Biografy 33
Biografy 33
Biografy 33
Lifetime
The century in which Kaṇāda lived is unclear and have been a subject of a long debate.[13] In his
review of 1961, Riepe states Kaṇāda lived sometime before 300 CE, but convincing evidence to
firmly put him in a certain century remains elusive.[19]
The Vaisheshika Sutras mention competing schools of Indian philosophy such as Samkhya and
Mimamsa,[20] but make no mention of Buddhism, which has led scholars in more recent
publications to posit estimates of 6th century BCE.[3][4][14] The Vaisheshika Sutras manuscript
has survived into the modern era in multiple versions and the discovery of newer manuscripts in
different parts of India by Thakur in 1957 and Jambuvijayaji in 1961, followed by critical edition
studies, suggest that the text attributed to Kaṇāda was systematized and finalized sometime between
200 BCE and the start of the common era, with the possibility that its key doctrines may be much
older.[20][4][21] Multiple Hindu texts dated to the 1st and 2nd century CE, such as the
Mahavibhasa and Jnanaprasthana from the Kushan Empire, quote and comment on Kaṇāda's
doctrines.[22] His ideas are also mentioned in Buddhist texts attributed to Aśvaghoṣa of the same
period.[22]
In Jainism literature, he is referred to as Sad-uluka, which means "the Uluka who propounded the
doctrine of six categories".[20] His Vaisheshika philosophy similarly appears with alternate names,
such as "Aulukya philosophy" derived from the nickname Uluka (literally owl, or grain eater in the
night).[20][note 1]
Kaṇāda was influential in Indian philosophies, and he appears in various texts by alternate names
such as Kashyapa, Uluka, Kananda, Kanabhuk among others.[1][2]
Ideas
Physics is central to Kaṇāda's assertion that all that is knowable is based on motion. His ascribing
centrality to physics in the understanding of the universe also follows from his invariance
principles. For example, he says that the atom must be spherical since it should be the same in all
dimensions.[23] He asserts that all substances are composed of four types of atoms, two of which
have mass and two are massless.
Kaṇāda presents his work within a larger moral framework by defining Dharma as that which
brings about material progress and highest good.[18][24] He follows this Sutra with another that
asserts that the Vedas have gained respect because they teach such Dharma, and something is not
Dharma simply because it is in the Vedas.[18]
Kanada makes empirical observations such as the rising upwards of fire, magnetic movement, rain
and thunder, the growth of grass, and offers naturalistic explanations to them in his text Vaisheshika
Sutra.[25]
Kaṇāda and early Vaisheshika scholars focused on the evolution of the universe by law.[26]
However, this was not unusual for his times since several major early versions of Hindu
philosophies such as Samkhya, Nyaya, Mimamsa along with sub-schools of Yoga and Vedanta, as
well as non-Vedic schools such as Jainism and Buddhism, were similarly non-theistic.[27][28]
Kaṇāda was among the sages of India who believed in man's potential to understand existence and
reach moksha on his own, without God, a notion of ancient Indians summarized by Nietzsche as the
belief that "with piety and knowledge of the Veda, nothing is impossible".[26]
The text states:[29]
• There are nine constituents of realities: four classes of atoms (earth, water, light and air),
space (akasha), time (kāla), direction (disha), infinity of souls (Atman), mind (manas).[30]
• Every object of creation is made of atoms (paramāṇu) which in turn connect with each other
to form molecules (aṇu). Atoms are eternal, and their combinations constitute the empirical
material world.
• Individual souls are eternal and pervade material bodies for a time.
• There are six categories (padārtha) of experience — substance, quality, activity, generality,
particularity, and inherence.
Several traits of substances (dravya) are given as colour, taste, smell, touch, number, size, the
separate, coupling and uncoupling, priority and posterity, comprehension, pleasure and pain,
attraction and revulsion, and wishes.[31]
Thus the idea of the subdivision is carried further to analytical categories as well, which explains its
affinity with Nyaya.
(...) That there is only one individual (soul) is known from the absence of particularity
when it comes to the emergence of an understanding of happiness and suffering,
(whereas) a multiplicity of individuals is inferred from their perseverance in dharma,
and from the strength of their teaching. – Vaisheshika Sutras 3.16-18
The true being is eternal, having no cause. Its indicator is its effect. The presence of the
effect arises from the presence of its cause. – Vaisheshika Sutras 4.1-3
—Kaṇāda, Translated by John Wells[34][35]
Kaṇāda proposes that paramanu (atom) is an indestructible particle of matter. The atom is
indivisible because it is a state at which no measurement can be attributed. He used invariance
arguments to determine properties of the atoms. He also stated that anu can have two states —
absolute rest and a state of motion.[36]
Kaṇāda postulated four different kinds of atoms: two with mass, and two without.[12] Each
substance is supposed to consist of all four kinds of atoms.
Kaṇāda's conception of the atom was likely independent from the similar concept among the
ancient Greeks, because of the differences between the theories.[37] For example, Kaṇāda
suggested that atoms as building blocks differ both qualitatively and quantitatively, while Greeks
suggested that atoms differed only quantitatively but not qualitatively.[37]
See also
• Timeline of atomic and subatomic physics
• List of Indian inventions and discoveries
• Leucippus
• Vedanta
• Vaiśeṣika Sūtra
Notes