6
6
6
1 language
Article
Talk
Read
Edit
View history
Tools
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
This article has multiple issues. Please help improve it or discuss these issues on
the talk page. (Learn how and when to remove these template messages)
This article includes a list of general references, but it lacks sufficient
corresponding inline citations. (April 2010)
This article possibly contains inappropriate or misinterpreted citations that do
not verify the text. (April 2010)
It has been suggested that this article be merged into Glossary of mathematics.
(Discuss) Proposed since March 2023.
The language of mathematics has a vast vocabulary of specialist and technical
terms. It also has a certain amount of jargon: commonly used phrases which are part
of the culture of mathematics, rather than of the subject. Jargon often appears in
lectures, and sometimes in print, as informal shorthand for rigorous arguments or
precise ideas. Much of this is common English, but with a specific non-obvious
meaning when used in a mathematical sense.
Some phrases, like "in general", appear below in more than one section.
Philosophy of mathematics
abstract nonsense
A tongue-in-cheek reference to category theory, using which one can employ
arguments that establish a (possibly concrete) result without reference to any
specifics of the present problem. For that reason, it's also known as general
abstract nonsense or generalized abstract nonsense.
[The paper of Eilenberg and Mac Lane (1942)] introduced the very abstract idea of a
'category' — a subject then called 'general abstract nonsense'!
Mathematicians may say that a theorem is beautiful when they really mean to say
that it is enlightening. We acknowledge a theorem's beauty when we see how the
theorem 'fits' in its place....We say that a proof is beautiful when such a proof
finally gives away the secret of the theorem....
almost all
A shorthand term for "all except for a set of measure zero", when there is a
measure to speak of. For example, "almost all real numbers are transcendental"
because the algebraic real numbers form a countable subset of the real numbers with
measure zero. One can also speak of "almost all" integers having a property to mean
"all except finitely many", despite the integers not admitting a measure for which
this agrees with the previous usage. For example, "almost all prime numbers are
odd". There is a more complicated meaning for integers as well, discussed in the
main article. Finally, this term is sometimes used synonymously with generic,
below.
arbitrarily large
Notions which arise mostly in the context of limits, referring to the recurrence of
a phenomenon as the limit is approached. A statement such as that predicate P is
satisfied by arbitrarily large values, can be expressed in more formal notation by
∀x : ∃y ≥ x : P(y). See also frequently. The statement that quantity f(x) depending
on x "can be made" arbitrarily large, corresponds to ∀y : ∃x : f(x) ≥ y.
arbitrary
A shorthand for the universal quantifier. An arbitrary choice is one which is made
unrestrictedly, or alternatively, a statement holds of an arbitrary element of a
set if it holds of any element of that set. Also much in general-language use among
mathematicians: "Of course, this problem can be arbitrarily complicated".
eventually
In the context of limits, this is shorthand meaning for sufficiently large
arguments; the relevant argument(s) are implicit in the context. As an example, the
function log(log(x)) eventually becomes larger than 100"; in this context,
"eventually" means "for sufficiently large x."
factor through
A term in category theory referring to composition of morphisms. If for three
objects A, B, and C a map
f
:
A
→
C
f\colon A\to C can be written as a composition
f
=
h
∘
g
f=h\circ g with
g
:
A
→
B
g\colon A\to B and
h
:
B
→
C
h\colon B\to C, then f is said to factor through any (and all) of
B
B,
g
g, and
h
h.
finite
When said of the value of a variable assuming values from the non-negative extended
reals
R
≥
0
∪
{
∞
}
,
{\displaystyle \mathbb {R} _{\geq 0}\cup \{\infty \},} the meaning is usually "not
infinite". For example, if the variance of a random variable is said to be finite,
this implies it is a non-negative real number, possibly zero. In some contexts
though, for example in "a small but finite amplitude", zero is meant to be
excluded. When said of the value of a variable assuming values from the extended
natural numbers
N
∪
{
∞
}
,
{\displaystyle \mathbb {N} \cup \{\infty \},} the meaning is simply "not infinite".
When said of a set or a mathematical object whose main component is a set, it means
that the cardinality of the set is less than
ℵ
0
\aleph _{0}.
frequently
In the context of limits, this is shorthand for arbitrarily large arguments and its
relatives; as with eventually, the intended variant is implicit. As an example, the
sequence
(
−
1
)
n
(-1)^{n} is frequently in the interval (1/2, 3/2), because there are arbitrarily
large n for which the value of the sequence is in the interval.
formal, formally
Qualifies anything that is sufficiently precise to be translated straightforwardly
in a formal system. For example. a formal proof, a formal definition.
generic
This term has similar connotations as almost all but is used particularly for
concepts outside the purview of measure theory. A property holds "generically" on a
set if the set satisfies some (context-dependent) notion of density, or perhaps if
its complement satisfies some (context-dependent) notion of smallness. For example,
a property which holds on a dense Gδ (intersection of countably many open sets) is
said to hold generically. In algebraic geometry, one says that a property of points
on an algebraic variety that holds on a dense Zariski open set is true generically;
however, it is usually not said that a property which holds merely on a dense set
(which is not Zariski open) is generic in this situation.
in general
In a descriptive context, this phrase introduces a simple characterization of a
broad class of objects, with an eye towards identifying a unifying principle. This
term introduces an "elegant" description which holds for "arbitrary" objects.
Exceptions to this description may be mentioned explicitly, as "pathological"
cases.
Norbert A'Campo of the University of Basel once asked Grothendieck about something
related to the Platonic solids. Grothendieck advised caution. The Platonic solids
are so beautiful and so exceptional, he said, that one cannot assume such
exceptional beauty will hold in more general situations.
aliter
An obsolescent term which is used to announce to the reader an alternative method,
or proof of a result. In a proof, it therefore flags a piece of reasoning that is
superfluous from a logical point of view, but has some other interest.
by way of contradiction (BWOC), or "for, if not, ..."
The rhetorical prelude to a proof by contradiction, preceding the negation of the
statement to be proved.
if and only if (iff)
An abbreviation for logical equivalence of statements.
in general
In the context of proofs, this phrase is often seen in induction arguments when
passing from the base case to the induction step, and similarly, in the definition
of sequences whose first few terms are exhibited as examples of the formula giving
every term of the sequence.
necessary and sufficient
A minor variant on "if and only if"; "A is necessary (sufficient) for B" means "A
if (only if) B". For example, "For a field K to be algebraically closed it is
necessary and sufficient that it have no finite field extensions" means "K is
algebraically closed if and only if it has no finite extensions". Often used in
lists, as in "The following conditions are necessary and sufficient for a field to
be algebraically closed...".