho-
lastic “theologia gloriae” to the Reformation “theologia crucis,” many highly
elaborate parts of the teaching on God and the Trinity, creation and Incar-
nation were immediately dropped:
We should worship the mysteries of the Godhead instead of investigating them. . . .
God Almighty, the Most-High, clothed His son in flesh so that He might lead us
from meditating on His majesty to meditating on the flesh and thus on our human
frailty. . . . Hence there is no reason why we should apply much effort to those most
exalted themes: God, His Unity, the Trinity, the mystery of creation, the nature and
manner of the Incarnation.97
Instead the theological discussion begins with the doctrine about man,
his faculties, his will, so as to go on and treat in detail the topics of sin and
the Law. For only when one knows the power of sin, the law and grace can
one really know Christ—and not when one speculates about His two na-
tures and the manner of the Incarnation.98 Not until the 1535 version are
the teachings on God, the Trinity, and creation actually developed, and as
of 1543 they are further elaborated with philosophical trains of thought,
although the biblical approach is still clearly predominant.99 Even now
the epistemological principal for the doctrine about God remains Christ,
in whom the Father is known. The “sapientia Christianorum” [“wisdom of
Christians”] is an altogether practical knowledge of God, which recognizes
100. CR 21.255–56.
101. See Wallmann, Theologiebegriff; Bayer, “Theologiebegriff.”
102. Even in the 1521 version: Introduction n. 1 (Pöhlmann 16–17).
103. CR 21.253.
104. See the detailed discussion in Leinsle, Ding, esp. 11–20.
105. Introduction n. 3 (Pöhlmann 18–19).
106. CR 1.638. 1044; 11.37–38; see also Wiedenhofer, Formalstrukturen, 1:391–94.
107. See CR I, 285.366.451.487.567; III, 1112: “summa quaedam seu methodus est informanda” [“a
certain summa or method should be fashioned”]; vgl. Köpf, “Melanchthon,” 117–22.
Humanist and Reformation Theology 263
tempts to express in brief formulas, so as to expound it in a way that makes
sense pedagogically: Man, who cannot find his salvation by himself, but
rather owes it to justification through Christ.108
This method is adopted by theology from general philosophical and
theoretical reflections about science that Melanchthon—in a clear return to
tradition—drew again from Aristotle beginning in 1536. In the 1538 version
of the Dialectica he explicitly recommends that students have Aristotle on
hand, for he is the “unus ac solus methodi artifex” [“one and only framer of a
method”].109 Without Aristotle there is no science, but only a great confu-
sion of doctrines.110 Of course, Melanchthon does not read his Aristotle in
the manner of the Scholastics, but rather as a humanist who is acquainted also
with Cicero and the Stoics; moreover he eliminates the Metaphysics, while
retaining the Ethics (unlike Luther).111 This new propaedeutic, which fur-
thermore still contains metaphysical elements (categories, the four causes) in
its dialectics, creates the conditions under which theological instruction can
once again become academic, although not Scholastic. This trend becomes
evident also in the reintroduction of disputations alongside humanist decla-
mations in Wittenberg from 1533 on. Melanchthon’s view of philosophy and
theology finds expression especially in the speech De philosophia dated 1536.
From the humanist perspective, philosophy consists of the various artes, and
their propaedeutic and methodological importance for theology is under-
scored. Indeed, for the humanist Melanchthon, the root problem consists
of an “inerudita theologia” of the sort that was common in the initial discus-
sions by the Reformers but could often be observed among the Scholastics
as well.112 It is “uneducated” because it lacks the correct method. It is a “con-
fusanea doctrina” in which the important points are not set forth precisely,
in which things that ought to be treated separately are mingled, and things
that should be explained in connection with each other are pulled apart. Of-
ten contradictory statements are made; whatever sounds like the truth is im-
mediately taken for a genuine argument. The result is a “doctrina monstrosa”
in which nothing is methodologically consistent, which can only give rise to
endless errors and disputes. A conventional knowledge of grammar and logic
is not enough to remedy this sorry state of affairs; rather an “erudita philoso-
118. See Ganoczy, Calvin; Reuter, Vom Scholaren; Partee, Calvin; Spijker, “Calvin”; Frank, Ver-
nunft, 69–74.
119. See Ganoczy, Calvin, 179–92; van’t Spijker, “Calvin,” 205–6.
120. OS 1:37: “Summa fere sacrae doctrinae duabus his partibus constat: Dei cognitione et nostri.”
See Augustinus, Soliloquia I, 2.7; on the influence of Bernard of Clairvaux: Reuter, Vom Scholaren,
63–65. On anthropology and self-knowedge, see Faber, Symphonie, 87–131.
121. OS 1:69–76.
122. OS 1:39.
266 Humanist and Reformation Theology
ever, also leads to a correct self-evaluation in God’s sight, which in turn cor-
responds to the steps in knowing God:
1. God is the Creator, our Lord and Father; we owe Him glorification,
respect and love.
2. N o one can accomplish this by his own unaided powers; therefore we are
all liable to judgment and eternal death.
3. C onsequently some way to salvation must be sought other than through
one’s own righteousness. Left to our own devices, we have nothing but
despair.
4. This way is opened up for us in the forgiveness of sins in Christ.
5. W ith His Spirit and equipped with a new heart, we are able to keep
His commandments.123
Therefore this knowledge of God is initially an altogether practical and
personal knowledge. Calvin’s theology here is consciously dependent on
its ideal of “pietas”; indeed, the Institutio is supposed to be the “summa” of
these religious duties.124 Already in the dedicatory epistle to King Francis
I (which is reprinted in all the later editions), he underscores his efforts in
this work to lead people “ad veram pietatem” [“to true piety”] and thus to
the knowledge of Christ.125 Theological knowledge is therefore conveyed
in a practical way that applies to everyday life; it does not lead to the knowl-
edge of a superterrestrial substance, but rather to knowledge of the living
God and of Christ.126 This pietas on the one hand corresponds to our sta-
tus as creatures, based on a proper acknowledgment of our duties with
regard to the Creator; an even more forceful reason, though, is our status
as adopted children of the Father.127 The learned jurist Calvin is certainly
thinking here in terms of Roman law. The meaning of pietas is summed up
in the right way of fearing and loving God.128 The “pietatis studiosi” [“those
seeking to practice piety”] for whom Calvin originally planned his work are
therefore not only students of theology. This fundamentally distinguishes
his intention from that of Melanchthon’s Loci: He does not want to write an
academic introduction for the study of theology. For, as Erasmus also had
said, all Christians are called to pietas as a lifelong endeavor: “Tota Christia-
123. OS 1:40. 124. See Ganoczy, Calvin, 220–32.
125. OS 1:21.
126. OS 1:23: “non nostra est, sed Dei viventis et Christi eius.”
127. OS 1:76; see also Faber, Symphonie, 81–85: “Geschöpfliche Wesenheit als Gehorsamakt”
[“Creaturely Essence as Act of Obedience”].
128. OS 1:52.
Humanist and Reformation Theology 267
norum vita quaedam pietatis meditatio esse debet, quoniam in sanctificationem
vocati sunt.”129 [“The whole life of Christians must be a certain preparation
or training for piety, for they are called to sanctification.”] In contrast, the
false worship of God, which Calvin sees in idolatry, superstition and Rom-
ish customs, is held up as “impietas” [“impiousness, irreverence”].130
Calvin’s approach as a Reformer leads to a demand for a new method
of theological instruction, which he himself means to provide in the Insti-
tutiones. The Scholastics appear as the “impii” who are to blame for the fact
that the truth of Christ, while not yet entirely vanished, is nevertheless bur-
ied under the rubble, that is to say, under an inextricable tangle of compli-
cated theses that have no basis is Scripture.131 The theologian should start
out from “scripturae simplicitas” [“the simplicity of Scripture”] and should
rule out all the secondary literature of the Scholastics, which Calvin—like a
good Augustinian—regards as the product of curiositas.132 The Scholastics
take up positions either this side of Scripture or beyond it; in no instance is
their doctrine in keeping with Scripture; instead it is their own intellectual
construct.133 Besides Scripture, the young Reformer—like a good human-
ist—approves of the Church Fathers only. They unanimously refused to
mingle God’s word with subtle sophistries or to make it the object of logical
wrangling. If the Fathers were to come back today and listen to a disputa-
tion in so-called speculative (= Scholastic) theology, they would not be able
to detect that the subject matter was God.134
Calvin confronts Scholastic theology with his ideal of the authentic,
simple, and pure word of God. Scripture, which in itself is clear, should be
interpreted plainly for simple people as an “appeal, exhortation and instruc-
tion for men.” Therefore, despite his humanistic and philological schooling,
he intends to follow a simple and nonscholarly method of teaching even in
his scriptural exegesis, without dismissing as irrelevant, however, a thor-
ough education in languages and the Church Fathers.135 Comprehensibil-
ity and brevity are considered methodological norms both for scriptural
136. See, for example, OS 3:6, 24–28 (Introduction to the Inst. 1539); see also Ganoczy and
Scheld, Hermeneutik, 122–23.
137. Johannis Calvini Opera quae supersunt omnia, ed. G. Baum, E. Cunitz, E. Reuss, 59 vols.
(Braunschweig, 1863–1900), 6:268; 9:533 et passim; see also Ganoczy and Scheld, Hermeneutik, 114–15.
138. OS 1:73.
139. See Iserloh, Johannes Eck; Smolinsky, “Johannes Eck.”
140. See Seifert, Logik.
141. See Greving, Johann Eck.
Humanist and Reformation Theology 269
Unlike Erasmus and the Reformers, Eck was also concerned about
refining and simplifying Scholasticism in theology. Thus in the dog days
[midsummer] of 1542 he was still lecturing: a short explanation of the first
book of the Sentences, in which he discussed the introductory theoretical
questions about science in a few pages.142 In contrast to the existential, an-
thropological approach of Reformation theology, Eck’s definition of theol-
ogy adopts the Scholastic tradition in summary form: “Theology is the sci-
ence that deals with God, His perfections, attributes and relations, and also
with creatures insofar as they are considered in relation to God.”143 Accord-
ing to the methodus definitiva et divisa [method of definition and division],
the individual expressions in the definition are then explained and/or illus-
trated. The relation of creatures to God is inherently twofold: creation and
sanctification [Beseligung]. The subjectum theologiae [subject of theology]
in the primary and perfect sense is therefore God, but secondarily also the
creature, especially man, since he can acquire grace and attain justification.
A clear, concise distinction is made between natural and supernatural the-
ology—the latter based on inspired Scripture—or between acquired and
infused theology. The theology of God, who is the “theologotatos,” in other
words, theology “in se” [“in itself ”] without regard to man’s status in salva-
tion history, is clearly separated from “theologia in nobis” [“theology in or
among us”] or theology as it is believed according to man’s status at a given
time as opposed to the “theologia in se,” which is known. “More philosopho-
rum loquendo” [“speaking in the manner of philosophers”], Eck adopts as
his criterion for the subject of a science the Scotist definition, namely that
it should contain virtually the truths of that science. The object of theology
consists of sacred Scripture and the valid conclusions that are drawn logical-
ly from it. Theology is—in keeping with the via moderna—partly practical,
partly affective, depending on the propositions that it contains. Thus “pater
genuit filium” [“The Father begot the Son”] is a theoretical proposition, even
when something about appropriate divine worship is inferred from it.144
Although Eck’s instructional method in his lectures on the Sentences is
consistently that of definition and division, in his Enchiridion locorum com-
munium adversus Lutherum et alios hostes ecclesiae [“Handbook of common-
142. In Primum Librum Sententiarum Annotatiunculae D. Johanne Eckio Praelectore Anno ab
Christo nato 1542, per dies caniculares, quos alioqui a studiis gravioribus feriari solebat, ed. W. L. More,
Jr. (Studies in Medieval and Reformation Thought 13) (Leiden, 1976), 15–17.
143. Ibid., In prol. (15.7–10): “Theologia est scientia quae de Deo, eius perfectionibus, attributis et
relationibus tractat, aut etiam de creaturis secundum quod in Deum referentur.”
144. Eck, I Sent. prol. (15–17).
270 Humanist and Reformation Theology
places contrary to Luther and other enemies of the Church”] (First printing
1525, successively enlarged until 1543) he has recourse to the common rep-
ertoire of Scholasticism as refined by humanism.145 Unlike Melanchthon’s
Loci, Eck does not try to give an overview of theology, but rather a sum-
mary of the main points of controversy between the religious parties, which
are treated according to a scheme of propositio (sometimes called axioma
also) and its probatio [proof] from established passages from Scripture and
the Fathers. The basic scheme is often that of a disputation as well: proposi-
tio—probatio—objectiones—solutiones.146 Even at the methodological level,
therefore, Eck’s loci [citations, passages]—Zwingli’s influential observation
notwithstanding—is not a Catholic imitation of Melanchthon’s;147 rather,
Eck is posing the question as to the order, relative weight, and authoritative
proof of the theological theses that are to be discussed controversially. The
following topics are situated at the head of the loci: Church—Council—pa-
pal primacy—Scripture. Then come: faith and works, the sacraments and
ecclesiastical rites and customs. The probatio of the central propositions
(e.g., the veneration of the saints, chapter 15) follows the pattern: Scrip-
ture—ratio—auctoritates sanctorum (the Fathers)—ecclesiae consuetudo
[custom of the Church] in broadly developed chapters. The practical pur-
pose of this controversial-theological presentation is underscored by refer-
ences to thematically related sermons by Eck.148 The practical significance
of the loci is set forth even more plainly in the foreword to the shorter Ger-
man edition of 1530: in connection with the “simple” humanist theology,
they are meant to serve as an abridgment of Scholastic theology.149 Here
Eck has “briefly drawn up and compiled in this little handbook the founda-
tion and summary idea [of theology], first and foremost the most important
sayings of Holy Divine Scripture, so that everyone—even somebody with
little understanding—might be able to gain insight quickly into any mat-
ter that may arise and to find at hand [i.e., conveniently] the chief passages
from Scripture, and sometimes also the authority of the holy divine doc-
145. Johannes Eck, Enchiridion locorum communium adversus Lutherum et alios hostes ecclesiae
(1525–1543), ed. P. Fraenkel (CCath 34) (Münster, 1979). On the history of its composition, see
Minnich, “Origins.”
146. For example, Enchiridion c. 1 prop. 4 (24–34).
147. See Fraenkel, Einleitung zu Eck, Enchridion 1*–16*; Zwingli’s letter to Vadian dated 22 April
1526: CR 95.574.
148. For example, Enchiridion, c.5 prop.2 (92.3).
149. Johannes Eck, Enchiridion: Handbüchlin gemainer stell unnd Artickel der jetzt schwebenden
Neuwen leeren, Faksimile-Druck der Ausgabe Augsburg 1533, ed. E. Iserloh (CCath 35) (Münster,
1980).
Humanist and Reformation Theology 271
tors, as they have then been accepted by the Christian Churches.”150 The
purely topical arrangement of the material is explained here by the charac-
ter of this small reference work. Of course, because this work is destined for
the “simple” Christian, a coarsening of the style can be observed, especially
in the supplementary material not found in the Latin original.151
Topical, controversial theological debate thus replaces the discovery of
truth through disputation. This is explicitly justified in the last chapter of the
original version: “Non disputandum cum haereticis” [“One should not dispute
with heretics”].152 Earlier, chapter 26 “De haereticis comburendis” [“On burn-
ing heretics”] cites an objection of the heretics (specifically Luther’s), that
one must dispute with them and defeat them with the sword of the Spirit,
that is, with the word of God, and not with fire.153 Relying on papal con-
demnations, Eck adduces proof of heresy in Luther’s case (Zwingli’s also in
the German version) by the tried and true procedure of showing that their
works repeat the teachings of the old condemned heretics: “then they re-
vive the old condemned heresies of Arius, Manes [and the Manichees],
Helvidius, Vigilantius, Jovinian, Aëtius, Eutyches, Felix, Wycliffe, Hus, and
other heretics; therefore one should not dispute with them.”154 The reproach
that disputation was vicious, which Luther had levelled against Scholasti-
cism and his Catholic opponents, is now turned against the heretics: they
lack fundamental docility; instead they just want to defend their tenets unto
death. Moreover they want to dispute, not in the presence of learned, edu-
cated individuals who are well-versed in theology, but rather (as in Zurich,
for example) “coram indoctis, vulgaribus laicis” [“before uneducated, common
lay people”], who are in no way capable of deciding such difficult questions
of faith. Furthermore, Eck has recourse to the condemnations of the new
doctrine by the universities (Paris, Spain, Oxford, Cambridge, Louvain/
Leuven, and Cologne). Disputation, an academic method of finding the
Only if suitable judges were present would a disputation still have any
value; otherwise the topical armamentarium of the Loci communes remains
the necessary preparation for the battle that is beginning in the Counter-
Reformation.
of his works, x–xiii. The commentary on the Sentences composed in Padua is unpublished: Paris,
Bibliothèque Nationale Cod. lat. 3076.
160. Johannes Capreolus, Defensiones theologiae Divi Thomae Aquinatis, ed. C. Paban—Th.
Pègues, 7 vols. (Tours, 1900–1908); see also Grabmann, “Johannes Capreolus.”
161. See Wicks, Cajetan, 10–19; Grabmann, “Stellung.”
162. See Hegyj, Bedeutung; Hallensleben, Communicatio, 53–220.
163. Cajetan, In I S.Th. prol. (1a).
164. Ibid., q.1 a.1 G (7a). (For the distinction see Cajetan, I S.Th., 5.38.)
165. Grabmann, “Cajetan,” 607–8.
274 Humanist and Reformation Theology
Aquinas’ understanding of theology, in its basic features, is valid for the
commentator as well. Yet the latter distinguishes much more precisely than
Thomas does between theologia dei [God’s knowledge of himself], the sub-
altern theologia in se [knowledge about God in himself] as a real science,
and theologia in nobis [knowledge about God in us, his creatures]—which
depending on one’s status is either the theology of the blessed or theolo-
gia viatorum [. . . of wayfarers, i.e., in salvation history]; in either case it is
only imperfectly a science and is moreover generally subordinated to God’s
knowledge. The discursive technique of our theology is regarded as an im-
perfection that is to be removed, and not as something constitutive for the
intuitive and necessary theological knowledge of God.166 Consequently
the first division of the sciences cannot be into theoretical and practical
sciences, but rather into infinite and finite knowledge. Only finite knowl-
edge is theoretical or practical. Therefore theology, regarded at first in prin-
ciple as the theology of God, can combine theoretical and practical knowl-
edge. What Thomas Aquinas attempted to resolve in terms of the theory
of science is now demonstrated metaphysically as a consequence of God’s
knowledge.167 Our theology, however, is nothing more than an “impressio
et sigillum proprium scientiae divinae” [“an impression and a particular seal
of divine knowledge”]; for both deal with God insofar as he is God (de Deo
inquantum Deus), but our knowledge does so in a derivative way, through
a slight but genuine participation in the light of God’s knowledge.168 This
provides the metaphysical proof for the speculative “theologia gloriae” that
Luther disputed; of course the boundary between acquired and infused the-
ology is less clearly emphasized. Our theology also grasps its formal object
(sub ratione Dei [considered in relation to God]) only in an epistemologi-
cal light that is diminished in comparison to the divine light, and therefore
it does not lead to a comprehensive knowledge of all truths about God.169
Remarkably, for his second proof for God as the subjectum theologiae, Ca-
jetan uses a Scotist argument that has been accommodated to Thomas: the
subject of a science contains the entire science virtually within itself. God,
however, is the subject of the articles of faith, which are the principles of
theology.170 In the question about the argumentative character of theology
(I q.1 a.8), Cajetan explicitly addresses the objection that Scholastic specu-
lative theology spends too much time on philosophical arguments that are
166. Cajetan, In I S.Th. q.1 a.1 F–G (6b–7b). 167. Ibid., q.1 a.4 C (12b–13a).
168. Ibid., E (12a). 169. Ibid., q.1 a.7 E (18ab).
170. Ibid., G (18b–20b); see also Leinsle, “Einheit der Wissenschaft nach Johannes Duns Scotus.”
Humanist and Reformation Theology 275
foreign to theology. Cajetan acknowledges that philosophical arguments
per se are foreign to theology. Yet the theologian may make use of them “ut
ministrae theologiae” [“as maidservants of theology”], and insofar as he does
this, they become genuinely theological arguments, even if only “ministerial-
iter” [“in an ancillary way”]. In particular, arguments from metaphysics and
natural philosophy are needed to refute opposing positions, to resolve ob-
jections and to declare the truths that theology deals with only secondarily,
for example, the existence and metaphysical attributes of God. Replying to
philosophical objections purely in terms of faith, however, makes theology
a laughingstock for philosophers.171
Luther’s meeting with the papal legate, Cajetan, in Augsburg in October
1518172 was thus the meeting of two very different intellectual paradigms and
theologies as well. Cajetan’s Augsburg treatises in the form of quaestiones—
“the first major work of controversial theology against the teachings and de-
mands of the Lutheran Reformation”—show this quite clearly.173 Cajetan’s
approach in countering Luther’s teachings is basically the one foreseen in
his commentary on the Summa: rational analysis within the framework of
natural reason, terminological clarification and the testing of theses against
accepted probative authorities. For Cajetan, however, the latter are of differ-
ent kinds (in contrast to Luther’s retreat to the position of “sola Scriptura”):
1. recta ratio [right reason] as the basis for philosophical-theological
argumentation;
2. the consensus of theologians; it is irresponsible to contradict it, especially
when this is done “sine ratione et sine auctoritate et contra communem
sententiam” [“without reason, without authority, and contrary to com-
mon opinion”];174
3. the sensus ecclesiae [mind of the Church], as a Spirit-wrought, infallible
guiding principle in the transmission of revelation, in questions of faith
and as an element of the Church’s unity;175
4. the official teaching of the Church, above all in papal decisions and bulls.
Luther’s anti-Thomistic stance, from as early as his controversy with
Tetzel (ca. 1465–1519) and Prierias (1456–1523), should be seen also as a con-
171. Cajetan, In I S.Th. q.1 a.8 F (21b–22a).
172. See Hennig, Cajetan und Luther; Wicks, Cajetan, 43–112; Morerod, Cajetan; Hallensleben,
Communicatio, 438–536; Lohse, Theologie, 125–34.
173. Wicks, Cajetan, 80–81; Cajetan, Opuscula omnia (Lyons, 1581), 91a–118b.
174. Cajetan, Opuscula, 108a.60–108b.2; see also Wicks, Cajetan, 86–93.
175. Cajetan, Opuscula, 103a.8; see also Cajetan, in II/II S.Th. q.1 a.1 (Leonine edition 7:8–10).
276 Humanist and Reformation Theology
frontation between the new theological claim that he makes for his asserti-
ones as opposed to Scholasticism, which because of its reliance on human
authority moves in principle solely at the level of opiniones.176 When Tetzel
appeals to Thomas and the latter’s approval by the Pope, this makes no more
impression on Luther than Cajetan’s insistence on the consensus among
theologians. Consensus usually comes about because later scholars are only
“yes-men and followers” of the opinions of our “dear cousins” [vetter, i.e.,
not quite “Fathers” = Väter] (Thomas, Bonaventure, Alexander of Hales).177
Thomas should not be considered an authority when he speaks without the
decisive probative authorities: Scripture, the Fathers, the canons, rationes.178
The decisive debate between Luther and Cajetan in Augsburg (conducted
in terms of the understanding of theology at that time) concerns the doc-
trine of the Church and her role with regard to Scripture: theses based (in
Luther’s view) on Scripture violate the norms of Scriptural interpretation,
ecclesial consensus and ecclesiastical decisions that are promoted by Ca-
jetan.179 Luther, given his understanding of Scripture and theology, could no
longer accept Cajetan’s insistence that in this case the official interpretation
of Scripture by the pope took precedence.180 The discrepancy between two
fundamental theological options was consequently obvious.
176. WA 1.647–48.
177. WA 1.384.
178. See Luther’s polemic against Prierias: WA 1.647–72.
179. WA Br. 1.238–39.
180. See also WA 2.9–16.
6 Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period
277
278 Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period
Ding, 369–70 (on Johann Heinrich Alsted [1588–1638]); Leinsle, Reformversuche, 27–28 ( Johann
Heinrich Bisterfeld [ca. 1605–1655]); 40–42 ( Johann Amos Comenius [1592–1670]).
7. See Leinsle, Dilinganae Disputationes, 17.
8. See Trunz, “Späthumanismus.”
9. See Paulsen, Geschichte, 1:219.
10. For example, the dispute about the “foundation candle” that was supposed to be handed
over to the bishop by the rector of the University of Dillingen: Specht, Geschichte, 140–43. On the
various sorts of Jesuit participation at or administration of universities, see also Hengst, Jesuiten.
11. See Codina Mír, Aux Sources; Leinsle, Dilinganae Disputationes, 27–48.
280 Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period
logiae of Aquinas. The decisive element, however, now became the profes-
sor’s dictation, although dictating lessons per se was prohibited—and not
only among the Jesuits.12 The lecture was accompanied by repetition as the
“sinew of instruction,” sometimes at the end of the lecture, at the beginning
of the next one, or at home at the residential college with “repetitors” who
were specially appointed for that purpose.13
Disputation was considered very important in all the confessions, de-
spite repeated objections from humanist and Reformation circles even at
Lutheran universities. Disputations were conducted in Greek and Hebrew
as well.14 Disputations were just the place to discuss current interreligious
questions or controversial issues within a confession. Above and beyond
the daily repetitions, we should distinguish at least the following:
eekly disputations in a smaller circle (disputationes circulares), in which
1. w
the students disputed publicly while a professor presided,15
2. m onthly disputations (disputationes menstruae), sometimes reduced to
four per year. In Dillingen, for example, they consisted of two two-hour
sessions in the morning and the afternoon and were supposed to cover
no more than twelve to fifteen theses. Seven argumentatores (opponents)
competed with five defendants.
3. ceremonial disputations (disputationes solemnes) pro gradu (leading to
the conferral of the baccalaureate, licentiate, master’s or doctor’s degree),
at the conclusion of a course (disputatio finalis) or on other important
occasions.16 At institutions of higher learning that were not authorized to
confer degrees (gymnasium illustre, lyceum) and at monastery schools the
degree disputations were omitted; graduation and occasional disputa-
tions were celebrated with eminent guests and considerable expense.17
18. See the pertinent sections of the HDG; for a summary from the Lutheran perspective:
W. Dantine, “Das Dogma im tridentinischen Katholizismus,” HDThG 2:411–98.
19. Fr. Diego Lainez (1512–1565) testified at the Council of Trent that the following were re-
quired in order to hear confessions: acquaintance with Latin, theological knowledge (mortal, ve-
nial sins, circumstances), canonical knowledge (reserved sins, ecclesiastical punishments): see also
H. Grisar, Iacobi Lainez secundi praepositi generalis Societatis Iesu Disputationes Tridentinae (Inns-
bruck, 1886), 2:440–41.
282 Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period
care of souls and the administration of the sacraments. The lecturer on the
Sentences is explicitly ordered to omit all useless questions that do not serve
to edify. In this program of instruction, which is basically still humanistic,
sacred Scripture and the Church Fathers are mentioned as the probative
authorities in explaining the Sentences. There is a strong warning against
quarreling, shouting, and useless questions during theological disputations,
which in 1550 were scheduled for the fifteenth of each month. Instead one
should modestly inquire about “veritas Catholicae et sanae doctrinae” [“the
truth of sound, Catholic doctrine”] and accept it charitably.20 In the initial
statutes from 1557 the lectures on the Sentences are expressly broadened to
include both Summas by Thomas Aquinas; Bonaventure and Alexander of
Hales are likewise recommended. This acknowledgment of Scholastic the-
ology still turns out to be critical, however: it must not be rejected, but any-
thing in it that does not pertain “ad rem,” that is, to edification in faith, hope,
and charity, should not be taught.21
Of far-reaching importance for the institutional theology of the post-
Tridentine era was the position accorded to it in the Ratio Studiorum of the
Jesuit Order. Ever since it took charge of the University of Coimbra (1542),
followed by the founding of Messina in 1548 and the takeover of Gandia in
1547 and of the Collegium Romanum in 1549, the Jesuits increasingly set
the tone for theological life in the early modern period.22 The Constitutions
from 1540 on already speak about Scholastic theology as the form of edu-
cation for members of the Society of Jesus, as distinguished from positive
theology.23 The latter comprises “conciliar decisions, works of ecclesiastical
writers, sections of canon law—excluding trial law—and moral themes or
writings.”24 Thus theology is arranged in three parts:
1. Sacred Scripture,
2. Scholastic theology,
3. positive theology.
Scholastic theology is bound up with the “doctrina Scholastica Divi
Thomae” [“Scholastic teaching of St. Thomas”], yet one should continue to
38. See Theiner, Entwicklung, 57–250; Quinto, Scholastica, 238–95; little attention is paid to
the development during the early modern period in Tshibanghu, Théologie positive (only Melchior
Cano is mentioned: 186–210).
39. Theiner, Entwicklung, 121.
40. On casuistry see Leites, ed., Conscience.
Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period 287
ics was understood as controversy with heretics (usually Protestants) over
those points of Catholic doctrine that they attacked. Here, too, the meth-
od was no longer that of Scholastic commentary but rather of the positive
presentation and apologetic refutation of false doctrines, often in connec-
tion with an explanation of the catechism.41 Often the professor of sacred
Scripture or a professor of Scholastic theology was one of the dignitaries in
charge of the debates.42
The decision as to which of the two courses a student should attend
was connected with the results of his philosophy examinations. If a student
did not display above-average speculative talent, he could not be admitted
to the cursus major. Merely average capacity was described as understand-
ing what was heard and read, and the ability to answer, although without
any special distinction in debating.43 This could easily give the impression
that the less gifted students were better suited (or good enough) for pasto-
ral ministry, while the Scholastic theologians lacked the requisite practical
skills. In order to prevent that misfortune, the 1591 plan of studies provides
for the establishment of a chair of moral theology in the cursus major also; in
1599, however, this was modified according to the custom in each individual
province.
The 1599 “Regulae Professoris Casuum Conscientiae” [“Rules for a Pro-
fessor of Casuistry”] immediately focus on educating “capable pastors or
ministers of the Sacraments.” Therefore the subjects taught are: sacraments,
ecclesiastical punishments, the duties of various states of life, and the Deca-
logue, whereby contracts are to be treated also under the seventh command-
ment. Less important matters are only to be discussed briefly: depositions,
demotions, magic, etc. Theological matters that have nothing to do with ca-
suistry should be omitted entirely; those that offer something of a founda-
tion for cases in moral theology should be noted briefly as definitions: for
example, what a sacramental character is, the difference between mortal sin
and venial sin, consent, etc. Expressly forbidden is the “apparatus scholasti-
cus,” that is, the usual method of disputation while quoting as many opinions
and arguments as possible. Moral theology works instead with dubitationes
[moral uncertainties] and conclusiones. Authorities should be cited sparingly;
general laws or rules should be illustrated by a few particular cases (around
three). Casuistic conferences, which serve as practical exercises, should be
41. A still indispensable study of the history of apologetics is, Werner, Apologetische Literatur.
42. This was the custom in Dillingen: Specht, Geschichte, 203.
43. See Theiner, Entwicklung, 212, 417.
288 Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period
clearly distinguished from Scholastic disputations. The “proof ” of one’s own
solution is carried out according to the principle of probability: one should
recognize also a certain probability in the rejected sententia according to the
reasons and authorities adduced in its favor.44
Out of this principle of probability developed “the most Jesuitical of
moral systems,” probabilism.45 In its simplest form this approach, which goes
back to Bartholomew Medina, O.P., is intended to facilitate moral judgment
of the individual specific act, and therefore it works to a great extent casu-
istically. In the individual case, however, one is often in doubt as to which
opinion to take as the basis for one’s action. The more certain or safer (tu-
tior) opinion then is the one which, if followed, enables the individual with
greater certainty to avoid breaking a law. On the other hand, the degree of
probability of an opinion depends on intrinsic reasons and on the authority
of the expert in the matter. The certainty and the probability of an opinion
can therefore differ in degree. For example, if there is doubt as to whether a
particular act is commanded or optional, or whether it is forbidden or per-
missible, according to probabilism one may morally follow the less certain
opinion, even if it is less probable (justifiable) [provided that there are solid
probable reasons for that opinion]. Probabilism with its subdivisions, which
have often been opposed and condemned as “laxism,” dominated moral
theology—not just of the Jesuits—and practical decision-making against
the opposition of tutiorism (one should follow the more certain opinion in
every case, even if a less certain opinion is more probable) and probabilior-
ism (one may follow a less certain opinion only if it is more probable than
the contrary opinion).46 Sometimes probabilists reply to the accusation of
laxism by painting probabiliorism as a form of Jansenism. The political con-
sequences of the moral system are displayed, not least, in its justification
of the alliance between France and the Turks. Within the Jesuit Order it-
self the Superior General Thyrsus Gonzalez (1624–1705) took steps against
radical, vulgarized probabilism, which caused a reaction that went so far as a
plan to depose him.47 Since the students of casuistry must have seemed less
gifted than the “Scholastics” anyway, the spread of a practical probabilism
or laxism was quite possible. Thus many considered as probable anything
that could be found in a book with an ecclesiastical imprimatur.
51. L. Babenstuber, Ethica Supernaturalis Salisburgensis sive Cursus Theologiae Moralis (Augs-
burg, 1718). Babenstuber explicitly describes himself as a “Theologiae, tum moralis, tum scholasticae,
necnon Sacrae Scripturae Professor” [“professor of both moral and Scholastic theology, as well as
Sacred Scripture”].
52. See below, 6.4.3.
53. In general, see Grabmann, Geschichte der katholischen Theologie, 147–205. Werner, Geschich-
te der katholischen Theologie.
54. See Jansen, “Scholastische Philosophie.”
55. See Jansen, “Thomisten.”
Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period 291
him the recognition of theologians. Besides the Dominican Order, which
was traditionally oriented to Thomas, the Discalced Carmelites (O.C.D.)
became especially zealous defenders of the teachings of the “Angelic Doc-
tor,” whom they were obliged to study by the statutes of their order.56 The
Universities of Salamanca and Alcalà became the center of Thomism in
Spain, which we can see in the great work of philosophical commentary
(on Aristotle) of the Complutenses (Alcalà) and in the Cursus theologicus
Salmanticensis (1631–1704). Francisco de Vitoria, O.P. († 1546) had already
brought the renewed Thomism to Salamanca from Paris. From there it went
into the Old and the New World through his students, the Tridentine con-
ciliar theologian Domingo de Soto, O.P. († 1560), the Oxford professor
Pedro de Soto († 1563), who also taught in Dillingen, and Melchior Cano
(† 1560, consecrated bishop of the Canary Islands 1552). The Superior Gen-
eral Philippus a SS. Trinitate, O.C.D. (Esprit Julien, 1603–1671), author of an
influential Summa theologiae thomisticae (5 vols., 1653) and a Summa theolo-
giae mysticae (1656), was for a time professor at his order’s house of studies
in Goa. The figures of Dominicus Báñez († 1604) and Bartholomaeus Me-
dina († 1581) lent particular weight to Salamancan Thomism in the contro-
versy de auxiliis, concerning the action of grace in conjunction with human
freedom [Gnadenhilfen]. The Cursus theologicus by the Portuguese Johannes
a S. Thoma ( Juan Poinsot, † 1644) acquired downright canonical impor-
tance. Thomism (initially of an Italian but later of a Spanish cast) found a
permanent home north of the Alps in the Benedictine University of Salz-
burg, which in turn radiated it to the monasteries and houses of studies of
the Benedictines, Cistercians, Augustinian Canons Regular, and Premon-
stratensians.57
The theology of the Scotists flourished a second time in the various
branches of the Franciscan family.58 Here too there was a tendency toward
a common discipline for the order. The 1633 General Chapter of the Friars
Minor in Toledo prescribed Scotism, as opposed to the earlier possibility
of choosing between the great friar-theologians, and commissioned a new
edition of the works of the Doctor subtilis. This was organized by the his-
torian of the order, Luke Wadding († 1657), at the Irish Franciscan Col-
lege of Saint Isidore in Rome (1639). Immediately the various branches of
78. May 1620: Theses theologicae (24 pp.); May 1621: Sponsalia (51 pp.); June 1621: Matrimonii im-
pedimenta (60 pp.); June 1621: Poenitentiae sacramentum (84 pp.); April 1622: Censurae (91 pp.); June
1622: Irregularitas (54 pp.); Jan. 1623: Suffragia (62 pp.); April 1623: Praedestinatio (38 pp.) June 1623:
Iesu Christi status triplex, mortalis, immortalis, sacramentalis (40 pp.; for his doctorate); June 1624:
Conscientia (78 pp.); Nov. 1624: Prolusiones theologicae (227 pp.); once for his doctorate, a second
time with another defendant for his licentiate); Feb. 1625: Eleemosyna (43 pp.); May 1625: Gratia
(63 pp.); see also Sommervogel, Bibliothèque, 1:1148–50.
79. See Leinsle, Dilinganae Disputationes, 37.
80. See Leinsle, Studium.
81. On Reding: Mittermüller, Beiträge, 19–21.
298 Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period
designed thesis page, which has been of interest mainly to art historians.82
Originally only the theses gathered from the defendant (often from ear-
lier pages) were posted on a display for vespers (on the afternoon before
the graduation).83 Especially when the patrons (“Maecenas”) were very
wealthy, at promotions in the presence of the prince-bishop, duke, or “sub
auspiciis Imperatoris” [“under the Emperor’s auspices”], the thesis pages
were designed as an exercise in Baroque symbolism with increasingly ex-
travagant (often emblematic) copperplate engravings “cum emblemate.”
In Augsburg a thriving business in printing thesis pages developed. These
served initially as a poster to announce the disputation and as a printed
invitation for special guests, but later as the “program” for those in atten-
dance, and finally as “trophies for the defendants and dedication pages for
the patrons”; as early as the seventeenth century, however, they also became
collector’s items.84 Thesis pages, like the frontispieces of published theses,
were also reused with different material. The text, which was only a small
portion anyway, was eliminated, for example, by pasting something else
over it. The philosophical or theological content of the thesis, which could
very well be omitted completely in the presentation copy, was frequently
reduced to a list of propositions that were printed, often in tiny type, in a
box or at the bottom margin of the page, which sometimes was composed
of several sheets of paper. The gift copies for the patrons sometimes had to
be printed on silk.85 When a graphically designed thesis page did not satisfy
the Baroque need for ostentation, the candidates had large thesis pictures
painted, sometimes also as the basis for the engraving. Only the beginning
of the Enlightenment would interfere with the disproportion between the
Baroque packaging and the meager contents of the thesis pages.86
87. See HDThG 2:306–52; 3:71–96; older literature: Ritschl, Dogmengeschichte; Althaus, Prinzip-
ien; Heppe, Dogmatik.
88. Overview in HDThG 2:102–38, 272–85.
89. Edition: BSLK 19676, 735–1110; see also HDThG 3:138–64.
90. BSLK 833, 9–16.
91. Ibid., 743, 42–49: “damit in unseren Landen und Gebieten denselben darin eingeführten und
je länger je mehr einschleichenden falschen verführerischen Lehren gesteuret und unsere Untertanen auf
rechter Bahn der einmal erkannten und bekannten göttlichen Wahrheit erhalten und nicht davon abge-
führet werden möchten.” [“so as to curb in our lands and territories those same false and seductive
teachings which have been introduced and which insinuate themselves more with each passing
day, and to keep our subjects on the right path of divine truth once it has been recognized and
professed, so that they may not be led astray from it.”]
300 Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period
works, law and Gospel, the Last Supper, Christology, predestination, and
church customs.
The Formula of Concord aimed at uniformity, even though it was by
no means generally accepted;92 the regional creeds of the Swiss and Calvin-
ist Reformation (e.g., the Confessio Helvetica posterior of Heinrich Bullinger
[1504–1575]) had nothing equivalent to offer.93 Although it was usually al-
lied with the Confessio Augustana [Augsburg Confession] and Melanch-
thon’s theology, Reformed theology came to oppose Lutheranism overtly
as a result of the second debate about the Last Supper and the formation
of regional confessions; it exhibited a more markedly regional character in
the individual schools (Bern, Geneva, Herborn, Heidelberg, Samur, Sedan,
Leiden, Groningen, Franeker, etc.).94
Both the Formula of Concord and the later creedal documents of the
Reformed Christians (and also the Heidelberg Catechism by Zacharias Ur-
sinus [1534–1583]) exhibited pronounced systematic tendencies. Neverthe-
less they still required a systematic theological interpretation. This is not
possible without an appropriate method and philosophy. Unlike Catholic
Scholasticism, Protestant Scholasticism could not have recourse to a ready-
made method but had to derive one—in a more or less deliberate way—
from contemporary philosophizing, which produced a plethora of treatises
De methodo [on methodology].95 The following were offered as such:
1. The relatively simple topical outline of Melanchthon and his school,
which restricted its understanding of philosophy to logic, ethics, and
physics and thus could readily be assimilated to theology. Following Mel-
anchthon’s example, the results were more or less systematically arranged
collections of loci or propositiones (axiomatic theology).
2. The dialectic of Peter Ramus (1515–1572) which was accepted especially
by Reformed Protestants and ran to 103 extant editions between 1581 and
1610 in the imperial realm alone.96 Originally quite antimetaphysical, Ra-
mus placed methodology at the center in the 1572 edition and outlined a
universal method of definition and arrangement based on conceptual logic
92. In Denmark it was forbidden under pain of death to propagate it; it was rejected by Eng-
land and important German territories.
93. See BSRK.
94. On the development of Reformed doctrine: HDThG 2:165–306; see also H. Leube, Kalvin-
ismus und Luthertum im Zeitalter der Orthodoxie (Leipzig, 1928; reprinted Aalen, 1966).
95. See Leinsle, Methodologie, 150–52.
96. See Ong, Ramus, 298; Bruyère, Méthode; Schmidt-Biggemann, Topica universalis, 47–48.
Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period 301
[begriffslogischer Natur]. This often resulted in tabular representations
of theology or of the sciences (e.g., Johann Heinrich Alsted [1588–1638],
Johannes Scharf [1595–1660]). The reception of Ramism in the school of
Melanchthon led to the development of the Philippo-Ramism that was
typical in the German schools before 1600, which was then combined
with Aristotelian elements in the methodus definitiva of Johannes Hülse-
mann (1602–1661) and Johann Adam Scherzer (1628–1683).
e Aristotelian methodology and theory of science in the Posterior
3. Th
Analytics, revived most notably by the Aristotelian movement in Padua
( Jacopo Zabarella [1533–1589], Francesco Piccolomini [1520–1604]).97
Unlike the Ramist arrangement, the methodus here is essentially de-
duction, argumentation, and syllogistic proof according to the rules of
the Posterior Analytics. All theoretical sciences are bound up with the
synthetic-deductive method, while all practical sciences rely on the ana-
lytic method (goal—means for attaining it).
In principle philosophy and theology can be pursued using all three
methods. The choice of one method is therefore often connected with the
local academic tradition (“philosophia recepta”). Continuing the tradition
of Catholic Scholasticism, or arguing with it, could be done most easily, of
course, with Aristotelian methodology and philosophy. Moreover Melanch-
thon and the later Ramus describe their methodologies as Aristotelian. If one
includes Aristotle in the theology curriculum, however, at least as a prepara-
tion, then soon there is one subject that one can no longer exclude: the Meta-
physics.98 Thus, for various reasons (intraconfessional disputes, polemics with
the Catholics, the humanist return to the complete works of Aristotle, the
methodological requirement of a First Philosophy), metaphysics was rein-
troduced around 1600 in Protestant institutions of higher learning.99 Schol-
ars dealt with it at least humanistically and philologically, even though—as in
Altdorf—they refused to accept the Scholastic-Jesuit metaphysics of Suárez
and Benedictus Pereira (1535–1610). The methodical development of meta-
physics, nevertheless, as argued by Lutherans Cornelius Martini (1567/68–
1621) in Helmstedt, Jakob Martini (1570–1649) in Wittenberg and Christoph
Scheibler (1589–1655) in Giessen, and among the Reformers by the contro-
versial Clemens Timpler (1563/4–1626) in Burgsteinfurt and Johann Heinrich
104. Johannes Gerhard, Loci theologici, ed. E. Preuss, vol. I (Berlin, 1863); see esp.: Wallmann,
Theologiebegriff; Schröder, Christologie; Kirste, Zeugnis.
105. In contrast to Scholastic theology, Melanchthon usually replaces the term with “doctrina”
or “Ecclesiastica doctrina,” e.g., CR 1:399–400.
106. See “Schema” in Schröder, Christologie, 45.
107. On Scaliger: Leinsle, Ding, 78–87.
108. Gerhard, Loci, prooem. §§1–3 (1:1); see also Wallmann, Theologiebegriff, 30–33.
304 Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period
it. This is the kind of theology that is actually scientific (accentuated here
as being systematic and polemical).109
The Synonymia is developed with the aid of the Rabbis, Scripture, and
the Fathers, from which the most important testimonials for the status and
importance of theology are also taken.110 The Pragmatologia opens with the
question as to the existence of theology (an sit), which is not insignificant
for the Lutheran tradition in view of Melanchthon’s silence and Luther’s re-
jection of Scholastic theology. The fact that there is such a thing as theology
is proved in a typical mixture from Scripture and philosophical (especially
Stoic) views:
1. from revelation as the efficient cause and principle of theology,
2. from the nature of God as “summum bonum communicativum et diffusi-
vum” [“the supreme good which communicates and diffuses itself ”],
which thus makes revelation possible in the first place,
3. from the end of creation: the knowledge of God,
4. f rom the natural endowment of man (a Stoic or Neoplatonic idea), the
natural and universal views of humankind (koinai ennoiai), along with
the obligation to worship God,
5. and consequently from the consensus gentium [consensus of the nations]
(another Stoic idea).111
The question of defining the nature of theology is answered syntheti-
cally by reviewing Scholastic and contemporary opinions.112 As the genus
proximum there is a choice between the Aristotelian habitus of science
(according to Thomas, with his arguments) and wisdom. If one wants to
squeeze theology into that framework, it can most readily be defined as wis-
dom, but more accurately as habitus νέος δότος [newly given habit], that is,
a habit granted by God and not (just) obtained through learning and prac-
tice.113 Gerhard sees clearly that theology can be grasped but inadequately
with the five Aristotelian habitus and has a different source than that of the
natural sciences. With the Franciscan tradition he maintains the at least in-
directly practical character of theology.114
109. Gerhard, Loci, prooem. §4 (1:1–2); see also Wallmann, Theologiebegriff, 33–45.
110. Gerhard, Loci, prooem. §§5–6 (1:2); on the inclusion of the rabbis, see also Steiger,
“Kirchenvater,” 59–61.
111. Ibid., §7 (1:2). 112. Ibid., §§8–31 (1:2–8).
113. From Aristoteles, Eth. Nik. A 10, 1099 b 12; see also Wallmann, Theologiebegriff, 71–75.
114. The practical character is strongly emphasized by Steiger, Johann Gerhard, 27–45.
Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period 305
The “division” of theology takes place whenever possible by way of di-
chotomy, as required by the later tabular presentations.115 Luther’s distinc-
tion between true and false theology is not a division, however, but rather
an equivocal use of language, since false theology (divided into vulgaris and
philosophica) cannot be considered as theology in the proper sense. True
theology can be observed in God (Ἀρχήτυπος), in Christ as the Head of the
Church (ἔκτυπος [the figure stamped out according to the pattern], theo-
logia unionis) and in rational creatures as its members. Here, according to
the subject’s status in salvation history, we should distinguish between the
theology of the saints who have already attained the beatific vision (wheth-
er angels or men, theologia comprehensorum) and that of believers who are
still on the way (theologia viatorum). The latter (theologia revelationis et viae)
is either natural or supernatural. Natural theology, which Gerhard has al-
ready presupposed in his proof of the existence of theology, is either innate
in the form of the κοιναὶ ἔννοιαι of universal human principles, or else ac-
quired. These principles are on the one hand of a theoretical nature, insofar
as they convince man of God’s existence, goodness and justice, but on the
other hand of a practical nature, insofar as they oblige him to worship God.
Acquired natural theology originates in the contemplation of creatures; a
distinction must be made according to its status in salvation history (un-
like innate natural theology, which is the same throughout history). Before
the fall it was substantially more complete than now, when according to the
Lutheran understanding only feeble vestiges of man’s likeness to God re-
main. Supernatural theology is found in an extraordinary manner in those
to whom revelation was entrusted (prophets, apostles), but ordinarily it
is acquired through the Lutheran triad of prayer, careful meditation while
reading and hearing Scripture, and testing by temptation (oratio, meditatio,
tentatio).116 Despite the overall practical orientation it can be divided into
theoretical and practical theology.
Supernatural theology is at all points a theology of revelation, founded
upon the God who reveals himself as the chief efficient cause and upon the
(internal and external) Word of God as the instrumental cause. Its adequate
epistemological principle [or principle of knowledge] is therefore revela-
tion, which is given definitively in sacred Scripture. In contrast, Thomas and
Capreolus notwithstanding, the articles of faith are not principles of theol-
115. See, for example, the division of J. Fr. König in Ratschow, Dogmatik, 1:32–33.
116. Summarized from Luther WA 50, 658, 29–659, 4; see also Wallmann, Theologiebegriff,
74–75.
306 Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period
ogy, but rather are themselves based on Scripture, which is proved in detail
from the attributes of principles according to the Posterior Analytics.117 In
no instance is human reason a second principle alongside revelation. The
recognition or adoption of natural truths in theology takes place purely on
the basis of the principles of revelation theology, which is to say, from Scrip-
ture. Therefore theological conclusions are unassailable, that is, not open to
criticism by philosophical reasoning. The theological truths that make up
the proper subject matter of theological instruction are consequently the
principles and conclusions derived from the revealed Word, their proper
epistemological principle [principle of knowledge]. Since theology ought
to serve the purpose of the glorification of God and the salvation of man,
and since its object, after the glorification of God, is man in need of re-
demption, the method suited to it is actually that of the practical sciences,
after the model of medicine: The first matter to be treated is the original
endowment and the fall of man, then the means to attain the goal. In the
concluding definition the concept of theology is summarized: “Theology
(considered systematically and abstractly) is a doctrine built up from the
Word of God, through which men are instructed in the true faith and in a
pious life unto eternal life. Considered as a habitus and concretely, theol-
ogy is a God-given habit, bestowed on man through the Word by the Holy
Spirit, which enables him, instructed through the illumination of his mind,
to affirm affectively with his heart what he has grasped with his understand-
ing upon recognizing the divine mysteries and to carry it out in deed unto
his salvation, but also to instruct others about these divine mysteries and
the way to salvation and to defend this heavenly truth against corruption
and gainsayers, so that men might be led by the true faith and good works to
the kingdom of heaven.”118
120. See Leinsle, Ding, 411–33; Tholuck, Geist, 185–211; Leube, Kalvinismus, 232–330; on his phi-
losophy, see Sparn, “Schulphilosophie,” 375–78.
121. A. Calov, Systema Locorum Theologicorum e Sacra potissimum Scriptura et antiquitate, nec
non adversariorum confessione, Doctrinam, Praxin et Controversiarum fidei tum veterum tum imprimis
recentiorum pertractationem luculentam exhibens (Wittenberg, 1655), Widmung (vol. I, Wid. 4–7).
122. Ibid. (I, Wid. 7–23).
123. Ibid., Proleg. c.1 s.2 q.15 (1:75–81): Utrum Theologiae scholasticae auctoritas sine fidei dis-
308 Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period
Cano’s praise for those who compiled sentences, summulas and quodlibets.
Together with the humanist critics, to whom Calov refers individually, one
should reject in particular the method of the Scholastics. “Theologia Patris-
tica et Scholastica” in this sense, as an historical discipline, forms only an un-
important addition to Theologia acroamatica (scientific theology).124
In another sense Calov himself professes a theologia scholastica, namely,
as one part of theology as a whole as it was clearly subdivided by Johann
Gerhard. This is defined as a practical habit of knowledge derived from di-
vine revelation; it deals with the true religion through which fallen man is
to be led through faith to eternal salvation.125 It should be subdivided into
theologia catechetica (catechetical instruction) and acroamatica (scientific
theology). The latter is divided into scholastica and ecclesiastica, whereby
Scholastic theology in turn falls under the headings of exegetica and didac-
tica, and the latter is further subdivided into polemic theology (contro-
versies) and systematic theology (loci communes). Ecclesiastical, or in the
special sense, “practical” theology, on the other hand, consists of ascetical
doctrine, homiletics, and casuistry. Theology is therefore at least partially
an academic discipline and therefore precisely in its systematic part requires
an academic method so as to attain its end of σωματοποίησις, the formation
of “unum corpus fidei” [“one body of faith”].126 Calov creates one by alternat-
ing theoremata didactica, doctrines or precepts, which are then explained in
detail (s. 1), and quaestiones (usually current controversies, s. 2), with a very
clear structure in each case (gainsayers or opponents—proofs of the thesis
while citing probative authorities exactly).
If we survey only the questions (seventeen in chapter 1 and twenty-one
in chapter 2) in the theory of theology, which runs to 267 pages, we can
speak at any rate about a certain re-Scholasticizing of Lutheran theology.
Thus, for example, in opposition to all supporters of absolute predestina-
tion there is a discussion of whether the theologia paradisiaca was based
purely on the Law or already on the Gospel, and what headings it con-
sisted of. In the seventeen loci communes of paradise theology, according to
crimine contemni, eiusque accuratiori Theologiae carere non possit? [Can the authority of Scholastic
theology be disregarded without imperilling the faith, and can one do without its more accurate
theology?] According to Cano a “scholasticus theologus” is someone “qui de deo, rebus divinis, apte
prudenter, docte literis institutisque sacris ratiocinetur” [“who reasons fittingly, prudently and learn-
edly about God and divine things by means of Sacred Scriptures and precepts”].
124. Ibid., s.1 (1:12–14). 125. Ibid. (1:1).
126. Ibid. (1:11–13).
Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period 309
Calov, not a trace of the Gospel is to be found.127 The philosopher Calov
pays particular attention, naturally, to the relation between philosophy and
theology.128 Luther’s teaching about the double truth, reiterated by Daniel
Hofmann, applies in Calov’s opinion only to propositions which necessar-
ily seem absurd to pure philosophy, such as “Verbum caro factum est” [“the
Word was made flesh”], and to the misuse of philosophy. Philosophy can by
no means be rejected as contradictory to theology, as beastly, earthly, im-
pure, and demonic (as the fanatics and theosophi claim). This is proved by
Romans 1:19–20; Romans 2:14 and from the common origin of philosophy
and theology in God, whose gifts they are, as even Melanchthon teaches.
Philosophy, moreover, leads us to the knowledge of God; the individual
disciplines thereof (physics, astronomy, music, arithmetic, geometry, ar-
chitecture, and practical philosophy) are praised in Scripture. Augustine
underscores the usefulness of philosophy for theology, especially in logic,
methodology, physics, and ethics, and it is recommended by the Church
Fathers. If, however, philosophy is to be learned from sacred Scripture, as
the “novelli prophetae” [“new prophets”] say, then how can it be carnal and
demonic? The only thing to be rejected is the misuse of philosophy, but by
no means the “notitia naturalis” [“natural knowledge”], which still exists in
man’s sinful state as a small vestige of his likeness to God. Apparent contra-
dictions are easy to resolve by making distinctions. Philosophy, neverthe-
less, should remain within its limits as a matter of principle. Calov strictly
rules out a mixture of philosophical and theological subjects.
Calov, a trained mathematician, was characteristically a systematic
thinker. Now the topical organization of the Loci no longer sufficed; a sys-
tem of loci had to be devised instead. Even more than in his 1655 Systema this
becomes evident in the Theologia positiva129 that he composed for his son
127. Ibid., s.2 q.3 (1:22–26). The loci are: de Deo, de creatione, de imagine Dei, de angelis, de provi-
dentia divina, de revelationibus Dei, de lege, de cultu et invocatione Dei, de sabbati sanctificatione, de pec-
cato et poena peccati, de Ecclesia et omnium hominum sanctorum cognitione, de Ministerio Ecclesiastico
(Adam übertragen mit Ehe- und Zeugungsauftrag), de Magisterio Politico (Herrschaft über Geschöpfe,
Vorrang des Mannes vor der Frau), de Conjugio, de Morte tum corporali, tum aeterna, de Fine huius vi-
tae, de vita aeterna. [on God, on creation, on the image of God, on the angels, on divine providence,
on God’s revelations, on the Law, on the worship and invocation of God, on keeping the Sabbath
holy, on sin and the punishment thereof, on the Church and the knowledge of all holy men, on
ecclesiastical ministry (Adam is charged with the duty of marriage and procreation), on political
authority (dominion over creatures, the precedence of man over woman), on marriage, on death—
both physical and eternal, on the end or goal of this life, on eternal life.]
128. Ibid., q.14 (1:67–75).
129. A. Calov, Theologia positiva, per definitiones, causas, affectiones, et distinctiones, locos Theo-
310 Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period
Abraham († 1685). In the Protestant tradition, as opposed to the Catholic,
“theologia positiva,” a translation of “θεολογία θετική,” designates the simple
presentation of theology in the form of theses with short proofs, dispensing
with quaestiones and controversies.130 Like Ariadne’s thread in the labyrinth,
it serves in the first place as a guide through the bewildering complexity of
Scriptural exegesis and thereby fulfills the original purpose of systematic
theology (e.g., in Peter Lombard). Thus Calov offers here the outline of a
Systema in 1,135 paragraphs printed on 610 octavo pages. The structure in it-
self follows the analytical method that is obligatory for practical sciences:
the end and the means for attaining it. Actually, though, this schema is com-
bined with a model from the theory of science which tries to explain the en-
tire structure of theology in terms of its definition (end—subject—means).
After the prolegomena about theology, religion, revelation, sacred Scripture,
and the articles of faith, the end or goal of theology is presented (part 1): God
and the blessed enjoyment of him (the latter topic, of course, is not treated,
but creation and providence instead). The subject of theology (part 2) is
subdivided into indirect (angels) and direct (man), resulting in angelognosia
and anthropologia (including sin, works, law, and Gospel). Then part 3 deals
with the causes and means of salvation, namely (sect. 1) the divine economy
of salvation (Christology, soteriology), the Church (Ecclesiometria, sect. 2),
the means of salvation from God’s perspective (word and sacrament, sect.
3) and from man’s (soteropoiia, sect. 4, in chapters that are often very short:
call to the Church, illumination, rebirth, conversion, justification, justifying
faith, repentance, mystical union with the faithful and with Christ, anoint-
ing by the Spirit, sanctification, glorification, sin against the Holy Spirit,
election, reprobation, the cross as the identification papers or passport of
the elect), divine legislation (divina nomothesia in the Decalogue, sect. 5),
and eschatology (sect. 6, in eight articles).
This structure clearly shows the intention to proceed reflectively, me-
thodically and systematically, which collides, however, with the theological
material. Whereas most of the third part, “de causis et mediis salutis” can be
explained in terms of the analytical structure, even this arrangement would
allow for alternative ways of including certain individual doctrines, for ex-
logicos universos, succincte, justoque ordine proponens: Ceu Compendium Systematis Theologici (Wit-
tenberg, 1682).
130. Ibid., Dedication: “Theologia positiva, qua thesin et dicta probantia sibi familiarem reddiderit,
solidum fundamentum iacturum universae Theologiae.” [“With positive theology, whereby the reader
will become acquainted with the thesis and the proofs, he will lay the foundation of universal the-
ology.”]
Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period 311
ample, Law and Gospel (nomothesia) and eschatology. The arrangement
of the soteropoiia still clearly betrays the topical origin of the individual
loci. The theologia positiva also shows, however, the tendency of Protestant
“Scholastic” theology, which had again become academic, to produce small-
er and smaller mnemonically organized textbooks for memorization and
reference in school.131
136. Ibid., Proleg. §16 (4). 137. Ibid., loc.8 §25 (221–39).
138. See Reichert, Johannes Scheffler.
139. Johann Adam Scherzer, Vade mecum sive Manuale philosophicum, reprinting of the 1675
Leipzig edition, edited with an introduction by Stephan Meier-Oeser (Stuttgart–Bad Cannstatt,
1996); see also Leinsle, Reformversuche, 21–22; Leinsle, Dilinganae Disputationes, 73–79.
140. Scherzer, Systema Theologiae, loc. 28 (843–72).
141. Scherzer, Breviculus theologicus, Unica Positione generali, Systema Theologiae exhibens (1675).
Edition consulted: (Leipzig, 1687). German edition: Kurzer Weg und Handgriff durch einen Haupt-
satz den Kern Heiliger Schrifft zu fassen (Leipzig, 1677); new edition 1732.
Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period 313
ology. All forty-three loci of theology are supposed to be contained in this
sentence, which is composed as a comprehensive definition of “theologia.”
In the explanations the previously listed opponents are noted only by ab-
breviations in the margins.
The revealed theology of human beings on their pilgrim way (the only
kind of theology treated here) is accordingly the wisdom which hands down,
explains and defends the true religion for the honor of God and the salva-
tion of mankind (loc. 1, de theologia); it does so on the basis of sacred Scrip-
ture. The latter consists of the Law and the Gospel; it is worthy of belief
both in light of God’s truthfulness and also on its own merits; it is one,
true, good and thus catholica (loc. 2, de Scriptura). It is revealed by God.
He is indefinable, pure spirit, everlasting, immortal, immense, omnipres-
ent, uniquely eternal, without temporal duration, omniscient, omnipotent,
supremely good; in accordance with his stern and equally merciful will he
imparts himself to all, but punishes with the necessary severity. He alone
therefore is to be honored in religion (loc. 3, de Deo). He is by nature one in
three Persons (loc. 4, de Trinitate). The Father begets the Son, who is truly
God, of the same nature as the Father; of the ever-Virgin Mary he became
the God-Man, fully God and fully man in the hypostatic union (and he is
consequently the Son of God according to his human nature also) with the
communication of the idiomata. He exercises a threefold ministry; for he
is anointed by the Holy Spirit with immeasurable riches to be the prophet
of the Good News, the sole and sinless priest of the New Testament, and
king. Thus he is mediator between the two natures, and through the obedi-
ence of his life and death he makes satisfaction and is thereby for us the
one universal Savior and Redeemer. He divests himself of everything, even
unto death. Although during the three days of his death the natural bond
between his soul and his body is broken, the latter was not a cadaver, nor
did Christ cease to exist during that time. After the revival of his humanity
by his own power and his exaltation, he is the future judge of the living and
the dead (loc. 5, de Christo). The Holy Spirit proceeds as the Third Divine
Person from the Father and the Son (loc. 6, de Spiritu Sancto). The whole
Trinity, however, is the Creator of the universe, that is, of heaven and earth
(loc. 7, de creatione), of the angels (some of whom were confirmed in their
original goodness after the voluntary fall of the others; loc. 8, de angelis) and
of men, the first of whom was Adam (loc. 9, de homine). Man and woman in
their original state were perfect, immortal, and supremely happy (loc. 10, de
imagine Dei); they fell however through their own fault and are now subject
314 Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period
to sin from conception and without exception (not even Mary; loc. 11, de
lapsu et peccato), completely dead to what is spiritual (loc. 12, de servo arbi-
trio). They can be reborn therefore only through an external cause (loc. 13,
de regeneratione) and restored through the Word and the two salvific sacra-
ments (the efficacy of which depends solely on God’s command and not on
the intention or holiness of the minister; loc. 14, de sacramentis in genere),
namely, Baptism by water (loc. 15, de Baptismo) and the Eucharist (loc. 16,
de Eucharistia), in the Church under Christ as the sole Head, who can have
no substitute or vicar (loc. 17, de Ecclesia). After previously applying the
pedagogy addressed to the natural light of reason through the Word (i.e.,
through gratia sufficiens or efficax, which however is not irresistible), God
calls all men to the Church (loc. 18, de vocatione) as penitents (loc. 19, de
poenitentia) through the forgiveness of sins (loc. 20, de absolutione). Instead
of these sins, the active and passive justice of Christ is imputed to men,
who are justified through faith alone without works (loc. 21, de justifica-
tione); they become holy, however, by living in consideration of God, their
neighbor and themselves (loc. 22, de bonis operibus), without giving scandal
(loc. 23, de scandalo), [and thus] finally are found to be true to that faith
which is the sole object of predestination in man (loc. 25, de praedestina-
tione) and the purpose of providence (loc. 26, de providentia), and after this
earthly life (loc. 26, de termino vitae) die in that faith (loc. 27, de morte). The
reprobate, however, on account of their unbelief, will be punished at the
end of their lives in hell with the devils for eternity, deprived of the vision
of God, and the glory of the blessed (loc. 28, de damnatis et inferno); anyone
who departs with genuine trust in Christ comes immediately to heaven into
the presence of God and will rejoice with the blessed (loc. 29, de statu pio-
rum post mortem). After the resurrection of the numerically [but not quali-
tatively] identical bodies [of the departed], regardless of their sex or state
of life (loc. 30, de resurrectione), and after the Last Judgment of the damned
(without the thousand-year reign of the Chiliasts; loc. 31, de extremo judi-
cio) and the end of the world (loc. 32, de consummation saeculi), they will
receive again, in glorified form, their former bodies and in them they will
behold God in perfect, ineffable, eternal beatitude (loc. 33, de glorificatione
et vita aeterna). According to divine law, all men are equal, notwithstand-
ing their hierarchical position (loc. 34, de tribus Hierarchiis): whether they
are legitimately called and ordained ministers of the Church or their hearers
(loc. 35, de ministerio ecclesiastico), whether they are the political authorities
established by God or their subjects (loc. 36, de magistrate politico), whether
Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period 315
they are tradesmen (loc. 37, de statu oeconomico), single, or married, that is,
united with one another by a humanly indissoluble bond, or their children,
servants or maids (loc. 38, de coelibatu et conjugio), or finally even the uni-
versal enemy, the Antichrist (loc. 39, de Antichristo), all heretics (loc. 40, de
Haeresi), schismatics (loc. 41, de Schismate), apostates (loc. 42, de Aposta-
sia), those who are unwilling to profess allegiance to any religion (neutrales)
or, like the syncretists, those who try to abolish the differences between the
confessions (loc. 43, de Syncretismo).142
With that, in Scherzer’s view, he has completely described theology,
but also the world of God’s creation until Judgment Day and mankind in all
possible ecclesiastical and secular manifestations. Theology thus makes an
encyclopedic claim, which is reminiscent of Johann Amos Comenius’ Orbis
pictus. On the other hand theology itself has become the framework of an
ontologized Bible that is squeezed into the loci of orthodoxy; since there is
no way to amplify it further, all that remains is to defend it.
145. Alsted, Triumphus Bibliorum Sacrorum Seu Encyclopaedia Biblica (Frankfurt, 1625), “Mens
authoris in hoc opera” (2r); see also Leinsle, “Lehet,” 248–51.
146. Alsted, Triumphus, Praef. (5v).
147. Ibid., Technologia sacra n. 3 (10); with references to 1 Kings 4:29–33; 2 Timothy 3:16; Exo-
dus 21; Genesis 50:2; Colossians 4:14; Ezra 3:2–3.; Sirach 43:2–6.
148. Ibid., n. 7 (13); elaborated on 286–413.
149. Alsted, Encyclopaedia 4:1505–49.
150. See Leinsle, Ding, 382–83.
151. Alsted, Encyclopaedia, Theol. s.1 c.1 (5:1555); on Keckermann’s concept of theology, see
also Frank, Vernunft, 186–204.
Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period 317
vided first into general and special parts. The general part teaches what is
necessary for man to know, believe and do in order to reach the goal men-
tioned in the definition. According to the epistemological principle, theol-
ogy is either natural or supernatural. The natural type is based on the natu-
ral light of reason (with innate principles) and, on the other hand, on the
book of nature (world and man). Its goal is the necessary knowledge about
the existence and supremacy of God as well as about the obligation to wor-
ship God and to love one’s fellow man. Now all this can readily be known,
independently of revelation, from the nature of reason, man and the world.
Natural theology therefore remains for Alsted the basis of revelation theol-
ogy also.152
Initially this is conveyed catechetically in the Theologia catechetica as a
compendium of the Christian religion which, modeled on the Hessian Cat-
echism of 1607,153 consists of five chapters: Creed, Ten Commandments,
Our Father, Baptism, and Lord’s Supper. For this theology, too, a special
modus docendi scholasticus [academic method of teaching] with three cat-
echism classes is envisaged besides the modus domesticus and ecclesiasticus
[home and church methods].154 Corresponding exactly to catechetics in its
structure is casuistry, which of course deals with the cases of conscience and
doubts arising from catechesis.155 Besides catechetical instruction there is
the ecclesiastical form in preaching and church institutions [Einrichtungen].
This is the object of theologia prophetica, the teaching of the prophetic, that
is, pastoral ministry in the Church. It consists of instructional preaching
(rhetorica ecclesiastica) and politia ecclesiastica, teaching about church pol-
ity with regard to persons and things.156 Moral theology (in its noncasuistic
form), finally, has the goal of forming morals that are worthy of a Christian.
After the pattern of practical philosophy it is subdivided into individual
ethics, economics [household management] and politics, and it presents
its teaching about the duties of all states of life (including that of the status
scholasticus with the duties of tutors, professors, and students) in the form
of rules that can be memorized easily.157
The really systematic theology, however, is the theologia didactica. This
is the system of forty-six loci theologici which have now been subdivided di-
152. Alsted, Encyclopaedia, Theol. s.1 c.1 (5:1555–65).
153. BSRK 822–33.
154. Alsted, Encyclopaedia, Theol. s.2 c.1 (5:1565–66); Theologia Catechetica: 5:1565–74.
155. Alsted, Encyclopaedia, Theol. s.5 (5:1662–74).
156. Ibid., s.6 (5:1674–84).
157. Ibid., s.7 (5:1684–90).
318 Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period
chotomously.158 Although he had still included it in 1625, Alsted now dis-
penses with the theologia positiva, which contains principles taken directly
out of Scripture. Instead he incorporates the positive theology into the di-
dactic, but distinguishes carefully between regulae positivae, which require
simple assent, and regulae didacticae, which serve to elucidate, to confirm,
or to refute false doctrines.159 Thus in loc. 1 (de sacra scriptura) we find the
following positive rules:
1. Scripture is inspired by God.
2. I t is a light, that is, clear [in itself, perspicuous] and a guiding principle
of faith and living.
3. It is complete.
4. It is to be read by all Christians.
5. It is read with different results, however, by the pious and the godless.
In Alsted’s writings also, didactic theology as a whole can be summarized
dichotomously in a comprehensive definition:160 It deals with sacred Scrip-
ture as the principle of all dogmas (loc. 1) and with the dogmas contained
therein, namely, God (loc. 2) and his works and deeds (loc. 3). The latter are
either eternal—in general his decrees (loc. 4), but in particular his providence
(loc. 5) and predestination (loc. 6)—or else temporal in their fulfillment. The
fulfillment of providence consists of creation (loc. 7) and his governance of
the universe (loc. 8), specifically of non-rational (loc. 9) and of rational na-
ture (loc. 10), that is, of the angels (loc. 11) and of men. Before the fall this
concerns the image and likeness of God (loc. 12) and the natural covenant
(loc. 13); after the fall, however, it concerns free will (loc. 14), sin (loc. 15) and
the limitation thereof through the law in general (loc. 16), but in particular
through marriage (loc. 17), political authority (loc. 18), and school (loc. 19).
In this life predestination is exercised with regard to the angels (loc. 20) and
men under the covenant of grace, which should be considered according to its
form (loc. 21) and its foundation, the mediator Christ (loc. 22). The [practi-
cal] application [Anwendung] of the covenant of grace is proclaimed by the
Gospel (loc. 23) in the Church as an assembly (loc. 24) under a leadership
that consists chiefly and most profoundly of the administration of God’s
gifts of grace, the most important of which is vocation (loc. 25)—with the
operation of repentance (loc. 26), faith (loc. 27) and holiness (loc. 28)—jus-
179. Ibid., c.12–13 (113–163). The manner of their movement is discussed at length.
180. Ibid., c.11 (93–113); see also Goudriaan, Gotteserkenntnis, 202–30.
181. Wittich, Theol. pacif. c.14–15. (163–94).
182. Ibid., c.16 (194–95); see also Knebel, “Necessitas moralis ad optimum”; Ramelow, Gott.
183. Wittich, Theol. pac. c.16 (194–216).
Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period 323
cal and soteriological questions a sort of linguistic criticism and exegetical
procedure that also dominates his interpretation of controversial passages
in the final chapters of his work.184 The “Scholastic” inquiries of Reformed
orthodoxy are rethought here on the basis of a new philosophy, which
certainly does not answer all the questions in the usual way yet despite its
unique character as a dualistic, voluntaristic metaphysics does not shatter
the fundamental theoretical framework of “scholastic” Protestant theology.
Sparn, “Subjekte,” 173–79: the connection in Protestantism concerns mainly the doctrine of pre-
destination and not the teaching about grace.
188. F. Suárez, De Incarnatione, disp. 31 s.5–6, in Opera omnia (Paris, 1877), 18:103–152; on the
development of Suárez’ teaching on grace: Stegmüller, Gnadenlehre.
189. See O. Wanke in HWPh 7:1166, where, however, he does not discuss the potentia oboedien-
tialis activa in the writings of Suárez.
190. Suárez, De Incarn. disp.31 s.5 n.7 (18:105–106b).
Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period 325
has to be discussed according to all the criteria for developing a theological
theory:
1. I t is free from contradiction. It is not logically inconsistent that God
designed creatures in that way.
2. I t has a certain degree of probability and credibility based on reasonable
arguments and authorities.
3. It resolves the questions related to the matter without excessive
difficulties.
Being a genuine metaphysician, Suárez regards the active instrumental-
ity of creatures as something already present in the complete concept of cre-
ated being. This instrumentality does not become active, however, without
the agens principale, just as a tool cannot work by itself.191 Furthermore it
does not mean a directly active ability to do something independently, but
rather only a more remote condition which makes the creature not potens
[“able,” in the sense of having both power and mastery] but rather capax
[capable] of being elevated by God to a supernatural mode of operation.192
Like any new theory, this one also faces formidable objections, which
Suárez meticulously lists and ultimately refutes. Particularly weighty is the
accusation that it involves a subtle Pelagianism and a confusion of the natu-
ral and the supernatural orders, since the theory assumes a natural endow-
ment of man to accomplish what is supernatural and thus appears to deny
the absolute necessity of grace for any good work.193 Suárez initially carries
out the positive proof of the new theory starting from metaphysical prin-
ciples that are acknowledged by his opponents also:
1. Action presupposes in its cause a power to act.
2. Th
e power to act as an instrument is not a special, superadded quality in
God’s instruments over and above their ontological endowment.
3. The power to act as God’s instrument is not a movement transferred to
the instrument.194
Based on these premises, Suárez defines what the “elevation” of the
creature to an instrument of God actually involves. It is not purely a matter
of terminology, nor is it a mere subordination to God’s will; rather it signi-
fies the elaboration of a creaturely endowment to a higher or nobler status.
191. Ibid., s.5 n.8 (106b–107a). 192. Ibid., s.5 n.9 (107a).
193. Ibid., s.6 n.4 (108a). 194. Ibid., s.6 n.10–17 (110b–114b).
326 Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period
Therefore it presupposes something that is elevated and an “agens superius”
[“higher agent”] that brings about this elevation with a superior natural
[physischer] efficacy. Here again there are three possibilities:
1. The entire operative power is imparted to the thing through the addition
of an inner form: for example, the warming of water.
2. Th
rough the addition of an inner form a potency, which by itself is insuf-
ficient, is rendered capable of operating (e.g., understanding and will
through grace to perform supernatural works).
3. Th
e operative power is perfected through union with an external cause
and is thus enabled to perform an operation for which the thing by itself
is incapable and unsuited. This is precisely the case with elevation to the
status of an instrument of God; it presupposes however a “vis activa et
intrinseca” [“an active, intrinsic power”] on the part of the thing being
elevated.195
Suárez defends himself vigorously against the suspicion of Pelagianism
yet at the same time admits that his theory includes within the creaturely
endowment of man a causal element which is partially responsible for su-
pernatural operations. By themselves, however, creatures cannot produce
such effects (as instruments), but rather only with a kind of supernatural
help, the nature of which is left unspecified.196 Indeed, the precise manner
of this supernatural help is the subject of the debate “de auxiliis.” The foun-
dation of cooperation with God (fundamentum cooperationis), however,
must exist in nature. For Suárez this is in no way Pelagianism but rather
the safeguarding of human freedom against Luther’s view.197 In order for
a created entity to be capable of being taken up by God as an instrument
in the full sense, therefore, we must assume that there is within it, by virtue
of its ontological endowment, an activity oriented toward this instrumen-
tal operation. Before its elevation to the status of an instrument, neverthe-
less, this is only a fundamental, rather remote disposition to “obedience”
vis-à-vis God’s action.198 The creature is by no means purely passive with
regard to this elevation to instrumental status; this happens, rather, through
214. Mastrius, I Sent. disp.3 q.3 f. (126b–187a); see also Anfray, “Prescience,” 556–86.
215. On Palacios (Palatius) see: Hurter, Nomenclator, 3:143.
216. See 6.3.4.; Anfray, “Prescience,” 580–83.
217. Mastrius, I Sent. disp.3 q.3 a.1–7 (126b–52b); see also Anfray, “Prescience,” 583–86.
218. Mastrius, I Sent. disp.3 q.3 a.8 (153ab); see also Anfray, “Prescience,” 586–91.
Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period 333
dependency but rather a mere simultaneity. With his sententia, which is au-
thenticated directly from Duns Scotus, Mastrius intends to take a middle
position between Thomists and “Neutrales,” who in their hypothesis of the
scientia media regard God’s knowledge as being dependent on man’s free de-
cision and therefore advocate a decretum sequens [subsequent decree] rather
than a decretum concomitans. The logical difference between a temporal hu-
man decision and an eternal divine decision should also find linguistic ex-
pression. Therefore we should say: from all eternity God has concomitantly
(thus simultaneously) defined the future free decisions of the created will.
This accompanying decree of God is at the same time the suitable medium
of God’s knowledge about our future free decisions.219
The proof of the Scotist teaching initially proceeds a posteriori from the
assignment of human perfections to God (the simultaneity of identical de-
cisions in two subjects), then a priori from the (typically Scotist) virtual
presence of all things contained in God: God as the First Cause virtually
contains within himself the powers of all secondary causes and can cause all
the effects of the secondary causes with or without them; in the same way
he contains virtually within himself as the “primum intelligens et intelligibile”
[“first intelligent subject and intelligible object”] all possible objects of un-
derstanding; likewise as the primum liberum [first free subject] he contains
within himself virtually all possible free decisions of creatures. Therefore he
can not only determine in advance all his own decisions, but also all those
which he voluntarily allows to occur at a particular future moment through
the action of secondary causes, in such a manner that they agree exactly
with his eternal decree. In this case freedom is not abolished, since the self-
determination of the created will to its corresponding effect continues to
exist.220
God’s foreknowledge is not the cause of the future existence of creature-
ly decisions. It is therefore not antecedent either, but rather logically simul-
taneous with (concomitans) or even logically later than (as the Jesuits main-
tained) the human being’s free decision. Therefore we cannot speak about
an external necessity, but only about an inferential necessity, comparable to
219. Mastrius, I Sent. disp.3 q.3 a.8 (153b): “Dicemus itaque in hoc sensu Deum ab aeterno concom-
itanter determinasse eventus liberos a creata voluntate futuros, et tale decretum esse sufficiens, ac idoneum
medium ad eos certo cognoscendos, etiam quatenus libere eventuros.” [“And so in this sense we will say
that God from all eternity concomitantly determined future free decisions made by a created will,
and that this decree is sufficient and the suitable medium in which to know them with certainty,
even insofar as they will occur freely.”]
220. Ibid. (155b).
334 Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period
the inference from the (natural) sign (smoke) to the object (fire): With this
sort of necessity one could conclude the future occurrence of an event from
an acquaintance with God’s foreknowledge.221 Mastrius advocates this ba-
sic position (along with the Thomists against the Jesuits) also with regard
to future free conditional decisions (futura contingentia conditionata). State-
ments about them acquire their definite truth only through corresponding
conditional decrees of God.222
The Scotist Mastrius explicitly acknowledges his allegiance to a school:
this linguistic usage should be accepted “in schola nostra” because it is rea-
sonable (proof) and at the same time agrees with the teaching of Duns Sco-
tus (authority).223
231. Ibid., s.3 (217a–18b); see also Knebel, “Necessitas,” 16–19; Sparn, “Subjekte von Freiheit,” 181.
232. Arriaga, Disp. theol. l.1 disp. 21 s.4 (218a).
233. See Knebel, “Scientia media,” 288; discussed in detail, e.g., in Hermann, De Deo sciente,
q.7 (283–359).
Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period 337
forgotten what I knew at point A. Thus at any later point in time I act as
though I had forgotten that I already knew at an earlier time how I would act.
That means that I am still free. In retrospect then I can say: I acted exactly in
accordance with my foreknowledge.234
Nor is man’s freedom impaired through this knowledge about future
conditional statements. This is because the actual accomplishment of the
matter in question (e.g., Peter’s conversion) remains within the scope of
man’s freedom. Thus there is no scientia media of the conversion of a specific
man (Peter):
a) if that man does not exist, or
b) if he does not correspond to the helping grace.
According to Arriaga, therefore, the man could say to himself at the mo-
ment when he exercises his freedom: “I can cause God to have no scientia
media of my conversion. If I do not correspond to the helping grace that he
has granted, then I cause God from all eternity to have no knowledge about
my cooperation (as a futuritio absoluta). Therefore God’s knowledge (exclu-
sively in this regard) is in my power.”235
Nevertheless God, too, remains free in bestowing his helping graces
and in his predestinating will. Before predestination, Peter and Judas are in
principle the same. If God knows through his scientia media, for example,
that Peter and Judas will correspond to four helping graces but will reject
four others, then according to his predestinating decision he will give to Pe-
ter one of the four that he corresponds to, but to Judas one that he rejects.
One might object that then there could be a person who would accept or
reject (creatura rebellis) all of them, and therefore would have to be saved
or damned; Arriaga counters by making a simple distinction: that is indeed
metaphysically (logically) possible, but not morally. Besides, God could
then still create only the one who accepts all the helping graces, but not the
other one. A human being is still free with respect to a helping grace insofar
as he makes that help, without which he cannot be saved (auxilium efficax)
effective through his action. A helping grace therefore does not work inde-
pendently of or antecedent to the human being’s actual deed.236
234. Arriaga, Disp. theol. l.1 disp. 21 s.4 (219ab); see also Sparn, “Subjekte von Freiheit,” 182–184.
The fact that the doctrine of scientia media also led to “florida ingeniorum exercitamenta, seu lusus”
[“extravagant exercises or games of ingenuity”] is noted already by, Henao, Scientia media, 396b.
235. Arriaga, Disp. theol. l.1 disp. 21 s.5 (221a).
236. Arriaga, Disp. theol. l.1 disp. 21 s.6 a.2 (222ab); see also Knebel, Wille, 186–87.
338 Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period
The truth or falsity of disparate conditional statements without a causal
connection is also known by God. In contrast, Arriaga (unlike Pedro de Ar-
rúbal [1559–1608]) is cautious about impossible conditional statements: “If
the chimera were free and were prompted by a helping grace of this sort,
she would correspond to it.” Such knowledge has no discernible purpose;
knowledge about individual propositions could be multiplied uselessly in
this way: “If this water atom were an angel, would it then be Michael or
Gabriel or some other one among all possible angels?” Such speculations,
while they show the logical possibilities of the calculus and the ultimate
ramifications of a fruitful theory, bring into disrepute the legitimate con-
cern of the scientia media in the doctrine about creation, predestination and
grace.237
249. Babenstuber, Philosophia l.2 Phys. disp.5 a.2 §1 n.1 (243a); see also Bauer, Metaphysik,
540–49.
250. Babenstuber, Philosophia l.2 Phys. disp.5 a.2 §1 n.2 (243a): “physica et realis motio a solo deo
procedens, causae creatae transeunter impressa, prioritate naturae praecedens ipsius operationem, ean-
demque causam constituens in ratione principii actualis et efficaciter applicans ad operandum conformiter
naturae ipsius”; see also Bauer, Metaphysik, 561–62.
251. Babenstuber, Philosophia l.2 Phys. disp.5 a.2 §1 n.5 (243b).
344 Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period
Thomas, rational arguments in particular are brought to bear here. Baben-
stuber presents five arguments that recur again and again in the Thomistic
teaching tradition, which are connected in part to the argumentation of the
quinque viae [five ways, i.e., of proving the existence of God] and thus un-
derscore the central position of the theory of physical predetermination in
the Thomistic view of God and creation:
1. The Aristotelian subordination of secondary causes to the First Cause
(cf. via II) is inconceivable without praemotio physica.252
2. E very secondary mover is moved by a first mover (cf. via I). The move-
ment of the second by the first is precisely this praemotio physica.253
3. D enial of the praemotio physica makes the secondary cause the first mover:
a consequence which is manifestly false and absurd to a metaphysician.254
4. Th e created free will is indifferent as to whether it will decide this way
or that; for freedom (libertas a necessitate) is plainly defined as indiffer-
ence or the freedom to decide between contrary actions.255 It therefore
requires a determination from outside by the First Cause, which is the
only thing that can move the created will internally. This determination,
which is causally antecedent to the free action, is the praedeterminatio
physica.256
5. I n order to act, the creature must first be so organized by its actus primus
(ontological constitution) as to function as an actus secundus (actual
principle of action). The constitutive factor is the praemotio physica.
Consequently there must be such a thing (i.e., it exists in keeping with
the theory). The praemotio physica is furthermore the causal principle of
action (actus secundus causalis), which immediately enables the second-
ary cause to perform real actions (actus secundus formalis).257
Contrary to the objections of the Jesuits and Scotists that the anteced-
ent determination by God abolishes man’s freedom, Babenstuber sees in it
The praedeterminatio is constitutive not only for the ability but also for
the action itself. Without it, man does not possess the full capacity to place
an act; for this is precisely what empowers him to act in the first place and
thereby frees him to exercise freedom. The mere capability (potentia proxima
expedita) to place the contrary act, however, is not abolished by the physical
predetermination, for example, to love God or hate him. For the contrary
act, however, God gives only the ontological capacity in the sphere of the ac-
tus primus (mere ability), whereas for the predetermined act he gives the real
action (actus secundus) along with the ability.260 The freedom imparted in the
praedeterminatio physica is real, positive liberation to act and is not compa-
rable with the simple application of fire to combustible material (physical
applicatio) or the mere lack of chains as freedom to go.261 Creaturely free-
dom in this Thomistic sense is always a freedom that is granted and caused,
not just man’s self-determination in his actions. A self-determination of man
(as a secondary cause) presupposes, rather, the determination by the First
Cause and is made possible by it. The necessity with which the praedetermi-
natio physica works is only the conditional necessity of a consequence that
is subsequently observed [festgestellte]; this is of course infallible. The fun-
damental ontological freedom to act otherwise does continue to exist; the
contrary act, however, is not compatible with the circumstances of the agent
that were created by the praemotio physica. Consequently for the contrary act
a corresponding praemotio would again be required.262 This theory does not
258. Ibid., §4 n.40 (259b) citing Summa Th. I q.38 a1 ad3 and I-II q.10 a.4. i.c; see also Bauer,
Metaphysik, 573–83.
259. Babenstuber, Philosophia l.2 Phys. disp.5 a.2 §4 n.40 (259b).
260. Babenstuber, Vindiciae praed. p.1 §2 n.20 (14ab).
261. Ibid., §3 n.38 (28b–29a).
262. Ibid., §4 n.64 (45a): “a quo determinetur, ut determinet etiam se ipsum” [“by which it is
determined, so that it might determine itself also”]. Ibid., §5 (73b).
346 Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period
make God the author of sin, as is repeatedly objected, since God causes only
the material action but not the formal wickedness.263
The Thomistic theory of the praedeterminatio physica—a defense against
modern Deism and an autonomous self-determination of man—is the logi-
cally consistent attempt to join God and creature to each other once again
through the metaphysical clamps of participation, dependence and the es-
sential ordering of causes. It can convince people, however, only as long as
the world view of Aristotelian-Thomistic metaphysics remains alive.
263. Babenstuber, Philosophia l.2 Phys. disp.5 a.2 §5 (272a–273a); see also Bauer, Metaphysik,
583–86.
264. See Leinsle, Ding, 2–4.
265. On his life and work see, Pastine, Juan Caramuel; Velarde Lombraña, Juan Caramuel;
Sousedík, Filosofie, 185–210; Jacob Schmutz, art. “Caramuel y Lobkowitz, Juan,” in BBKL 17:224–32.
266. Caramuel, Theologia moralis fundamentalis, (Frankfurt, 1651); this discussion cites the cor-
rected four-volume 4th edition (Lyon, 1675/6); on this subject see Fleming, Defending probabilism.
267. Caramuel, Theologia moralis fundamentalis, Prologus De mente Authoris, Moralium
Opinionum nexu et Theologicorum nominum significatione [Prologue on the Author’s intention,
the center of moral opinions and the significance of theological terms] (1:1–5), with its explana-
Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period 347
form the universal principles of moral theology, of both a speculative and a
practical sort. The speculative foundations are those that refer to the human
mind and are said to provide it with certainty (ch. 1): grace and freedom,
whereby Caramuel rejects both the scientia media and the praedeterminatio
physica in the strict sense;268 first truth and first truthfulness, that is, God
and his revelation; the certainty and infallibility of the Roman Church; the
veracity of the pope; the College of Cardinals and the Rota; the definitions
of the universities;269 the alleged and actual authority of scholars;270 the
opinions of contemporaries; the authority of demons (with a reference to
the Daemonis Logica or his course on philosophy), sensory experience, and
probable opinions. The practical foundations are based on divine or human
authority and legislation, and laws are treated according to the Aristotelian
scheme of categories. Book 2 then presents the Decalogue, book 3—sac-
ramental doctrine, based on a sacramental grammar (with its own chapter
De Orthographia divina), mathematics, dialectic and physics. Finally, book 4
presents a Dialexis de non certitudine.
The struggle for certainty and the binding character of ecclesiastical
theological decisions acquire downright explosive force in light of the Co-
pernican worldview. Caramuel discusses the question in connection with
the authority of the College of Cardinals, for hitherto only they had rejected
the cosmology of Copernicus and Galileo. Their decision has a solely prac-
tical significance; they cannot declare a formal heresy if it was not previ-
ously determined to be one.271 The teaching that the earth moves about the
sun was a probable opinion before the condemnation, but no longer is now.
In fact, however, what is at issue according to Caramuel is not a question of
astronomy but rather the admissibility of a metaphorical interpretation of
Scripture. Once this is admitted in the case of astronomy, it can also gain a
foothold in sacramental doctrine (as the heretics claim). We should there-
tions of: Deus, Trinitas, homoousios, ens secundum dici, ens morale, ens virtuale, libertas, dubium nega-
tivum, probabilitas.
268. Ibid., l.1 c.1 fund.1 (1:55–56). Concerning Caramuel’s position in the debate on grace,
which in itself is Molinist, see also Armogathe, “Probabilisme,” 36, 39; on his hypothesis of a prae-
determinatio infallibilitans see Velarde Lombraña, Juan Caramuel, 41–42.
269. He considers the most important ones to be Salamanca, Alcalà, Paris, Louvain/Leuven,
Douay, Cologne, Ingolstadt, Mainz, Würzburg, and Prague. Whatever they teach that has not been
condemned has a claim to probability.
270. With a harsh polemic aimed at worthless or purchased academic degrees, according to
the proverb: “Maneat eius argentum apud nos, asinusque Laureatus revertatur ad patriam” [“Let his
money stay with us, and let the ass with the Degree return to his fatherland”] (1:120a); on the au-
thorities of extrinsic probability see also Leinsle, “Servatius de Lairuelz,” 288–92.
271. Caramuel, Theologia moralis fundamentalis l.1 c.1 fund.5 (1:104b).
348 Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period
fore, says Caramuel, be grateful to the cardinals that they warded off this
possible misuse of Scripture by their condemnation of Copernicus. For in
interpreting Scripture there is a general obligation to follow the literal sense,
as long as this is not contradictory, thus forcing us to seek a metaphorical
or moral interpretation.272 This new theory, nevertheless, is not formally
heretical, since it has not been condemned as such by the pope.273 Noth-
ing about this has changed even through the Galileo affair: There is no per-
mission to defend the heliocentric system.274 On purely rational grounds
the Copernican system is at least possible, since one cannot demonstrate
that God could not have created a world in which this system is valid. Car-
amuel himself simply wishes to abide by the Church’s decision, especially
since both systems have their difficulties, and so he affirms that the earth is
motionless and rejects the contrary opinion as heretical and condemned by
sacred Scripture.275
With the condemnation of Galileo, Caramuel considers the systems
of David Origanus (1558–1628; professor in Frankfurt an der Oder) and
Christian Longomontanus (1562–1647, professor in Copenhagen) as being
repudiated also.276 A physical proof of heliocentrism is impossible. All the
ingenious endeavors by the mathematicians to find one are therefore fruit-
less effort and useless torment for the reader. Yet even if—per impossibile—
a proof were someday found, Caramuel could reject it as the impossible and
absurd consequence of an impossible premise, especially since the earth’s
rest and the sun’s movement have been proved through the discovery of
sunspots by the Jesuit Christoph Scheiner (1573–1650). For Caramuel a
contrary proof against a valid proof is impossible as a matter of pure log-
ic.277 Fidelity to the positive ecclesiastical decision is thus legitimized theo-
logically, scientifically, and logically.
Desgabets is aware that he has thus preserved the mystery of the Eucharist
with regard to the efficacy of the sacrament, but that he has removed the dif-
287. See Lemaire, Cartésianisme, 99–133.
288. See Armogathe, Theologia cartesiana, 91–92.
289. Ibid., 94–96 with newly compiled documentation.
290. Desgabets, Explication familière, MS Epinal 43, 69; cited in Arbogathe, Theologia Cartesi-
ana, 98.
Scholastic Theology: Early Modern Period 351
ficulty of separated, absolute accidents with his new theory. With logical con-
sistency, Desgabets answers in the negative the classical question of whether
during the time between Christ’s death and his resurrection a transubstantia-
tion would have resulted from an attempted consecration, claiming that his
answer is probable, because during that time Christ’s soul did not inform a
body. The Blood of Christ, on the other hand, is not immediately informed by
the soul but rather by an inner movement.291 Desgabets explicitly submits to
the teaching of the Council of Trent, which remains open with regard to the
interpretive paradigm. Nevertheless his theory was exposed to vehement at-
tacks from theologians and was denounced to the king and the archbishop of
Paris as a teaching that was harmful to the “Respublica Scholastica.”292
304. Amort, Theol. ecl., Tr. de Deo disp.5 De scientia Dei (I, 341–445).
305. Ibid., disp.5 q.3–4 (I, 368–425).
306. Theol. ecl., De Angelis disp.4: De imperio. Potestate et operationibus Daemonum (II,
357–414).
307. See Precht-Nussbaum, Zwischen Augsburg und Rom, 520–88.
7 Prospect: Enlightenment and New Scholasticism
354
Prospect: Enlightenment and New Scholasticism 355
Neologie [new doctrine] and also, in the Catholic world, into the research of
the Maurists and the Bollandists into the primary sources, although among
Catholics it did not drive out the Scholastic paradigm of theology.3
3. Another decisive factor was the philosophical critique by the secular,
usually antimetaphysical and sometimes materialistic Enlightenment
philosophy, especially in France. It was relatively easy to adapt Christian
Wolff ’s Scholastic system [of philosophy], which had a new methodol-
ogy but was traditional in its metaphysical orientation, for the purposes
of theology.4 Institutionally, the philosophical cursus used previously was
replaced—definitively after the Jesuit Order was dissolved in 1773—by
the textbooks of Enlightenment philosophy.5 The philosophy of Kant,
German Idealism and early Romanticism, when adapted theologically,
produced another kind of theology of the sort that would appear in the
nineteenth century (Anton Günther [1783–1863], the Tübingen School).6
The justification of such theology was radically called into question by
the Church in the so-called crisis of Modernism.7
The abandonment of the old program did not take place abruptly, how-
ever. Nor were defenders of the old method lacking, and many suggestions
for reform were eventually realized in the eighteenth-century university
reforms.8 Thus the Viennese professor Petrus Gazzaniga, O.P. (1723–1799),
whose works were sometimes obligatory in the realm of the Habsburg do-
minions during the period of Josephism, defended a moderate use of the
Scholastic method in systematic theology.9 It had to be supplemented,
however, by philological and historical studies. In this he showed himself
to be the disciple of Abbot Stephan Rautenstrauch (1734–1785), who led
the Maria-Theresian and Josephist reform of theological studies.10 Both
scholars relied on the small but fundamental treatise De recto et perverso usu
Theologiae scholasticae by the later Prince-Abbot of Sankt Blasien, Martin
Gerbert (1720–1793).11
3. See Merkt, Das patristische Prinzip, 196–213.
4. See Schäfer, Kirche und Vernunft, 103–51.
5. In Ingolstadt, for example, the works of the (Protestant) professor from Göttingen, Johann
Heinrich Georg Feder (1740–1821).
6. See the essays in Coreth, Neidl, and Pfligersdorffer, eds., Christliche Philosophie, 1:86–419.
7. See esp. Weiss, Modernismus.
8. Concerning Würzburg, see, for example, Lesch, Neuorientierung.
9. See Wehofer, “Gazzaniga.”
10. See Menzel, Abt Stephan Rautenstrauch.
11. M. Gerbert, De recto et perverso usu Theologiae scholasticae (Sankt Blasien, 1758); see also
Deissler, Fürstabt Martin Gerbert.
356 Prospect: Enlightenment and New Scholasticism
Harking back to the critique of Scholasticism by John Gerson and the
humanists, while employing also the methodology of Francis Bacon (1561–
1626), Gerbert tried again—following in Mabillon’s footsteps—to combine
theological reform with monastic life. Although Fr. François Vavasseur, S.J.
(1605–1681) cited as advantages of the Scholastic method its orderliness,
concision and clarity, the ecclesiastical reliability and certainty of its opin-
ions and sententiae, as well as the penetration and force of its arguments,
in Gerbert’s opinion this was only partially true.12 They are outweighed by
disadvantages: repugnant, artificial terminology (he points to Caramuel’s
leptotatos as the prime example), unnecessary controversies over mere
words in matters about which we know nothing in the first place (e.g., about
the beatific vision and the nature of the light of glory), the multiplication
of useless questions, excessive use of reason while neglecting study of the
sources, too much philosophy and logic while neglecting the auxiliary sci-
ences, but above all the mere insistence on the dictated text of the teacher.
Useless Scholastic questions are detrimental to monastic life, according
to the Spanish Thomist and Benedictine Cardinal Joseph Saënz d’Aguirre
(1630–1699). They deal with matters that are either clear anyway or else
entirely incomprehensible; they not infrequently offend against piety and
good morals. They treat subjects in the wrong place (e.g., the introductory
questions about the theory of science) or are humanly insoluble.13 Not only
does this Scholasticism fail to promote morality as it should; Gerbert sees
harmful consequences also and especially for theology and the Church as
well as for the theologian himself. As a result of the obscurity of Scholastic
terminology, most mysteries of the faith cannot be explained correctly to
the faithful. They are consequently deprived of the fruits of faith and knowl-
edge. The most talented, however, are frightened off from the study of the-
ology; on the other hand, the only ones who do put on the harness are the
ones who debate the best and can shout the loudest. Moreover, because of
the poor organization of the courses, after completing their studies theolo-
gians, priests, and religious have no interest whatsoever in continuing edu-
cation in theology, since “it always deals with the same subjects.”14
Now the reform of theology, which Gerbert views in biblical terms as
the restoration of the Lord’s vineyard, is not to be achieved by discarding
Scholastic theology as a whole, but rather by making its alleged advantages
23. See Aubert, “Die Enzyklika ‘Aeterni Patris’”; Quinto, Scholastica, 408–11.
24. See Weiss, Modernismus.
25. See Kluxen, “Die geschichtliche Erforschung.”
Bibliography
Aertsen, Jan A. “‘Von Gott kann man nichts erkennen, außer dass er ist’ (Satz 215 der
Pariser Verurteilung): Die Debatte über die (Un-)möglichkeit einer Gotteserkennt-
nis quid est.” In Nach der Verurteilung. Edited by Aertsen, et al., 2001, 22–37.
———, and Andreas Speer, eds. Was ist Philosophie im Mittelalter? Akten des X. Internatio-
nalen Kongresses für mitteralterliche Philosophie der Socitété Internationale pour l’Étude
de la Philosophie Médiévale, 25. bis 30. August 1997 in Erfurt. Miscellanea Mediaevalia
26. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1998.
———, et al., eds. Nach der Verurteilung von 1277: Philosophie und Theologie an der Uni-
versität von Paris im letzten Viertel des 13. Jahrhunderts: Studien und Texte. Miscellanea
Mediaevalia 28. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 2001.
Albrecht, Michael. Eklektik: Eine Begriffsgeschichte mit Hinweisen auf die Philosophie- und
Wissenschaftsgeschichte. Quaestiones 5. Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt, 1993.
Altermatt, Augustinus. Zum Problem der physischen Prämotion: Die Prämotionslehre nach
dem Salzburger Philosophen P. Ludwig Babenstuber OSB. Diss., Fribourg, 1931.
Althaus, Paul. Die Prinzipien der deutschen reformierten Dogmatik im Zeitalter der aristo-
telischen Scholastik. Leipzig, 1914.
Amorós, León. “La teologia como ciencia practica en la escuela franciscana en los tiempos
que preceden a Escoto.” AHD 9 (1934): 261–303.
Anfray, Jean-Pascal. “Prescience divine, décrets concomitants et liberté humaine d’après
Bartolomeo Mastri.” In Rem in seipsa cernere: Saggi sul pensiero filosofico di Bartolo-
meo Mastri (1602–1673). Edited by Marco Forlivesi. Subsidia Mediaevalia Patavina 8.
Padua, 2004, 556–92.
Angelini, Giuseppe. L’Ortodossia e la Grammatica: Analisi di struttura e deduzione storica
della Teologia Trinitaria di Prepositino. Rome, 1972.
Angenendt, Arnold. Geschichte der Religiosität im Mittelalter. Darmstadt, 1997.
Antolić-Piper, Pia A. “Zur Begründung der Theologie im Horizont von Philosophie,
Heiliger Schrift und Weisheit bei Roger Bacon OFM.” In What is “Theology?” Edited
by Olszewski, 2007, 673–94.
Appuhn-Radtke, Sibylle. Das Thesenblatt im Hochbarock: Studien zu einer graphischen Gat-
tung am Beispiel der Werke Bartholomäus Kilians. Weissenhorn, 1988.
Armogathe, Jean-Robert. Theologia Cartesiana: L’explication physique de l’Eucharistie chez
Descartes et Desgabets. Archives internationales d’histoire des idées 84. The Hague,
1977.
———. “Probabilisme et Libre-Arbitre: la théologie morale de Caramuel y Lobkowitz.”
In Le meraviglie del probabile. Juan Caramuel 1606–1682: Atti del Convegno internazio-
361
362 Bibliography
nale di studi, Vigevano 29–31 ottobre 1982. Edited by Paolo Pissavino. Vigevano, 1990,
35–40.
Ashworth, E. Jennifer. Language and Logic in the Post-Medieval Period. Synthese 12. Boston,
1971.
Aubert, Roger. “Die Enzyklika ‘Aeterni Patris’ und die weiteren päpstlichen Stellungnah-
men zur christlichen Philosophie.” In Christliche Philosophie. Edited by Coreth, Neidl,
and Pfligersdorffer, 1988, 2:310–32.
Baeumker, Clemens. “Die christliche Philosophie des Mittelalters.” In Die Kultur der
Gegenwart: Ihre Entwicklung und ihre Ziele. Edited by Paul Hinneberg. Leipzig, 1913,
339–43.
Baldwin, John W. Masters, Princes and Merchants: The Social Views of Peter the Chanter and
His Circle. 2 vols. Princeton, N.J., 1970.
Baltzer, Otto. Die Sentenzen des Petrus Lombardus: Ihre Quellen und ihre dogmengeschicht-
liche Bedeutung. Leipzig, 1902. Reprint, Aalen, 1972.
Bannach, Klaus. Die Lehre von der doppelten Macht Gottes bei Wilhelm von Ockham. VIEG
75. Wiesbaden, 1975.
Baron, Frank. “Der erste Druck einer Schrift Augustins: Ein Beitrag zur Geschichte des
frühen Buchdrucks und des Humanismus.” HJ 91 (1971): 108–18.
Bataillon, Louis-Jaques. La prédication au XIIIe siècle en France et Italie: Études et documents.
Aldershot-Brookfield, 1993.
———. “Sermons rédigés, sermons réportés (XIIIe siècle).” Prédication 3:69–86.
———. “Les instruments de travail des prédicateurs au XIIIe siècle.” Prédication
4:197–209.
———. “Intermédiaires entre les traités de morale pratique et les sermons: les distinctio-
nes bibliques alphabétiques.” Prédication 6: 213–26.
———. “Les crises de l’Université de Paris d’après les sermons universitaires.” Prédication
8: 155–69.
———. “L’emploi du langage philosophique dans les sermons du treizième siècle.”
Prédication 9: 983–91.
———. “Similitudines et exempla dans les sermons du XIIIe siècle.” Prédication 10:
191–205.
———. “Les images dans les sermons du XIIIe siècle.” Prédication 11: 327–95.
———. “La predicazione dei religiosi mendicanti del secolo XIII nell’ Italia centrale.”
Prédication 12: 691–94.
Baudry, Léon. La querelle des futurs contingents (Louvain 1465–1475). Études de Philoso-
phie Médiévale 38. Paris, 1950.
Bauer, Emmanuel J. Thomistische Metaphysik an der alten Benediktineruniversität Salzburg:
Darstellung und Interpretation einer philosophischen Schule des 17./18. Jahrhunderts.
Salzburger Theologische Studien 1. Innsbruck/Vienna, 1996.
Bayer, Oswald. “Melanchthons Theologiebegriff.” In Der Theologe Melanchthon. Edited by
Frank, 2000, 25–47.
Bazán, B. Carlos. “Conception of the Agent Intellect and the Limits of Metaphysics.” In
Nach der Verurteilung. Edited by Aertsen, et al., 2001, 178–210.
Beaude, Joseph. “Desgabets et son œuvre.” Revue de synthèse 35 (1974): 7–17.
———. “Cartésianisme et anticartésianisme de Desgabets.” Studia Cartesiana 1 (1979):
1–24.
Beckmann, Jan P. “Weltkontingenz und menschliche Vernunft bei Wilhelm von Ockham.”
Bibliography 363
In L’homme et son univers au moyen âge. Edited by Christian Wenin. Louvain-la-Neuve,
1986, 445–57.
Beinert, Wolfgang. Die Lehre von der Kirche nach den Schriften des Rupert von Deutz,
Honorius Augustodunensis und Gerhoch von Reichersberg. BGPhThMA, n.s., 13. Münster,
1973.
Bejczy, István. Erasmus and the Middle Ages: The Historical Consciousness of a Christian
Humanist. Brill’s Studies in Intellectual History 106. Leiden, 2001.
Benrath, Gustav Adolf. “Die deutsche evangelische Universität der Reformationszeit.” In
Universität und Gelehrtenstand. Edited by Rössler and Franz, 1970, 63–83.
Benson, Robert Louis, and Gilles Constable. Renaissance and Renewal in the Twelfth
Century. Oxford, 1982.
Berg, Dieter. Armut und Wissenschaft: Beiträge zur Geschichte des Studienwesens der Bettel-
orden im 13. Jahrhundert. Geschichte und Gesellschaft 15. Düsseldorf, 1977.
Bériou, N. “Les sermons latins après 1200.” In Sermon. Edited by Kienzle, 2000, 363–447.
Berndt, Rainer. “Hugo von St. Viktor. Theologie als Schriftauslegung.” In Theologen.
Edited by Köpf, 2002, 96–112.
———. André de Saint Victor († 1175): Exégète et théologien. Bibliotheca Victorina 2. Paris,
1991.
Bertola, Eremengildo. “La ‘Glossa ordinaria’ biblica ed i suoi problemi.” RThAM 54
(1978): 34–78.
Bérubé, Camille. “Der ‘Dialog’ S. Bonaventura—Roger Bacon.” In Roger Bacon in der
Diskussion. Edited by Florian Uhl. Frankfurt, 2001, 67–135.
Beumer, Johannes. “Die Theologie als intellectus fidei: Dargestellt an Hand der Lehre des
Wilhelm von Auxerre und Petrus von Tarantasia.” Scholastik 17 (1942): 32–41.
———. “Erleuchteter Glaube: Die Theorie Heinrichs von Gent und ihr Fortleben in der
Spätscholastik.” FStud 37 (1955): 129–60.
———. “Die Stellung Heinrichs von Gent zum theologischen Studium der Frau.” Scho-
lastik 32 (1957): 81–85.
———. “Augustinismus und Thomismus in der theologischen Prinzipienlehre des Ae-
gidius Romanus.” Scholastik 32 (1957): 542–60.
Beyer, Michael, and Günther Wartenberg, eds. Humanismus und Wittenberger Refor-
mation: Festgabe anlässlich des 500. Geburtstages des Praeceptor Germaniae Philipp
Melanchthon am 16. Februar 1997. Leipzig, 1996.
Bianchi, Laura. “1277: A Turning Point in Medieval Philosophy?” In Was ist Philosophie im
Mittelalter? Edited by Aertsen and Speer, 1998, 90–110.
Bizer, Ernst. Frühorthodoxie und Rationalismus. Theologische Studien 71. Zürich, 1963.
Bliemetzrieder, Franz. Anselm von Laons systematische Sentenzen. BGPhMA 18/2, 3. Mün-
ster, 1919.
———. “Autour de l’œuvre théologique d’Anselme de Laon.” RThAM 1 (1929): 435–83.
Blum, Paul Richard. Philosophenphilosophie und Schulphilosophie: Typen des Philosophierens
in der Neuzeit. StudLeib Sonderheft 27. Stuttgart, 1998.
Boehm, Laetitia. “Humanistische Bildungsbewegung und mittelalterliche Universitätsver-
fassung: Aspekte zur frühneuzeitlichen Reformgeschichte der deutschen Univer-
sitäten.” In Universités. Edited by Paquet and Ijsewijn, 1978, 315–46.
Bohatec, Josef. Die cartesianische Scholastik in der Philosophie und reformierten Dogmatik
des 17. Jahrhunderts. Leipzig, 1912. Reprint, Hildesheim, 1966.
Borgolte, Michael. “‘Selbstverständnis’ und ‘Mentalitäten’: Bewußtsein, Verhalten und
364 Bibliography
Handeln mittelalterlicher Menschen im Verständnis moderner Historiker.” Archiv für
Kulturgeschichte 79 (1997): 189–210.
Boulnois, Olivier. “Le chiasme: La philosophie selon les théologiens et la théologie selon
les artistes, de 1267 à 1300.” In Was ist Philosophie im Mittelalter? Edited by Aertsen
and Speer, 1998, 595–607.
Bruyère, Nelly. Méthode et Dialectique dans l’œuvre de La Ramée. De Pétrarque à Descartes
45. Paris, 1984.
Burger, Christoph. Aedificatio, Fructus, Utilitas: Johannes Gerson als Professor der Theologie
und Kanzler der Universität Paris. Beiträge zur Historischen Theologie 70. Tübingen,
1986.
———. “Der Augustinschüler gegen die modernen Pelagianer: Das ‘auxilium speciale
dei’ in der Gnadenlehre Gregors von Rimini.” In Gregor von Rimini. Edited by Ober-
man, 1981, 195–240.
Burger, Maria. “Die Bedeutung der Aristotelesrezeption für das Verständnis der Theologie
als Wissenschaft bei Albertus Magnus.” In Albertus Magnus und die Anfänger der
Aristoteles-Rezeption im lateinischen Mittelalter: Von Richardus Rufus bis zu Franciscus
de Mayronis. Edited by Honnefelder, Ludger, et al. Subsidia Albertina 1. Münster,
2005, 281–306.
Burrows, Mark Steven. Jean Gerson and De Consolatione Theologiae (1418): The Consola-
tion of a Biblical and Reforming Theology for a Disordered Age. Beiträge zur Historisch-
en Theologie 78. Tübingen, 1991.
Cantin, André. “‘Ratio’ et ‘auctoritas’ dans la première phase de la controverse eucharis-
tique entre Bérenger et Lanfranc.” RÉAug 20 (1974): 155–86.
———. “La ‘raison’ dans le ‘De sacra coena’ de Bérenger de Tours.” RechAug 12 (1977):
174–211.
Caruso, Ester. Pedro Hurtado de Mendoza e la rinascita del nominalismo nella Scolastica del
Seicento. Pubblicazioni del “Centro si Studi del Pensiero Filosofico del Cinquecento
e del Seicento in relazione ai problemi della scienza” del Consiglio Nazionale delle
Ricerche. Università degli Studi di Milano. Serie I, 13. Florence, 1979.
Castro, Manuel de. “Bibliographía de franciscanos escotistas españoles.” In Homo et Mun-
dus: Acta Quinti Congressus Scotistici Internationalis, Salamanticae, 21–26 septembris
1981. Edited by Camille Bérubé. Studia Scholastico-Scotistica 8. Rome, 1984, 437–58.
Cazier, Pierre. “Le Livre des règles de Tyconius: Sa transmission du De doctrina christiana
aux Sentences d’Isidore de Séville.” RÉAug 19 (1973): 241–61.
———. Isidore de Séville et la naissance de l’Espagne catholique. Théologie historique 96.
Paris, 1994.
Charland, Thomas-Marie. Artes Praedicandi: Contribution à l’histoire de la rhétorique au
moyen âge. Publications de l’Institut d’Études Médiévales d’Ottawa 7. Paris, 1936.
Châtillon, François. “Vocabulaire et prosodie du distique attributé à Augustine de Dacie
sur les quatre sens de l’écriture.” In L’Homme devant Dieu. Festschrift H. de Lubac.
Lyon, 1964, 2:17–28.
Châtillon, Jean. “Le mouvement théologique dans la France de Philippe August.” In
D’Isidore de Séville à Saint Thomas d’Aquin. Vol. IX. London, 1985, 881–902.
Chenu, Marie-Dominique. “Théologie symbolique et exégèse scolastique aux XIIe et XIIIe
siècles.” In Melanges Joseph de Ghellinck S.J. Gembloux, 1951, 2:509–26.
———. La Théologie comme science au XIIIe siècle. Bibliothèque Thomiste 33. Paris, 1957.
———. La théologie au douzième siècle. Paris, 1966.
Bibliography 365
———. “Un essai de méthode théologique au XIIe siècle.” MS 35 (1973): 258–67.
Claus, A. Ho Scholastikós. Diss., University of Cologne, 1962.
Cloes, Henri. “La systématisation théologique pendant la première moitié du XIIe siècle.”
EThL 34 (1958): 277–329.
Clouse, Robert Gordon. The Influence of John Henry Alsted on English Millenarian Thought
in the Seventeenth Century. Ann Arbor, 1963.
Codina Mír, Gabriel. Aux Sources de la pédagogie des Jésuites: Le “Modus Parisiensis.” Biblio-
theca Instituti Historici S.I. 28. Rome, 1968.
Colish, Marcia L. Peter Lombard. 2 vols. Brill’s Studies in Intellectual History 41. Leiden,
1994.
Coreth, Emerich, Walter M. Neidl, and Georg Pfligersdorffer, eds. Christliche Philosophie
im katholischen Denken des 19. und 20. Jahrhunderts. Vol. 2, Rückgriff auf scholastisches
Erbe. Graz, 1988.
Cottiaux, Jean. “La conception de la théologie chez Abélard.” RHE 28 (1932): 247–95,
533–51, 788–828.
Courtenay, William J. Capacity and Volition: A History of the Distinction of Absolute and
Ordained Power. Quodlibet 8. Bergamo, 1990.
———. “The Paris Faculty of Theology in the Late Thirteenth and Early Fourteenth
Centuries.” In Nach der Verurteilung. Edited by Aertson, et al., 233–47.
Craig, William Lane. The Problem of Divine Foreknowing and Future Contingents from Aris-
totle to Suarez. Brill’s Studies in Intellectual History 7. Leiden, 1988.
Crusius, Irene. “Gabriel Biel—eine Karriere zwischen vita contemplativa und vita activa.”
In Gabriel Biel und die Brüder vom gemeinsamen Leben: Beiträge aus Anlass des 500.
Todestages des Tübinger Theologen. Edited by Ulrich Köpf and Sönke Lorenz. Contu-
bernium 47. Stuttgart, 1998, 1–23.
Dales, Richard C. “The Origins of the Doctrine of the Double Truth.” Viator 15 (1984):
169–79.
———. Medieval Discussions of the Eternity of the World. Brill’s Studies in Intellectual His-
tory 18. Leiden, 1990.
Dalfen, Ch. Die Stellung des Erasmus von Rotterdam zur scholastischen Methode. Osnabrück,
1936.
Daniel, Norman. The Arabs and Medieval Europe. London, 1975.
Davy, Marie-Madelaine. Les sermons univeritaires Parisiens de 1230–1231. Études de philoso-
phie médiévale 15. Paris, 1931.
Deissler, Alfons. Fürstabt Martin Gerbert von St. Blasien und die theologische Methode.
SMGB Erg.H. 15. Munich, 1940.
Derwich, Marek, and Martial Staub, eds. Die “Neue Frömmigkeit.” in Europa im Spätmittelal-
ter. Veröffentlichungen des Max-Planck-Instituts für Geschichte 205. Göttingen, 2004.
Dettloff, Werner. Die Entwicklung der Akzeptations- und Verdienstlehre von Duns Scotus bis
Luther. BGPhThMA 40, no. 2. Münster, 1963.
Dibon, Paul A. G. L’enseignement philosophique dans les Universités Néerlandaises à l’époque
pré-cartésienne. Diss., Leiden, 1954.
Dohmen, Christoph. “Vom vielfachen Schriftsinn—Möglichkeiten und Grenzen neuerer
Zugänge zu biblischen Texten.” In Neue Formen der Schriftauslegung? QuD 140. Edited
by Thomas Sternberg. Freiburg, 1992, 13–74.
Döllinger, Ignaz v., and Franz Heinrich Reusch. Geschichte der Moralstreitigkeiten in der
römisch-katholischen Kirche seit dem sechzehnten Jahrhundert. 2 vols. Nördlingen, 1889.
366 Bibliography
Donneaud, H. “Le sens du mot ‘theologia’ chez Bonaventure.” RThom 102 (2002): 273–95.
Doucet, Vincent. Commentaires sur les Sentences. Quaracchi, 1954.
Dreitzel, Horst. Protestantischer Aristotelismus und absoluter Staat: Die “Politica” des Hen-
ning Arnisaeus (ca. 1575–1636). VIEG 55. Wiesbaden, 1970.
Dreyer, Mechthild. More mathematicorum: Rezeption und Transformation der antiken
Gestalten wissenschaftlichen Wissens im 12. Jahrhundert. BGPhThMA, n.s., 47. Münster,
1996.
Drossbach, Gisela. “Innovation und Inquisition: Literaturproduktion in Wien um 1400.”
In What Is “Theology?” Edited by Olszewski, 2007, 487–506.
Duchrow, Ulrich. Sprachverständnis und biblisches Hören bei Augustin. Hermeneutische
Untersuchungen zur Theologie 5. Tübingen, 1965.
Duhr, Bernhard. Geschichte der Jesuiten in den Ländern deutscher Zunge. Vols. 1–2. Freiburg
im Breisgau, 1913/1928.
Ebeling, Gerhard. Lutherstudien. 3 vols. Tübingen, 1971–89.
Eckert, Willehad Paul, ed. Thomas von Aquino. Interpretation und Rezeption. Walberberger
Studien, Phil. Reihe 5. Mainz, 1974.
Egenter, Richard. “Vernunft und Glaubenswahrheit im Aufbau der theologischen Wis-
senschaft nach Aegidius Romanus.” In Philosophia perennis: Abhandlungen zu ihrer
Vergangenheit und Gegenwart. Festschrift J. Geyser. Regensburg, 1930, 1:195–208.
Ehrle, Franz. Der Sentenzenkommentar Peters von Candida, des Pisaner Papstes Alexanders
V. FStud Beih. 9. Münster, 1925.
Elswijk, H. C. van. Gilbert Porreta: Sa vie, son œuvre, sa pensée. SSL 33. Leuven, 1966.
Emery, Kent, Jr. “The Image of God Deep in the Mind: The Continuity of Cognition Ac-
cording to Henry of Ghent.” In Nach der Verurteilung. Edited by Aertsen, et al., 2001,
59–124.
Enders, Markus. “Zur Bedeutung des Ausdrucks theologia im 12. Jahrhundert und seinen
antiken Quellen.” In What Is “Theology”? Edited by Olszewski, 2007, 19–37.
Ernst, Stephan. Gewissheit des Glaubens: Der Glaubenstraktat Hugos von St. Viktor als
Zugang zu seiner theologischen Systematik. BGPhThMA, n.s., 30. Münster, 1987.
Evans, Gillian R. “Boethian and Euclidean Axiomatic Method in the Theology of the Lat-
er Twelfth Century.” Archives Internationales d’histoire des Sciences 105 (1980): 36–52.
———. Old Arts and New Theology: The Beginning of Theology as an Academic Discipline.
Oxford, 1980.
———. “Zachary of Besançon and the Bible Contradictions.” AnPraem 58 (1982): 319–23.
———. Philosophy and Theology in the Middle Ages. London, 1993.
———, ed. The Medieval Theologians. Oxford, 2001.
Eynde, Damien van den. “Les Magistri du Commentaire ‘Unum ex Quattuor’ du Zacha-
rias Chrysopolitanus.” Antonianum 23 (1948): 1–32, 181–222.
Faber, Eva-Maria. Symphonie von Gott und Mensch: Die responsorische Struktur und Vermit-
tlung in der Theologie Johannes Calvins. Neukirchen-Vluyn, 1999.
Ferrarino, Pietro. “Quadruvium (Quadrivio dei sei arti?—La caverna platonica).” In
Atti del Congresso Internazionale di Studi Varroniani, Rieti Settembre 1974. Rieti, 1976,
2:359–64.
Fichtenau, Heinrich. Ketzer und Professoren: Häresie und Vernunftglaube im Hochmittelalter.
Munich, 1992.
Filthaut, Ephrem. Roland von Cremona O.P. und die Anfänge der Scholastik im Prediger-
orden: Ein Beitrag zur Geistesgeschichte der älteren Dominikaner. Vechta i.O., 1936.
Bibliography 367
Finkenzeller, Josef. Offenbarung und Theologie nach der Lehre des Johannes Duns Skotus:
Eine historische und systematische Untersuchung. BGPhThMA 38, no. 5. Münster, 1960.
Flasch, Kurt. Geschichte der Philosophie in Text und Darstellung. Vol. 2, Mittelalter. Stuttgart,
1982.
———. Einführung in die Philosophie des Mittelalters. Darmstadt, 1987.
———, ed. Aufklärung im Mittelalter? Die Verurteilung von 1277: Das Dokument des
Bischofs von Paris. Excerpta classica 6. Mainz, 1989.
Fleming, Julia A. Defending Probabilism: The Moral Theology of Juan Caramuel. Washing-
ton, D.C., 2006.
Fontaine, Jacques. Isidore de Seville et la culture classique dans l’Espagne wisigothique. Paris,
1983.
Forlivesi, Marco. Scotistarum Princeps: Bartolomeo Mastri (1602–1673) e il suo tempo. Fonti
e Studi Francescani 11. Padua, 2002.
Francescini, Sylvio Hermann de. “Le thomisme au secours du jansénisme dans la querelle
de la grace: Vrais et faux thomistes au temps de la Bulle Unigenitus.” RThom 115
(2007): 375–418.
Frank, Günter. Die theologische Philosophie Philipp Melanchthons (1497–1560). Erfurter
Theologische Studien 67. Hildesheim, 1995.
———. Die Vernunft des Gottesgedankens: Religionsphilosophische Studien zur frühen
Neuzeit. Quaestiones 13. Stuttgart, 2003.
———, ed. Der Theologe Melanchthon. Melanchthon-Schriften der Stadt Bretten 5.
Stuttgart, 2000.
Frank, Isnard W. “Der Wiener Dominikaner Johannes Werd († 1510) als Verfasser von
Thomaskommentaren.” In Thomas von Aquino. Edited by Eckert, 609–40.
Freedman, Joseph S. European Academic Philosophy in the Late Sixteenth and Early
Seventeenth Centuries: The Life, Significance and Philosophy of Clemens Timpler
(1563/4–1624). Studien und Materialien zur Geschichte der Philosophie 27. 2 vols.
Hildesheim, 1988.
Friedensburg, Walter. Der Reichstag zu Speyer 1526 im Zusammenhang der politischen und
kirchlichen Entwicklung Deutschlands im Reformationszeitalter. Historische Unter-
suchungen 5. Berlin, 1887. Reprint, Nieuwskoop, 1970.
Friederichs, Josef. Die Theologie als spekulative und praktische Wissenschaft nach Bonaven-
tura und Thomas von Aquin. Bonn, 1940.
Fuchs, Michael. Zeichen und Wissen: Das Verhältnis der Zeichentheorie zur Theorie des Wissens
und der Wissenschaften im dreizehnten Jahrhundert. BGPhThMA, n.s., 51. Münster, 1999.
Gabriel, Astrik Ladislaus. “The Conflict between the Chancellor and the University of
Masters and Students at Paris during the Middle Ages.” In Auseinandersetzungen an
der Pariser Universität im XIII. Jahrhundert. Edited by Zimmerman, 1976, 106–54.
———. “‘Via Antiqua’ and ‘Via Moderna’ and the Migration of Paris Students and Mas-
ters to the German Universities in the Fifteenth Century.” In Antiqui und Moderni.
Edited by Zimmerman, 1971, 439–83.
Ganoczy, Alexandre. Le jeune Calvin: Genèse et évolution de sa vocation réformatrice. VIEG
40. Wiesbaden, 1966.
———, and Stefan Scheld. Die Hermeneutik Calvins: Geistesgeschichtliche Voraussetzungen
und Grundzüge. VIEG 114. Wiesbaden, 1983.
Geerlings, Wilhelm. “Les Commentaires patristiques latins.” In Commentaire. Edited by
Goulet-Cazé, 199–211.
368 Bibliography
Gemeinhardt, Peter. “Die theologische Methode Anselms von Canterbury in seiner Epis-
tola de incarnatione Verbi.” In What Is “Theology.” Edited by Olszewski, 2007, 39–57.
Gerwing, Manfred. “Die sogenannte Devotio moderna.” In Jan Hus. Edited by Seibt,
49–58.
Geyer, Bernhard. “Der Begriff der scholastischen Theologie.” In Synthesen in der Philoso-
phie der Gegenwart: Festgabe A. Dyroff. Edited by Erich Feldmann. Bonn, 1926, 112–25.
———. “Facultas theologica. Eine bedeutungsgeschichtliche Untersuchung.” ZKG 75
(1964): 133–45.
Ghellinck, Joseph de. Le mouvement théologique du XIIe siècle. Brügge, 1948.
Giacon, Carlo. La seconda scolastica. 3 vols. Milan, 1944–1950.
Gibson, M. “The Case of Berengar of Tours.” Studies in Church History 7 (1971): 61–68.
Gilbert, Paul. “Die dritte Scholastik in Frankreich.” In Christliche Philosophie. Edited by
Coreth, Neidl, and Pfligersdorffer, 1988, 2:412–36.
———. “Ockham, Wyclif and the ‘Via moderna.’” In Antiqui und Moderni. Edited by
Zimmerman, 1971, 85–125.
Gilson, Etienne. “Avicenne en Occident au moyen âge.” AHD 44 (1969): 89–94.
Glorieux, Palémon. La littérature quodlibétique de 1260 à 1320. Bibliothèque Thomiste 5.
Le Saulchoir, 1925.
———. Répertoire des Maîtres en Théologie de Paris au XIIIe siècle. 2 vols. Paris, 1933/34.
———. “Les Deflorationes de Werner de Saint-Blaise.” In Mélanges Joseph de Ghellinck, S.J.
Gembloux, 1951, 2:699–721.
———. “Les années 1242–1247 à la Faculté de Théologie de Paris.” RThAM 29 (1962):
234–49.
———. “L’enseignement au moyen âge: Techniques et méthodes en usage à la Faculté de
Théologie de Paris, au XIIIe siècle.” AHD 43 (1968): 65–186.
———. “Le conflit de 1252–1257 à la lumière du Mémoire de Guillaume de Saint-Amour.”
RThAM 24 (1975): 364–72.
Glorieux, Pierre. “La Somme ‘Quoniam homines’ d’Alain de Lille.” RThAM 17 (1950):
29–45.
Gössmann, Elisabeth. Metaphysik und Heilsgeschichte: Eine theologische Untersuchung der
Summa Halensis. Alexander von Hales. München, 1964.
———. Antiqui und Moderni im Mittelalter: Eine geschichtliche Standortbestimmung.
Veröffentlichungen d. Grabmann-Institutes 23. Paderborn, 1974.
Goudriaan, Aza. Philosophische Gotteserkenntnis bei Suárez und Descartes im Zusammen-
hang mit der niederländischen reformierten Theologie und Philosophie des 17. Jahrhun-
derts. Brill’s Studies in Intellectual History 98. Leiden, 1999.
Goulet-Cazé, Marie-Odile, ed. Le Commentaire entre traditon et innovation: Actes du collo-
que international de l’Institut des Traditions textuelles. Paris et Villejuif, 22–25 septem-
bre 1999. Paris, 2000.
Grabmann, Martin. Geschichte der scholastischen Methode. 2 vols. Freiburg im Breisgau,
1909/11.
———. Forschungen über die lateinischen Aristotelesübersetzungen des XIII. Jahrhunderts.
BGPhMA 17, nos. 5–6. Münster, 1916.
———. Geschichte der katholischen Theologie seit dem Ausgang der Väterzeit. Freiburg, 1933.
———. Mittelalterliches Geistesleben. Munich, 1936.
———. “Aristoteles im Werturteil des Mittelalters.” In Mittelalterliches Geistesleben, 1936,
2:62–102.
Bibliography 369
———. “Die italienische Thomistenschule des XIII. und beginnenden XIV. Jahrhun-
derts.” In Mittelalterliches Geistesleben, 1936, 1:322–91.
———. “Die Opuscula de summo bono sive de vita philosophi und de sompniis des Bo-
ethius von Dacien.” In Mittelalterliches Geistesleben, 1936, 2:200–24.
———. “Die Stellung des Kardinals Cajetan in der Geschichte des Thomismus und der
Thomistenschule.” In Mittelaterliches Geistesleben, 1936, 2:602–13.
———. “Einzelgestalten aus der mittelalterlichen Dominikaner- und Thomistenschule.”
In Mittelalterliches Geistesleben, 1936, 2:512–612.
———. “Forschungen zur Geschichte der ältesten deutschen Thomistenschule des
Dominikanerordens.” In Mittelalterliches Geistesleben, 1936, 1:392–431.
———. “Hilfsmittel des Thomasstudiums aus alter Zeit (Abbreviationes, Concordantiae,
Tabulae).” In Mittelalterliches Geistesleben, 1936, 2:424–89.
———. “Johannes Capreolus O.P., der ‘Princeps Thomistarum’ († 1444) und seine Stel-
lung in der Geschichte der Thomistenschule.” In Mittelalterliches Geistesleben, 1936,
3:370–410.
———. I divieti ecclesiastici di Aristotele sotto Innocenzo III e Gregorio IX. Miscellanea
Historiae Pontificiae 5. Rome, 1941.
———. Die theologische Erkenntnis- und Einleitungslehre des hl. Thomas von Aquin auf Gr-
und seiner Schrift “In Boethium de Trinitate.” Thomistische Studien 4. Fribourg, 1948.
———. “Methoden und Hilfsmittel des Aristotelesstudiums im Mittelalter.” In Gesam-
melte Akademieabhandlungen. Paderborn, 1975, 1447–637.
Grane, Leif. Contra Gabrielem: Luthers Auseinandersetzung mit Gabriel Biel in der Disputa-
tio Contra Scholasticam Theologiam 1517. Acta Theologica Danica 4. Gyldendal, 1962.
———. Modus loquendi theologicus: Luthers Kampf um die Erneuerung der Theologie
(1515–1518). Acta Theologica Danica 12. Leiden, 1975.
Grauwen, Wilfried Marcel. Norbert aartsbischop van Maagdenburg (1124–1134). Verhan-
delingen van de Koninklijke Academie voor Wetenschappen, Letteren en Schone
Kunsten van België. Klasse der Letteren. Jaargang XL. Nr. 86. Brussels, 1978.
Green-Pedersen, Niels J. The Tradition of the Topics in the Middle Ages: The Commentaries
on Aristotle’s and Boethius’ “Topics.” Munich, 1984.
Greive, Hermann. “Die Maimonideische Kontroverse und die Auseinandersetzungen in der
lateinischen Scholastik.” In Auseinandersetzungen. Edited by Zimmerman, 1976, 170–80.
Greving, Joseph. Johann Eck als junger Gelehrter: Eine literar- und dogmengeschichtliche
Untersuchung über seinen Chrysopassus praedestinationis aus dem Jahre 1514. RGST 1.
Münster, 1906.
Grillmeier, Aloys. “Vom Symbolum zur Summa.” In Kirche und Über-lieferung (Festschrift
Geiselmann). Johannes Betz—Heinrich Fries. Freiburg, 1950, 119–69.
———. “Fulgentius von Ruspe, De Fide ad Petrum und die Summa Sententiarum: Eine
Studie zum Werden der frühscholastischen Systematik.” Scholastik 34 (1959): 526–65.
Grimm, Herold J. Lazarus Spengler, a Lay Leader of the Reformation. Columbus, Oh., 1978.
Grosse, Sven. Heilsungewissheit und Scrupulositas im späten Mittelalter: Studien zu Johannes
Gerson und Gattungen der Frömmigkeitstheologie seiner Zeit. Beiträge zur Historischen
Theologie 85. Tübingen, 1994.
Grundmann, Heribert. Religiöse Bewegungen im Mittelalter. Historische Studien 267. Ber-
lin, 1935. Reprint, Hildesheim, 1977.
Guelluy, Robert. Philosophie et théologie chez Guillaume d’Ockham. Louvain, 1947.
Hackett, Jeremiah. “Roger Bacon: His Life, Career and Works.” In Roger Bacon and the
370 Bibliography
Sciences: Commemorative Essays. Studien und Texte zur Geistesgeschichte des Mit-
telalters 57. Leiden, 1997, 9–24.
Hageneder, Othmar. “Der Häresiebegriff der Juristen des 12. und 13. Jahrhunderts.” In
Concept. Edited by Lourdaux and Verhelst, 41–103.
Hallensleben, Barbara. Communicatio: Anthropologie und Gnadenlehre bei Thomas de Vio
Cajetan. Reformationsgeschichtliche Studien und Texte 123. Münster, 1985.
Hamm, Berndt. Promissio, Pactum, Ordinatio. Freiheit und Selbstbindung Gottes in der scho-
lastischen Gnadenlehre. Beiträge zur historischen Theologie 54. Tübingen, 1977.
Hämmerl, Alfons. Die Welt—Symbol Gottes oder eigenständige Wirklichkeit? Verachtung und
Hochschätzung der Welt bei Heinrich von Langenstein († 1397). Studien zur Geschichte
der katholischen Moraltheologie 31. Regensburg, 1994.
Hammerstein, Notker. “Universitäten des Heiligen Römischen Reiches Deutscher Nation
als Ort der Philosophie des Barock.” StudLeib 13 (1981): 242–67.
Häring, Nikolaus M. “The Commentary of Gilbert of Poitiers on Boethius’ de hebdoma-
dibus.” Traditio 9 (1953): 177–211.
———. The Commentaries on Boethius by Thierry of Chartres and His School. Pontificial
Institute of Mediaeval Studies, Studies and Texts 20. Toronto, 1971.
———. Die Zwettler Summe. MGPhThMA, n.s., 15. Münster, 1977.
———. “Commentary and Hermeneutics.” In Renaissance. Edited by Benson and Con-
stable. Oxford, 1982, 173–200.
Hattrup, Dieter. Ekstatik der Geschichte: Die Entwicklung der christologischen Erkenntnis-
theorie Bonaventuras. Paderborner theologische Studien 23. Paderborn, 1993.
Heffernan, Thomas J. Sacred Biography: Saints and their Biographers in the Midde Ages.
New York, 1988.
Hegyj, Johannes. Die Bedeutung des Seins bei den klassischen Kommentatoren des heiligen
Thomas von Aquin, Capreolus—Silvester von Ferrara—Cajetan. Pullacher philoso-
phische Forschungen 4. Pullach, 1959.
Heim, Karl. Das Gewissheitsproblem in der systematischen Theologie bis zu Schleiermacher.
Leipzig, 1911.
Hellgardt, Ernst. Zum Problem symbolbestimmter und formalästhetischer Zahlenkomposi-
tion in mittelalterlicher Literatur: Mit Studien zum Quadrivium und zur Vorgeschichte
des mittelalterlichen Zahlendenkens. Münchener Texte und Untersuchungen zur
deutschen Literatur des Mittelalters 45. Munich, 1973.
———. “Victorinisch-zisterziensische Zahlenallegorese.” Beiträge zur Geschichte der
deutschen Sprache und Literatur 98 (1976): 331–50.
Hellyer, Marcus. “The Construction of the Ordinatio pro studiis superioribus of 1651.” AHSI
72 (2003): 3–43.
Hengst, Karl. Jesuiten an Universitäten und Jesuitenuniversitäten: Zur Geschichte der Univer-
sitäten in der Oberdeutschen und Rheinischen Provinz der Gesellschaft Jesu im Zeitalter
der konfessionellen Auseinandersetzung. Quellen und Forschungen auf dem Gebiet der
Geschichte, n.s., 2. Paderborn, 1981.
Henke, Ernt Ludwig Theodor. Georg Calixtus und seine Zeit. 2 vols. Halle, 1853/60.
Hennig, Gerhard. Cajetan und Luther: Ein historischer Beitrag zur Begegnung von Thomis-
mus und Reformation. Arbeiten zur Theologie II, no. 7. Stuttgart, 1966.
Henningsen, Jürgen. “‘Enzyclopädie’: Zur Sprach- und Deutungsgeschichte eines pädago-
gischen Begriffs.” ABG 10 (1966): 271–363.
———. “Orbis Doctrinae: Encyclopaedia.” ABG 11 (1967): 241–45.
Bibliography 371
Heppe, Heinrich. Die Dogmatik der evangelisch-reformierten Kirche. Neukirchen, 1958.
Herold, Vilém. Pražka Univerzita a Wyclif: Wyclifovo učení o ideách a geneze husitkého
revolučního myšlení. Prague, 1985.
Hödl, Ludwig. “Die confessio Berengarii von 1059: Eine Arbeit zum frühscholastischen
Eucharistietraktat.” Scholastik 37 (1962): 370–94.
Hoenen, Maarten J. F. M. Marsilius van Inghen († 1396) over het goddelijke weten: Zijn
plaats in de ontwickkeling van de opvattingen over hat goddelijke weten ca. 1255–1396.
Diss., Nijmegen, 1989.
———. Marsilius of Inghen: Divine Knowledge in Late Medieval Thought. Studies in the
History of Christian Thought 50. Leiden, 1993.
Hoffmann, Fritz. Die Schriften des Oxforder Kanzlers Johannes Lutterell. Leipzig, 1959.
———. Die theologische Methode des Oxforder Dominikanerlehrers Robert Holcot.
BGPhThMA, n.s., 5. Münster, 1972.
———. Crathorn: Quästionen zum ersten Sentenzenbuch. BGPhThMA, n.s., 29. Münster,
1988.
———. Die “Conferentiae” des Robert Holcot OP und die akademischen Auseinander-
setzungen an der Universität Oxford 1330–1332. BGPhThMA, n.s., 36. Münster, 1993.
———. Ockham-Rezeption und Ockham-Kritik im Jahrzehnt nach Wilhelm von Ockham in
Oxford 1322–1332. BGPhThMA, n.s., 50. Münster, 1998.
———. “Der Satz als Zeichen der theologischen Aussage bei Holcot, Crathorn und
Gregor von Rimini.” In Repraesentatio. Edited by Zimmerman, 1971, 296–313.
Hoffmann, Manfred. Erkenntnis und Verwirklichung der wahren Theologie nach Erasmus von
Rotterdam. Beiträge zur Historischen Theologie 44. Tübingen, 1972.
Höhn, Erich. “Köln als Ort der ersten Kommentare zur ‘Summa Theologiae’ des Thomas
von Aquin.” In Thomas von Aquino. Edited by Eckert, 641–55.
Holeček, František J. “Hussens Kirchverständnis.” In Jan Hus. Edited by Seibt, 183–91.
Holopainen, Toivo J. Dialectic and Theology in the Eleventh Century. Studien und Texte zur
Geistesgeschichte des Mittelalters 54. Leiden, 1996.
Holtz, Louis. “Le rôle des commentaires d’auteurs classiques dans l’émergence d’une mis
en page associant texte et commentaire (Moyen âge occidental).” In Commentaire.
Edited by Goulet-Cazé, 103–17.
Honnée, Eugène. “Die Religionsverhandlungen der Reichstage von Nürnberg (1524),
Speyer (1526) und Augsburg (1530) und die Entstehung der Idee eines Religions-
gesprächs.” Nederlands archief voor kerkgeschiedenis 73 (1993): 1–30.
Horn, Ewald. Die Disputationen und Promotionen an den Deutschen Universitäten vornehm-
lich seit dem 16. Jahrhundert. Zentralblatt für Bibliothekswesen, Beih. 11. Leipzig, 1893.
Reprint, Wiesbaden, 1968.
Hrdlička, Jaroslav. “Hus und Páleč.” In Jan Hus. Edited by Seibt, 103–6.
Hübener, Wolfgang. “Der theologisch-philosophische Konservativismus des Jean Ger-
son.” In Antiqui und Moderni. Edited by Zimmerman, 1971, 171–200.
Hurter, Hugo. Nomenclator literarius theologiae catholicae. 6 vols. Innsbruck, 1903–1913.
Imbach, Ruedi. Deus est intelligere: Das Verhältnis von Sein und Denken in seiner Bedeutung
für das Gottesverständnis bei Thomas von Aquin und in den Pariser Quaestionen Meister
Eckharts. Studia Friburgensia, n.s., 53. Fribourg, 1976.
Iserloh, Erwin. Johannes Eck (1486–1543): Scholastiker, Humanist, Kontroverstheologe.
Katholisches Leben und Kirchenreform im Zeitalter der Glaubensspaltung 41.
Münster, 1981.
372 Bibliography
Jansen, Bernhard. “Zur Philosophie der Skotisten des 17. Jahrunderts.” FStud 23 (1936):
28–58, 150–75.
———. “Die scholastische Philosophie des 17. Jahrhunderts.” PhJ 50 (1937): 401–44.
———. “Zur Phänomenologie der Philosophie der Thomisten des 17. und 18. Jahrhun-
derts.” Scholastik 13 (1938): 49–71.
Jenkins, John I. Knowledge and Faith in Thomas Aquinas. Cambridge, 1997.
Jolivet, Jean. Godescalc d’Orbais et la Trinité: La méthode de théologie à l’époque carolingi-
enne. Paris, 1958.
———. Arts du langage et théologie chez Abélard. Études de philosophie médiévale 57.
Paris, 1969.
Jung, Martin H., and Peter Walter, eds. Theologen des 16. Jahrhunderts. Humanismus—
Reformation—Katholische Erneuerung: Eine Einführung. Darmstadt, 2002.
Kann, Christoph. “Skepsis, Wahrheit, Illumination. Bemerkungen zur Erkenntnistheorie
Heinrichs von Gent.” In Nach der Verurteilung. Edited by Aertsen, et al., 2001, 38–58.
Kantorowicz, Hermann. “The Quaestiones disputatae of the glossators.” Revue d’histoire
du droit 16 (1937/38): 1–67.
Kerlen, Dietrich, Assertio. Die Entwicklung von Luthers theologischem Anspruch und der
Streit mit Erasmus von Rotterdam. VIEG 78. Wiesbaden, 1976.
Kessler, Eckhard, Charled H. Lohr, and Walter Sparn, eds. Aristotelismus und Renaissance:
In memoriam Charles B. Schmitt. Wolfenbütteler Forschungen 40. Wiesbaden, 1988.
Kienzle, Beverly Mayne, ed. The Sermon. Typologie des sources du Moyen âge occidental, fasc.
81–83. Turnhout, 2000.
Kienzler, Klaus. Glauben und Denken bei Anselm von Canterbury. Freiburg im Breisgau,
1981.
Kirste, Reinhard. Das Zeugnis des Geistes und das Zeugnis der Schrift: Das testimonium
spiritus sancti internum als hermeneutisch-polemischer Zentralbegriff bei Johann
Gerhard in der Auseinandersetzung mit Robert Bellarmins Schriftverständnis. Göttinger
theologische Arbeiten 6. Göttingen, 1976.
Klein, Jürgen, and Johannes Kramer, eds. J. H. Alsted: Herborns calvinistische Theologie und
Wissenschaft im Spiegel der englischen Kulturreform des frühen 17. Jahrhunderts. Aspekte
der englischen Geistes- und Kulturgeschichte 16. Frankfurt, 1988.
Klinkenberg, Hans Martin. “Die Devotio moderna unter dem Thema ‘Antiqui—Moderni’
betrachtet.” In Antiqui und Moderni. Edited by Zimmerman, 1971, 394–419.
Kluxen, Wolfgang. “Thomas von Aquin.” In Grundprobleme der großen Philosophen. Edited
by Josef Speck. Göttingen, 1972, 177–220.
———. “Die geschichtliche Erforschung der mittelalterlichen Philosophie und die
Neuscholastik.” In Christliche Philosophie. Edited by Coreth, Neidl, and Pfligers-
dorffer, 1988, 2:362–89.
Knebel, Sven K. “Necessitas moralis ad optimum: Zum historischen Hintergrund der
Wahl der besten aller möglichen Welten.” StudLeib 23 (1991): 3–24.
———. “Scientia media: Ein diskursarchäologischer Leitfaden durch das 17. Jahrhun-
dert.” ABG 34 (1991): 262–94.
Knuuttila, Simo. “Trutfetter: Usingen and Erfurtian Ockhamism.” In Was ist Philosophie
im Mittelalter? Edited by Aertson and Speer, 818–23.
Kobusch, Theo. “Grammatica speculativa (12.–14. Jahrhundert).” In Klassiker der
Sprachphilosophie: Von Platon bis Noam Chomsky. Edited by Borsche and Tilman.
Munich, 1996, 77–93.
Bibliography 373
———. Christliche Philosophie: Die Entdeckung der Subjektivität. Darmstadt, 2006.
Koch, Josef. Artes liberales: Von der antiken Bildung zur Wissenschaft des Mittelalters. Stu-
dien und Texte zur Geistesgeschichte des Mittelalters 5. Leiden, 1959.
———. “Von der Bildung der Antike zur Wissenschaft des Mittelalters.” In Kleine
Schriften. Edited by Josef Koch. Rome, 1973, 115–32.
Köhn, Rolf. “Monastisches Bildungsideal und weltgeistliches Wissenschaftsdenken: Zur
Vorgeschichte des Mendikantenstreites an der Universität Paris.” In Auseinanderset-
zungen. Edited by Zimmerman, 1976, 1–37.
Kolesnyk, Alexander. “Hussens Eucharistiebegriff.” In Jan Hus. Edited by Seibt, 193–202.
Kölmel, Wilhelm. “‘Scholasticus literator’: Die Humanisten und ihr Verhältnis zur Scho-
lastik.” HJ 93 (1973): 301–35.
Köpf, Ulrich. Die Anfänge der theologischen Wissenschaftstheorie im 13. Jahrhundert. Beiträge
zur historischen Theologie 49. Tübingen, 1974.
———. “Melanchthon als systematischer Theologie neben Luther.” In Der Theologe
Melanchthon. Edited by Frank, 2000, 103–27.
———, ed. Theologen des Mittelalters: Eine Einführung. Darmstadt, 2002.
Kraml, Hans. Die Rede von Gott, sprachkritisch rekonstruiert aus Sentenzenkommentaren
Innsbrucker theologische Studien 13. Innsbruck, 1984.
———, and Gerhard Leibold, Wilhelm von Ockham. Zugänge zum Denken des Mittelal-
ters 1. Münster, 2003.
Krebs, Engelbert. Theologie und Wissenschaft nach der Lehre der Hochscholastik. BGPhMA
11, nos. 3–4. Münster, 1912.
Kreuzer, Georg. Heinrich von Langenstein: Studien zur Biographie und zu den Schismatrak-
taten unter besonderer Berücksichtigung der Epistola pacis und der Epistola concilii pacis.
Quellen und Forschungen aus dem Gebiet der Geschichte, n.s., 6. Paderborn, 1987.
Kristeller, Paul Oskar. “Humanism and Scholasticism in the Italian Renaissance.” In Stud-
ies in Renaissance Thought and Letters. Rome, 1956, 553–83.
———. Humanismus und Renaissance, German translation by E. Kessler. 2 vols. Mu-
nich, 1974/76.
Krüger, Friedhelm. Humanistische Evangelienauslegung: Desiderius Erasmus von Rotterdam
als Ausleger der Evangelien in seinen Paraphrasen. Beiträge zur Historischen Theologie
68. Tübingen, 1968.
Kuchařova, Hedvika. “Premonstrátska kolej Norbertinum v Praze (1637–1785).” Biblio-
theca Strahoviensis 3 (1997): 15–57.
Lacroix, B. “Hugues de Saint-Victor et les conditions du savoir au moyen âge.” In An
Etienne Gilson Tribute. Edited by Charles J. O’Neill. Milwaukee, 1959, 118–34.
Lambert, Malcom. Medieval Heresy: Popular Movements from the Gregorian Reform to the
Reformation. Oxford, 1992.
Lambert, Michel. “Nouveaux éléments pour une étude de l’authenticité Boécienne des
Opuscula Sacra.” In Boèce ou la chaîne des savoirs: Actes du Colloque International de la
Fondation Singer-Polignac, présidée par Monsieur Éduard Bonnefous, Paris, 8–12 juin 1990.
Edited by Alain Galonnier. Philosophes Médiévaux 44. Louvain-la-Neuve, 2003, 171–91.
Lamboij, H. Th. M., and J. A. Mol, eds. Vitae Abbatum Orti Sancte Marie: Vijf abtenlevens
van het klooster Mariëngaarde in Friesland. Hilversum, 2001.
Landgraf, Arthur M. “Drei Zweige der Pseudo-Poitiers Glosse zu den Sentenzen des
Lombarden.” RThAM 9 (1937): 167–204.
———. “Sentenzenglossen des beginnenden 13. Jahrhunderts.” RThAM 10 (1938): 36–55.
374 Bibliography
———. “Zum Begriff der Scholastik.” CollFr 11 (1941): 487–90.
———. Einführung in die Geschichte der theologischen Literatur der Frühscholastik unter
dem Gesichtspunkt der Schulenbildung. Regensburg, 1948.
———. Dogmengeschichte der Frühscholastik. 4 vols. Regensburg, 1956.
Lang, Albert. Die Loci theologici des Melchior Cano und die Methode des dogmatischen
Beweises. Munich, 1925.
———. Die Wege der Glaubensbegründung bei den Scholastikern des 14. Jahrhunderts.
BGPhMA 30, nos. 1–2. Münster, 1930.
———. Heinrich Totting von Oyta: Ein Beitrag zur Entstehungsgeschichte der ersten
deutschen Universitäten und zur Problemgeschichte der Spätscholastik. BGPhThMA 33,
no. 4/5. Münster, 1937, 50–53.
———. “Die Bedeutung Alberts des Großen für die Aufrollung der fundamentaltheolo-
gischen Frage.” In Studia Albertina: Festschrift B. Geyer. BGPhThMA Sup. IV. Münster,
1952, 343–73.
———. Die theologische Prinzipienlehre der mittelalterlichen Scholastik. Freiburg, 1964.
Lang, Justin. Die Christologie bei Heinrich von Langenstein: Eine dogmenhistorische Unter-
suchung. Freiburger Theologische Studien 85. Freiburg, 1966.
Langer, Otto. “Aristoteles und die Folgen: Zur Rezeption der aristotelischen Logik und
Wissenschaftstheorie im 12. und 13. Jahrhundert.” FZPhTh 53 (2006): 559–88.
Lawn, Brian. The Rise and Decline of the Scholastic “Quaestio Disputata”: With Special Em-
phasis on Its Use in the Teaching of Medicine and Science. Education and Society in the
Middle Ages and Renaissance 2. Leiden, 1993.
Leclercq, Jean. “Le genre épistolaire au moyen âge.” RMAL 2 (1946): 63–70.
———. “Drogon et Saint Bernard.” RBen 63 (1963): 116–31.
———. Wissenschaft und Gottverlangen. Düsseldorf, 1963.
———. “The Renewal of Theology.” In Renaissance. Edited by Benson and Constable.
Oxford, 1982, 68–87.
Leff, Gordon. Bradwardine and the Pelagians: A Study of His “De causa Dei” and Its Op-
ponents. Cambridge, 1957.
———. Heresy in the Later Middle Ages: The Relation of Heterodoxy to Dissent c. 1250–
c. 1450. Manchester, 1967.
———. Paris and Oxford Universities in the Thirteenth and Fourteenth Centuries: An Institu-
tional and Intellectual History. New York, 1968.
———. William of Ockham: The Metamorphosis of Scholastic Discourse. Manchester, 1975.
Leibold, Gerhard. “Die Kontroverse zwischen den Philosophen und Theologen in der
ersten Quaestio des Prologs der ‘Ordinatio’ von Johannes Duns Scotus.” In Was ist
Philosophie im Mittelalter? Edited by Aertson and Speer, 629–36.
Leinsle, Ulrich G. Res et signum: Das Verständnis zeichenhafter Wirklichkeit in der Theologie
Bonaventuras. Veröffentlichungen des Grabmann-Institutes 26. Munich, 1976.
———. Vivianus von Prémontré: Ein Gegner Abaelards in der Lehre von der Freiheit. Biblio-
theca Analectorum Praemonstratensium 13. Averbode, 1978.
———. “Abt Hieronymus Hirnhaim: Zur Wissenschaftskritik des 17. Jahrhunderts.”
AnPraem 55 (1979): 171–95.
———. “Die Einheit der Wissenschaft nach Johannes Duns Scotus.” WiWei 43 (1979):
157–76.
———. “Die Einheit der Wissenschaft nach Wilhelm von Ockham.” WiWei 43 (1980):
107–29.
Bibliography 375
———. “Die Hugo von St. Viktor zugeschriebenen Texte ‘De libero arbitrio’ und Vivi-
anus von Prémontré.” AnPraem 57 (1981): 183–95.
———. “Aristoteles und die ‘Moderni’ in der Vita Siardi.” AnPraem 58 (1982): 210–24.
———. Das Ding und die Methode: Methodische Konstitution und Gegenstand der frühen
protestantischen Metaphysik. Augsburg, 1985.
———. Reformversuche protestantischer Metaphysik im Zeitalter des Rationalismus. Augs-
burg, 1988.
———. “Von der Weltordnung zur Lebensordnung: Aufgabe und Grenzen der Philoso-
phie nach Augustinus’ Dialog ‘De Ordine.’” ThPQ 137 (1989): 369–77.
———. “Benediktinischer Thomismus bei den Prämonstratensern.” AnPraem 74 (1998):
177–203.
———. Studium im Kloster: Das philosophisch-theologische Hausstudium des Stiftes Schlägl
1633–1783. Bibliotheca Analectorum Praemonstratensium 20. Averbode, 2000.
———. “‘Charitati militare’: Der klösterliche Kampf um den Frieden nach Adamus
Scotus († 1212).” AnPraem 79 (2003): 5–24.
———. “Festdisputationen in Prälatenklöstern.” In Solemnitas: Barocke Festkultur in
Oberpfälzer Klöstern, Beiträge des 1. Symposions des Kultur- und Begegnungszentrums
Abtei Waldsassen vom 25. bis 27. Oktober 2002. Edited by Manfred Knedlik and Georg
Schott. Veröffentlichungen Kultur- und Begegnungszentrums Abtei Waldsassen 1.
Kallmünz, 2003, 101–13.
———. “Lehet-e filozófiát alapozni a Bibliára? (Philosophie aus der Bibel?)” Vigilia 70
(2005): 246–57.
———. Dilinganae Disputationes: Der Lehrinhalt der gedruckten Disputationen an der Phil-
osophischen Fakultät der Universität Dillingen 1555–1648. Jesuitica 11. Regensburg, 2006.
———. “Servatius de Lairuelz und Juan Caramuel Lobkowitz OCist: Zwei Auslegungen
der Augustinus-Regel.” AnPraem 82 (2006): 283–320.
———. “Die Scholastik der Neuzeit bis zur Aufklärung.” In Christliche Philosophie. Edited
by Coreth, et al., 1988, 2:54–69.
———. “Methodologie und Metaphysik bei den deutschen Lutheranern um 1600.” In
Aristotelismus und Renaissance. Edited by Kessler, et al., 1988, 149–62.
Leites, Edmund, ed. Conscience and Casuistry in Early Modern Europe. Cambridge, 1988.
Lemaire, Paul. Le Cartésianisme chez les Bénédictins: Dom Robert Desgabets: Son Système,
son influence et son école. Diss., Grenoble-Paris, 1901.
Leone, Marialucrezia. “Zum Status der Theologie bei Heinrich von Gent—Ist sie eine
praktische oder theoretische Wissenschaft.” In What is “Theology?” Edited by Olszew-
ski, 2007, 195–224.
Leppin, Volker. Geglaubte Wahrheit: Das Theologieverständnis Wilhelms von Ockham.
FKDG 63. Göttingen, 1995.
———. Theologie im Mittelalter. Kirchengeschichte in Einzeldarstellungen I/11. Leipzig,
2007.
Lesch, Karl Josef. Neuorientierung der Theologie im 18. Jahrhundert in Würzburg und Bamberg.
Forschungen zur Fränkischen Kirchen- und Theologiegeschichte 1. Würzburg, 1978.
Leube, Hans. Kalvinismus und Luthertum im Zeitalter der Orthodoxie. Leipzig, 1928. Re-
print, Aalen, 1966.
Libera, Alain de. “Philosophie et censure: Remarques sur la crise universitaire parisienne
de 1270–1277.” In Was ist Philosophie im Mittelalter? Edited by Aertsen and Speer, 1998,
71–89.
376 Bibliography
Liguš, Ján. “Hussens Schriftbegriff in seinen Predigten.” In Jan Hus. Edited by Seibt,
127–38.
Little, A. G. “The Franciscan School at Oxford in the Thirteenth Century.” AFrH 19
(1926): 803–74.
Lohse, Bernhard. Ratio und Fides: Eine Untersuchung über die ratio in der Theologie Luthers.
Forschungen zur Kirchen- und Dogmengeschichte 8. Göttingen, 1957.
———. “Luthers Selbstverständnis in seinem frühen Romkonflikt und die Vorgeschichte
des Begriffs ‘Theologia Crucis’: Untersucht anhand des Briefwechsels zwischen 1517
und 1519/20.” In Humanismus. Edited by Beyer and Wartenberg, 15–31.
———. Luthers Theologie in ihrer historischen Entwicklung und in ihrem systematischen
Zusammenhang. Göttingen, 1995.
Long, R. James. “The Science of Theology according to Richard Fishacre: Edition of the
Prologue to his Commentary on the Sentences.” MS 34 (1972): 71–98.
———, and Maura O’Caroll. The Life and Works of Richard Fishacre OP: Prolegomena
to the Edition of his Commentary on the Sentences. Bayerische Akademie der Wis-
senschaften, Veröffentlichungen der Kommission für die Herausgabe ungedruckter
Texte aus der mittelalterlichen Geisteswelt 21. Munich, 1999.
Lottin, Odon. “Le premier commentaire connu des Sentences de Pierre Lombard.”
RThAM 11 (1939): 64–71.
———. Psychologie et Morale aux XIIe et XIIIe siècles. 6 vols. Louvain, 1942–1960.
Lourdaux, Willem, and Daniel Verhelst, eds. The Concept of Hersesy in the Middle Ages
(11th–13th C.) Proceedings of the International Conference, Louvain May 13–16, 1973.
Mediaevalia Lovaniensia I, 4. Leuven, 1976.
Lubac, Henri de. “A propos de la formule ‘Diversi, non adversi.’” RSR 40 (1951/52): 27–40.
———. Exégèse médiévale: Les quatre sens de l’écriture. Paris, 1959–1964. English transla-
tion by Mark Sebanc (vol. 1) and E. M. Macierowski (vol. 2). Medieval Exegesis.
Grand Rapids, Mich.: Eerdmans, 1998, 2000.
Luscombe, David E. The School of Peter Abelard: The Influence of Abelard’s Thought in the
Early Scholastic Period. Cambridge, 1969.
Lurz, Wilhelm. Adam Tanner und die Gnadenstreitigkeiten des 17. Jahrhunderts: Ein Beitrag
zur Geschichte des Molinismus. Breslauer Studien zur historischen Theologie 21.
Breslau, 1932.
Lütcke, Karl-Heinrich. “Auctoritas” bei Augustin. Tübinger Beiträge zur Altertumswissen-
schaft 44. Stuttgart, 1968.
Madiski, George. “The Scholastic Method in Medieval Education: An Inquiry into Its
Origins in Law and Theology.” Speculum 49 (1974): 640–61.
Mandonnet, Pierre. Siger de Brabant et l’averroisme latin au XIIIe siècle. Fribourg, 1899.
Manrangon, Paolo. “Le origini e le fonti dello scotismo padovano.” In Regnum Hominis et
Regnum Dei: Acta Quarti Congressus Scotistici Internationalis: Patavii, 24–29 septembris
1976, vol. II. Edited by Camille Bérubé. Studia Scholastico-Scotistica 7. Rome, 1978,
11–52.
Manser, Gallus. “Die mittelalterliche Scholastik nach ihrem Umfange und Charakter.”
HPBL 139 (1907): 317–39; 407–31.
Manstetten, Rainer. Esse est Deus: Meister Eckharts christologische Versöhnung von Philoso-
phie und Religion und ihre Ursprünge in der Tradition des Abendlandes. Freiburg, 1992.
Marcolino, Venício. “Der Augustinertheologe an der Universität Paris.” In Gregor von
Rimini. Edited by Oberman, 1981, 127–94.
Bibliography 377
Marenbon, John. From the Circle of Alcuin to the School of Auxerre: Logic, Theology and
Philosophy in the Early Middle Ages. Cambridge, 1981.
Marrou, Henri-Irénée. Augustinus und das Ende der antiken Bildung. Paderborn, 1981.
Menzel, Beda Franz. Abt Stephan Rautenstrauch von Břevnov-Braunau: Herkunft, Umwelt
und Wirkungskreis. Veröffentlichungen des Königsteiner Instituts für Kirchen- und
Geistesgeschichte der Sudentenländer 5. Königstein, 1969.
Merkt, Andreas. Das patristische Prinzip: Eine Studie zur theologischen Bedeutung der Kirch-
enväter. Supplements to Vigiliae Christianae 58. Leiden, 2001
Merl, Otho. Theologia Salmanticensis: Untersuchung über Entstehung, Lehrrichtung und
Quellen des theologischen Kurses der spanischen Karmeliten. Regensburg, 1947.
Metz, Detlef. Gabriel Biel und die Mystik. Contubernium 55. Stuttgart, 2001.
Meyer, Heinz, and Rudolf Suntrup. Lexikon der mittelalterlichen Zahlenbedeutungen. Mün-
sterische Mittelalter-Schriften 56. Munich, 1987.
Micaelli, Claudio. Studi sui trattati teologici di Boezio. Naples, 1988.
———. Dio nel pensiero di Boezio. Storie e testi 4. Naples, 1995.
Miethke, Jürgen. “Papst, Ortsbischof und Universität von Paris in den Pariser Theolo-
genprozessen des 13. Jahrhunderts.” In Auseinandersetzungen. Edited by Zimmerman,
1976, 52–94.
———. “Theologenprozesse in der ersten Phase ihrer institutionellen Ausbildung:
Die Verfahren gegen Peter Abaelard und Gilbert von Poitiers.” Viator 6 (1975): 87–
116.
Minnich, N. H. “On the Origins of Eck’s ‘Enchirdion.’” In Johannes Eck (1486–1543) im
Streit der Jahrhunderte. Edited by Erwin Iserloh. RGST 127. Münster, 1988, 37–73.
Mitschelich, Antonius. Kommentatoren zur Summa Theologiae des hl. Thomas von Aquin.
Graz, 1924. Reprint, Hildesheim, 1981.
Mittermüller, Rupert. Beiträge zu einer Geschichte der ehemaligen Benedictiner-Universität in
Salzburg. Salzburg, 1889.
Möhle, Hannes. Formalitas und modus intrinsecus: Die Entwicklung der scotischen
Metaphysik bei Franciscus de Mayronis. BGPhThMA, n.s., 70. Münster, 2007.
Moore, Philip S. The Works of Peter of Poitiers, Master in Theology and Chancellor of Paris
(1193–1205). Publications in Medieval Studies 1. Notre Dame, Ind., 1936.
Morerod, Charles. Cajetan et Luther en 1518. 2 vols. Fribourg, 1994.
Neumann, Siegfried. Gegenstand und Methode der theoretischen Wissenschaften nach Thom-
as von Aquin aufgrund der Expositio super librum Boethii De Trinitate. BGPhThMA 41,
no. 2. Münster, 1965.
Niederbacher, Bruno, and Gerhard Leibold, eds. Theologie als Wissenschaft im Mittelalter:
Eine Einführung. Münster, 2006.
Nielsen, Lauge O. Theology and Philosophy in the Twelfth Century: A Study of Gilbert Por-
reta’s Thinking and the Theological Exposition of the Doctrine of Incarnation during the
Period 1130–1180. Acta Theologica Danica 15. Leiden, 1982.
———. “Peter Abelard and Gilbert of Poitiers.” In Medieval Theologians. Edited by Evans,
102–28.
Niggli, Ursula. “Philosophischer Scharfsinn in der theologischen Kritik.” In Peter Abae-
lard: Leben—Werk—Wirkung. Edited by Niggli. Forschungen zur Europäischen
Geistesgeschichte 4. Freiburg im Breisgau, 2003, 235–65.
Oberman, Heiko Augustinus. Der Herbst der mittelalterlichen Theologie. Zürich, 1965.
———. “Tuus sum, salvum me fac: Augustinréveil zwischen Renaissance und Ref-
378 Bibliography
ormation.” In Scientia Augustiniana: Festschrift A. Zumkeller OSA. Cassiciacum 30.
Würzburg, 1975.
———. Werden und Wertung der Reformation: Vom Wegestreit zum Glaubenskampf. Tü-
bingen, 1977.
———. “Hus und Luther: Der Antichrist und die zweite reformatorische Entdeckung.”
In Jan Hus. Edited by Seibt, 319–46.
———, ed. Gregor von Rimini: Werk und Wirkung bis zur Reformation. Spätmittelalter und
Reformation 20. Berlin, 1981.
Oediger, Friedrich Wilhelm. Über die Bildung der Geistlichen im späten Mittelalter. Leiden,
1953.
Oelrich, Karl Heinz. Der späte Erasmus und die Reformation. RGST 86. Münster, 1961.
Oliva, Adriano. Les debuts de l’enseignement de Thomas d’Aquin et sa conception de la sacra
doctrina, avec l’édition du prologue de son Commentaire des Sentences. Bibliothèque
Thomiste 58. Paris, 2006.
Olivares, Estanislao. “Juan de Lugo (1583–1660): Datos biográficos, sus escritos, estudios
sobre su doctrina y bibliografía.” ATG 47 (1984): 5–129.
Olszewski, Miko ai, ed. What Is “Theology” in the Middle Ages? Religious Cultures of Europe
(11th–15th Centuries) as Reflected in Their Self-Understanding. Archa Verbi, Subsisdia 1.
Münster, 2007.
Ong, Walter J. Ramus: Method and the Decay of Dialogue: From the Art of Discourse to the
Art of Reason. Cambridge, Mass., 1958.
Oppermann, Hans, ed. Humanismus. Wege der Forschung 17. Darmstadt, 1970.
Osborne, Kenan B. “Alexander of Hales: Precursor and Promotor of Franciscan Theol-
ogy.” In The History of Franciscan Theology. Edited by Osborne. St. Bonaventure, N.Y.,
1994, 1–38.
Ott, Ludwig. Untersuchungen zur theologischen Briefliteratur der Frühscholastik unter beson-
derer Berücksichtigung des Viktorinerkreises. BGPhThMA 34. Münster, 1937.
Otte, Gerhard. “Der Probabilismus: Eine Theorie an der Grenze zwischen Theologie und
Jurisprudenz.” In La seconda scolastica nella formazione del diritto privato moderno:
Incontro di studio Firenze 16–18 ottobre 1972. Edited by Paolo Grossi. Per la storia del
pensiero giuridico moderno 1. Milan, 1973, 283–302.
Otten, Willemien. “Carolingian Theology.” In Medieval Theologians. Edited by Evans,
65–82.
Paqué, Ruprecht. Das Pariser Nominalistenstatut: Zur Entwicklung des Realitätsbegriffs der
neuzeitlichen Naturwissenschaft: Occam, Buridan und Petrus Hispanus, Nikolaus von
Autrecourt und Gregor von Rimini. Quellen und Studien zur Geschichte der Philoso-
phie 14. Berlin, 1970.
Paquet, Jacques, and Joseph Ijsewijn, eds. Les Universités à la fin du moyen âge: Actes du
Congrès international de Louvain 26–30 mai 1975. Louvain, 1978.
Pařez, Jan, and Hedvika Kuchařova. Hyberni v Praze: Éireannaigh i bPrág: Déjiny
františkánké kolej Neposkvrnéného početí Panny Marie v Praze (1629.1786). Prague, 2001.
Partee, Charles. Calvin and Classical Philosophy. Studies in the History of Christian
Thought 14. Leiden, 1977.
Pastine, Dino. Juan Caramuel: Probabilismo ed Enciclopedia. Florence, 1976.
Paulsen, Friedrich. Geschichte des gelehrten Unterrichts auf den deutschen Schulen und Uni-
versitäten vom Ausgang des Mittelalters bis zur Gegenwart. Leipzig, 1919.
Pelster, Franz. “Die Bedeutung der Sentenzenvorlesung für die theologische Spekulation
Bibliography 379
des Mittelalters: Ein Zeugnis aus der ältesten Oxforder Dominikanerschule.” Scholas-
tik 2 (1927): 250–55.
———. “Das Leben und die Schriften des Oxforder Dominikanerlehrers Richard Fish-
acre († 1248),” ZKTh 54 (1930): 518–53.
Pergamo, Basilius. “De Quaestionibus ineditis Fr. Odonis Rigaldi, Fr. Guilelmi de
Melitona et Codicis Vat. lat. 782 circa naturam theologiae deque earum relatione ad
Summam Theologicam Fr. Alexandri Halensis.” AFrH 29 (1936): 3–54, 308–64.
Perler, Dominik. “Notwendigkeit und Kontingenz: Das Problem der ‘futura contingentia’
bei Wilhelm von Ockham.” In Die Philosophie im 14 und 15. Jahrhundert: In memoriam
Konstanty Michalski (1879–1949). Edited by Olaf Pluta. Amsterdam, 1988, 39–65.
———. Der propositionale Wahrheitsbegriff im 14. Jahrhundert. Quellen und Studien zur
Philosophie 33. Berlin, 1992.
Petersen, Peter. Geschichte der aristotelischen Philosophie im protestantischen Deutschland.
Leipzig, 1921.
Pieper, Josef. Scholastik: Gestalten und Probleme der mittelalterlichen Philosophie. Munich,
1960.
Poppi, Antonino. La dottrina della scienza in Giacomo Zabarella. Padua, 1972.
Porro, Pasquale. “Lo statuto della philosophia in Enrico di Gand.” In Was ist Philosophie im
Mittelalter? Edited by Aertsen and Speer, 1998, 497–504.
Prassel, Peter. Das Theologieverständnis des Ägidius Romanus O.E.S.A. (1243/7–1316). Eu-
ropäische Hochschulschriften XXIII, no. 201. Frankfurt, 1983.
Precht-Nussbaum, Karin. Zwischen Augsburg und Rom: Der Pollinger Augustiner-Chorherr
Eusebius Amort (1692–1775): Ein bedeutender Repräsentant katholischer Aufklärung. Pub-
likationen der Akademie der Augustiner-Chorherren von Windesheim 7. Paring, 2007.
Prügl, Thomas. Die Ekklesiologie Heinrich Kalteisens OP in Auseinandersetzung mit dem
Basler Konziliarismus: Mit einem Textanhang. Veröffentlichungen des Grabmann-
Institutes 40. Paderborn, 1995.
———. Antonio de Cannara: De potestate pape supra Concilium Generale contra errores
Basiliensium: Einleitung, Kommentar und Edition augewählter Abschnitte. Veröffent-
lichungen des Grabmann-Institures 41. Paderborn, 1996.
Quinto, Riccardo. “Doctor Nominatissimus” Stefano Langton († 1228) e la tradizione delle sue
opere. BGPhThMA, n.s., 39. Münster, 1994.
———. Scholastica: Storia di un concetto. Subsidia Mediaevalia Patavina 2. Padua, 2001.
Ramelow, Tilman. Gott, Freiheit, Weltenwahl: Der Ursprung des Begriffs der besten aller
möglichen Welten in der Metaphysik der Willenfreiheit zwischen Antonio Perez S.J.
(1599–1649) und G. W. Leibniz (1646–1715). Brill’s Studies in Intellectual History 72.
Leiden, 1997.
Randall, John Herman. The School of Padua and the Emergence of Modern Science. Padua,
1961.
Rashdall, Hastings. The Universities of Europe in the Middle Ages. 3 vols. 1937. Reprint,
Oxford, 1987.
Ratschow, Carl Heinz. Lutherische Dogmatik zwischen Reformation und Aufklärung. Güt-
ersloh, 1966.
Ratzinger. The Theology of History in St. Bonaventure. Chicago: Franciscan Herald Press,
1971, 1989.
Reichert, Ernst Otto. Johannes Scheffler als Streittheologe. Studien zu Religion, Geschichte
und Geisteswissenschaft 4. Gütersloh, 1967.
380 Bibliography
Reinhardt, Karl. Pedro Luis SJ (1538–1602) und sein Verständnis der Kontingenz, Praescienz
und Praedestination. Münster, 1965.
Rentsch, Thomas. “Kultur der quaestio: Zur literarischen Formgeschichte der Philoso-
phie im Mittelalter.” In Literarische Formen der Philosophie. Edited by Gottfried
Gabriel and Christiane Schildknecht. Stuttgart, 1990, 73–91.
Reuter, Karl. Vom Scholaren bis zum jungen Reformator: Studien zum Werdegang Johannes
Calvins. Neukirchen-Vluyn, 1981.
Richter, Vladimír. “Aus der Nominalismus-Forschung: Zu den kritischen Ausgaben der Sen-
tenzenkommentare Wilhelms von Ockham und Gabriel Biels.” ZKTh 96 (1974): 431–37.
———. Studien zum literarischen Werk von Johannes Duns Scotus. Bayeriche Akademie der
Wissenschaften, Veröffentlichungen der Kommission für die Herausgabe ungedruck-
ter Texte aus der mittelalterlichen Geisteswelt 14. Munich, 1988.
———. “Textstudien zum Prolog des Oxforder Sentenzenkommentars von Johannes
Duns Scotus.” ZKTh 111 (1989): 431–49.
———. “Duns Scotus’ Text zur Theologie als praktischer Theologie.” CollFr 60 (1990):
459–75.
———. “Duns Scotus’ Text zur Univozität.” In Historia Philosophiae Medii Aevi: Studien
zur Geschichte der Philosophie des Mittelalters. Edited by Burkard Mojsich and Olaf
Pluta. Amsterdam, 1991, 2:889–910.
———. “Zu Ockhams Entwicklung in der Universalienfrage.” In Unterwegs. Richter and
Liebold, 105–21.
———. “Unterwegs zum historischen Ockham. Historisch-literarische Bemerkungen
zur Authentizität von Ockhams Schriften.” In Unterwegs. Richter and Liebold, 137–53.
———, and Gerhard Leibold.Unterwegs zum historischen Ockham. Mediaevalia Oenipon-
tana 1. Innsbruck, 1998.
Rijk, Lambert M. de. La philosophie au moyen âge. Leiden, 1985.
Ritschl, Otto. System und systematische Methode in der Geschichte des wissenschaftlichen
Sprachgebrauchs und der philosophischen Methodologie. Bonn, 1905.
———. Dogmengeschichte des Protestantismus. 4 vols. Göttingen, 1908–1927.
Ritter, Gerhard. “Die geschichtliche Bedeutung des deutschen Humanismus.” HZ 127
(1923): 393–453.
Robson, John Adam. Wyclif and the Oxford Schools: The Relation of the “Summa de Ente” to
Scholastic Debates at Oxford in the Later Fourteenth Century. Cambridge, 1966.
Rodis-Lewis, Geneviève. “Quelques échos de la thèse de Desgabets sur l’indefectibilité
des substances.” Studia Cartesiana 1 (1979): 124–28.
Roensch, Frederik J. Early Thomistic School. Dubuque, 1964.
Rohner, Anselm. “De natura Theologiae iuxta S. Albertum Magnum.” Angelicum 16 (1939):
3–23.
Rössler, Hellmuth, and Günther Franz, eds. Universität und Gelehrtenstand 1400–1800:
Büdinger Vorträge. Deutsche Führungsschichten in der Neuzeit 4. Limburg, 1970.
Rossmann, Heribert. “Die Sentenzenkommentare des Franz von Meyronnes OFM.”
FStud 53 (1971): 129–227.
———. Die Hierarchie der Welt. Gestalt und System des Franz von Meyronnes OFM mit
besonderer Berücksichtigung seiner Schöpfungslehre. Franziskanische Forschungen 23.
Werl, 1972.
Roth, Bartholomäus. Franz von Mayronis O.F.M.: Sein Leben, seine Werke, seine Lehre vom
Formalunterschied in Gott. Franziskanische Forschungen 3. Werl, 1936.
Bibliography 381
Roth, Cornelius. Discretio spirituum: Kriterien geistlicher Unterscheidung bei Johannes Ger-
son. Studien zur systematischen und spirituellen Theologie 33. Würzburg, 2001.
Roth, Dorothea. Die mittelalterliche Predigttheorie und das Manuale Curatorum des Johann
Ulrich Surgant. Basler Beiträge zur Geschichtswissenschaft 58. Basel-Stuttgart, 1956.
Rouse, Richard H., and Mary A. Rouse. “Statim invenire: Schools, Preachers and New
Attitude to the Pages.” In Renaissance. Edited by Benson and Constable, 201–25.
Rückert, Georg. Eusebius Amort und das bayerische Geistesleben im 18. Jahrhundert. Beiträge
zur altbayerischen Kirchengeschichte 20, 2. Munich, 1956.
Russo, Renato. La metodologia del sapere nel Sermone di S. Bonaventura “Unus est magister
vester Christus” con nuova edizione critica e traduzione italiana. Spicilegium Bonaventu-
rianum 22. Grottaferrata, 1982.
Ruh, Kurt. Meister Eckhart: Theologe, Prediger, Mystiker. 2nd rev. ed. Munich, 1989.
Rupprich, Hans. Das Wiener Schrifttum des ausgehenden Mittelalters. Sitzungsberichte der
Österreichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Phil.-Hist. Klasse 228, no. 5. Vienna,
1954.
Santos Noya, Manuel. “Die ‘Auctoritates theologicae’ im Sentenzenkommentar des Mar-
silius von Inghen.” In Philosophie und Theologie des ausgehenden Mittelalters: Marsilius
von Inghen und das Denken seiner Zeit. Edited by Maarten J. E. M. Hoenen and Paul J.
J. M. Bakker. Leiden, 2000, 197–210.
Saxlová, Tereza, and Stanislav Sousedík, eds. Rodrigo de Arriaga († 1667) Philosoph und
Theologe: Prag 25.–28. Juni 1996. Prague, 1998.
Schäfer, Philipp. Kirche und Vernunft: Die Kirche in der katholischen Theologie der
Aufklärungszeit. Münchener Theologische Studien 42. Munich, 1974.
Schaffner, Otto. Eusebius Amort (1692–1775) als Moraltheologe. Abhandlungen zur Moral-
theologie. Paderborn, 1963.
Scheible, Heinz. “Aristoteles und die Wittenberger Universitätsreform: Zum Quellenwert
von Lutherbriefen.” In Humanismus. Edited by Beyer and Wartenberg, 123–44.
———. Melanchthon: Eine Biographie. Munich, 1997.
Schilling, Johannes. “Melanchthons Loci communes deutsch.” In Humanismus. Edited by
Beyer and Wartenberg, 337–52.
Schirpenbach, Meik Peter. Wirklichkeit als Beziehung: Das strukturontologische Schema der
Termini generales im Opus Tripartitum Meister Eckharts. BGPhThMA, n.s., 66. Münster,
2004.
Schleiff, Arnold. Selbstkritik der lutherischen Kirchen im 17. Jahrhundert. Neue Deutsche
Forschungen, Abt. Religions- und Kirchengeschichte 6. Berlin, 1937.
Schmidinger, Heinrich M. “Der Streit um die Anfänge der italienischen Neuscholastik.”
In Christliche Philosophie. Edited by Neidl, and Pfligersdorffer, 1988, 2:72–82.
———. “‘Scholastik’ und ‘Neuscholastik’—Geschichte zweier Begriffe.” In Christliche
Philosophie. Edited by Coreth, et al., 1988, 2:23–53.
———. “Überblick zur Neuscholastik in Frankreich und Belgien.” In Christliche Philoso-
phie. Edited by Coreth, Neidl, and Pfligersdorffer, 1988, 2:195–205.
Schmidt, Martin Anton. “Scholastik.” In Die Kirche in ihrer Geschichte. Vol. 2, Lieferung G.
Göttingen, 1969, 67–181.
Schmidt-Biggemann, Wilhelm. Topica universalis: Eine Modellgeschichte humanistischer und
barocker Wissenschaft. Paradeigmata 1. Hamburg, 1983.
Schmitt, Charles B. The Aristotelian Tradition and Renaissance Universities. London, 1984.
Schmitz, Philipp. “Probabilismus—das jesuitischste der Moralsysteme.” In Ignatianisch:
382 Bibliography
Eigenart und Methode der Gesellschaft Jesu. Edited by Michael Sievernich and Günter
Switek. Freiburg im Breisgau, 1990, 355–68.
Schneyer, Johann Baptist. Die Unterweisung der Gemeinde über die Predigt bei scholast-
ischen Predigten: Eine Homiletik aus scholastischen Prothemen. Veröffentlichungen des
Grabmann-Institutes, n.s., 4. Munich, 1968.
———. Geschichte der katholischen Predigt. Freiburg im Breisgau, 1969.
———. Repertorium der lateinischen Sermones des Mittelalters. 11 vols. Münster, 1969–1990.
Schöffler, Herbert. Deutsches Geistesleben zwischen Reformation und Aufklärung. Frankfurt,
19562.
Schönberger, Rolf. Was ist Scholastik? Philosophie und Religion 2. Hildesheim, 1991.
Schrama, Martijn. Gabriel Biel an zijn leer over de allerheiligste Drievuldigheid volgens
het eerste boek van zijn Collectorium. Bayerische Akademie der Wissenschaften.
Veröffentlichungen der Kommission für die Herausgabe ungedruckter Texte aus der
mittelalterlichen Geisteswelt 9. Munich, 1981.
Schrimpf, Gangolf. Die Axiomenschrift des Boethius (De hebdomadibus) als philosophisches
Lehrbuch des Mittelalters. Studien zur Problemgeschichte der antiken und mittelal-
terlichen Philosophie 2. Leiden, 1966.
———. Das Werk des Johannes Scottus Eriugena im Rahmen des Wissenschaftsverständnisses
seiner Zeit. BGPhThMA, n.s., 23. Münster, 1982.
———. “Bausteine für einen historischen Begriff der scholastischen Philosophie.” In
Philosophie im Mittelalter, Ian P. Beckmann. Hamburg, 1987, 1–25.
Schröcker, Hubert. Das Verhältnis der Allmacht Gottes zum Kontradiktionsprinzip nach
Wilhelm von Ockham. Veröffentlichungen des Grabmann-Institutes 49. Berlin, 2003.
Schröder, Richard. Johann Gerhards lutherische Christologie und die aristotelische
Metaphysik. Beiträge zur Historischen Theologie 67. Tübingen, 1983.
Schubert, Ernst. “Zur Typologie gegenreformatorischer Universitätsgründungen: Jesuiten
in Fulda, Würzburg und Dillingen.” In Universität und Gelehrtenstand. Edited by
Rössler and Franz, 85–105.
Schulze, Manfred. “‘Via Gregorii’ in Forschung und Quellen.” In Gregor von Rimini. Edited
by Oberman, 1981, 1–126.
Schüssler, Hermann. Der Primat der Heiligen Schrift als theologisches und kanonistisches
Problem im Spätmittelalter. VIEG 86. Wiesbaden, 1977.
Schwamm, Hermann. Das göttliche Vorherwissen bei Duns Scotus und seinen ersten An-
hängern. Philosophie und Grenzwissenschaften 5. Innsbruck, 1934.
Seibt, Ferdinand, ed. Jan Hus: Zwischen Zeiten, Völkern, Konfessionen. Veröffentlichungen
des Collegium Carolinum 85. Munich, 1997.
Seifert, Arno. Logik zwischen Scholastik und Humanismus: Das Kommentarwerk Johann
Ecks. Humanistische Bibliothek I, no. 31. Munich, 1978.
Senner, Walter. “Zur Wissenschaftstheorie der Theologie im Sentenzenkommentar
Alberts des Grossen.” In Albertus Magnus. Doctor universalis 1280/1980. Edited by
Gerbert Meyer and Albert Zimmerman.Walberberger Studien. Phil. Reihe 6. Mainz,
1980, 323–43.
Sicard, Patrice. Hugues de Saint-Victor et son école. Turnhout, 1991.
Sileo, Leonardo. Teoria della scienza teologica: Quaestio de scientia theologiae di Odone
Rigaldi e altri testi inediti (1230–1250). Rome, 1984.
Smalley, Beryl. “A Commentary on the Hebraica by Herbert of Bosham.” RThAM 18
(1951): 29–63.
Bibliography 383
———. “Robert Holcot.” AFP 26 (1956): 5–97.
———. English Friars and Antiquity in the Early Fourteenth Century. Oxford, 1960.
———. The Study of the Bible in the Middle Ages. Oxford, 1983.
Smolinsky, Heribert. “Johannes Eck: Scholastiker, Humanist, Kontroverstheologe.” In
Theologen des 16. Jahrhunderts. Edited by Jung and Walter, 103–15.
Sommervogel, Carlos. Bibliothèque de la Compagnie de Jesus. 9 vols. Brussels, 1890. Re-
print, 10 vols. Toulouse, 1911.
Sousedík, Stanislav. “Huss et la doctrine eucharistique ‘rémanentiste.’” Divinitas 21 (1977):
383–407.
———. “La Obra filosófica de Rodrigo de Arriaga.” Ibero-Americana Pragensia 15 (1981):
103–46.
———. “Der Scotismus in den böhmischen Ländern.” CollFr 60 (1990): 494–503.
———. “Wyclif und Böhmen.” Contemporary Philosophy 6 (1990): 521–31.
———. Filosofie v českźch zemích mezi středověkem a osvícenstvím. Prague, 1997.
Southern, Richard W. Western Views of Islam in the Middle Ages. Cambridge, Mass., 1962.
———. Robert Grosseteste: The Growth of an English Mind in Medieval Europe. Oxford,
1986.
Sparn, Walter. Wiederkehr der Metaphysik: Die ontologische Frage in der lutherischen
Theologie des frühen 17. Jahrhunderts. Calwer Theologische Monographien Reihe B, 4.
Stuttgart, 1976.
———. “Die Schulphilosophie in den lutherischen Territorien.” In Grundriss der Ge-
schichte der Philosophie, started by Friedrich Ueberweg, new rev. ed., Die Philosophie
des 17. Jahrhunderts. Basel, 1998–2002, IV,1, 475–606.
———. “Subjekte von Freiheit: Roderigo de Arriagas Lehre von der scientia media im
frühneuzeitlichen Kontext.” In Arriaga. Edited by Saxlová and Sousedík, 169–88.
Specht, Thomas. Geschichte der ehemaligen Universität Dillingen (1549–1804) und der mit
ihr verbundenen Lehr- und Erziehungsanstalten. Freiburg im Breisgau edition, 1902.
Reprint, Aalen, 1987.
Speer, Andreas. “Sapientia nostra: Zum Verhältnis von philosophischer und theologischer
Weisheit in den Pariser Debatten am Ende des 13. Jahrhunderts.” In Nach der Verur-
teilung. Edited by Aertsen, et al., 2001, 248–75.
Spijker, Willem van’t. “Calvin: Biographie und Theologie.” In Die Kirche in ihrer Geschichte,
vol. 3. Lieferung J 2. Göttingen, 2001, 101–236.
Spitz, Hans-Jörg. Die Metaphorik des geistigen Schriftsinns: Ein Beitrag zur allegorischen
Bibelauslegung des ersten christlichen Jahrtausends. Münsterische Mittelalter-Schriften
12. Munich, 1972.
Steenberghen, Fernand Van. Die Philosophie im 13. Jahrhundert. Munich, 1977.
Stegmüller, Friedrich. Zur Gnadenlehre des jungen Suárez. Freiburg, 1933.
———. Francisco de Vitoria y la doctrina de la gracia en la escuela Salmantina. Biblioteca
histórica de la Biblioteca Balmes II, 10. Barcelona, 1934.
———. Geschichte des Molinismus. BGPhThMA 32. Münster, 1935.
———. “Zur Prädestinationslehre des jungen Vasquez.” Aus der Geisteswelt des Mittelal-
ters. BGPhThMA Sup. III, no. 2. Münster, 1935, 1287–311.
———. Repertorium commentariorum in Sententias Petri Lombardi. 2 vols. Würzburg,
1947.
———. Repertorium Biblicum Medii Aevi. Madrid, 1950–1961; Supplementum. Edited with
N. Reinhardt 1976–1980. 11 vols.
384 Bibliography
Steiger, Johann Anselm. Johann Gerhard (1582–1637): Studien zu Theologie und Frömmigkeit
des Kirchenvaters der lutherischen Orthodoxie. Doctrina et Pietas I, 1. Stuttgart, 1997.
———. “Johann Gerhard. Ein Kirchenvater der lutherischen Orthodoxie.” In Theologen
des 17. und 18. Jahrhunderts: Konfessionelles Zeitalter—Pietismus—Aufklärung. Edited
by Peter Walter and Martin H. Jung. Darmstadt, 2003, 54–69.
Stempel, H. A. Melanchthons pädagogisches Wirken. Untersuchungen zur Kirchengeschich-
te 11. Bielefeld, 1979.
Stiglmayr, Emmerich. Verstossung und Gnade: Die Universalität der hinreichenden Gnade
und die strengen Thomisten des 16. und 17. Jahrhunderts. Rome, 1964.
Stock, Brian. The Implications of Literacy: Written Language and Models of Interpretation in
the Eleventh and Twelfth Centuries. Princeton, N.J., 1983.
Stockmeier, Peter. Glaube und Kultur: Studien zur Begegnung von Christentum und Antike.
Düsseldorf, 1983.
Studer, Basil. Schola Christiana: Die Theololgie zwischen Nizäa und Chalcedon. Paderborn,
1998.
Sturlese, Loris. Die deutsche Philosophie im Mittelalter: Von Bonifatius bis zu Albert dem
Großen (748–1280). Munich, 1993.
Swanson, Jenny. “The Glossa Ordinaria.” In Medieval Theologians. Edited by Evans, 2001,
156–67.
Swanson, Robert N. Universities, Academics and the Great Schism. Cambridge, 1979.
Tavard, George H. Transiency and Permanence: The Nature of Theology According to St.
Bonaventure. St. Bonaventure, N.Y., 1954.
Theiner, Johannes. Die Entwicklung der Moraltheologie zur eigenständigen Disziplin. Studien
zur Geschichte der kath. Moraltheologie 17. Regensburg, 1970.
Thijssen-Schoute, C. Louise. Nederlands Cartesianisme. Verhandelingen der K. Ned. Akad-
emie van Wetenschappen, Afd. Letterkunde, Nieuwe Reeks 60. Amsterdam, 1954.
Tholuck, August. Der Geist der lutherischen Theologen Wittenbergs im Verlaufe des 17. Jahr-
hunderts. Hamburg-Gotha, 1852.
———. Das akademische Leben des siebzehnten Jahrhunderts mit besonderer Beziehung auf
die protestantisch-theologischen Fakultäten Deutschlands. Vorgeschichte des Rationalis-
mus 1. Teil. I. Abt. [Section I]. Halle, 1853.
Trunz, Erich. “Der deutsche Späthumanismus um 1600 als Standeskultur.” In Deutsche
Barockforschung: Dokumentation einer Epoche. Edited by Richard Alewyn. Cologne,
1966, 147–81.
Tshibangu, Tharcisse. Théologie positive et théologie speculative: Position traditionnelle et
nouvelle problématique. Publications de l’Université Lovanium de Léopoldville 14.
Louvain, 1965.
Uiblein, Peter. “Zu den Beziehungen der Wiener Universität zu anderen Universitäten im
Mittelalter.” In Universités. Edited by Paquet and Ijsewijn, 1978, 169–89.
Valentini, Eugenio. “Il primo commentario protestante al ‘Liber Sententiarium’ di Pier
Lombardo.” In Miscellanea Lombardiana. Novara, 1957, 327–36.
Vansteenkiste, Clemente J. “S. Tommaso d’Aquino ed Averroè.” Rivista di studi orientali 32
(1957): 585–623.
Vázquez Janeiro, Isaac. “Rutas e hitos del escotismo primitivo en España.” In Homo et Mun-
dus: Acta Quinti Congressus Scotistici Internationalis, Salamanticae, 21–26 septembris 1981.
Edited by Camille Bérubé. Studica Scholastico-Scotistica 8. Rome, 1984, 419–36.
Velarde Lombraña, Julián. Juan Caramuel: Vida y obra. Oviedo, 1989.
Bibliography 385
Verbeek, Theo, ed. Johannes Clauberg (1622–1655) and Cartesian Philosophy in the Seven-
teenth Century. Archives Internationales d’histoire des idées 164. Dordrecht, 1999.
Vocht, H. de. History of the foundation and the rise of the Collegium Trilingue Lovaniense
1517–1550. 4 vols. Leuven, 1951–1955.
Vooght, Paul de. L’Hérésie de Jean Huss. Bibliothèque de la Revue d’Histoire Ecclésias-
tique 34 bis. Louvain, 1975.
Wallmann, Johannes. Der Theologiebegriff bei Johann Gerhard und Georg Calixt. Beiträge
zur Historischen Theologie 30. Tübingen, 1961.
Wéber, Édouard-Henri. “Les discussions de 1270 à l’université de Paris de leur influence
sur la pensée philosophique de S. Thomas d’Aquin.” In Auseinandersetzungen. Edited
by Zimmerman, 1976, 285–316.
Wehofer, Thomas M. “Der Dominikaner und Wiener Universitätsprofessor Petrus Gaz-
zaniga über den pädagogischen Wert der scholastischen Methode des achtzehnten
Jahrhunderts.” Mitteilungen der Gesellschaft für deutsche Erziehungs- und Schulgeschichte
8 (1898): 191–97.
Weijers, Olga. Terminologie des Universités au XIIIe siècle. Lessico Intellettuale Europeo 39.
Rome, 1987.
Weiss, Otto. Der Modernismus in Deutschland: Ein Beitrag zur Theologiegeschichte. Regens-
burg, 1995.
Weisweiler, Heinrich. Das Schrifttum der Schule Anselms von Laon und Wilhelms von Cham-
peaux in deutschen Bibliotheken. BGPhMA 33, nos. 1–2. Münster, 1936.
———. “Die Arbeitsmethode Hugos von St. Viktor: Ein Beitrag zum Entstehen seines
Hauptwerkes De Sacramentis.” Scholastik 20–24 (1945/49): 59–87, 232–67.
———. “Die Arbeitsweise der sogenannten Sententiae Anselmi: Ein Beitrag zum Entste-
hen der systematischen Werke der Theologie.” Scholastik 34 (1959): 190–232.
———. “Wie entstanden die frühen Sententiae Berolinenses der Schule Anselms von
Laon? Eine Untersuchung über die Verbindung von Patristik und Scholastik.” Scho-
lastik 34 (1959): 321–69.
Werner, Hans-Joachim. “‘Meliores viae sophiae’: Alkuins Bestimmung der Philosophie
in der Schrift ‘Disputatio de vera philosophia.’” In Was ist Philosophie im Mittelalter?
Edited by Aertsen and Speer, 1998, 452–59.
Werner, Karl. Geschichte der apologetischen und polemischen Literatur der christlichen Theolo-
gie. 5 vols. Schaffhausen, 1861–1887.
———. Die Scholastik des späteren Mittelalters IV, 2. Vienna, 1887, 70–94.
———. Geschichte der katholischen Theologie: Seit dem Trienter Concil bis zur Gegenwart.
Reprint, 1866 Munich edition, New York: Hildesheim, 1966.
Wicks, Jared. Cajetan und die Anfänge der Reformation. Katholisches Leben und Kirchen-
reform im Zeitalter der Glaubensspaltung 43. Münster, 1983.
Wiedenhofer, Siegfried. Formalstrukturen humanistischer und reformatorischer Theologie bei
Philipp Melanchthon. Regensburger Studien zur Theologie 2. Bern, 1976.
Wiesinger, Peter. “Zur Autorschaft und Entstehung des Heinrich von Langenstein zu-
geschriebenen Traktats ‘Erkenntnis der Sünde.’” Zeitschrift für deutsche Philologie 97
(1978): 42–60.
Winkler, Gerhard. Erasmus von Rotterdam und die Einleitungsschriften zum Neuen Testa-
ment: Formale Strukturen und theologischer Sinn. RGST 108. Münster, 1974.
Wolf, Karl. “Niederländischer Einfluss auf Nassau um 1600.” Nassauische Annalen 58
(1938): 87–109.
386 Bibliography
Wriedt, Markus. “Die theologische Begründung der Bildungsreform bei Luther und Mel-
anchthon.” In Humanismus. Edited by Beyer and Wartenberg, 155–83.
Wulf, Maurice de. Geschichte der mittelalterlichen Philosophie. Tübingen, 1913.
Zier, Mark A. “Sermons of the Twelfth Century Schoolmasters and Canons.” In Sermon.
Edited by Kienzle, 325–62.
Zimmerman, Albert. “‘Mundus est aeternus’—Zur Auslegung dieser These bei Bonaven-
tura und Thomas von Aquin.” In Auseinandersetzungen. Edited by Zimmerman, 1976,
317–30.
———, ed. Der Begriff der Repraesentatio im Mittelalter. Miscellanea Mediaevalia 8. Ber-
lin: Walter de Gruyter, 1971.
———, ed. Antiqui und Moderni: Traditionsbewusstsein und Fortschrittsbewusstsein im
späten Mittelalter. Miscellanea Mediaevalia 9. Berlin, 1971.
———, ed. Die Auseinandersetzungen an der Pariser Universität im XIII. Jahrhundert.
Miscellanea Mediaevalia 10. Berlin, 1976.
Zumkeller, Adolar. “Die Augustinerschule des Mittelalters: Vertreter und philosophisch-
theologische Lehre.” Analecta Augustiniana 27 (1964): 167–262.
Index of Names
Abelard, Peter, 10–11, 35, 41, 47, 55, 56, 61–65, 67, 181, 187, 209, 211, 244, 246, 255–60, 263–64,
72, 91–94, 96, 98–100, 102, 107, 112, 116–19 272, 291, 301, 343
Adam of Marsh, 128 Arius, 148, 271
Adam of Dryburgh (Adamus Scotus), 113–14 Arnauld, Antoine, 350
Adam of Parvipontanus (Petit Pont), 82 Arriaga, Rodrigo de, 293, 332, 334–39
Adam Woodham/Goddam, 185, 191, 194, 231, Athanasius, 19
235 Augustine, 21–28, 31, 33–35, 37–38, 41, 50, 52, 54,
Adelmann of Lüttich, 66 56, 59, 61, 66, 68, 75–76, 78, 80–81, 83, 90, 95,
Aegidius of Rome (Ægidius Romanus), 145, 100–101, 127, 131, 135, 137, 148, 158, 163–66, 175,
179, 180–81, 187, 190–91, 293 178–80, 184, 187, 190, 192–94, 199, 206, 209,
Aelred of Rievaulx, 65 231, 233–34, 244, 249, 255–56, 265, 293, 309,
Agnellus of Pisa, 125 324, 328, 330–31, 339, 357
Alan of Lille (Alanus ab Insulis), 29, 68, 102–3, Augustine de Dacia, 49
106, 109, 111–13 Averroës (Ibn Rushd), 136–39, 141–42, 187,
Alberic of Rheims, 82 191, 273
Albert the Great (Albertus Magnus), 53, 136, Avicenna (Ibn Sina), 135–37, 139, 146, 177, 187
141, 158–62, 167, 170–71, 178, 181, 191, 303, Azor, Johannes, 289
328
Alcuin, 35–36 Babenstuber, Ludwig, 290, 342–46
Alexander IV, Pope, 126 Bacon, Francis, 356
Alexander of Hales, 99, 122, 125, 128, 134, 142, Baconthorp, John, 293
154, 191, 240, 276, 282 Baeumker, Clemens, 6
Alphons Vargas Toletanus, 190 Báñez, Dominicus, 291, 323, 332, 342
Alsted, Johann Heinrich, 301–2, 315–18 Baron, Vincent, 340
Altenstaig, Johannes, 208 Bede (the Venerable), 44, 52, 59
Amaury of Bène, 139 Bellarmine, Robert, 329
Ambrose, 59, 78 Belluti, Bonaventura, 292
Amerbach, Johannes, 193 Benedict XIV, Pope, 351, 353
Amort, Eusebius, 290, 351–53 Berengar of Tours, 44, 66, 78–79, 83, 96, 115, 118
Andrew of St. Victor, 48, 51, 90, 137 Bernard of Chartres, 89
Anselm of Canterbury, 10, 13, 65, 78–86, 94, 105, Bernard of Clairvaux, 65, 67, 112–15, 117–19
112, 148, 176, 218, 228 Bernard of Trilia, 188
Anselm of Laon, 41, 44, 58–60 Bernold of Constance, 11
Antonius a Matre Dei, 296 Bertola, Eremengildo, 44
Anthony of Egypt, 19 Bidermann, Jakob, S.J., 297
Aquaviva, Claudius, 284 Biel, Gabriel. See Gabriel Biel
Aristotle, 2–4, 7, 9–10, 19, 28, 37, 71, 73, 95, Bliemetzrieder, Franz, 82
131–42, 145, 148–49, 154, 166–67, 174, 177, 179, Boethius of Dacia, 135, 142–43, 145
387
388 Index of Names
Boethius, Anicius Manlius Severinus, 12, Duns Scotus, Johannes, 14, 137, 183, 188–89, 191,
28–30, 34, 37, 39, 43–44, 81, 92, 95, 97–98, 209–16, 218, 219, 222, 231, 240, 250, 255, 292,
102–3, 106, 131, 134, 154, 157, 169, 178 307, 332–34, 360
Bonaventure, 14, 19, 53–54, 71, 126, 129, 135, 141, Dupasquier, Sebastian, 292
144, 162–67, 176, 178, 191, 276, 282, 292, 307, Durand of Saint Pourçain, 227
328, 360 Durandus of Troarn, 350
Bossuet, Jean-Baptiste, 354 Durandus, Bartholomäus, 292
Braun, Peter, 208
Bruno the Carthusian, 44 Eck, Johannes (Maier von Egg an der Günz),
Bullinger, Heinrich, 300 268–72
Burgundio of Pisa, 100 Eckhart, Meister, 218–22
Buridan, John, 192 Erasmus von Rotterdam, Desiderius, 3,
Busenbaum, Hermann, S.J., 289 246–50, 257, 259, 265–66, 269
Buzzetti, Vincenzo, 358 Eriugena, John Scotus, 10, 36, 44, 74–78
Euclid, 29, 102, 104, 106
Cajetan (Thomas de Vio, OP), 186, 268, Eugene III, Pope, 100
272–77, 328, 332 Eusebius of Caesarea, 18
Calcidius, 134
Calixt, Georg, 306 Faber, Philippus, 332
Calov, Abraham, 306–11 Faber Stapulensis, Jakob, 307
Calvin, John, 247, 264–68, 299 Fabri, Johannes, 253
Cano, Melchior, 291, 307 Faustus of Milève, 339
Capreolus, Johannes, OP, 255, 273, 305, 328, 332 Fénélon, François, 354
Caramuel Lobkowitz, Juan, 346–51, 356 Flasch, Kurt, 7
Cassiodorus, Flavius Magnus Aurelius, 34, 37 Florus of Lyons, 78
Celsus, 18 Forer, Lorenz, 312
Charlemagne, 34 Francis I, King of France, 266
Charles the Bald, 75 Francis de Sales, 354
Cicero, Marcus Tullius, 2, 39, 66, 68, 244, 263 Francis of Assisi, 45
Clauberg, Johannes, 320 Francis of Meyronnes, 189, 214–16, 227
Clement of Alexandria, 17 Francis of Retz, 186
Clerselier, Claude, 349 Frederick II, Emperor, 136
Clichtovaeus, Jodok, 307 Fulgentius of Ruspe, 31, 33, 101
Cloes, Henri, 59
Cocceius, Johannes, 319 Gabriel Biel, 185–87, 192, 208, 238–40, 242,
Comenius, Johann Amos, 278, 315 255–56
Comitibus a Mediolano, Blasius Antonius de, Gaetani, Cardinal Benedetto (Pope Boniface
292 VIII), 126
Copernicus, Nicolaus, 320 Galilei, Galileo, 346–48
Crathorn, 188, 227–29 Gansfort, Wessel, 208
Crockaert, Peter, OP, 186, 277 Gazzaniga, Petrus, 355
Cuno of Preneste, 118 Gennadius of Marseille, 33
Cyprian of Carthage, 20–21 Gerard of Abbeville, 126
Gerard of Cremona, 133
David of Dinant, 139 Gerard of Csanád, 46
Davy, Marie-Magdelaine, 71 Gerard of St. Quentin, 67
Descartes, René, 320–22, 349 Gerbert, Martin, 355
Desgabets, Robert, 348–51 Gerhard, Johann, 302–6, 308
Donatus, 39, 43 Gerhoh of Reichersberg, 14, 112, 116
Dreier, Christian, 4, 354 Gerson, John, 183, 192, 199–203, 208, 240, 243,
Drogo of St. Nikasius in Rheims, 82 356
Index of Names 389
Geyer, Bernhard, 7, 11 Hugolin of Orvieto, 190
Gilbert Porreta (de la Porrée, of Poitiers), 29, Hülsemann, Johannes, 301, 311
94–99, 102–3, 115–17, 119 Hunnius, Ægidius, 307
Gilbertus Universalis, 44, 82 Huntpichler, Leonhard, 186
Gilson, Étienne, 137 Hurtado de Mendoza, Pedro, 293
Goclenius, Rudolf, 3 Hus, Jan, 193–97
Godfrey of Fontaines, 123 Hutter, Leonhard, 307
Gonet, Jean-Baptiste, 292, 338–40, 353, 358
Gonzalez de Santalla, Thyrsus, 288 Innocent II, Pope, 117–18
Gottschalk of Fulda (of Orbeil), 74–75, 77, Innocent III, Pope, 116, 121
115, 118 Innocent IV, Pope, 141
Goudin, Antoine, 358 Isidore of Seville, 31–33, 54, 59
Grabmann, Martin, 5–6, 10 Ivo of Chartres, 11, 59, 100
Gregory the Great, Pope, 33, 50, 59, 68, 127
Gregory VII, Pope, 116 James of Viterbo, 190
Gregory IX, Pope, 140–41, 149,151 James of Vitry, 140
Gregory of Rimini, 190–93, 205, 228, 231–39, Jerome, 44, 51–52, 59, 66, 114, 140, 208–9, 244
241 Jerome of Prague, 197
Gregory of Valencia, 293 Joachim of Fiore, 130, 183
Groote, Geert, 207, 235 Johann Georg, Duke of Sachsen, 307
Guibert of Nogent, 66, 68 Johannes a S. Thoma ( Juan Poinsot), 291
Günther, Anton, 355 Johannes ab Annuntiatione, 296
Johannes Pupper of Goch, 208
Haimo of Auxerre, 2 Johannes Ruchrath of Wesel, 208
Haimo of Halberstadt, 41, 44 Johannes Tinctoris, 186
Haller, Johannes, 319 Johannes Werd, 186
Hannibaldus de Hannibaldis, 188 Johannes Wessel Gansfort, 208
Haunold, Christoph, 293 John XXI, Pope, 145
Haymo of Faversham, 125 John XXII, Pope, 222
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 7 John XXIII, anti-Pope, 197
Heinrich of Gorkum, 186 John Damascene, 100, 260, 350
Heinrich of Langenstein (Hainbuch), 186, John of Barastre, 124
203–4 John of Bassoles, 189
Heinrich Totting of Oyta, 185–87, 203–5, 235 John of Kelso, 114
Henríquez, Enrique, 289 John of Mirecourt, 191
Henry of Ghent, 123, 137, 175–81, 185, 187, 189, John of Saint Gilles, 125
211, 213–14, 293 John of Salisbury, 41
Herbert of Bosham, 51 John of Sterngassen, 188
Heribrand, Abbot of St. Laurentius, Lüttich, 85 John of Tours, 82
Hermann of Schildesche, 190
Hilary of Poitiers, 59 Kant, Immanuel, 355
Hinkmar of Rheims, 75 Karlstadt, Andreas Bodenstein von, 255, 258
Hirnhaim, Hieronymus, 294 Keckermann, Bartholomäus, 316
Hirscher, Johann Baptist, 358 Kempf, Nikolaus, 203
Hofmann, Daniel, 302, 309 Kluxen, Wolfgang, 7–8, 10
Honorius of Autun (H. Augustodunensis), Konrad of Waldhausen, 197
55, 59
Hrabanus Maurus, 44, 75 Lanfranc of Bec, 44, 79–80, 83
Hugh of St. Cher, 53, 125, 129 Lang, Narcissus, 292
Hugh of St. Victor, 48–49, 53, 55–57, 59–60, 63, Laymann, Paul, 289, 293
65, 67, 86–90, 100, 112–13, 127, 149, 156, 164 Leclercq, Jean, 9, 111
390 Index of Names
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, 312, 349 Palacios, Miguel de, 332
Leo XIII, Pope, 360 Páleč, Stephan, 197–98
Longomontanus, Christian, 348 Paschasius Radbertus, 44
Lottin, Odon, 82 Peckham, John, 187
Louis of Bavaria (IV), Emperor, 189 Pelagius, 231
Louis XI, King of France, 191 Pereira, Benedictus, 301
Lugo, Juan de, 289 Peter Aureol, 215
Lupus of Ferrières, 36, 75 Peter Damian, 39, 112, 116
Luther, Martin, 3, 183, 190, 199, 209, 234, 239, Peter Lombard (Magister Sententiarum), 12,
246, 251–52, 254–60, 263–64, 268, 270–72, 44, 52, 54, 59–61, 63, 72, 98–102, 107, 115,
274–76, 279–80, 302, 304–7, 309, 326–27 121–22, 128, 148, 152, 158, 185, 260, 279, 307,
Lutterell, John, 225 310
Peter of Ailly, 183, 191, 199, 240, 242, 255–56
Mabillon, Jean, 356–57 Peter of Corbeil, 139–40
Macrobius, 92 Peter of Poitiers, 52, 107, 109
Maignan, Emmanuel, 349 Petrus Cantor (Peter Cantor), 48–50, 53, 55, 68
Maior, Johannes, 265, 328 Petrus Comestor, 3, 48, 51–52, 112, 128, 139
Maldonato, Johannes, 357 Petrus Rogerii (Pope Clement VI), 215
Manser, Gallus, 6 Petrus Venerabilis, 114, 119
Maresius, Samuel, 319–21 Peuntner, Thomas, 203
Marsilius of Inghen, 234–38 Philip the Chancellor, 53, 134
Maritain, Jacques, 359 Philip II, King of France, 121
Martianus Capella, 37, 39, 43 Philipp of Harvengt, 112
Martin of Léon, 72 Philippus a SS. Trinitate, 291
Martini, Cornelius, 301–2 Photius, 11
Martini, Jakob, 301 Piccolomini, Francesco, SJ, 284
Mastri, Bartolomeo (Mastrius), 292, 331–34 Piccolomini, Francesco, 301
Maurice of Spain (Mauritius Hispanus), 139 Pico della Mirandola, Giovanni, 244
Medina, Bartholomew, OP, 288, 291 Pieper, Josef, 7
Melanchthon, Philipp, 192, 245–47, 257, Pius V, Pope, 290
259–66, 270, 299–301, 303–4, 307, 309 Plato, 19, 92, 106, 134, 166, 214, 230, 244
Mezger, Paulus, 295 Pliny the Elder, 259
Milič, Jan, of Kremsier, 197 Pomponazzi, Pietro, 273
Molina, Luis de, 293, 323, 334 Poncius, Johannes ( John Punch), 292, 332
Moses Maimonides, 138, 142 Porphyry, 37, 256
Praepositinus of Cremona, 38, 107–11, 131, 139,
Nicole, Pierre, 350 148
Nicholas Cusanus, 220 Prierias, Silvester, 275
Nicholas Manjacoria, 47 Priscianus, 43
Nicholas of Amiens, 102, 104, 106, 111 Prosper of Aquitaine, 31, 54
Nicholas of Dinkelsbühl, 203 Prudentius of Troyes, 75, 78
Nicholas of Lyra, 53 Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite, 12, 39, 202
Norbert of Xanten, 82
Quintilian, 259
Odo of Ourscamp, 40–41
Omnebene, Magister, 62 Radulphus Ardens, 72
Origanus, David, 348 Radulfus of Laon, 44, 59, 82–83
Origen, 16, 18–19, 250 Rahner, Karl, 324
Ott, Ludwig, 67 Ramus, Peter (Pierre de la Ramée), 300–301
Otto of Freising, 114 Rassler, Johann Christoph, 342
Oviedo, Francisco de, 293 Ratramnus of Corbie, 75
Index of Names 391
Rautenstrauch, Stephan, 355 Stanislaus of Znaim, 196, 198
Reding, Augustinus, 297 Staupitz, Johannes von, 190, 193
Reeb, Georg, 312 Steinbach, Wendelin, 208
Reimarus, Hermann Samuel, 354 Stephen Harding, 47
Remigius of Auxerre, 59 Stephen Langton, 48, 50, 52, 127
Remigius of Florence, 188 Stephen of Tournai, 115–16
Reuchlin, Johannes, 192 Sturlese, Loris, 137
Richard Fishacre, 129–30, 150–52 Suárez, Francisco, 293–94, 301, 323–27
Richard of Knapwell, 188
Richard of St. Victor, 41, 48, 67, 113 Tanner, Adam, 293, 312
Richter, Vladimír, 189 Tempier, Étienne, 144, 146
Rijk, Lambert Marie de, 8 Tertullian, 17–20
Robert Grosseteste, 125, 127–29, 134, 139 Tetzel, Johannes, 275–76
Robert Holcot, 188, 227–30, 236 Theophrast, 2
Robert Kilwardby, 152–53, 187 Thierry of Chartres, 118
Robert of Basevorn, 71 Thomas Aquinas, 4, 11–13, 42–43, 45, 51, 54–55,
Robert of Courson/Courçon, 121, 139, 140 123, 126, 129–30, 134–37, 141, 145, 167–71,
Robert of Melun, 41, 45–46, 55–56 173–75, 177–81, 185–88, 191, 208–9, 211,
Robert of Oxford, 188 219–20, 265, 272–74, 276, 282–84, 286, 290,
Roger Bacon, 127–30, 137, 141, 187, 200 293, 296, 304–5, 324, 327–28, 339, 344–45,
Roland, Magister (Bandinelli), 62, 64–65 359, 360
Roland of Cremona, 125, 149–51, 156 Thomas Bradwardine, 193–94, 230–31, 237
Roselli, Salvatore, 358 Thomas Docking, 129
Ruiz de Montoya, Diego, 293 Thomas Eccleston, 127
Rupert of Deutz, 112 Thomas Gascoigne, 45
Thomas of York, 126
Sabellius, 148 Thomasius, Christian, 4
Saënz d’Aguirre, Joseph, 356 Thomasius, Jakob, 354
Sanchez, Thomas, 289 Timpler, Clemens, 301
Sannig, Bernhard, 292 Toletus, Franciscus, 293
Scaliger, Julius Caesar, 303 Trutfetter, Jodok, 258–59
Scharf, Johannes, 301 Tyconius, 27, 31
Scheffler, Johannes, 312
Scheibler, Christoph, 3, 301 Urban IV, Pope, 141
Scheidsach, Fructuosus, 349 Ursinus, Zacharias, 300
Scheiner, Christoph, 348
Scherzer, Johann Adam, 301, 311–15 Valla, Lorenzo, 244
Schneyer, Johannes Baptist, 69 Van Steenberghen, Fernand, 6
Schönberger, Rolf, 8 Vavasseur, François, 356
Schrimpf, Gangolf, 10 Vázquez, Gabriel, 293, 327–31
Semler, Johann Salomo, 354 Vitoria, Francisco de, OP, 186, 277, 291
Seneca, Lucius Annaeus, 66, 127 Vivianus of Prémontré, 57, 67, 85
Siard of Mariengaarde, 72 Voetius, Gisbert, 319
Siger of Brabant, 135, 142, 144–45
Silesius, Angelus. See Scheffler, Johannes Wadding, Luke, 291–92
Simon of Tournai, 148 Walafried Strabo, 44
Simonzin, Ludwig, 342 Waldburg, Otto Truchsess von, 281, 352
Socrates, 214, 230 Walter of Chatton, 227
Soto, Domingo de, OP, 291 Walter of Mortaigne, 67
Soto, Pedro de, 238, 291 Weisweiler, Heinrich, 82, 84
Spengler, Lazarus, 253 Werner of St. Blasien, 59
392 Index of Names
William de la Mare, 171–75, 178, 187–88, 210 Wolff, Christian, 312, 355
William of Auvergne, 135–38, 140, 205–7 Wulf, Maurice de, 6
William of Auxerre, 140–41, 147–49 Wycliffe, John, 183, 193–96, 271
William of Champeaux, 59, 86
William of Ockham, 43, 164, 183, 188–89, Zabarella, Jacopo, 301
222–27, 231, 235–36, 238–40, 255, 266 Zacharias Chrysopolitanus, 47–48, 59, 300
William of Saint Amour, 126 Zumel, Francisco, 342
William of St. Thierry, 118 Zwingli, Huldrych, 253, 270–71
Wittich, Christoph, 319–23
•
Introduction to Scholastic Theology was
designed and typeset in Arno by Kachergis
Book Design of Pittsboro, North Carolina. It
was printed on 50-pound Natural and bound
by Versa Press of East Peoria, Illinois.