Islamic Astronomy - F. Jamil Ragep
Islamic Astronomy - F. Jamil Ragep
Islamic Astronomy - F. Jamil Ragep
and
Copernicus
Prof. Dr.
Prof.
F. Jamil
Dr. F.Ragep
Jamil Ragep
Islamic Astronomy
and
Copernicus
F. Jamil Ragep
Ankara, 2022
Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
F. Jamil Ragep
© Turkish Academy of Sciences Publications
Science and Thought Series, No: 37
ISBN: 978-625-8352-02-3
DOI: 10.53478/TUBA.978-625-8352-02-3
The scientific responsibility for the language, scientific, ethical and legal aspects of all the articles
included in the book belongs to the authors. Turkish Academy of Sciences and editors have no
responsibility.
Author
Prof. Dr. F. Jamil Ragep
Graphical Design
Ece Yavuz
Esra Yılmaz
First Edition
1000 pcs.
Ragep, F. Jamil
Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus / F. Jamil Ragep. Ankara: Turkish Academy of Sciences, 2022.
xvi, 380 pages; 24 cm. – (Bilim ve Düşün Serisi No; 37)
Includes bibliographical references.
ISBN 978-625-8352-02-3
1.Astronomi. 2. Astronomy. 3. Astronomi_İslam. 4. Astronomy_Islam. 5. İslam_Kopernik Bağlantısı.
6. Islamic_Copernicus Connection. 7. Bilim_Tarih. 8. Science_History. 9. Astronomi_Tarih.
10. Astronomy_History.
QB23. R34 2022
520
FOREWORD............................................................................................................ v
INTRODUCTION.................................................................................................... ix
Section I
General Works........................................................................................................... 1
Section II
Chioniades................................................................................................................ 149
Section III
iii
Section IV
Ibn al-Haytham and Eudoxus: The Revival of Homocentric Modeling in Islam.... 299
Index........................................................................................................................ 355
iv
FOREWORD
The Turkish Academy of Sciences (TUBA) is an autonomous apex body for the de-
velopment and promotion of sciences in Turkey. The origins of the Academy go back
to the Ottoman society called the “Encümen-i Dāniş” (Society of Scholars), which
was founded in 1851 and known as the first Turkish science academy in the modern
sense. TUBA is the single national academy in Turkey, and its interest covers all
scientific fields, which are grouped under the following three categories: a) basic and
engineering sciences, b) health and life sciences, and c) social sciences and human-
ities. TUBA is committed to contributing to the promotion of scientific research by
organizing working groups, offering grants and awards, preparing, and supporting the
preparation of, scientific reports, as well as by collaborating with sister academies all
around the world.
Supporting and publishing studies on the history of science are among TUBA’s pri-
orities with the intention of increasing awareness regarding scholarly and scientific
exchanges across cultures throughout history. In this respect, as TUBA’s president,
I would like to express my pleasure to mark the publication of the volume at hand
entitled “Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus.” It brings together 15 articles penned
by F. Jamil Ragep, which were earlier published in journals, encyclopaedias, or ed-
ited books. It is important for us to reprint these articles which have made, and will
continue to make, substantial contributions to the literature on the Islamic influence
on Copernican astronomy. Moreover, F. Jamil Ragep was the recipient of the TUBA
International Academy Prize in the Social Sciences and Humanities in 2019 thanks
to his studies in the field, especially those dealing with the Islamic background of the
Copernican system. We are pleased to draw attention to F. Jamil Ragep’s scholarship
on this subject with this publication.
This foreword is too short to highlight properly the significance and context of the
articles in this volume but let me stress one of F. Jamil Ragep’s remarkable historio-
graphic achievements. His scholarship leaves no doubt that in order to make sense of
the ways in which Islamic astronomy had an influence on European astronomy in gen-
v
eral and on Copernicus in particular, along with examining technical and astronomical
contents of the key texts connecting Copernicus’s scholarship to Islamic astronomical
traditions, one should also deal with intellectual and philosophical discussions that
later stimulated the astronomical and cosmological transformations in the medieval
and early modern periods. This broader perspective adopted by F. Jamil Ragep paved
the way for new evidence regarding the Islamic background to the scientific and intel-
lectual environment in which Copernicus had flourished.
I hope that the publication of this volume will provide an insight for those interested
in this important episode of the history of science. In line with TUBA’s mission of
promoting rigorous scientific research, we are committed to sharing this volume with
a wider audience. In this respect, it will be available as an open-access publication on
our website, and we will send its copies to many Turkish libraries, TUBA’s counter-
part science academies, and several umbrella organizations.
By way of conclusion, I would like to express my heartfelt gratitude to the dear author
F. Jamil Ragep, and his former student Hasan Umut, who contributed to the prepara-
tion of the work for publication. My special thanks also go to the TUBA staff who put
their efforts to make this publication possible.
vi
About Author
Born in West Virginia (USA), he attended the University of Michigan, where he re-
ceived degrees in Anthropology and Near Eastern Studies, and later took a Ph.D. in
the History of Science at Harvard University. He was Canada Research Chair in the
History of Science in Islamic Societies at McGill University in Montreal, Canada
from 2007 until 2020, at which time he retired as Professor Emeritus. He has written
extensively on the history of science in Islam and has co-edited books on the transmis-
sion of science between cultures and on water resources in the Middle East. Thanks to
major grants from the Canada Foundation for Innovation and the Quebec government,
and in collaboration with the Max Planck Institute for the History of Science (Berlin),
Ragep was able to initiate an ongoing international effort to catalogue all Islamic
manuscripts in the exact sciences and provide a means to access information online on
the intellectual, institutional, and scientific contexts of these texts (Islamic Scientific
Manuscripts Initiative [ISMI]). Most recently, TÜBA International Academy Prizes
laureate Prof. Dr. F. Jamil Ragep has published a number of articles and co-edited a
volume of essays dealing with the Islamic background to the Copernican revolution.
vii
INTRODUCTION
There has been considerable scholarly interest in the question of the Islamic
background to early modern European astronomy and particularly to the astronomy
of Nicholas Copernicus (1473-1543 CE). There is virtually no controversy, at least
among reputable scholars, that Islamic astronomy influenced medieval and early
modern astronomy through the Latin translations or reworkings of numerous Islamic
astronomical works and through the translations of Arabic translations of Greek
astronomical texts. To get a sense of the range and depth of that influence, examples
are numerous: one need only cite works by al-Battānī (Albategnius [Albatenius], d.
317 H/929 CE), Thābit ibn Qurra (d. 288 H/901 CE), and al-Biṭrūjī (Alpetragius, fl.
ca. 1200 CE), as well as the twelfth-century Latin translation of Ptolemy’s (fl. 140 CE)
Almagest that apparently used multiple Arabic versions. Much more debatable has
been the claim that Copernicus’s models were borrowed—wholesale—from Islamic
sources. The articles herein collected are related to this question, and I am deeply
indebted to the Turkish Academy of Sciences (TÜBA) for making them more widely
available.
I was initially reluctant to enter into the Copernicus question. The wealth of
unexamined Islamic scientific writings, I believed and still believe, make it imperative
to contextualize those works, especially the many neglected works after the so-called
“Golden Age,” which has been erroneously claimed to have ended about 1200 CE.
The question of influence on other cultural groups seemed to me at the time to be more
properly within the purview of those expert in their traditions and languages. And
the contributions of scholars such as Noel Swerdlow and Otto Neugebauer certainly
supported that view. But it has become clear to me that the Islamic context, which
is not readily accessible to Latinists, can assist Europeanists in understanding the
sometimes arcane astronomical models and epistemic choices of their subjects. The
Islamic context may also help Latinists and early modernists take into account the
evolution of scientific ideas and avoid the temptation to assume the ideas, models,
instruments, etc. they encounter were new and unprecedented. Of course, there is
always the possibility of “parallelism”; since the Islamic and European scientific
traditions had similar sources, it would not be surprising that new ideas in one culture
were “rediscovered” independently in the another. But recent historical research has
ix
shown over and over again that the diffusion and exchange of science was a reality
long before the modern age, considerably undercutting the parallelism argument.
The fifteen articles included in this volume are divided into four sections, each
emphasizing a different aspect of the Islam-Copernicus connection. The first
section includes three articles that are more general in nature. “Copernicus and His
Islamic Predecessors” provides a historiographical overview of the discovery of
the mathematical connections between Islamic astronomers and Copernicus. But I
stress that focusing on the mathematical models is not sufficient for understanding
the possible influence of Islamic thinkers on Copernicus; one must also take into
account the rise of a kind of “mathematical humanism” within an Islamic context
that made it possible to question the Aristotelian doctrine of a non-moving Earth at
the center of the universe. This argument is developed in “Freeing Astronomy from
Philosophy,” which deals with the influence of Islamic doctrines on the development
of science in Islam. In particular, I argue that the criticism by Islamic theologians of
Aristotelian tenets, especially the claim that natural philosophy dictated a stationary
Earth, made it possible to consider other alternatives. This was most forcefully
articulated by the fifteenth-century theologian/scientist ʿAlī Qushjī (d. 879 H/1474
CE). The last article in this section, “Islamic Reactions to Ptolemy’s Imprecisions,”
explores the rather dramatic increase in accuracy of observations during the Islamic
period and proposes Islam’s creationist perspective, which prioritized the phenomenal
world of the senses over the Platonic world of “Ideas,” as a possible explanation.
Along with the development of trigonometry and other mathematical tools, this
often underappreciated aspect of the Islamic contribution to science should be seen
as a significant transformation that was an important component of the transition to
modern science.
The next section includes five articles concerning the Ṭūsī-couple, which is a device
invented by Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī (d. 672 H/1274 CE) that produces a straight-line
motion from two circular motions. J. L. E. Dreyer in 1906 CE had already pointed out
that Ṭūsī’s device was used by Copernicus,1 and many historians of science have since
then emphasized the couple as significant evidence of transmission. In addition to
the articles included here, I dealt with the couple in detail in my two-volume edition,
translation, and study of Ṭūsī’s Memoir on Astronomy (al-Tadhkira fī ʿilm al-hayʾa).2 In
“The Two Versions of the Ṭūsī Couple,” I emphasized that Ṭūsī had actually developed
1
J. L. E. Dreyer, History of the Planetary Systems from Thales to Kepler (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1906), 269.
2
F. J. Ragep, Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī’s Memoir on Astronomy, 2 vols. (New York: Springer, 1993), 2: 427-57.
x
two separate devices, one that produced rectilinear oscillation, while the intention of
the other was to generate a curvilinear oscillation on the surface of a sphere. The
rectilinear oscillation was mainly used for longitudinal motions, allowing Ṭūsī to treat
distance independently from circular motion for his planetary models. The curvilinear
version was used, among other things, for planetary latitudes. In all cases, the purpose
was to produce motions that would avoid Ptolemy’s violations of uniform, circular
motions in the celestial region. “From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-
Couple” is my most recent summary of both the mathematical and historical aspects
of the couple. Among the surprising things I discovered since my initial research was
that Ṭūsī’s original formulations of the couple and his planetary models, presented
in his Persian al-Risāla al-Muʿīniyya and its Supplement,3 was different from what
was in the later Tadhkira and had at least one significant error. This allowed me to
show that the Ṭūsī-couple and models contained in the work of the Byzantine scholar
George Chioniades (d. ca. 1320 CE), entitled “The Schemata of the Stars,” were in
fact from al-Risāla al-Muʿīniyya, not the Tadhkira. The evidence is presented in
“New Light on Shams” and in “From Tūn to Toruń.” It is significant that Chioniades’s
“Schemata” was available in the Vatican Library at the time Copernicus was in Rome
around 1500 CE. To contextualize Chioniades, I also include a short encyclopedia
article summarizing his life and contributions. Finally, in this section, “The Origins of
the Ṭūsī-Couple Revisited” provides some recently discovered evidence that allows
us to give a chronology of Ṭūsī’s discovery and evolving versions of his couples. This
shows that Naṣīr al-Dīn first announced his new models in al-Risāla al-Muʿīniyya,
but did not actually present them until almost ten years later in the Supplement to that
work. Shortly after completing the Supplement, he would present an adaptation of his
rectilinear version in the Recension (Taḥrīr) of Ptolemy’s Almagest. But it was only
in writing the Tadhkira that he provided a corrected version of the rectilinear device
and his newly developed curvilinear version.
xi
Swerdlow and Otto Neugebauer continued and supplemented the research of Roberts
and Kennedy, with Swerdlow concluding that “the relation between the models is so
close that independent invention by Copernicus is all but impossible.”5 Swerdlow had
mainly emphasized the connections between the “first anomaly,” the part of the models
dealing with the planets’ motions through the zodiac. Here both Ibn al-Shāṭir and
Copernicus had used a double-epicycle model to resolve the irregular motion brought
about by Ptolemy’s equant device. For the “second anomaly,” the one having to do with
motion on Ptolemy’s epicycle that was connected with the planet’s motion with respect
to the Sun, Swerdlow proposed that Copernicus had used Regiomontanus’s (d. 1476
CE) models that transformed Ptolemy’s epicycles into eccentrics.6 In “Ibn al-Shāṭir and
Copernicus: The Uppsala Notes Revisited,” I proposed a different interpretation, one
in which Ibn al-Shāṭir’s models were more holistically connected to both the first and
second anomalies in the Copernican models. Basing myself upon an important insight
of my then student and present-day colleague Sajjad Nikfahm-Khubravan, I argued
that there was a “heliocentric bias” in Ibn al-Shāṭir’s models that greatly facilitated the
transition from a geocentric to a heliocentric cosmology. This was followed with a more
technical article on the Mercury model (“Ibn al-Shāṭir and Copernicus on Mercury”),
co-authored with Nikfahm-Khubravan. We maintained there that the mathematical
equivalence of Copernicus’s most complex model in De revolutionibus with that of Ibn
al-Shāṭir’s was decisive evidence for Copernicus’s dependence on his predecessor. But
beyond this obvious point, we claimed that the rather different model in Copernicus’s
earlier Commentariolus, though clearly still dependent on Ibn al-Shāṭir, indicated
that Copernicus was striving for a different sort of cosmology at that earlier stage of
his career. This was a kind of quasi-homocentrism, which allowed for epicycles but
disallowed eccentrics. Unfortunately, this did not work very well, so eccentrics made
a reappearance in De revolutionibus. Finally, this section includes a brief biography of
Ibn al-Shāṭir (also written with Nikfahm-Khubravan) that contributes some additional
information to what is known of this remarkable fourteenth-century Damascene.
In the final section are four articles that deal in varying degrees with other Islamic
connections with Copernicus. The first, “ʿAlī Qushjī and Regiomontanus,” underscores
the remarkable similarity of Regiomontanus’s transformations of epicyclic into
eccentric models with a similar, earlier endeavor by ʿAlī Qushjī. This conversion
5
Noel Swerdlow, “Copernicus, Nicolaus (1473–1543),” in Encyclopedia of the Scientific Revolution from Copernicus to Newton, ed. W.
Applebaum (New York and London, 2000), 165.
6
For Swerdlow’s analysis, see his “The Derivation and First Draft of Copernicus’s Planetary Theory: A Translation of the Commentariolus
with Commentary,” Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 117 (1973): 423-512 and N. M. Swerdlow and O. Neugebauer,
Mathematical Astronomy in Copernicus’s De revolutionibus, 2 parts (New York/Berlin: Springer, 1984), esp. 1: 41-54.
xii
has been held by Swerdlow and others to be crucial for the transformation from a
geocentric to heliocentric cosmology, but I have come to believe that it is far less
important than the central role played by Ibn al-Shāṭir’s models for both the first
and second anomalies. In any event, the nearly identical figures accompanying ʿAlī
Qushjī’s treatise and the printed version of Regiomontanus’s Epitome of the Almagest
provide yet more evidence of the interchange of ideas between Islam and Europe
during the fifteenth century.
The article “Ibn al-Haytham and Eudoxus” points to an interesting use of homocentric
modeling by Ibn al-Haytham (d. ca. 432 H/1040-41 CE) to provide physical orbs
to achieve part of Ptolemy’s planetary motions in latitude. This is one of several
instances in Islamic astronomy in which homocentric modeling, along the lines
advocated by Eudoxus and Aristotle (both 4th c. BCE), gained some adherents among
Islamic astronomers, the most well-known being al-Biṭrūjī. Needless to say, this is
part of a complex story of homocentricity and quasi-homocentricity that should form
part of the story of Copernican astronomy.
The final article in this section, “Al-Battānī, Cosmology, and the Early History of
Trepidation in Islam,” concerns the complex and intriguing history of trepidation, an
alternative to the monotonic precession of the equinoxes. It was often connected with
the apparent decrease in the obliquity of the ecliptic. Although variable precession
xiii
was an incorrect theory from antiquity that was eventually abandoned by later Islamic
astronomers, it gained a number of adherents in the early centuries of Islamic science.
Regarding the connection to medieval and early modern European astronomers, it is
noteworthy that several of them continued to believe in the theory despite long-term
observations in the Islamic world that showed precession to be basically monotonic.
Copernicus himself gave a model for trepidation in De revolutionibus (Bk. III, Chs.
3-5) that was meant to account for both variable precession and the change in obliquity;
remarkably, it was essentially the same as that suggested by Ṭūsī in the Tadhkira.
Ṭūsī, though, was skeptical of the theory and only presented it “if the fact of these two
motions [variable precession and the obliquity] and their variability is ascertained.”7
Again, let me thank the Turkish Academy of Sciences and in particular its President,
Prof. Dr. Muzaffer Şeker, for their encouragement and support in republishing these
articles. I would also like to thank my former student and current colleague, Dr. Hasan
Umut, whose assistance in getting this book published has been invaluable.
The author and the Turkish Academy of Sciences wish to thank the following
publishers and institutions for permission to reproduce the articles in this volume:
1) Brill Publishers
a. Ragep, F. Jamil. “New Light on Shams: The Islamic Side of Σὰμψ
Πουχάρης.” In Politics, Patronage and the Transmission of Knowledge
in 13th - 15th Century Tabriz, edited by Judith Pfeiffer, 231–247. Leiden:
E. J. Brill, 2014.
b. Nikfahm-Khubravan, Sajjad, and F. Jamil Ragep. “Ibn al-Shāṭir.” In The
Encyclopaedia of Islam, Third Edition, Part 2019-2, 67–72. Leiden: E.
J. Brill, 2019.
c. Ragep, F. Jamil. “Ibn al-Haytham and Eudoxus: The Revival of
Homocentric Modeling in Islam.” In Studies in the History of the Exact
Sciences in Honour of David Pingree, edited by Charles Burnett, Jan P.
Hogendijk, Kim Plofker, and Michio Yano, 786–809. Leiden: E. J. Brill,
2004.
2) Cambridge University Press
a. Nikfahm-Khubravan, Sajjad, and F. Jamil Ragep. “The Mercury Models
7
Ragep, Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī’s Memoir on Astronomy, 1: 222-23.
xiv
of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus.” Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 29
(2019): 1–59.
b. Ragep, F. Jamil. “Ṭūsī and Copernicus: The Earth’s Motion in Context.”
Science in Context 14, nos. 1-2 (2001): 145–163. (Persian translation as
“Ṭūsī wa Kūpirnīk: ‘ḥarakat zamīn’ dar mutūn nujūmī,” Farhang 20,
nos. 61-62 (2007): 31–56.)
3) John Wiley & Sons, Inc.
a. Ragep, F. Jamil. “The Two Versions of the Ṭūsī Couple.” In From
Deferent to Equant: Studies in Honor of E.S. Kennedy, edited by David
King and George Saliba, 329–356. Vol. 500 of The Annals of the New
York Academy of Sciences, 1987.
4) McGill-Queen’s University Press
a. Ragep, F. Jamil. “From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-
Couple.” In Before Copernicus: The Cultures and Contexts of Scientific
Learning in the Fifteenth Century, edited by Rivka Feldhay and F. Jamil
Ragep, 161–197 + notes. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press,
2017.
5) Sage Publishing
a. Ragep, F. Jamil. “Copernicus and His Islamic Predecessors: Some
Historical Remarks.” History of Science 45 (2007): 65–81.
b. Ragep, F. Jamil. “Ibn al-Shāṭir and Copernicus: The Uppsala Notes
Revisited.” Journal for the History of Astronomy 47 (Nov. 2016): 395–
415.
c. Ragep, F. Jamil. “ʿAlī Qushjī and Regiomontanus: Eccentric
Transformations and Copernican Revolutions.” Journal for the History
of Astronomy 36/4 (2005): 359–371. (Translated into Turkish by Yavuz
Unat as “Ali Kuşçu ve Regiomontanus: Dişmerkezli Dönüşümler ve
Kopernik Devrimi,” Osmanlı Bilimi Araştırmaları VIII/1 (2006): 81–96.)
6) Springer Nature
a. Ragep, F. Jamil. “Islamic Reactions to Ptolemy’s Imprecisions.” In
Ptolemy in Perspective, edited by Alexander Jones, 121–134 + bibl.
Dordrecht; New York: Springer-Verlag, 2010.
7) University of Barcelona
xv
a. Ragep, F. Jamil. “Al-Battānī, Cosmology, and the Early History of Trepidation in
Islam.” In From Baghdad to Barcelona. Studies in the Islamic Exact Sciences in
Honour of Prof. Juan Vernet, 2 vols., edited by Josep Casulleras and Julio Samsó,
1: 267–298. Barcelona: Universitat de Barcelona, 1996.
8) University of Chicago Press
a. Ragep, F. Jamil. “Freeing Astronomy from Philosophy: An Aspect of Islamic
Influence on Science.” Osiris 16 (2001): 49–71.
9) Open Access
a. Ragep, F. Jamil. “The Origins of the Ṭūsī-Couple Revisited.” In Instruments
– Observations – Theories: Studies in the History of Astronomy in Honor of
James Evans, edited by Alexander Jones and Christián Carman, 229–237, 2020,
DOI: 10.5281/zenodo.3928498. Open access distribution under a Creative
Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC-BY) license. https://archive.nyu.edu/
bitstream/2451/61288/59/14.%20Ragep.pdf
b. Ragep, F. Jamil. “Chioniades, Gregor [George].” [This is the original English
version, for which I own the copyright, that has appeared in Persian translation as
“Khiyūniyādis [Chioniades],” in Dāʾirat al-Maʿārif-i Buzurg-i Islāmī (Iran) [Great
Islamic Encyclopedia], vol. 23 (Tehran: Markaz-i Dāʾirat al-Maʿārif-i Buzurg-i
Islāmī, 1396 [2018]), 355–358.]
xvi
Section I
General Works
COPERNICUS AND HIS ISLAMIC PREDECESSORS:
SOME HISTORICAL REMARKS
F. Jamil Ragep
McGill University
As a result of research over the past half century, there has been a growing recogni-
tion that a number of mathematical models used by Copernicus had originally been
developed by Islamic astronomers. This has led to speculation about how Copernicus
may have learned of these models and the role they played in the development of
his revolutionary, heliocentric cosmology. Most discussion of this connection has
thus far been confined to fairly technical issues related to these models; recently,
however, it has been argued that the connections may go deeper, extending into the
physics of a moving Earth and the way in which astronomy itself was conceived. The
purpose of this article is to give an overview of these possible connections between
Copernicus and his Islamic predecessors and to discuss some of their implications
for Copernican studies.
That Copernicus was acquainted with a number of his Islamic predecessors has
been evident since 1543, when Copernicus in De revolutionibus explicitly cited five
Islamic authors.1 The latest of these authors, al-Bitruji, flourished in Spain in the
last part of the twelfth century, so Copernicus’s references end around 1200, which
is the approximate terminus date for Islamic authors who were translated into Latin.
Until recently, most historiography related to Copernicus has assumed that this was
the end of the story, at least as far as Islamic influence goes. But since the 1950s, a
series of discoveries has shaken this neatly constricted picture and caused a major
re-evaluation of the relation of Copernicus (as well as other Renaissance astronomers)
to later Islamic astronomy.
The first modern acknowledgement of a connection between Copernicus and
a later (i.e. post-1200) Islamic astronomer was made by J. L. E. Dreyer in 1906.
In a footnote, Dreyer noted that the new device invented by Nasir al-Din al-Tusi
(d. 1274) was also used by Copernicus in Book III, chap. 4 of De revolutionibus.2
Typical for the time, Dreyer offered no further explanation or speculation; nor did
anyone else until the discovery in the 1950s of a connection between another Islamic
astronomer and Copernicus. E. S. Kennedy, who was a professor of mathematics
at the American University of Beirut, happened by chance to notice some unusual
(i.e. non-Ptolemaic) astronomical models while browsing through the Nihayat al-
sul of cAla’ al-Din Ibn al-Shatir, a Damascene astronomer of the fourteenth century
who had been the time-keeper of the Umayyad Mosque. Upon showing these to his
4 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
friend and mentor, Otto Neugebauer of Brown University, Kennedy was amazed to
learn that these models were ones that had been thought to have first appeared in the
works of Nicholas Copernicus. This led to a series of articles by Kennedy and his
students that discussed various aspects of these models by Ibn al-Shatir as well as
by other late Islamic astronomers.3
The picture that emerged can be summarized as follows. Islamic authors from an
early period were critical of Ptolemy’s methods, observations, and models.4 One par-
ticular irritant was the use of devices by Ptolemy that violated the accepted physical
principles that had been adopted by most astronomers in the ancient and medieval
periods. Later Islamic astronomers came to list sixteen of these violations: six having
to do with having the reference point for uniform motion of an orb being different
from the actual centre of the orb (often referred to as the “equant” problem); nine
having to do with a variety of Ptolemaic devices meant to bring about latitudinal
variation in the planets’ motions (i.e. deviation north or south of the ecliptic); and,
finally, an irregular oscillation of the lunar epicycle due to the reference diameter
being directed to a “prosneusis” point rather than the deferent centre of the epicycle.5
The earliest systematic attempt in Islam to criticize Ptolemy’s methods and devices
occurred in al-Shukuk cala Batlamyus (Doubts against Ptolemy) by Ibn al-Haytham
(d. c. 1040), who was better known in Europe for his great work on optics. In addition
to his blistering critique of Ptolemy, Ibn al-Haytham also wrote a treatise in which he
attempted to deal with some of the problems of Ptolemy’s planetary latitude models.6
A contemporary of Ibn al-Haytham, Abu cUbayd al-Juzjani, who was an associate of
Abu cAli Ibn Sina (= Avicenna, d. 1037), also dealt with these issues and proposed
a model to deal with the equant problem.7
These early attempts notwithstanding, the major thrust to provide alternative
models occurred in the twelfth century and continued for several centuries thereafter.
In Islamic Spain, there were a number of criticisms that questioned the very basis of
Ptolemaic astronomy, in particular its use of eccentrics and epicycles, which culmi-
nated in an alternative cosmological system by al-Bitruji that used only orbs that were
homocentric with the Earth.8 But though Bitruji’s work had important influences in
Europe — indeed Copernicus mentions his view that Venus is above the Sun9 — the
Spanish “revolt” against Ptolemy should be seen as episodic rather than marking the
beginning of a long-lived tradition of Islamic homocentric astronomy.
In the Islamic East the situation was otherwise. Beginning in the first half of the
thirteenth century, a number of works appeared that proposed alternatives to Ptolemy’s
planetary models. This was the start of an extremely fruitful period in the history of
science in Islam in which a series of creative mathematical models were produced
that dealt with the problems of Ptolemaic astronomy. Among the most important of
these new models were those of Nasir al-Din al-Tusi (1201–74), Mu’ayyad al-Din
al-cUrdi (d. c. 1266), Qutb al-Din al-Shirazi (1236–1311), cAla’ al-Din Ibn al-Shatir
(d. c. 1375), and Shams al-Din al-Khafri (fl. 1525).10 In essence, these astronomers
developed mathematical tools (such as the “Tusi couple” and the “cUrdi lemma”)
that allowed connected circular motions to reproduce approximately the effects
66
Copernicus and His Islamic Predecessors: Some Historical Remarks 5
brought about by devices such as Ptolemy’s equant.11 In the case of the rectilinear
Tusi couple, two spheres, one half the size and internally tangent to the other, rotate
in opposite directions with the smaller twice as fast as the larger. The result of these
motions is that a given point on a diameter of the larger sphere will oscillate recti-
linearly. (There is an analogous curvilinear Tusi couple in which the oscillation is
meant to occur on a great circle arc on the surface of a sphere.) What this allowed
Tusi and his successors to do was to isolate the aspect of Ptolemy’s equant model
that brought about a variation in distance between the epicycle centre and the Earth’s
centre from the aspect that resulted in a variation in speed of the epicycle centre
about the Earth. Such mathematical dexterity allowed these astronomers to present
models that to a great extent restored uniform circular motion to the heavens while
at the same time producing motions of the planets that were almost equivalent to
those of Ptolemy.12
Noel Swerdlow and Otto Neugebauer, in discussing this Islamic tradition, famously
asked: “What does all this have to do with Copernicus?” Their answer was: “Rather
a lot.”13 In his commentary on Copernicus’s Commentariolus, Swerdlow made the
case for this connection through a remarkable reconstruction of how Copernicus had
arrived at the heliocentric system. According to Swerdlow, Copernicus, somehow
aware of this Islamic tradition of non-Ptolemaic astronomy, began his work to reform
astronomy under its influence. In particular Copernicus objected explicitly to Ptole-
my’s use of the equant, an objection that had been a staple of Islamic astronomy for
some five centuries at that point (but which seems not to have been made by earlier
European astronomers).14 Swerdlow then proposed that although Copernicus was
able to use some of these models, in particular those of Ibn al-Shatir, to deal with
the irregular motion brought about by the first anomaly (the motion of the epicycle
centre on the deferent), it was the second anomaly (related to the motion of the
planet on the epicycle) that remained problematic. For the outer planets this motion
corresponds to the motion of the Earth around the Sun, so a transformation of this
motion from an epicyclic to an eccentric would lead to a quasi-heliocentric system,
whereby the planet goes around the Sun. Of course the Earth could still remain at
rest while the Sun, with the planets going around it, could then go around the Earth.
In other words, Copernicus’s transformations could have led to a Tychonic system.
Swerdlow argued that this was not an option for Copernicus, since it led to the notori-
ous intersection of the spheres of the Sun and Mars, which simply was not possible
in the solid-sphere astronomy to which Copernicus was committed. Thus Copernicus
was compelled to opt for a heliocentric system with the Earth, as a planet, in motion
around the Sun.15
In his reconstruction, Swerdlow assumed that Copernicus must have had access
to the models of his Islamic predecessors. Because of the scarcity of concrete evidence
for this assertion (i.e. translated texts in Latin, earlier European references to these
models, or the like), Swerdlow was clearly swayed by the similarity of complex
67
6 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
HISTORIOGRAPHICAL REACTIONS
One would have expected that these historical discoveries, some of which are now a
half-century old, would have caused a substantial reevaluation of the origins of the
68
Copernicus and His Islamic Predecessors: Some Historical Remarks 7
“scientific revolution” or at the least an attempt to deal with the role of Islamic science
in that revolution. The fact that this has not yet occurred to any significant degree
may be traced to several factors. First, recent trends in the historiography of science
have resulted in critiques of the very notion of a “scientific revolution”, which have
tended to downplay the traditional preeminence of the Copernicus-Galileo-Newton
narrative.21 But even those who still hold to some notion of a scientific revolution have
tended to focus their attention on local contexts (usually European) for explanations
and to look at the consequences rather than the origins of Copernicanism.22 Second,
the increasing realization that Copernicus was rather conservative in his scientific
outlook, holding on, for example, to the traditional orbs and their uniform, circular
motions, has called his revolutionary status into question. So there seems to be an
underlying assumption that the enormous complexity in De revolutionibus is more or
less irrelevant for the truly important innovation, heliocentricism, which, according
to this view, is all that really mattered for Kepler, Galileo, et al. 23 Thus the convo-
luted story of “Copernicus and the Arabs”, which is mostly about the complicated
but supposedly irrelevant models, becomes more trouble than it is worth.24 Third,
despite, but in part due to, the trend towards “political correctness”, there has been a
tendency to essentialize different scientific traditions, sometimes because of a benign
cultural relativism, sometimes for more invidious reasons. Thus the “essential” part
of the scientific revolution, of which the de-centring of the Earth is fundamental, is
seen as European.25 Finally, the simple fact of academic boundaries has played a role.
Because historians of science specializing in Islamic civilization have tended to be
marginalized, in part for disciplinary reasons, in part because of the arcane nature of
many of their publications, it has been surprisingly difficult to initiate an on-going
dialogue between medieval Latinists, Islamists, and early modernists.26
Although the larger history of science community seems so far to have resisted
dealing with the implications of the Islamic connection to Copernicus, some historians
of astronomy who do not specialize in Islamic science have been influenced by the
discoveries of Kennedy and his colleagues. We have already discussed Neugebauer
and Swerdlow. Jerzy Dobrzycki and Richard L. Kremer also explored possible con-
nections between Islamic astronomy and early modern European astronomy in their
incisive article “Peurbach and Maragha astronomy”; they raised the distinct pos-
sibility that Peurbach may well have developed non-Ptolemaic models based upon
Islamic sources that were similar (if not the same) as ones that would be used in the
next generation by Copernicus. Given this earlier possibility of transmission, they
came to an interesting conclusion: “We may be looking for a means of transmission
both more fragmentary and widespread than a single treatise, and at least one of the
Maragha sources must have been available to the Latin West before 1461, the year
of Peurbach’s death.”27 But not all historians of early modern astronomy have been
so willing to accept a connection, even in the face of numerous coincidences. I. N.
Veselovsky claimed that it is more likely that Copernicus got the Tusi couple from
a mathematically-related theorem in Proclus’s Commentary on the First Book of
Euclid’s Elements.28 More recently, Mario di Bono has maintained that independent
69
8 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
Di Bono’s article serves to highlight what has been missing in the analysis of the
connection between Islamic astronomy and Copernicus. The emphasis on the models
alone obscures several crucial historiographical, conceptual, and physical issues that
need to be considered when dealing with the Copernican transformations. Let us first
look briefly at some of these historiographical issues. What seems to be overlooked
by those who advocate a reinvention by Copernicus and/or his contemporaries of
the mathematical models previously used by Islamic astronomers is the lack of an
historical context for those models within European astronomy. At the least, one
would expect to find some tradition of criticism of Ptolemy in Europe in which those
models would make sense. But in fact this is not the case. Copernicus’s statement
of his dissatisfaction with Ptolemaic astronomy, which is the ostensible reason he
gives for his drastic cosmological change, had no precedent in Europe but did have
a continuous five-hundred-year precedent in the Islamic world. Here is what he says
in the introduction to the Commentariolus:
… these theories [put forth by Ptolemy and most others] were inadequate unless
they also envisioned certain equant circles, on account of which it appeared that
the planet never moves with uniform velocity either in its deferent sphere or with
respect to its proper centre. Therefore a theory of this kind seemed neither perfect
enough nor sufficiently in accordance with reason.
Therefore, when I noticed these [difficulties], I often pondered whether perhaps
a more reasonable model composed of circles could be found from which every
apparent irregularity would follow while everything in itself moved uniformly,
just as the principle of perfect motion requires.30
Since the Commentariolus is the initial work in which Copernicus presents his new
cosmology, one would assume that it would be here, and not in the much later De
revolutionibus, in which we should search for his original motivations.31 What do
we learn from this passage? Copernicus puts himself squarely within the tradition of
Islamic criticisms of Ptolemy’s violations of uniform, circular motions in the heavens.
It is important to keep in mind that this tradition began in the Islamic world as early
as the eleventh century and led to the series of alternative models outlined above.
Furthermore this tradition lasted for some six centuries in which there was a very
70
Copernicus and His Islamic Predecessors: Some Historical Remarks 9
71
10 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
one approaches it rigorously”.34 Though his position had the potential to free the
astronomer from the natural philosopher, in actuality a kind of compromise emerged
in which the astronomer and the natural philosopher were said to differ not on the
actual set of doctrines but rather on the way to prove them. This is clearly laid out
in a passage from Geminus preserved in Simplicius’s commentary on Aristotle’s
physics:
Now in many cases the astronomer and the physicist will propose to prove the
same point, e.g., that the Sun is of great size or that the Earth is spherical, but
they will not proceed by the same road. The physicist will prove each fact by
considerations of essence or substance, of force, of its being better that things
should be as they are, or of coming into being and change; the astronomer will
prove them by the properties of figures or magnitudes, or by the amount of
movement and the time that is appropriate to it.35
Most Islamic astronomers followed this formulation, elaborating and clarifying it
using the fact/reasoned fact (quia/propter quid) distinction of Aristotle’s Posterior
analytics. Thus the astronomers were seen as giving the facts of various cosmological
issues (e.g. that the Earth was spherical) using observational and mathematical tools
as is done in Ptolemy’s Almagest, whereas the proof of the natural philosopher, such
as in Aristotle’s De caelo, provided the reason or the “why” behind these facts.36
This relatively benign view of the relationship between the astronomer and the
physicist came, over time, to be modified in significant ways. Most likely under the
influence of Islamic theologians, who were fundamentally opposed to Aristotelian
notions of natural cause, we can see subtle shifts in how physical principles were
presented in the introductory parts of astronomical texts.37 Nasir al-Din al-Tusi, for
example, presented the critical principle of the uniformity of celestial motion in such
a way that it did not depend upon the ultimate cause. Thus the monoformity of falling
bodies, and the uniformity of celestial motions, both of which moved “in a single
way”, was what was important. It became irrelevant that the former was brought
about by a “nature” while the latter was brought about by a “soul”.38
Slowly, then, we see an attempt in Islamic astronomy to provide a self-contained
mathematical methodology that ran parallel to the methods of the natural philoso-
phers. But Tusi for one did not believe that this meant that the astronomer could be
completely independent of the natural philosophers and metaphysicians, since there
were certain principles that only the natural philosophers could provide the astrono-
mer. In fact this was generally the position of Islamic astronomers with the notable
exception of cAli Qushji in the fifteenth century.
Qushji was the son of the falconer of Ulugh Beg (1394–1449), the Timurid prince
who was a generous patron of the sciences and arts. Ulugh Beg was an active sup-
porter and participant in the magnificent Samarqand observatory, which was one of
the greatest scientific institutions that had been established up to that time. As a boy,
Qushji became his protégé and student and eventually occupied an important posi-
tion at the observatory. After the assassination of Ulugh Beg, Qushji was attached to
72
Copernicus and His Islamic Predecessors: Some Historical Remarks 11
various courts in Iran but would end his career in Constantinople under the patronage
of Mehmet II, who had conquered the city for the Ottomans.
Qushji held that the astronomer had no need for Aristotelian physics and in fact
should establish his own physical principles independently of the natural philoso-
phers.39 This position had profound implications for one principle in particular, namely
that the element earth had a principle of rectilinear inclination that precluded it from
moving naturally with a circular motion.40 Tusi had maintained that there was no
way for the astronomer, using mathematics and observation, to arrive at the “proof of
the fact” that the Earth was either moving or at rest. This was contrary to Ptolemy’s
position in the Almagest (I.7), namely that one could establish a static Earth through
observation. After Tusi, we can trace a three-century discussion in which various
authors argued whether he or Ptolemy was correct regarding the possibility of an
observational proof of the Earth’s state of rest. Qushji, though, took a somewhat
different approach. Starting with his view that the astronomer should not depend on
the natural philosopher, but also rejecting Ptolemy’s view that an observational test
was possible, Qushji made the remarkable claim that nothing false follows from the
assumption of a rotating Earth.41
The connection with Copernicus, though, might seem tenuous at best. What makes
this an arguable possibility is the remarkable coincidence between a passage in De
revolutionibus (I.8) and one in Tusi’s Tadhkira (II.1[6]) in which Copernicus follows
Tusi’s objection to Ptolemy’s “proofs” of the Earth’s immobility.42 This passage,
which is quoted by numerous Islamic scholars after Tusi, including Qushji, formed
the starting point for their discussion of the Earth’s possible motion. The closeness
of the passage in Copernicus is one more bit of evidence that he seems to have been
influenced not only by Islamic astronomical models but also by a conceptual revolu-
tion that was going on in Islamic astronomy. This conceptual revolution was opening
up the possibility for an alternative “astronomical” physics that was independent of
Aristotelian physics.
It is this point that has been missed up to now in seeking to understand the Islamic
background to Copernicus. Clearly there is more to the Copernican revolution than
some clever astronomical models that arose in the context of a criticism of Ptolemy.
There also needed to be a new conceptualization of astronomy that could allow for an
astronomically-based physics. But there is hardly anything like this in the European
tradition before Copernicus.43 The fact that we can find a long, vigorous discussion
in Islam of this issue intricately-tied to the question of the Earth’s movement should
indicate that such a conceptual foundation was there for the borrowing. It will be
argued, of course, that the mechanism for such borrowing has yet to be found. But
again, in my opinion it is more important at this point in our knowledge to focus on
the products rather than the mechanism of transmission. By doing so, we can get a
clearer idea not only of the possible Islamic connection to Copernicus but also of
the Copernican revolution itself.
73
Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
74
FIG. 1. Comparison of diagrams of Regiomontanus and Qushji. (Left) J. Regiomontanus and G. Peurbach, Epytoma Joannis de monte regio In almagestum
ptolemaei (Venice, 1496), n4r, and (right) cAli Qushji, Fi anna asl al-kharij…, Carullah MS 2060, f. 137a. Reproductions courtesy of the History
of Science Collections, University of Oklahoma Libraries, and of the Süleymaniye Library, Istanbul, respectively.
12
Copernicus and His Islamic Predecessors: Some Historical Remarks 13
FURTHER THOUGHTS
In the two years since I first developed the views expressed above, I have published
a small treatise by cAli Qushji (d. 1474) that presents and proves a proposition that
appears in Book XII of Regiomontanus’s Epitome of the Almagest, which was com-
pleted in 1463.44 The importance of this proposition can scarcely be overstated, since
it allows one to transform all of Ptolemy’s planetary epicyclic models into eccentric
models, which is generally accepted as crucial for the transformation from a geocentric
to a heliocentric cosmology (see above). In that article, I argue that the possibility of a
connection to Regiomontanus was strengthened by the lack of a context or justification
in which Regiomontanus presented the proposition, which stands in stark contrast
to the expansive manner in which Qushji discusses his own discovery (as a result
of dealing with the Mercury model) and his attempt to explain why Ptolemy disal-
lowed such a transformation for the lower planets (Mercury and Venus). The striking
similarity of Qushji’s figure that accompanies his text and that of Regiomontanus
(Figure 1) adds to the possibility that this is a matter of transmission.
Given that Qushji was also willing to allow for the possibility of the Earth’s rota-
tion, the connections to Copernicus seem irresistible. Here I should emphasize the
point that I made at the end of the original article above, namely that it is important
to keep in mind that more is involved than a simple transmission of propositions or
mathematical models. The sudden appearance in Europe at the end of the fifteenth
century of what can be called “mathematical humanism” is what really demands an
explanation. Obviously the interest in reforming and/or transforming the Ptolemaic
system along the lines that had developed over many centuries in the hay’a tradition
of eastern Islamic astronomy is one aspect of this. But clearly there is much more
in Regiomontanus’s mathematical Programme than Ptolemaic astronomy (although
it plays a major role in his thinking).45 It is here that I think more work needs to be
done.
James Stephen Byrne has recently argued that “Regiomontanus’s vision of math-
ematics is that of a mathematician, rather than that of a historian, an educator, or a
philosopher”. Rather than viewing Regiomontanus simply through a humanist lens,
Byrne contends that one should see his “mathematical humanism” as “deeply rooted
in the traditional university curriculum ... [but] [a]bove all, it is rooted in mathemati-
cal texts, both curricular and extra-curricular”.46 But as Michael Shank has pointed
out: “With respect to the university, it is important to note first that from almost
every point of view except intrinsic interest and later historiographical significance,
the mathematical sciences at Vienna were on the margins. Institutionally, they had a
place, but it was a minor one. They appear in the curriculum, but do not form its core.
Statistically, they are distinctly in the minority; they are taught, read, and practiced
by a minority.”47 But Shank goes on to argue that this does not make them any less
important or significant. And clearly there must have been some pre-existing interest
in the mathematical sciences in order for Cardinal Bessarion, the Greek prelate who
“desperately wanted to preserve and breathe new life into the intellectual heritage of
classical Greece”, to have inspired Peurbach and Regiomontanus to undertake what
75
14 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
76
Copernicus and His Islamic Predecessors: Some Historical Remarks 15
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
The first and largest part of this article (before “Further Thoughts”) is a slightly revised
version of the author’s “Copernicus and his Islamic predecessors: Some historical
remarks”, which appeared in Filozofski vestnik, xxv (2004), 125–42. The author and
Publisher are grateful to Dr Matjaž Vesel and Filozofski vestnik for permitting the
reuse of this material. I also wish to thank Dr Nevzat Kaya (Istanbul) and Dr Marilyn
Ogilvie (Oklahoma) for permission to reproduce images from their collections.
REFERENCES
1. These are: al-Battani, al-Bitruji, al-Zarqallu, Ibn Rushd, and Thabit ibn Qurra. Copernicus also refers
to al-Battani in his Commentariolus, which remained unpublished during his lifetime. “Islamic”
here refers to the civilization of Islam, not the religion, since a number of “Islamic” astronomers,
such as Thabit, were not Muslims.
2. J. L. E. Dreyer, History of the planetary systems from Thales to Kepler (Cambridge, 1906), 269. Dreyer
knew of Tusi’s work from the translation by Carra de Vaux of a chapter of his al-Tadhkira fi
c
ilm al-hay’a (“Les sphères célestes selon Nasir Eddin-Attusi” in Paul Tannery, Recherches sur
l’histoire de l’astronomie ancienne (Paris, 1893), Appendix VI, pp. 337–61).
3. These have been conveniently collected in E. S. Kennedy and Imad Ghanem (eds), The life & work of
Ibn al-Shatir: An Arab astronomer of the fourteenth century (Aleppo, 1976), and in E. S. Kennedy
et al., Studies in the Islamic exact sciences (Beirut, 1983), 50–107. The most important of these
is E. S. Kennedy, “Late medieval planetary theory”, Isis, lvii (1966), 84–97.
4. See, for example, the very critical remarks, most likely by the Banu Musa (ninth century), in Régis
Morelon, Thabit ibn Qurra: Œuvres d’astronomie (Paris, 1987), 61.
5. F. J. Ragep, Nasir al-Din al-Tusi’s memoir on astronomy (2 vols, New York, 1993), i, 48–51.
6. F. Jamil Ragep, “Ibn al-Haytham and Eudoxus: The revival of homocentric modeling in Islam”, in
Studies in the history of the exact sciences in honour of David Pingree, ed. by C. Burnett et al.
(Leiden, 2004), 786–809.
7. George Saliba, “Ibn Sina and Abu cUbayd al-Juzjani: The problem of the Ptolemaic equant”, Journal
for the history of Arabic science, iv (1980), 376–403; reprinted in idem, A history of Arabic
astronomy: Planetary theories during the golden age of Islam (New York, 1994), 85–112.
8. See Nur al-Din abu Ishaq al-Bitruji, On the principles of astronomy, ed. and transl. by B. Goldstein
(2 vols, New Haven, 1971). Cf. A. I. Sabra, “The Andalusian revolt against Ptolemaic astronomy:
Averroes and al-Bitruji”, in Transformation and tradition in the sciences, ed. by E. Mendelsohn
(Cambridge, 1984), 133–53.
9. Nicholas Copernicus, De revolutionibus orbium coelestium, transl. by E. Rosen as On the revolutions
(Baltimore, 1978), 18.
10. Good overviews can be found in George Saliba, “The astronomical tradition of Maragha: A historical
survey and prospects for future research”, Arabic science and philosophy, i (1991), 67–99
(reprinted in idem, History (ref. 7), 258–90), and George Saliba, “Arabic planetary theories after
the eleventh century AD”, in Encyclopedia of the history of Arabic science, ed. by R. Rashed (3
vols, London, 1996), i, 58–127.
11. Today we would say that these mathematical tools were equivalent to linkages of constant-length
vectors rotating at constant angular velocities; but it is important to remember that Islamic
astronomers conceived of their devices as physical and not simply mathematical. Cf. Ragep,
op. cit. (ref. 5), ii, 433–7.
12. F. Jamil Ragep, “The two versions of the Tusi couple”, in From deferent to equant: Studies in honor
77
16 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
of E. S. Kennedy, ed. by D. King and G. Saliba (The annals of the New York Academy of Sciences,
d (1987)), 329–56.
13. N. M. Swerdlow and O. Neugebauer, Mathematical astronomy in Copernicus’s De revolutionibus (2
parts, New York and Berlin, 1984), i, 47.
14. N. M. Swerdlow, “The derivation and first draft of Copernicus’s planetary theory: A translation of
the Commentariolus with commentary”, Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society,
cxvii (1973), 423–512, p. 434.
15. Admittedly, this is a grossly simplified version of a fuller and much more careful exposition that
one may find in Swerdlow and Neugebauer, op. cit. (ref. 13), i, 41–64. A good summary is also
provided by Michael H. Shank, “Regiomontanus on Ptolemy, physical orbs, and astronomical
fictionalism: Goldsteinian themes in the ‘Defense of Theon against George of Trebizond’”,
Perspectives on science: Historical, philosophical, social, x (2002), 179–207.
16. Swerdlow and Neugebauer, op. cit. (ref. 13), i, 47. Cf. Neugebauer’s earlier remark that “The
mathematical logic of these methods is such that the purely historical problem of contact or
transmission, as opposed to independent discovery, becomes a rather minor one” (O. Neugebauer,
“On the planetary theory of Copernicus”, in Vistas in astronomy, x (1968), 89–103, p. 90; reprinted
in idem, Astronomy and history (New York, 1983), 491–505, p. 492).
17. N. Swerdlow, “Copernicus, Nicolaus (1473–1543)”, in Encyclopedia of the scientific revolution from
Copernicus to Newton, ed. by W. Applebaum (New York and London, 2000), 165.
18. Swerdlow and Neugebauer claim that it is a translation. The recent editors and translators of the text
argue that it is an original Byzantine work that is simply influenced to some degree by Arabic or
Persian sources (E. A. Paschos and P. Sotiroudis, The schemata of the stars (Singapore, 1998),
11–18). The closeness to Islamic sources, however, and the use of the standard Arabic corruption
Kakkaous rather than the Greek Cepheus argue for a greater dependence than the authors wish
to admit. Clearly more research on this question is needed.
19. See N. Swerdlow, “Aristotelian planetary theory in the Renaissance: Giovanni Battista Amico’s
homocentric spheres”, Journal for the history of astronomy, iii (1972), 36–48, and Mario Di Bono,
“Copernicus, Amico, Fracastoro and Tusi’s device: Observations on the use and transmission of
a model”, Journal for the history of astronomy, xxvi (1995), 133–54. In a passage in III.4 of De
revolutionibus that was deleted prior to publication, Copernicus himself speaks of others who
had used the Tusi device; see Ragep, op. cit. (ref. 5), ii, 431.
20. Willy Hartner, “Copernicus, the man, the work, and its history”, Proceedings of the American
Philosophical Society, cxvii (1973), 413–22, p. 421.
21. A session at a recent American History of Science Society annual meeting was entitled: “The late,
great scientific revolution”. Cf. Margaret J. Osler (ed.), Rethinking the scientific revolution
(Cambridge, 2000).
22. Two recent examples are Peter Dear’s Revolutionizing the sciences: European knowledge and its
ambitions, 1500–1700 (Princeton, 2001), and Steven Shapin’s The scientific revolution (Chicago,
1996). Both ignore Islamic science entirely and scarcely discuss medieval European contributions
to the scientific revolution.
23. Copernicus’s conservatism was emphasized in 1959 both in a scholarly and in a popular context.
As for the former, Derek de Solla Price’s “Contra-Copernicus” provided a technical account
that showed that Copernicus was really still part of ancient and medieval astronomy. As Price
concludes: “... Copernicus made a fortunate philosophical guess without any observation to prove
or disprove his ideas, and ... his work as a mathematical astronomer was uninspired. From this
point of view his book is conservative and a mere reshuffled version of the Almagest” (Derek J.
de S. Price, “Contra-Copernicus: A critical re-estimation of the mathematical planetary theory
of Ptolemy, Copernicus, and Kepler”, in Critical problems in the history of science, ed. by M.
Clagett (Madison, 1969), 197–218, p. 216). The popular presentation of this viewpoint was made
78
Copernicus and His Islamic Predecessors: Some Historical Remarks 17
by Arthur Koestler in his The sleep walkers: A history of man’s changing vision of the universe
(London, 1959), where Copernicus is referred to as the “timid canon”. How Copernicus can be
“saved” despite this conservatism and/or his connection to Islamic astronomy is well-illustrated
by Erna Hilfstein’s remarks regarding the significance of Copernicus’s achievement: “Copernicus
may have used the geometrical devices of his Greek or Arab predecessors (for example, from the
‘Maragha school’), yet his system, and the perception of the cosmos it established, was entirely
novel” (“Introduction to the softcover edition” of Nicholas Copernicus, On the revolutions, transl.
and comm. by E. Rosen (Baltimore, 1992), p. xiii.
24. We should note, though, that recently Michał Kokowski, in defending Copernicus’s originality,
has also conceded that the Islamic models are also somehow revolutionary according to his
“correspondence principle” inasmuch as they supersede those of Ptolemy by overcoming the
problematic equant (Copernicus’s originality: Towards integration of contemporary Copernican
studies (Warsaw, 2004), 75–77). Here he follows George Saliba, who maintained that the Maragha
school astronomers were revolutionary because of their “realization that astronomy ought to
describe the behaviour of physical bodies in mathematical language, and should not remain a
mathematical hypothesis, which would only save the phenomena” (“The rôle of Maragha in the
development of Islamic astronomy: A scientific revolution before the Renaissance”, Revue de
synthèse, cviii (1987), 361–73, p. 372; reprinted in idem, History (ref. 7), 245–57, p. 256). It
is not clear how Saliba reconciles this position with his later claim that the sixteenth-century
astronomer al-Khafri had reached “unparalleled heights” in this tradition by “realiz[ing] that all
mathematical modeling had no physical truth by itself and was simply another language with
which one could describe the physical observed reality” (George Saliba, “Arabic versus Greek
astronomy: A debate over the foundations of science”, Perspectives on science, viii (2000),
328–41, p. 339). For a contrary view, see A. I. Sabra, who has argued that this Islamic scientific
tradition was not revolutionary but should be regarded as “normal science” in the Kuhnian sense
(“Configuring the universe: Aporetic, problem solving, and kinematic modeling as themes of
Arabic astronomy”, Perspectives on science, vi (1998), 288–330, pp. 292, 321–3). As should
be clear in what follows, I believe that the emphasis on the mathematical models — whether
revolutionary or not — has distracted us from what is the most significant and innovative part
of Islamic theoretical astronomy.
25. Recent books by two mediaevalists, A. C. Crombie and Edward Grant, advocate the European nature of
modern science, thus reverting to the more traditional viewpoint. See Crombie’s Styles of scientific
thinking in the European tradition: The history of argument and explanation especially in the
mathematical and biomedical sciences and arts (London, 1994), and Grant’s The foundations
of modern science in the Middle Ages: Their religious, institutional, and intellectual contexts
(Cambridge, 1996) and idem, God and reason in the Middle Ages (Cambridge, 2001). This
view is held by both Western and Islamic scholars so cannot be simply ascribed to some biased
antagonism towards Islamic civilization. For example, the Iranian expatriate S. H. Nasr has
stated that although “all that is astronomically new in Copernicus can be found essentially in the
school of al-Tusi”, Islamic astronomers were prescient enough not to break with the traditional
Ptolemaic cosmology “because that would have meant not only a revolution in astronomy, but
also an upheaval in the religious, philosophical and social domains” (S. H. Nasr, Science and
civilization in Islam, 2nd edn (Cambridge, 1987), 174).
26. Cf. Sonja Brentjes, “Between doubts and certainties: On the place of history of science in Islamic
societies within the field of history of science”, N.T.M., xi (2003), 65–79.
27. J. Dobrzycki and R. L. Kremer, “Peurbach and Maragha astronomy? The ephemerides of Johannes
Angelus and their implications”, Journal for the history of astronomy, xxvii (1996), 187–237,
p. 211.
28. I. N. Veselovsky, “Copernicus and Nasir al-Din al-Tusi”, Journal for the history of astronomy, iv
(1973), 128–30. This turns out to be implausible since Copernicus probably did not know of the
79
18 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
Proclus theorem (actually the converse of the Tusi couple) until many years after he used the
device; see Ragep, op. cit. (ref. 5), ii, 430–1.
29. Di Bono, op. cit. (ref. 19), 153–4.
30. Swerdlow, op. cit. (ref. 14), 434–5.
31. Recently B. R. Goldstein (“Copernicus and the origin of his heliocentric system”, Journal for the
history of astronomy, xxxiii (2002), 219–35) has sought to undermine Swerdlow’s reconstruction
of the origins of Copernicus’s heliocentric system by emphasizing a passage in De revolutionibus
(I.10). In it Copernicus points to the distance–period relationship of the planets to justify his
system, which Goldstein takes to be the initial motivation. But again, it is odd that this is hardly
mentioned in the Commentariolus.
32. For this Spanish episode in Islamic astronomy, see Sabra, op. cit. (ref. 8), 133–53.
33. It is difficult, if not impossible, to prove a negative, but it is highly suggestive that one does not find
the word “equant” in Edward Grant’s monumental (816-page) Planets, stars, and orbs: The
medieval cosmos, 1200–1687 (Cambridge, 1994). Even in the generation immediately before
Copernicus, there seems to have been no precedent for what was a commonplace in Islamic
astronomy. As stated in Dobrzycki and Kremer, op. cit. (ref. 27), 211: “We know of no extant
text by Peurbach or Regiomontanus in which the Ptolemaic models are criticized explicitly on
the grounds that they violate uniform, circular motion.”
34. G. J. Toomer, Ptolemy’s Almagest (London, 1984), 36.
35. The translation is due to T. L. Heath in his Aristarchus of Samos (Oxford, 1913), 276; reprinted in
Morris R. Cohen and I. E. Drabkin, A source book in Greek science (Cambridge MA, 1948),
90–91. Cf. G. E. R. Lloyd, “Saving the appearances”, Classical quarterly, n.s., xxviii (1978),
202–22, pp. 212–14 (reprinted with new introduction in idem, Methods and problems in Greek
science (Cambridge, 1991), 248–77).
36. Ragep, op. cit. (ref. 5), i, 38–41, 106–7; ii, 386–8.
37. Much of what follows is elaborated in F. Jamil Ragep, “Freeing astronomy from philosophy: An
aspect of Islamic influence on science”, Osiris, xvi (2001), 49–71.
38. Ragep, op. cit. (ref. 5), i, 44–46, 98–101; ii, 380–1.
39. Ragep, op. cit. (ref. 37), 61–63.
40. A discussion of this Islamic discourse on the Earth’s possible rotation is in F. Jamil Ragep, “Tusi and
Copernicus: The Earth’s motion in context”, Science in context, xiv (2001), 145–63.
41. Ibid., 157.
42. Ibid., 145–8.
43. In the fourteenth century, one finds Nicole Oresme and Jean Buridan discussing the Earth’s rotation.
The former, in particular, presents quite cogent reasons why one might believe in this motion.
But in the end he rejects them for theological reasons. In both cases, it is clear that they have no
interest in a reconceptualization of astronomy along the lines that occurred in Islamic astronomy
(ibid., 158–60). The possibility that such a discussion might have taken place in the fifteenth
century in the circle of Peurbach and Regiomontanus is being investigated by M. Shank; cf. op.
cit. (ref. 15).
44. F. Jamil Ragep, “cAli Qushji and Regiomontanus: Eccentric transformations and Copernican
revolutions”, Journal for the history of astronomy, xxxvi (2005), 359–71.
45. See Menso Folkerts, “Regiomontanus’ role in the transmission and transformation of Greek
mathematics”, in Tradition, transmission, transformation: Proceedings of two conferences
on premodern science held at the University of Oklahoma, ed. by F. J. Ragep and S. P. Ragep
(Leiden, 1996), 89–113.
46. James Steven Byrne, “A humanist history of mathematics? Regiomontanus’s Padua Oration in context”,
Journal of the history of ideas, lxvii (2006), 41–61, p. 61.
80
Copernicus and His Islamic Predecessors: Some Historical Remarks 19
47. Michael H. Shank, “The classical scientific tradition in fifteenth-century Vienna”, in F. J. Ragep and
S. P. Ragep (eds), Tradition, transmission, transformation (ref. 45), 115–36, p. 131.
48. Ibid., 126.
49. See above, ref. 18 (on the transmission of Islamic astronomy to Byzantium). And as Otto Neugebauer
has remarked: “There is no reason to assume that there is any period in which Islamic astronomy
was not known in Constantinople” (A history of ancient mathematical astronomy (3 parts,
New York, 1975), i, 11). Cf. Maria Mavroudi, A Byzantine book on dream interpretation: The
Oneirocriticon of Achmet and its Arabic sources (Leiden, 2002); Alain Touwaide, “Arabic urology
in Byzantium”, Journal of nephrology, xvii (2004), 583–9; and Alain Touwaide, “Arabic medicine
in Greek translation: A preliminary report”, Journal of the International Society for the History
of Islamic Medicine, i (2002), 45–53.
50. Anne Tihon, “Les tables astronomiques persane à Constantinople dans la première moitié du XIVe
siècle”, Byzantion, lvii (1987), 471–87. Reprinted in Tihon, Études d’astronomie Byzantine
(Aldershot, 1994).
51. F. J. Ragep and S. P. Ragep (eds), Tradition, transmission, transformation (ref. 45), pp. xv–xviii.
52. A very important article that takes up the mathematical humanism of Samarqand is Ihsan Fazlıo¢lu’s
“Osmanlı felsefe-biliminin arkaplanı: Semerkand matematik-astronomi okulu”, Dîvân ilmî
araºtırmalar, xiv/1 (2003), 1–66. A revised version in English will appear in a forthcoming issue
of the Journal for the history of Arabic science.
53. George Makdisi, The rise of humanism in classical Islam and the Christian West (Edinburgh, 1990),
349–50, p. 354.
81
22 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
50
Freeing Astronomy from Philosophy An Aspect of Islamic Influence on Science 23
51
24 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
52
Freeing Astronomy from Philosophy An Aspect of Islamic Influence on Science 25
53
26 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
54
Freeing Astronomy from Philosophy An Aspect of Islamic Influence on Science 27
55
28 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
56
Freeing Astronomy from Philosophy An Aspect of Islamic Influence on Science 29
57
30 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
58
Freeing Astronomy from Philosophy An Aspect of Islamic Influence on Science 31
59
32 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
60
Freeing Astronomy from Philosophy An Aspect of Islamic Influence on Science 33
61
34 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
62
Freeing Astronomy from Philosophy An Aspect of Islamic Influence on Science 35
63
36 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
64
38 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
67
Freeing Astronomy from Philosophy An Aspect of Islamic Influence on Science 39
68
40 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
69
Freeing Astronomy from Philosophy An Aspect of Islamic Influence on Science 41
70
42 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
71
Islamic Reactions to Ptolemy’s Imprecisions
F. Jamil Ragep
Consider the following quotation from the author of the treatise Fī sanat al-shams
(“On the Solar Year”), most likely written in Baghdad in the first part of the ninth
century:
Ptolemy, in persuading himself that the period of the solar year should be taken according
to points on the ecliptic, also persuaded himself as to the observations themselves and did
not in reality perform them; coming from his imagination, this was of the greatest harm
for what was described for the calculations (Morelon 1987, p. 61; my translation).
For quite some time, I have had the impression that there is a significant differ-
ence between the types of observations one finds in antiquity and those one finds
in the Islamic world, beginning sometime in the early ninth century during the
ʿAbbāsid period. In what follows, I shall first try to give a sense of the differences
by providing some examples. I will then try to characterize these differences. And
lastly I will provide some reasons, admittedly speculative, that might account for
these differences.
Before continuing, let me explain a few terms that I will be using. By exact
methods, I mean those mathematical and observational procedures that could
potentially lead to accurate results. By accurate results, I mean those that are in
accord with modern values. Now exact methods may or may not lead to accurate
results, depending on the underlying mathematical and observational tools that are
used. Results may be precise, i.e. to several digits, without being accurate, since
many of these digits could be spurious, i.e. the result of carrying out calculations
to a greater precision than supported by the original data or measurements. In or-
der to determine accuracy, one needs to engage in testing, i.e. checking received
values by some means to determine their accord with newer observations or theo-
ries. I distinguish between confirmation of earlier parameters or results that leads
to the acceptance of a received value, and the testing of parameters or results that
may or may not lead to the revision of those values. (I’ll have more to say about
this later.)
Let us take as our first example the measurement of the size of the Earth.
There is a heroic story that is well-known in the secondary literature about the
early measurements of the Earth. Eratosthenes (3rd c. BCE), head of the library of
Alexandria, is said by Cleomedes (1st c. BCE) to have measured the size of the
Earth using a simple but effective means (see Fig. 1). This consisted of taking a
known distance along a meridian in linear distance, finding its equivalent angular
distance, and then setting up a proportion that would yield the meridional circum-
ference. Eratosthenes is said to have taken the linear distance between Alexandria
and Syene (modern day Aswan) to be 5,000 stades, and he found the angular dis-
tance to be 1/50 of a complete circle. In addition, Eratosthenes evidently made the
following assumptions:
(a) Syene is on the tropic of Cancer, so there would be no shadow cast by the Sun
at noon on the day of the summer solstice.
(b) The Sun is at an infinite distance, so all its rays are parallel.
(c) Alexandria and Syene are on the same meridian.
122
Islamic Reactions to Ptolemy’s Imprecisions 45
Now all three assumptions are false; the effect of (b) is negligible, but (a) and
(c) could cause some distortion. But of more effect on the accuracy of the final re-
sult are the “observations” of 5,000 stades and 1/50 of a circle. Now the roundness
of these numbers, as well as the final result of 250,000 stades, immediately puts
one (or should put one) on guard. These numbers are just too nice. But let’s give
Eratosthenes the benefit of the doubt. The 5,000 stades could be rounded from
some value close to 5,000 (and given the uncertainties involved this might be rea-
sonable), and the 1/50 is said to have been from an observation of a shadow cast in
a bowl at the summer solstice. But several modern authors have cast doubt on
whether these numbers were the result of actual observations. R.R. Newton, for
example, proposed that the 1/50 was calculated based on latitude differences, or
more likely on equinoctial noontime shadow differences, between Alexandria and
Syene (Newton 1980, p. 384). And others have pointed out that a survey of linear
distance between Alexandria and Syene would have been difficult to attain in an-
tiquity to any degree of accuracy and that Eratosthenes was probably relying on
travelers’ reports (Dutka 1993, p. 62).
Other reports we have of Greek values for the Earth’s circumference confirm
the sense that we are dealing with “guesstimates” of various sorts (see Table 1).
Besides the obviously rounded numbers, the post-Aristotle values are divisible by
the standard Babylonian base 60. The one exception that proves the rule is the
value that comes out of Eratosthenes’ reported observations, namely 250,000,
which was changed to 252,000 (perhaps by Eratosthenes himself?) in order to be
divisible by 60.
123
46 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
Table 1 Greek values for the circumference of the Earth (cf. Dutka 1993)
124
Islamic Reactions to Ptolemy’s Imprecisions 47
simply taking the latitude difference of two Syrian cities, Raqqa and Palmyra
(assumed on the same meridian) with Ptolemaic latitudes of 35°20′ and 34°,
respectively. (The modern values are 35°58′ and 34°35′; in actuality, Raqqa is
about 45′ east of Palmyra.) Since the Ptolemaic distance was given as 90 Roman
miles, this did more or less confirm the Ptolemaic value of 66 ⅔ miles/meridian
degree or 180,000 stades for the Earth’s circumference. (Note this is based upon a
Roman mile of 7.5 Ptolemaic stades rather than the 8 Attic stades presumably used
by Eratosthenes; see above.) What is interesting about this story is that Maʾmūn
seems not to have been happy with this “confirmation,” perhaps because he was,
correctly, not convinced that his astronomers knew the exact length of a Roman
mile. Maʾmūn’s reaction, judging from a number of reports, was then to order a
scientific expedition to find a meridian degree by means of a survey. A group was
sent to the Plain of Sinjār in upper Mesopotamia. (The Sinjār area is located in the
2
northwestern part of Iraq and constitutes approximately 2,250 km of a flat plain.
Sinjār Mountain (1,460 m height) is the major geomorphological feature in the
area.) The method we find described in Ibn Yūnus (d. 1009 CE) is instructive.
Two groups, one going due north, the other due south, laid out survey lines using
long ropes until the Sun’s altitude descended or ascended one degree. The two
groups then came back to the starting point and compared notes and arrived at an
average figure of 56 Arabian miles. (There are other reports giving slightly differ-
ent numbers.) Since we know that each of these miles was 4,000 cubits, and we
also know that the cubit used at the time of Maʾmūn was approximately 49 cm,
Carlo Nallino in the early 1900s concluded that the Maʾmūnī value for the circum-
ference of the Earth was within a few hundred kilometers (off by less than 1%). It
is instructive to compare this with a recent attempt by the MIT physicist Phillip
Morrison and his wife Phyllis Morrison to measure a meridian line along
370 miles of US 183, running between Nebraska and Kansas. Taking two observa-
tions of Antares at the beginning and end of the trip and using the car’s odometer
to measure distance, they came up with a circumference of 26,500 statute miles,
off by about 6% (actual value 24,900) (as reported by Dutka 1993, p. 64).
Here we can usefully distinguish, I believe, between the conventionalist at-
tempt by Muḥammad ibn Mūsā to confirm the Ptolemaic value with Maʾmūn’s
demand to test that value. We can also say that Muḥammad was using an ap-
proach not all that different from what seems to have occurred rather frequently in
antiquity—taking a received value and then using some observation or other
means to confirm that it was approximately correct without seeking in any way to
modify it. What seems new here is that a patron, in this case representing the state,
is intervening to demand observational accuracy. While state patronage of science
was certainly not unprecedented (one thinks of the Ptolemies and several Sasanian
rulers not to mention Babylonian and Assyrian kings), this type of personal inter-
vention by Maʾmūn as reported in contemporary accounts does seem to mark a
new departure (Langermann 1985). We will return to this below.
125
48 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
The Ptolemaic length for the tropical year, as well as others reported from anti-
quity, were clearly at variance with what was observed in the ninth century; the
problem was how to interpret these conflicting values. Ptolemy’s (and most likely
Hipparchus’s) length for a tropical year (365d5h55m12s) is about 6 min per year too
long, so over the 300 years between Ptolemy and Hipparchus there would have
been almost a 30-h disparity between, say, a predicted vernal equinox by Hip-
parchus for Ptolemy’s time and an actual observation made by Ptolemy himself.
And indeed Ptolemy’s reports of the times of equinoxes and summer solstices are
about a day later than they should have been, which is one of the bases for saying
that he faked his observations in order to keep Hipparchus’s value. By the time we
reach the ninth century, this discrepancy would have reached well over 4 days! Of
course, Maʾmūn’s astronomers and Muḥammad ibn Jābir al-Battānī (d. 929 CE)
had a longer baseline to work from than did Ptolemy, so it would be surprising,
not to say shocking, if they hadn’t modified Ptolemy’s length for the tropical year.
But let us look at this another way. Ptolemy decided not to tamper with the year he
had inherited from Hipparchus, despite the fact that there would have been a dis-
crepancy of more than a day. The Islamic astronomers of the ninth century had, in
some ways, a more difficult problem to confront. How were they to understand the
values they had inherited from the Ancients? Were they simply better observers
than their predecessors or were there actual changes that had occurred in the inter-
vening years in the motion of the Sun and, perhaps, in that of the stars as well that
might account for the observed variations?
Thābit ibn Qurra (d. 901 CE) wrote his friend and collaborator Isḥāq ibn
Ḥunayn asking him if he knew of a solar observation between the time of Ptolemy
and Maʾmūn. (See Ragep 1996 for details on this (esp. pp. 282–283) and on what
follows in this section.) There are several things at work here. Presumably, he
wanted to check how well Ptolemy’s tables would predict this intermediate posi-
tion of the Sun, which might indicate whether changes in the Sun’s motion and/or
parameters had occurred in the years since Ptolemy. But I suspect he also wanted
to ascertain whether this new observation might give a clue regarding the variation
in year-lengths, which might then be coordinated with the varying precessional
rates reported by Ptolemy and Maʾmūn’s astronomers (1°/100 years for the former,
1°/66 years for the latter). Briefly, the reported differences in year-lengths could
be the result of a speeding up of the rate of precession, here interpreted to mean a
variable speed of the eighth orb containing the fixed stars that would be transmit-
ted to the solar orbs, causing the Sun to reach the vernal equinox sooner than it
would otherwise and thus resulting in a variation in the tropical year (see Fig. 2).
Given this possibility, Battānī in his Zīj (astronomical handbook) entertains
the idea that variable precession (whether or not connected with an oscillatory
126
Islamic Reactions to Ptolemy’s Imprecisions 49
Fig. 2 A continuous speeding up (by trepidation or some other means) of the motion of the
Eighth/Fixed Star Orb is here transmitted to the Sun’s orbs, causing the Sun to reach the fixed
vernal equinox sooner than it would with a simple monotonic precession. Battānī claims this might
explain the differences in year-lengths reported by the ancients and early Islamic astronomers
trepidation motion) could explain the observations. Here we may turn to Tables 2
and 3 for an indication of what Battānī had in mind. Table 2 lists the tropical year
lengths (and corresponding solar speeds) from the ancients and his own observa-
tions. (Note the odd value for Hipparchus, which is at variance with the normal
127
50 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
reading from the Almagest; Battānī, who elsewhere indicates that Ptolemy used
the same year length as Hipparchus, may here be fudging the figures to indicate a
steadily decreasing year-length.) Table 3 represents my reconstruction of the ef-
fect of variable precession, following Battānī’s suggestion and using his year-
length and reported precessional difference between him and Ptolemy to calculate
the earlier values. Note the close relationship between the predicted year-lengths
in Table 3 and the reported ones in Table 2.
Despite noting this correlation between an increasing rate of precession and an
increased speed of the Sun (and thus a decreasing length of the tropical year), Bat-
tānī indicates his dilemma and that of the first generations of Islamic astronomers:
how could he know whether Ptolemy’s values were correct or whether Ptolemy
was simply a bad observer and/or whether he was using an instrument that had
been miscalibrated or had warped over time. So Battānī must leave the matter as
undecided, with the hope that what he calls “true reality” will be attained over
time. By the thirteenth century, most eastern Islamic astronomers, with several
hundred years of reliable data behind them, were able to conclude that Ptolemy’s
year-length was bogus and that variable precession to account for the ancient val-
ues was unnecessary (Ragep 1993, v. 2, p. 396).
A third example concerns Ptolemy’s value for the ecliptic, 23°51′20″, which has
always been a bit mysterious inasmuch as it is off by almost 11 min. In a recent ar-
ticle, Alexander Jones provides us with a plausible and compelling argument for
the origins of this number as well as another indication of Ptolemy’s observa-
tional procedures (Jones 2002b). Jones shows that with a simple calculation
one can get this result, or one very close to it, from a rounded value for the lati-
tude of Alexandria of 31° (based upon an equinoctial shadow ratio of 3:5), the
5,000-stade distance of Alexandria to Syene (presumed on the Tropic of Cancer),
128
Islamic Reactions to Ptolemy’s Imprecisions 51
and a circumference of the Earth of 252,000 stades. The ratio of the arc between
the tropics, i.e. 47°42′40″, and 360° then translates by continued fractions into the
enigmatic ratio 11/83 that is given by Ptolemy. Again we see the curious way in
which Ptolemy has taken a Hellenistic value (probably from Eratosthenes) with
evidently little attempt to verify it or its underlying parameters. (It is worth noting
that Ptolemy’s own latitude value for his hometown of Alexandria (30°58′),
apparently taken from Eratosthenes’ rather crude methods of equinoctial shadow
ratios, is off by a quarter degree.)
Moving into the ninth century, we again have a familiar tale. Maʾmūn’s astrono-
mers arrived at a figure of 23°35′, which is accurate to about half a minute. But
again there was confusion: was their value the correct one, allowing them to safely
discard Ptolemy’s, or had the obliquity actually been changing? In point of fact,
the obliquity had been changing, but not so drastically as implied by Ptolemy’s
figure. There are reports of early attempts to deal with this by postulating an addi-
tional orb that would eventually lead to the obliteration of the obliquity entirely,
leading to catastrophe in the opinions of some because of the subsequent lack of
seasons. By the tenth century, there began to appear a number of creative attempts
to deal both with a changing obliquity and a changing rate of precession, in part,
no doubt, because early models meant to deal with a changing obliquity probably
were seen (correctly) as interfering with the precessional rate (Ragep 1993, v. 2,
pp. 396–408). While these attempts to provide models that would explain both the
ancient and Islamic values for the obliquity were progressing apace, there were
quite a few new measurements of the obliquity as we can see from Abū al-Rayḥān
al-Bīrūnī’s (d. ca. 1050) reports presented in Table 4 (al-Bīrūnī 1954–1956, v. 1,
pp. 361–368). Note that most of these values are accurate to within a minute.
(Bīrūnī himself notes that the two outliers, Abū al-Faḍl ibn al-ʿAmīd and Khujandī,
were due to instrumental error.)
Bīrūnī describes the ecliptic ring needed to make the observations and remarks
that it needs to be large enough in order to inscribe divisions in minutes. We also
have a report from Ibn Sīnā (Avicenna; d. 1037), who gives a much less detailed
account of earlier work in the appendix to his own Almagest that is part of his
monumental work, al-Shifāʾ. There he merely reports that an observation of 23°34′
had been made after Maʾmūn’s time. But then Ibn Sīnā gives his own observation
to the nearest half minute, namely 23°33½′. This is a remarkably good value
inasmuch as the estimate using modern tools gives 23°33′53″ for 1030. We have
another report by Ibn Sīnā’s long-term collaborator, ʿAbd al-Wāḥid al-Jūzjānī,
who, writing after Ibn Sīnā’s death, tells us that in Isfahan he obtained a value of
23°33′40″, which for 1040 would have been correct to within 8 or 9 s (al-Jūzjānī,
Khilāṣ kayfiyyat tarkīb al-aflāk, Mashhad MS Āstān-i Quds 392 (=Mashhad
5593), p. 96). How they obtained such astonishing accuracy is not entirely clear,
since they have not left us with detailed observational notes. We do, though, know
that Ibn Sīnā was very interested in observations and invented an innovative
observing device of some sophistication (Wiedemann and Juynboll 1927). It is
also worth mentioning here that Ibn Sīnā claimed to have observed a Venus transit
129
52 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
and also found the longitude distance between Jurjān and Baghdad to be 9°20′
[modern: 10°3′; traditional: 8°] (Ragep and Ragep 2004, p. 10). Although Bīrūnī
did not think much of Ibn Sīnā’s astronomical abilities, it is interesting that Bīrūnī
basically ended up “confirming” the Maʾmūnī observations, whereas Ibn Sīnā and
his circle seem to have embarked upon a serious observing program to test, and
modify, previous results. Whether the remarkably accurate values they came up
with are a matter of accident or due to innovative observational techniques remains a
matter of conjecture. (It is worth noting that although the normal human visual
acuity is limited to 1 min of arc, it is possible under certain circumstances involv-
ing the observation of a moving object to become hyperacute, with the capability
to distinguish even 5 s of arc (Buchwald 2006, pp. 620–621)).
130
Islamic Reactions to Ptolemy’s Imprecisions 53
Let us look a bit more closely at the distinction I am trying to make between con-
firming and testing. (For the following, I am much indebted to Sabra 1968.) One
often finds derived forms of the verb iʿtabara to indicate something like testing in
the sense of checking whether a received value or parameter is correct; this is what
Bīrūnī uses when saying that he wishes to test his predecessors’ values for the
obliquity. We also find another word, imtiḥān, which is used in the names of some
zījes such as the Mumtaḥan Zīj of the early ʿAbbāsid astronomer Yaḥya ibn Abī
Manṣūr, and also in works that are meant to weed out incompetents, such as al-
Qabīṣī’s (10th c.) Risāla fī imtiḥān al-munajimīn (treatise on testing the astrolo-
gers). Now Ptolemy, of course, also uses the idea of testing in various places in the
Almagest. For example, in Almagest VII.1 he discusses the question of whether all
stars or only those along the zodiac participate in the precessional motion. He pro-
poses testing this by comparing his stellar observations with those of Hipparchus.
Now the word used for comparison is σύγκρισις and for test πεῖρα. When the Al-
magest was first translated into Arabic by al-Ḥajjāj ibn Maṭar (early ninth cen-
tury), he used iʿtibār for σύγκρισις and tajriba for πεῖρα. Later, in the second half
of the ninth century, Isḥāq b. Ḥunayn would translate σύγκρισις as muqāyasa and
πεῖρα as al-miḥna wa-ʾl-iʿtibār thus using two words for one. Since Isḥāq some-
times uses iʿtibār to translate σύγκρισις, A.I. Sabra has suggested that he may
well have been trying to capture the idea of testing values over a longer interval by
using the two words together. There are many examples in Islamic astronomy of
the use of the conjoined al-miḥna wa-ʾl-iʿtibār or of one or the other alone to indi-
cate testing. And Sabra has argued that iʿtibār from an astronomical context was
used by Ibn al-Haytham for his idea of testing optical theories in his Kitāb al-
manāẓir. (Note that the Latin translator of this work used experimentum for
iʿtibār.)
Let me suggest that something more has been added in the translation process.
When Isḥāq rendered πεῖρα as al-miḥna wa-ʾl-iʿtibār, he may well have meant to
convey a stronger form of testing, one that was not simply a confirmation. Indeed,
the word miḥna had attained a certain notoriety in the ninth century, since it was
the inquisitory procedure used during the reign of the Caliph al-Maʾmūn to test
adherence to the imposed state dogma of the createdness of the Qurʾān. Isḥāq was
not translating in a vacuum. He was certainly aware that the author of Fī sanat al-
shams believed that Ptolemy’s πεῖρα for the solar year was suspect (see above).
And his collaborator Thābit ibn Qurra was, as we have seen, suspicious as well.
Thus this linguistic turn of phrase could well have reflected what had already hap-
pened in the first half of the ninth century, a felt need to critically test Ptolemy’s
parameters.
But what was the basis of this “need”? Given the many examples we have in
Greek astronomy of confirmation rather than testing, I think we can safely say that
there is nothing natural about testing with the intention to modify what has been
131
54 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
received. Thomas Kuhn long ago made a persuasive case for the normalness of
working within the paradigms of normal science, and though Kuhn did not neces-
sarily have the safeguarding of parameters in mind, one can certainly understand
the reluctance to change established values, especially something as entrenched as
the length of the year. What seems to me in need of explanation are the many ex-
amples in early Islamic astronomy that point to a process not of confirming but of
critical testing, with an intention and methodology that could result in revisions,
sometimes drastic, to the received and heretofore accepted values.
Let us once again look at the case of measuring the Earth. Recall that
Muḥammad ibn Mūsā seems to have followed the tried and true method of con-
firming earlier values in the way he went about using Ptolemy’s Geography to
show that Ptolemy’s value was correct. But note the intervention of Maʾmūn, who
exhibited a healthy skepticism and called for a new, indeed revolutionary ap-
proach to the problem—he insisted upon each value being independently derived
using reproducible methods that resulted in testable values. And from a modern
perspective, the results are very good indeed.
Now the question arises: what could possibly have motivated Maʾmūn? Of
course in the case of the size of the Earth, the obvious answer might be that he
wanted to be able to have a basis for making maps of his vast empire, which was
growing all the time. But to me this practical argument, though appealing, lacks a
certain sufficiency. Didn’t any ruler before Maʾmūn want a good value for the size
of the Earth, going back to the Ptolemies and continuing through to the Romans,
the Persians and many others? And this does not serve to explain the reports that
show Maʾmūn riding his astronomers to produce better results on a whole range of
observations (Langermann 1985). My own preference would be to see this as a
kind of cultural transformation, one of many, that resulted from the appropriation
of Greek science into Islam. Part of this transformation involved a much greater
number of people involved in the enterprise, as is evidenced by Bīrūnī’s list of ob-
servations of the obliquity. One can well sympathize with Ptolemy, who after all
was a pioneer in many ways without a huge body of good observations at his dis-
posal. But I think he also inherited an ambivalence about the phenomena that
might well have stymied an excessive demand for accuracy. Though exactly what
Ptolemy’s philosophical and metaphysical stances may have been regarding ulti-
mate reality is unclear, the Platonist strand at the time was strong, and Ptolemy
may well have had to contend with attitudes such as we find in Proclus
(4th c. CE):
The great Plato, my friend, expects the true philosopher at least to say goodbye to the
senses and the whole of wandering substance and to transfer astronomy above the heavens
and to study there slowness-itself and speed-itself in true number. But you seem to me to
lead us down from those contemplations to these periods in the heavens and to the
observations of those clever at astronomy and to the hypotheses they devised from these,
[hypotheses] which Aristarchuses and Hipparchuses and Ptolemies and such-like people
are used to babbling about. For you desire indeed to hear also the doctrines of these men,
132
Islamic Reactions to Ptolemy’s Imprecisions 55
in your eagerness to leave, so far as possible, nothing uninvestigated of what has been
discovered by the ancients in the inquiry into the universe. (Proclus, Hypotyposis;
translation by Lloyd 1978, p. 207, who also provides the Greek text.)
What would the early Muslims have made of all this? I think, and here I must
speculate, that they would have been profoundly puzzled. The religion of Islam
reemphasized the concept of monotheism (tawḥīd) and the nobility of the created
world. Thus in theory a Muslim so inclined could (some would say should) try to
understand that world and its Maker’s intentions. For a Platonist, this is a fool’s
errand, since what we experience through our senses is definitely not the Real.
Furthermore Islamic law by its very nature emphasized the here and now to a re-
markable extent despite the strong Islamic belief in the afterlife. How might these
tendencies have influenced the course of Islamic science? In at least three ways.
On the one hand, the earliest Islamic theological writings indicate an extensive
interest in the material world and the type of world that would be compatible with
God’s will and intentions (Dhanani 1994). Another way in which interest in the
mundane world could have been encouraged was in the demand for evidence
brought by Islamic jurisprudence (uṣūl al-fiqh) and by the requirements needed to
establish correct historical reconstructions to divine the Prophet’s actual sayings
and deeds (the ḥadīth). The third is the effect these religious aspects had on Helle-
nistic philosophy and philosophers in Islam. Though they were arch rivals, the
mutakallims (theologians) and falāsifa (Hellenized philosophers) grudgingly
acknowledged the presence of one another and reacted to each other’s doctrines.
One of the ways that this manifested itself was in the striking transformation of
what we can call the philosophy of science of Islamic philosophers. It has been
customary to refer to such people, such as al-Kindī, al-Fārābī and Ibn Sīnā
(Avicenna), as neo-Platonists. But these are very odd neo-Platonists. As should be
clear from Ibn Sīnā, he had more than a passing interest in the phenomenal world
held in such low esteem by the neo-Platonists of late antiquity. And even when
those neo-Platonists wrote on astronomy, as Proclus did in his Hypotyposis, we
can not help but notice his skepticism (as above), something one rarely finds in the
philosophers of Islam. The insistence by Islamic philosophers and astronomers on
the importance of empirical studies, manifested, for example, in Ibn Sīnā’s strik-
ing observational program and in Fārābī’s studies of contemporary musical prac-
tice, also bespeak a shift from late antiquity.
Could this shift in attitude account for Islamic astronomical exactitude? Here
again we can only speculate since it is difficult to establish the relationship be-
tween ideological tendencies and actual practice. And we need to keep in mind
that critical testing was episodic not universal in Islamic astronomy. Even Bīrūnī
would seem to have succumbed to bouts of “confirmationism.” And in the thir-
teenth century it is striking that no less a personage than Quṭb al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī
was skeptical about the Maʾmūnī value for the Earth’s circumference and thought
it better to return to the authority of the Ancients (Ragep 1993, v. 2, pp. 509–510).
133
56 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
But the ongoing interest in observations and the ever increasing size of the instru-
ments to make those observations—eventually culminating in the creation of the
large-scale observatory—were often justified in terms of glorifying God’s creation
(Ragep 2001). If my suspicions are correct, it would seem that one of the unexpected
consequences of the transplantation of ancient astronomy into Islamic soil was the
subtle yet potent effect of monotheistic creationism in encouraging the astronomer
to pay close attention to the sensual, phenomenal, and mundane world.
134
Islamic Reactions to Ptolemy’s Imprecisions 57
Bibliography
al-Bīrūnī, Abū Rayḥān Muḥammad ibn Aḥmad. 1954-1956. al-Qānūn al-Masʿūdī. 3 vols.
Hyderabad: Dāʾirat al-maʿārif al-ʿUthmāniyya.
Dhanani, A. 1994. The Physical Theory of Kalām: Atoms, Space, and Void in Basrian Muʿtazilī
Cosmology. Leiden: E.J. Brill.
Dutka, J. 1993. “Eratosthenes’ Measurement of the Earth Reconsidered”. Archive for History of
Exact Sciences 46. 55-66.
Engels, D. 1985. “The Length of Eratosthenes’ Stade”. The American Journal of Philology 106.
298-311.
Ibn al-Haytham, al-Ḥasan. 1971. al-Shukūk ʿalā Baṭlamyūs. Edited by A. I. Sabra and N.
Shehaby. Cairo: Dār al-kutub. [2nd ed., Cairo 1996.]
Jones, A. 2002. “Eratosthenes, Hipparchus, and the Obliquity of the Ecliptic”. Journal for the
History of Astronomy 33. 15-19.
King, D. A. 2000. “Too Many Cooks... A New Account of the Earliest Muslim Geodetic
Measurements”. Suhayl 1. 207-241.
Langermann, Y. T. 1985. “The Book of Bodies and Distances of Ḥabash al-Ḥāsib”. Centaurus
28. 108-128.
58 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
Lloyd, G. E. R. 1978. “Saving the Appearances”. Classical Quarterly NS 28. 202-222. Reprinted
with new introduction in G. E. R. Lloyd. 1991. Methods and Problems in Greek Science.
Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. 248-277.
Morelon, R. 1987. Thābit ibn Qurra: Œuvres d’astronomie. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.
Ragep, F. J. 1993. Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī’s Memoir on Astronomy (al-Tadhkira fī ʿilm al-hayʾa). 2
vols. New York: Springer.
Ragep, F. J. 1996. “Al-Battānī, Cosmology, and the Early History of Trepidation in Islam”. In
From Baghdad to Barcelona. Essays on the History of the Islamic Exact Sciences in Honour of
Prof. Juan Vernet. J. Casulleras and J. Samsó, eds. Barcelona: Universidad de Barcelona.
Facultad de Filología. 267-298.
Ragep, F. J., and S. P. Ragep. 2004. “The Astronomical and Cosmological Works of Ibn Sīnā:
Some Preliminary Remarks”. In Sciences, techniques et instruments dans le monde iranien (Xe–
XIXe siècle). N. Pourjavady et Ž. Vesel, eds. Tehran: Presses Universitaires d’Iran and l’Institut
Français de recherche en Iran. 3–15.
Sabra, A. I. 1998. “Configuring the Universe: Aporetic, Problem Solving, and Kinematic
Modeling as Themes of Arabic Astronomy”. Perspectives in Science 6. 288-330.
Wiedemann, E., and Th. W. Juynboll. 1927. “Avicennas Schrift über ein von ihm ersonnenes
Beobachtungsinstrument”. Acta orientalia 11/5. 81-167. Reprinted in E. Wiedemann. 1984.
Gesammelte Schriften zur arabisch-islamischen Wissenschaftsgeschichte. 3 vols. Frankfurt am
Main: Institut für Geschichte der Arabisch-Islamischen Wissenschaften. Vol. 2. 1117-1203.
Section II
F. Jamil Ragep
162
circumference going through the produces oscillation on a chord)
centre of the other, one circle rotating
twice as fast as the other to produce
rectilinear oscillation of a given point
Three-sphere Three concentric spheres with Intended to account for Ptolemaic Spherical version (Saliba and Kennedy) 659/1261
curvilinear different axes, one inside the other, motions needing curvilinear Spherical version with oblique axes and
version (figs 7.6 rotating uniformly oscillation on a great circle arc equal radii (Di Bono, 136)
and 7.7) (mostly works as intended but
with a minor distortion)
Two-sphere Truncated version of the full three- For certain astronomical models ca. 1400
curvilinear sphere curvilinear version (used by Ibn Naḥmias and later
version (fig. 8.4) Copernicus)
* It was often referred to as such in astronomical texts after Ṭūsī. He himself does not explicitly use this term to refer to the device although it is implied in the
terminology he uses in the Tadhkira, as distinct from the Ḥall (see below).
Sources: Mario Di Bono, “Copernicus, Amico, Fracastoro, and Ṭūsī’s Device: Observations on the Use and Transmission of a Model,” Journal for the History of Astronomy 26,
no. 2 (1995): 133-54; F. Jamil Ragep, Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī’s Memoir on Astronomy (al-Tadhkira fī ʿilm al-hayʾa) (New York: Springer-Verlag, 1993), vol. 2, 427-56; George Saliba
and Edward S. Kennedy, “The Spherical Case of the Tūsī Couple,” Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 1, no. 2 (1991): 285-91.
64
From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-Couple 65
confusion, about what exactly the Ṭūsī-couple is. This confusion, in turn,
has made it difficult to trace transmission. So a quick historical overview
is in order.2
M at h e m at i c a l R e c t i l i n e a r V e r s i o n
The first version of the Ṭūsī-couple was announced by Naṣīr al-Dīn al-
Ṭūsī in a Persian astronomical treatise entitled Risālah-i Muʿīniyya
(Muʿīniyya Treatise), the first version of which was completed on
Thursday, 2 Rajab 632 (22 March 1235).3 Dedicated to the son of the
Ismāʿīlī governor of Qūhistān, in the eastern part of modern Iran, the
treatise is a typical hayʾa (cosmographical) work, one that provides a sci-
entifically based cosmology covering both the celestial and terrestrial
regions. But in presenting the Ptolemaic configuration of the Moon’s
orbs and their motions, Ṭūsī notes that the motion of the epicycle centre
on the deferent is variable, which is inadmissible according to an ac-
cepted rule of celestial physics, namely that all individual motions of
orbs in the celestial realm should be uniform. He goes on to say, “This is
a serious doubt with regard to this account [of the model], and as yet no
practitioner of the science has ventured anything. Or, if anyone has, it
has not reached us.” But “there is an elegant way to solve this doubt but
it would be inappropriate to introduce it into this short treatise.” He
then teasingly turns to his patron: “If at some other time the blessed
temper of the Prince of Iran, may God multiply his glory, would be so
pleased to pursue this problem, concerning that matter a treatment will
be forthcoming.” In the chapter on the upper planets and Venus, as well
as the one on Mercury, he makes a similar claim, namely that he has a
solution that will be presented later. In addition to the problem of the
irregular motion of the deferent (sometimes referred to as the “equant
problem,” although it is somewhat different for the Moon), Ṭūsī brings
up another “doubt” or difficulty, namely that pertaining to motion in
latitude – that is, north or south of the ecliptic. Claudius Ptolemy had
rather complex models in his Almagest and Planetary Hypotheses that gen-
erated quite a bit of discussion among Islamic astronomers. One of
these was Abū ʿAlī al-Ḥasan ibn al-Haytham (d. ca. 430/1040), who ob-
jected to the lack of physical movers for these models and provided his
own in a treatise that is currently not extant. However, Ṭūsī refers to it in
the Muʿīniyya and also notes that it is not entirely satisfactory; but as with
his purported models for longitude, he eschews any details.4
Since Ṭūsī claims to have an elegant solution, one assumes that he
would have presented it to his patron in short order. But, as we shall see,
he waited almost ten years to present his new models. One clue to the
163
66 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
delay could well be overoptimism on the part of the young Naṣīr al-Dīn;
he claimed in the Muʿīniyya that he had solutions for all the planets, but
as it turned out he was never able to solve the complexities of Mercury.
Indeed, as an older man many years later, he was to admit this setback in
his Al-Tadhkira fī ʿilm al-hayʾa (Memoir on the Science of Astronomy):
“As for Mercury, it has not yet been possible for me to conceive how it
should be done.”5
The partial solution occurs in a short treatise that was again dedicated
to his patron’s son, Muʿīn al-Dīn. This work has come to us with a variety
of names: Dhayl-i Muʿīniyya (Appendix to the Muʿīniyya [Treatise]),
Ḥall-i mushkilāt-i Muʿīniyya (Solution to the Difficulties of the Muʿīniyya),
Sharḥ-i Muʿīniyya (Commentary on the Muʿīniyya), and so on.6 In all cas-
es of which I know, the work is explicitly tied to Risālah-i Muʿīniyya, lead-
ing one to assume that it must have been written a short time after the
treatise to which it is appended. This assumption, however, turns out
not to be correct. Thanks to the recent discovery in Tashkent of a manu-
script witness of the Dhayl-i Muʿīniyya with a dated colophon, we can
now date this treatise, as well as the first appearance of the Ṭūsī-couple,
to 643/1245: “The treatise is completed. The author, may God elevate
his stature on the ascents to the Divine, completed its composition dur-
ing the first part of Jamādā II, 643 of the Hijra [i.e., late October
1245], within the town of Tūn in the garden known as Bāgh Barakah.”7
As we can infer from the colophon, Ṭūsī was still in the employ of the
Ismāʿīlī rulers of Qūhistān in southern Khurāsān. Tūn, present-day
Firdaws, lay some eighty kilometres (or fifty miles) west-north-west of
the main town of the region, Qāʾin, which was the primary regional
capital of the Ismāʿīlīs.8
It clearly took Naṣīr al-Dīn longer than he anticipated to reach a solu-
tion, and even then it was not complete by any means. This “first ver-
sion” of the Ṭūsī-couple consisted of a device composed of two uniformly
rotating circles that could produce oscillating straight-line motion in a
plane between two points. One of these two circles was twice as large as
the second, the smaller one being inside the larger one and tangent at a
point (see figure 7.1). The rotation of the smaller circle was twice that
of the larger one. Although mathematically speaking the production of
an oscillating point on a straight line could also be produced by the
small circle “rolling” inside the larger, Ṭūsī is explicit that the larger cir-
cle “carries” (mī bard) the smaller one. The reason for this is that Ṭūsī
will transform these circles into the equators of solid orbs rotating in the
celestial realm, where any penetration of one solid body by another is
expressly forbidden.9 The transformation into solid orbs, the “physical-
ized rectilinear version,” is shown in figure 7.2. Note that one needs a
164
From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-Couple 67
third orb, what he calls the “enclosing sphere [muḥṭīa] for the epicycle,”
in order not to disrupt the epicycle; this third orb keeps D aligned with
C and A. More on this later when I discuss Nicole Oresme.
Ṭūsī then proceeds to use the device to construct his alternative to
Ptolemy’s lunar model. It will be instructive, and important for tracing
transmission, to compare this model from the Ḥall with the model Ṭūsī
would present in Al-Tadhkira fī ʿilm al-hayʾa, which, unlike the Muʿīniyya
and the Ḥall, was written in Arabic rather than Persian. The first version
of the Tadhkira was completed in 659/1261 when Ṭūsī was in the employ
of his new patrons, the Mongol Īlkhānid conquerors of Iran. Table. 7.2
provides a summary.
In the Tadhkira, Ṭūsī has made a number of changes in the lunar model
that he first presented in the Ḥall. The most obvious is the change in ter-
minology: “the dirigent orb” (mudīr) has now become the “large sphere,”
and the “epicycle’s deferent orb” (ḥāmil) has been renamed the “small
sphere.” This change is most likely due to the confusion resulting from
using the terms “dirigent” and “deferent,” which are employed for other
parts of the planetary models, to also designate the two outer spheres
165
68 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
166
From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-Couple 69
Table 7.2 Ṭūsī’s lunar models from the Ḥall and the Tadhkira
Ḥall Tadhkira
Note: Motion in the sequence (s) or countersequence (cs) of the signs is determined by the orb’s
apogee point.
7.3 Lunar model from the Ḥall, showing six orbs in four different positions.
167
70 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
7.4 Lunar model from the Tadhkira, showing seven orbs in four different
positions.
truism in the history of science, that such devices and models take time
to evolve and be perfected. A sudden appearance of a complete and
perfected theory or model should make us wary of claims of no trans-
mission or influence.
Two-Equal-Circle Version
168
From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-Couple 71
But before the final curvilinear version was introduced in the Tadhkira
in 1261, it evolved slowly over a considerable period of Ṭūsī’s lifetime. In
the Muʿīniyya, when discussing the models for latitude, Ṭūsī notes that
Ibn al-Haytham had dealt with latitude in a treatise and gives a brief
sketch of his theory. But he finds this solution lacking, and criticizes it
without going into details since “this [i.e., the Muʿīniyya] is not the place
to discuss it.” Despite this criticism, Ṭūsī does not claim to have a solu-
tion for the problem of latitude, unlike the case of the longitudinal mo-
tions of the Moon and planets.11 In the Ḥall, Ṭūsī refrains from the
earlier criticism of Ibn al-Haytham and instead presents the latter’s
model for latitude. Basically, this is an adaptation of the Eudoxan system
of homocentric orbs, described in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, applied to
Ptolemy’s latitude models, which used motion on small circles to pro-
duce latitudinal variation.12 It is curious that Ṭūsī offers no model of his
own, nor does he note, as he does later in the Tadhkira, that motions in
circles will produce not only latitudinal variations but also unwanted
longitudinal changes.
But a little over a year later, on 5 Shawwāl 644 (13 February 1247), to
be exact, Ṭūsī published a sketch of another version of his couple that
was meant to resolve some of the difficulties of Ptolemy’s latitude mod-
els.13 This version was presented in the context of his discussion of these
models in book 13 of his Taḥrīr al-Majisṭī (Recension of the Almagest).
After presenting a summary of Ptolemy’s latitude model for the planets,
and his special pleading regarding the complicated nature of these
models, which include the endpoints of the epicycle diameters rotating
on small circles to produce latitude in a northerly or southerly direc-
tion,14 Ṭūsī provides the following comment:
I say: this discussion is external to the discipline (ṣināʿa) [201b] and is not per-
suasive for this matter. For it is necessary for a practitioner of this discipline to
establish circles and bodies having uniform motions according to an order and
arrangement [such that] from all of them [circles and bodies] these various per-
ceived motions will be constituted. For then these motions being on the circum-
ferences of the mentioned small circles, just as they result in the epicycle diameters
departing from the planes of the eccentrics in latitude northward and southward,
so too will they result in their departing from alignment with the centre of the
ecliptic, or from being parallel with diameters in the plane of the ecliptic with the
exact same longitude, through accession and recession in the exact same amount
of that latitude. And this is contrary to reality. And it is not possible to say that that
difference is perceptible in latitude but not perceptible in longitude since they
are equal in size and distance from the centre of the ecliptic.
169
72 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
Now, if the diameter of the small circle were made in the amount of the total
latitude in either direction, and one imagines that its centre moves on the cir-
cumference of another circle equal to it whose centre is in the plane of the ec-
centric in the amount of half the motion of the endpoint of the diameter of the
epicycle on the circumference of the first circle and opposite its direction, there
will occur a shift to the north and south in the amount of the latitude without
there occurring a forward or backward [motion] in longitude.
To show this, let AB be a section of the eccentric and GD be from the latitude
circle that passes through the endpoint of the diameter of the epicycle. And they
intersect at E. EZ EM are the total latitude in the two directions. And EH is half
of it in one of them. We draw about H with a distance EH a circle EZ and about
E with a distance HE a circle HTKL. We imagine the endpoint of the diameter of
the epicycle at point Z to move on circle EZ in direction G to B and the center H
to move on circle HTKL in the direction G to A with half that motion. Then it is
clear that when H traverses a quarter and reaches T, Z will traverse a half and
reach E. Then when H traverses another quarter and reaches K, Z will traverse
another half and reach M. And when H traverses a third quarter and reaches L,
Z will traverse another half and will reach E once again. And when H completes
a rotation, Z will return to its original place so that it will always oscillate in what
is between ZM on the line GD without inclining from it in directions AB. This is
the explanation of this method. However, it requires that the time the diameter
is in the north be equal to the time it is in the south; in reality, it is different from
that. As for what is said regarding its motion on the circumference of a circle
about a point that is not its centre, as stated by Ptolemy, this needs consideration
to verify it according to what has preceded. We now return to the book [i.e., the
Almagest].15
There are several things we can say about this device. First of all, as
Ṭūsī notes, it does not accurately model Ptolemy’s latitude theory since it
results in equal times in the north and in the south.16 Second, the mo-
tion of the epicycle endpoint is uniform with respect to the epicycle’s
mean apex, which again is contrary to what Ptolemy’s model requires.
Third, and more significant for our purposes, this model is actually a
slightly modified version of the rectilinear Ṭūsī-couple that was first pre-
sented in the Ḥall. The problem, however, is that the motion of the end-
point of the epicycle’s diameter is on a straight line, ZM, whereas the
necessary motion should be on a great circle arc. This problem is curi-
ous. Surely, Ṭūsī is aware that the motion in latitude should occur on the
surface of a sphere; why, then, does he have this rather stripped-down
version of his couple that can result only in rectilinear oscillation? The
answer, it seems, is that at this point he does not have a curvilinear ver-
sion. He is dissatisfied with Ptolemy’s small circles and also realizes that
170
From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-Couple 73
Ibn al-Haytham’s model does little more than provide a solid-sphere ba-
sis for the inadequate small circles, but all he has to offer is a kind of
vague notion that his couple might be modified to create the necessary
motion in latitude. He clearly is still in the thinking stage.
Ṭūsī does not in fact offer a true curvilinear version until almost fifteen
years later, during the first part of Dhū al-qaʿda 659 (September or
October 1261), at which time he publishes the first version of his Al-
Tadhkira fī ʿilm al-hayʾa. There, he puts forth a model consisting of three
additional orbs enclosing the epicycle that are meant to produce a cur-
vilinear oscillation that results in the motion in latitude (see figures 7.6
and 7.7).17 It is interesting that Ṭūsī presents this new model as a modifi-
cation of Ibn al-Haytham’s earlier attempt,18 which, as we have seen,
simply provides a physical basis for Ptolemy’s small circles using
171
74 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
There is another issue related to the rectilinear couple that may have a
bearing on tracing transmission. Quṭb al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī, one of Ṭūsī’s as-
sociates in Marāgha and subsequently one of the eminent philosophers
and scientists at Mongol courts in Tabrīz, remarks in his Al-Tuḥfa al-
shāhiyya fī al-hayʾa, written after Ṭūsī’s death in 684/1285, that “it is
172
From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-Couple 75
7.7 Polar view of the complete curvilinear version, showing the motion
of the endpoint of the diameter of the epicycle along a great circle arc.
173
76 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
174
From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-Couple 77
7.9 Motion of the endpoint of the diameter of the epicycle on a circular path
rather than a great circle arc.
Transmission to Byzantium
175
78 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
176
From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-Couple 79
Avner de Burgos
The Jewish philosopher and polemicist Avner de Burgos (ca. 1270–
1340), a convert to Christianity who became known as Alfonso de
Valladolid, proved a theorem in a Hebrew work identical to a rectilinear
Ṭūsī-couple. Tzvi Langermann has noted that Avner “adduces his theo-
rem in a mathematical context, the stated purpose of which is ‘to con-
struct (li-ṣayyer) a continuous and unending rectilinear motion, back
and forth along a finite straight line, without resting when reversing di-
rection [literally: “between going and returning”].’”34 What is interest-
ing here is that this use of the couple, as part of the quies media debate, is
not something one finds in Ṭūsī but is to be found in the work of his as-
sociate and student Shīrāzī. As we will see, this may well have implica-
tions for the transmission of the couple to Europe.
Nicole Oresme
Nicole Oresme (ca. 1320–82), in his Questiones de spera, which treats
Johannes de Sacrobosco’s On the Sphere of the World, describes some sort
of model that will produce reciprocating rectilinear motion from three
circular motions. Both Garrett Droppers and Claudia Kren raised the
possibility that Oresme was somehow influenced by “Ṭūsī’s device.”35
Recently, André Goddu has challenged this possibility and has raised
another one, namely that Oresme hit upon a solution similar to Ṭūsī’s
for producing rectilinear motion from circular motions – although still
leaving open the (weak?) alternative that Oresme may have come across
some description of it.36 Because Goddu’s speculations, discussed below,
depend upon several misinterpretations of both Ṭūsī and Oresme, we
need to carefully consider what Oresme is proposing. Here is Kren’s
translation of the relevant passage with my suggested revisions:37
Concerning this problem [i.e., whether celestial bodies move in circular mo-
tion], I propose three interesting conclusions. First, it is possible for some planet
to be moved perpetually according to its own nature in a rectilinear motion
composed of several circular motions. This motion can be brought about by
several intelligences, any one of which may endeavor to move in a circular mo-
tion, nor would this purpose be in vain [rev: and (the intelligence) is not frustrated
in this endeavor].
Proof: Let us propose, conceptually, as do the astrologers, that A is the deferent
[rev: deferent circle] of some planet, or its center; B is the epicycle [rev: epicycle
circle] of the same planet; and C is the body of the planet, or its center; I take
these [latter two?] as equivalent. Let us also imagine line BC from the center of
the epicycle to the center of the planet, and CD, a line in the planet on which BC
177
80 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
falls perpendicularly. Let circle A move on its center toward the east, and B to-
ward the west. The planet, C, revolves on its own center toward the east. Moreover,
since line BC is of constant length, because it is a radius, let us propose that the
distance [rev: amount] B descends in [rev: according to] the motion of the defer-
ent is the distance which [rev: as much as] point C may ascend [rev: ascends] with
the motion of the epicycle. From this one can obviously observe that point C in
some definite time will be moved in a straight line. Let us then further assume that
point B would ascend by its own motion on just the circumference on which it may descend
with the motion of the planet [rev: Let us then further assume that the circuit on
which B would ascend by its own motion is as much as the motion of the planet
descends]. It is further clear that point D will move continually on the same line;
thus the entire body of the planet will be moved to some terminus in a rectilinear
motion and will return again with a similar motion.38
178
From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-Couple 81
direction. These movements will then result in the planet’s centre (C)
oscillating on a straight line. They will not, however, result in the apex of
the planet (D) moving rectilinearly. As shown in the diagram, when the
deferent and epicycle have rotated from an initial position (where A, B,
C, and D were on the same line), D will move from D0 to D1. To deal
with this issue, Ṭūsī introduces what he calls an enclosing sphere (kura
muḥīṭa), which is shown in the diagram as an orb enclosing and concen-
tric with the planet (C). This orb would then have the job of moving D
from D1 back to its initial position of D0. Since ∠BAC = ∠D0CD1, the
enclosing sphere needs to move with the same speed and direction of
the deferent (A) in order to keep D oscillating on the straight line.
Kren has assumed that Oresme is simply copying Ṭūsī’s physicalized
rectilinear version, and she has some tortured readings that would intro-
duce this fourth, enclosing orb into Oresme’s account. But Oresme
clearly says he only needs three circular motions, and in fact Ṭūsī’s com-
mentators indicate that one could replace orb C and the enclosing orb
by combining their motions into a single orb. Ṭūsī does not do so,
179
82 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
1 A is the deferent, which “carries” (deferre) the epicycle (B); the plan-
et (C) is moved by the epicycle. According to most standard medi-
eval accounts, and presumably this idea is what Oresme intends by
referring to the conceptualization of the astrologers, the epicycle is
embedded in the deferent and the planet is embedded in the epi-
cycle, as shown.
2 A radius (CD) of the planet would in general not be perpendicular
to line BC in this construction; however, it would be perpendicular
at the quadratures, as noted by Kren. As mentioned above, the alter-
native given by Droppers and followed by Goddu (see figure 7.10)
does not fit the stipulation that D remain on the line of oscillation.
3 The directions of the motions (A eastward, B westward, and C east-
ward) is consistent with Ṭūsī’s model.
4 Oresme emphasizes that BC is a radius of constant length, which
probably indicates that he is aware that this stipulation is part of the
proof for the Ṭūsī-couple. For this model to work so that point C
remains on a straight line, Oresme needs to make B rotate twice as
fast as A (or in his terms, point B will descend due to A, while C will
ascend with twice the speed due to B). However, he seems to imply
that the deferent and epicycle rotate at the same speed (or descend
and ascend in equal amounts). Unless he has some other sense for
“ascend” and “descend,” Oresme does not seem to be in control
of this rather critical part of the model.
5 If one accepts my emended translation, Oresme does understand
that the planet will need to rotate in the direction opposite that of
the epicycle. Again, we are not provided with any amounts, but it
seems that Oresme is conceiving of D0 being displaced to D1 by the
“ascending” motion of B, which would then need to be countered
by the descending motion of the planet (see figure 7.2). The flow of
the argument is then clear: he begins by “proving” that C will oscil-
late on a straight line and follows with his “proof” that D will follow
180
From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-Couple 83
suit and stay on the straight line by means of the additional motion
of the planet.
181
84 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
Georg Peurbach
From an extensive mathematical analysis of the 1510 and 1512 annual
ephemerides of Johannes Angelus, Jerzy Dobrzycki and Richard Kremer
have concluded that they were based upon modifications of the Alfonsine
Tables, these modifications consisting of mechanisms meant to produce
harmonic motion that were somehow added to the standard Ptolemaic
models.45 Because Angelus seems to indicate that these were based upon
a new table of planetary equations due to Georg Peurbach (d. 1461),
Dobrzycki and Kremer speculate that the underlying models used by
Peurbach incorporated one of the Marāgha models, perhaps the Ṭūsī-
couple or the mathematically equivalent epicycle/epicyclet of ʿAlāʾ al-
Dīn ibn al-Shāṭir. Aiton has also raised the possibility that Peurbach in
his Theoricae novae planetarum may be referring to Ibn al-Haytham’s
Eudoxan-couple when he states, “On account of these inclinations and
slants of the epicycles, some assume that small orbs have the epicycles
within them, and that the same things happen to their motion.”46
Although speculative, these authors’ conclusions do point to the possi-
bility that European astronomers in the late fifteenth and early sixteenth
centuries, other than Copernicus, used and adapted devices that we nor-
mally associate with Islamic astronomy. This is an important point that
we will revisit when we discuss some of the objections that have been
raised to astronomical transmission from Islam to Latin Europe.
Johann Werner
In his De motu octavae sphaerae, Johann Werner (1468–1522) uses a two-
equal-circle device to deal with the issue of variable precession, or trepi-
dation. According to Dobrzycki and Kremer, “Werner allotted the
trepidational motion of ‘Thabit’s’ [Thābit ibn Qurra’s] and Peurbach’s
models to the solstitial points of two concentric spheres. Two circles of
182
From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-Couple 85
Nicholas Copernicus
Noel Swerdlow and Otto Neugebauer succinctly summarize Copernicus’s
use of the various devices invented by Ṭūsī: “In De revolutionibus he uses
the form of Ṭūsī’s device with inclined axes for the inequality of the pre-
cession and the variation of the obliquity of the ecliptic, and in both the
Commentariolus and De revolutionibus he uses it for the oscillation of
the orbital planes in the latitude theory. In the Commentariolus he uses
the form with parallel axes for the variation of the radius of Mercury’s
orbit, and by implication does the same in De revolutionibus although
without giving a description of the mechanism.”54
183
86 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
T h e T r a n s m i s s i o n S k e p t i c s 60
184
From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-Couple 87
185
88 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
186
From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-Couple 89
Mancha makes it very clear that what they are dealing with is Ibn al-
Haytham’s Eudoxan-couple, not the Ṭūsī-couple.75 Thus when Goddu
seeks to make Oresme the source for Hesse and subsequent writers, he
is making a fundamental mistake, namely having something that is like-
ly to have been some sort of Ṭūsī device be the source for a totally differ-
ent type of model. Oresme was seeking to produce rectilinear motion
from circular motion, whereas most of the other authors Goddu deals
with (excepting Copernicus, of course) are simply reporting a way to
physicalize the small circle motion of Ptolemy’s latitude theory or are
using the same device for the oscillation of the lunar apogee due to the
Moon’s prosneusis point.76 That Goddu further claims that an adapta-
tion by Copernicus of the Eudoxan model that Brudzewo describes is
equivalent to the wholesale incorporation of Ibn al-Shāṭir’s models into
the Commentariolus is, to say the least, bizarre in the extreme.77
Both Di Bono and Goddu ask for more evidence for transmission before
passing judgment. This is a fair comment, and in what follows I present
some of the evidence that has been discovered over the past twenty-five
years or so.78 I divide this evidence up into different pathways that trans-
mission did take or could have taken.
As mentioned above, it is now clear that the Ṭūsī-couple first made its way
into another cultural context through Byzantine intermediaries, first
and foremost Gregory Chioniades, who travelled to Tabrīz around 1295
and studied with a certain Shams Bukharos, whom we can now identify
as Shams al-Din al-Wābkanawī.79 That this transmission occurred through
an adapted translation from Persian into Greek raises some interesting
issues of intercultural exchange. Was this translation a result of the fact
that the language of trade between Byzantium and Iran was mainly in
Persian? If so, Chioniades may have had an easier time finding someone
to teach him Persian than Arabic. And indeed, most of the Islamic astro-
nomical works that found their way into Greek seem to have been from
Persian sources.80 This Persian bias may help us to understand why an
ostensibly out-of-date treatise, such as Ṭūsī’s Persian Muʿīniyya and its ap-
pendix, the Ḥall, which, as we have seen, contained the first versions of
Ṭūsī’s rectilinear couple and lunar model, were provided and taught to
Chioniades rather than the mature versions found in Ṭūsī’s later
Tadhkira, which was in Arabic. But there could be other reasons. One of
187
90 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
in a short while he [i.e., Chioniades] was taught by the Persians, having both
consorted with the King, and met with consideration from him. Then he de-
sired to study astronomical matters, but found that they were not taught. For it
was the rule with the Persians that all subjects were available to those who wished
to study, except astronomy, which was for Persians only. He searched for the
cause, which was that a certain ancient opinion prevailed among them, concern-
ing the mathematical sciences, namely, that their king will be overthrown by the
Romans, after consulting the practice of astronomy, whose foundation would
first be taken from the Persians. He was at a loss as to how he might come to
share this wonderful thing. In spite of being wearied, and having much served
the Persian king, he had scarcely achieved his objective; when, by Royal com-
mand, the teachers were gathered. Soon Chioniades shone in Persia, and was
thought worthy of the King’s honor. Having gathered many treasures, and orga-
nized many subordinates, he again reached Trebizond, with his many books on
the subject of astronomy. He translated these by his own lights, making a note-
worthy effort.81
188
From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-Couple 91
189
92 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
190
From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-Couple 93
Manuscripts Galore
191
94 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
192
From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-Couple 95
Conclusion
193
96 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
194
From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-Couple 97
The next theoretical point to pursue is the question of “how much evi-
dence is enough.” It is a commonplace in the history of science to trace
intercultural transmission through the reappearance of numbers, ob-
jects, models, propositions, and even ideas that we can locate in an
earlier source. In fact, one might consider it our most precise way to
document intercultural transmission. The gold standard in our field is
arguably Hipparchus of Nicaea’s value for the mean synodic month (re-
ported by Ptolemy), namely 29;31,50,8,20 days (sexagesimal). Once
Franz Kugler demonstrated in the 1890s that this value came from what
is now known as Babylonian System B, the argument for Greek knowl-
edge and use of Babylonian astronomy (at least its parameters) became
incontestable. The same is also true of the fact that Hipparchus, despite
what is reported by Ptolemy, did not make a recalculation using new ob-
servations. But why can we reach these conclusions? The answer is obvi-
ous. Would anyone seriously argue that two identical values to the fourth
sexagesimal place is a coincidence? According to Di Bono and Goddu,
the appearance of Ṭūsī’s couple, Muʾayyad al-Dīn al-ʿUrḍī’s lemma, Ibn
al-Shāṭir’s models, and so on in the work of Copernicus is not sufficient
to prove transmission. But what makes this case different from the case
of Hipparchus’s value for the mean synodic month? The case made by
Di Bono, and echoed by Goddu, is that somehow the “internal logic” is
such that anyone confronting the problem of Ptolemy’s irregular mo-
tions would come up with the same solutions.107 But Di Bono makes it
clear that his criteria for accepting transmission are so high that even a
“high number of coincidences between Copernican and Arab models” is
insufficient since it then “becomes very difficult to explain how such a
quantity of models and information, which Copernicus would derive
from Arab sources, has left no trace – apart from Ṭūsī’s device – in the
works of the other western astronomers of the time.”108 This argument
is a curious one; given the tenuous nature of transmission, an insis-
tence on multiple examples would render many cases moot, even one as
strong as the transmission of the Babylonian synodic month.
Let us now turn to the issue of “internal logic” and parallel develop-
ment. In fact, what we have in Islam and in the Latin West represent two
very different historical developments. The criticism of Ptolemy on vari-
ous fronts, including observational ones, begins quite early in Islam;109
and certainly by the time of Ibn al-Haytham (d. ca. 1040), we have sus-
tained criticisms of the irregularities in Ptolemy’s planetary models.110
By the thirteenth century, we see a number of attempts to deal with
these criticisms by using alternative models that employ devices consist-
ing of uniformly rotating spheres, those of Ṭūsī, ʿUrḍī, and Shīrāzī being
the most prominent; the proposal of alternative models continues for
195
98 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
196
From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-Couple 99
197
100 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
chapter seven
1 F.J. Ragep, “Copernicus.” This point is made even more forcefully in my
“Ibn al-Shāṭir and Copernicus: The Uppsala Notes Revisited,” where I main-
tain that there is a stronger connection between ʿAlāʾ al-Dīn ibn al-Shāṭir
(fourteenth century) and Copernicus’s models and heliocentrism than has
been previously claimed.
2 Here, we need to acknowledge Mario Di Bono, who, in a valuable article, in-
sists on distinguishing the various versions of the Ṭūsī-couple. Di Bono, “Coper-
nicus, Amico, Fracastoro.” Di Bono is building on the earlier work of Noel
”Swerdlow, especially his “Aristotelian Planetary Theory in the Renaissance.
3 On Risālah-i Muʿīniyya, see F.J. Ragep, “Persian Context,” and Naṣīr al-Dīn
al-Ṭūsī’s Memoir, vol. 1, 65–6. See also Kennedy, “Two Persian Astronomical
”Treatises.
4 The relevant parts of the Persian text discussed in this paragraph, along
with translation, are in F.J. Ragep, “Persian Context,” 123–5.
5 F.J. Ragep, Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī’s Memoir, vol. 1, 208.
6 The name “Dhayl-i Muʿīniyya” is found in the only dated manuscript of
Ṭūsī’s text, namely Tashkent, Uzbekistan, Al-Biruni Institute of Oriental
Studies, MS 8990, fols 1a, 33a, 33b.
7 Ṭūsī, Dhayl-i Muʿīniyya, Tashkent, Al-Biruni Institute of Oriental Studies, MS
8990, fol. 46a (original foliation):
ﲤﺖ اﻟﺮﺳﺎ� اﺗﻔﻖ ﻓﺮاغ اﳌﺼﻨﻒ رﻓﻊ ﷲ ﻣﺮاﺗﺒﻪ ﰲ ﻣﻌﺎرج اﻟﻘﺪس ﻣﻦ ﺗأﻟﯿﻔﻪ ٔاواﺋﻞ ﺟﲈدى
�ﺮﻛﻪأﻟﯿﻔﻪ ٔاواﺋﻞ ﺟﲈدى ﺑﺒﺎغﻣﻦ ﺗ اﻟﻘﺪس ﺑ�ةﷲﺗﻮنﻣﺮﺎﺑﻟ�اﺗﺒﻪﺴﰲ�ﺘﺎنﻣﻌﺎرج
اﳌﻌﺮوف اﳌﺼﻨﻒ
ﲟﻘﺎم رﻓﻊ ۶۴۳ﺮاغﳗﺮﯾﺔ �ﻨﺔ اﺗﻔﻖ ﻓ اﻟﺮﺳﺎ�
ﲤﺖﺧﺮة ﺳ ااﻟٓ
8 On Tūn as one of the �residencesﺮﻛﻪ
�ﺘﺎنofاﳌﻌﺮوف ﺑﺒﺎغ localﺴthe Ismﺗﻮن ﺎﺑﻟ� ﲟﻘﺎمāʿﺑ�ة seeﳗﺮﯾﺔ
īlī rulers, ۶۴۳Daftary, ااﻟٓﺧﺮة ﺳ�ﻨﺔ
“Dāʿī,” 592, col. 1.
9
اﻣﺎ اﺳ�ﺘﻘﺎﻣﺖ ﺣﺮﻛﺖ ﻣﺮﻛﺰ ﺗﺪو�ﺮ از ﳏﯿﻂ ﻣﺎﯾﻞ �ﺮ ﲰﺖ ﻣﺮﻛﺰش وﺑﻌﺪ از آن رﺟﻮع او ﱒ �ﺮ
Ṭūsī, Ḥall-i mushkilāt-i Muʿīniyya, 7:
ﺣﺮﰷتﱒراﻩ�ﺮ �ﻠ�ﺑﻌﺪﺎﺑﺳاز آن
�ﺘﺪارترﺟﻮع او ﻣﺮﻛﺰش و ﲰﺖ آﯾﺪ � اﻟﺘﯿﺎﱉ ﻻزم ﳏﯿﻂ ﻣوﺎﯾﻞ �ﺮ �ﯿﺪن ﺗﺪﰉوا ٓ�ﺮ�ﻜﻪاز ﺧﺮﰵ ﲟﺤﯿﻂﻛﺖرﺳﻣﺮﻛﺰ ﲰﺖ �
�ﺘﻘﺎﻣﺖ ﺣﺮ اﻣﺎ اﺳآن
ﻛﻨﲓ.ﺧﺮﰵ و اﻟﺘﯿﺎﱉ ﻻزم آﯾﺪ � �ﻠ� ﺎﺑﺳ�ﺘﺪارت ﺣﺮﰷت راﻩ �دٓ�ﻜﻪ
�ﯿﺪنﻛﻪﰉ ا ﲟﺤﯿﻂاﻧﺪرﺳﺑﻮد
ﲰﺖن�وﺟﻪ ﺗﻮ �ﺑﺬ �ﺮ ا ٓ آن
�ﺑﺬ �ﺮ آن وﺟﻪ ﺗﻮاﻧﺪ ﺑﻮد ﻛﻪ �د ﻛﻨﲓ.
“The ��rectilinear
motionﻣﻦ اﻟﻮاﺟﺐ ﻫﺬاofاﳌﻮﺿﻊ ﻓﺎ ّٕن centerﰲthe ٮ{�ofﲑ ﻣﻘ�ﻊ the201 awayاﻟﺼﻨﺎ�ﺔ }
epicycle fromﻣﻦ �م �ﺎرج ٔاﻗﻮل ﻫﺬا
the circum-
ferenceﺗ�ﺐ �� و�ﺮof
اﺟﺐ ﻧﻀﺪاﻟ
theﻮ ��ٕن
inclinedﻣﻦ ﻣ�ﺸﺎﲠﺔ
اﳌﻮﺿﻊ ﻓﺎ ّ ][orbﺣﺮﰷتﻫﺬا
in
theﰲ directionاتﻣﻘ�ﻊ
ٮ{ ذو
�ﲑ 201ﺟﺮاﻣ ًﺎ
اﺋﺮofو ٔا centreدو
} its
اﻟﺼﻨﺎ�ﺔ ﻣﻦ ﯾﻀﻊ ٔ andان
اﻟﺼﻨﺎ�ﺔ
�thenﺎرج �مitsﻫﺬﻩﺻﺎﺣﺐﻫﺬا re-ٔاﻗﻮل
ّturn on that same line until it reaches the circumference – without there
anyا�واﺋﺮ
ﺗ�ﺐ being
ﳏﯿﻂ �� و�اﳊﺮﰷت ﻧﻀﺪ
tearingﺮ ﻣ�ﺸﺎﲠﺔ��and ﻛﻮن ﻫﺬﻩ
mending, ﺣﺮﰷت anyاتﰒorا ّٕنا�ﺘﻠﻔﺔ اﶈﺴﻮﺳﺔﺮاﻣ ًﺎ
ruptureذو اﳊﺮﰷتدوinاﺋﺮ و ٔاﺟ
the ﻫﺬﻩ ٔان
circularﯾﻀﻊ ﲨﯿﻌﻬﺎ
اﻟﺼﻨﺎ�ﺔ ﺻﺎﺣﺐﻣﻦﻫﺬﻩ
motions
ﯾﱰﻛ–ﺐ
ًcan
beوﺷﲈاﺋﺮﻻ اﻟﻌﺮضا�
��wayﰲtheﳏﯿﻂ
in اﳊﺮﰷتاﻛﺰ
اﳋﺎرﺟﺔweاﳌﺮ
shall ﺳﻄﻮح
ا�ﺘﻠﻔﺔ ﰒﻋﻦا ّٕن ﻛﻮن
”mention.ﻫﺬﻩ اﶈﺴﻮﺳﺔاﻟﺘﺪاو�ﺮ ﺧﺮوج ٔاﻗﻄﺎر اﳊﺮﰷت ﻫﺬﻩ�� ﲨﯿﻌﻬﺎﻛﲈ ﺗﻘ
اﳌﺬﻛﻮرةاﻟﺼﻐﺎر ﻣﻦ
ﯾﱰﻛّﺐ
10 See F.J. Ragep, Naṣīr al-D ī n al- Ṭū s ī ’s Memoir, vol. 1, 208–23, vol. 2,
اﻟﱪوجﺷﲈ ًﻻ
448–56.
ﺳﻄﺢاﻟﻌﺮض ��اﻛﺰ ﰲﻗﻄﺎر اﳌﺮاﳋﺎرﺟﺔ ﺳﻄﻮحزاة ٔا
اﻟﱪوج ٔاو ﻣﻮا ﻣﺮﻛﺰو�ﺮ ﻋﻦ ﳏﺎذاة اﻟﺘﺪا
ﻋﻦ ٔاﻗﻄﺎر ﺧﺮوج ﺧﺮو�ﺎ
ﺗﻘ��ﺗﻘ�� اﻟﺼﻐﺎر ﻛﺬ�
اﳌﺬﻛﻮرة ﻛﲈ وﺟ�ﻮ ًﺎﺑ
11 The اﻟﱪوج ٔان
ﳝﻜﻦ ﺳﻄﺢوﻻ
relevant ﻟﻠﻮﺟﻮد
ﳐﺎﻟﻒ��
passages fromﻗﻄﺎروذ� ٔا
Risﻮازاةﻋﯿﺎﳖﺎ ﻣ
ٔ lah-iاāواﻟﻌﺮوض ﺑأ
اﻟﱪوج Mu ﻣﺮﻛﺰ
ʿīniyya,ﺑﻘﺪر ﺗ�
ﳏﺎذاة ﺧﺮو�ﺎر ًا ﻋﻦ
book دﺎﺑ
chsوٕا 2,ٕﻗ�ﺎ ًﻻ
6,ا5,
ﺗﻘ�� اﻟﻄﻮل
ﻛﺬ�
8, ﻋﯿﺎﳖﺎ ﰲ
with ﺑأوﺟ�ﻮ ًﺎﺑ
English translation, can be found
اﻟﺒﻌﺪ
ﳝﻜﻦو ٔان اﳌﻘﺪار
ﻟﻠﻮﺟﻮدﰲ وﻻﻟ�ﺴﺎوﳞﲈ ﳐﺎﻟﻒ اﻟﻄﻮل وذ� ﻋﯿﺎﳖﺎﰲ
ﳏﺴﻮس اﻟﻌﺮوض ﺑinأ
F.J.
Ragep,و�ﲑ اﻟﻌﺮض
ﺑﻘﺪر ﺗ� “Persian
ﺴﻮس ﰲ ”Context,ﳏوٕادﺎﺑر ًا
اﻟﺘﻔﺎوت ًﻻ
ذ�اﻟﻄﻮل إﻗ�ﺎ 123–5.
ﻋﯿﺎﳖﺎ ّنﰲ ﺑأﯾﻘﺎل ٕا
ﺗﻮﱒ ٔا ّن
اﻟﺒﻌﺪ اﳌﻘﺪار و ّ
اﳉﻬﺘﲔ و اﻟﻄﻮلﰲ إ�ﺪى
ﻟ�ﺴﺎوﳞﲈ ﰲ ﲨﯿﻊﰲاﻟﻌﺮض ﳏﺴﻮس و�ﲑ ﺑﻘﺪر اﻟﻌﺮضاﻟﺼﻐﲑة ﻗﻄﺮﰲا�اﺋﺮة ﺴﻮس ﺟﻌﻞ اﻟﱪوج ﻓﺎٕن
اﻟﺘﻔﺎوت ﳏ ﻣﺮﻛﺰذ� ﯾﻘﺎل ٕا ّنﻣﻦ
ﻧﺼﻒ ّن ﺑﻘﺪرو ّ
ﺗﻮﱒ ٔا اﳉﻬﺘﲔ ٕ�ﺪىاﳌﺮﻛﺰ
اﳋﺎرج ﺳﻄﺢﰲ ا ﲨﯿﻊﰲاﻟﻌﺮض ﻣﺮﻛﺰﻫﺎ ﺑﻘﺪر 262
اﻟﺼﻐﲑةﻟﻬﺎ
ا�اﺋﺮةﻣﺴﺎوﯾﺔ ﻗﻄﺮ ٔاﺧﺮى ﺟﻌﻞداﺋﺮة ��ﺎٕنﳏﯿﻂ ﯾﺘﺤﺮك
اﻟﱪوج ﻓ ﻣﺮﻛﺰ ّ ﻣﺮﻛﺰﻫﺎ ﻣﻦ
ﺑﻘﺪرإﱃﻧﺼﻒ اﳌﺮﻛﺰﻧﺘﻘﺎل
�ﺪث ﻻا ��ﺎاﳋﺎرج �ﻼفﺳﻄﺢ وﱃ وٕاﱃ
ﻣﺮﻛﺰﻫﺎ ﰲ ٔ
ا�اﺋﺮةواﯾﺔاﻟ ﻟﻬﺎ
ﺧﺮى ﻣﺴﺎ داﺋﺮة ٔاﳏﯿﻂ
ﳏﯿﻂ�ﺮ �� ﯾﺘﺤﺮكﻗﻄﺮ��اﻟﺘﺪو ﻃﺮف
ﻣﺮﻛﺰﻫﺎ ّ ﺣﺮﻛﺔ
اٮ ﻟﯿﻜﻦﻻاﻟﺒﯿﺎﻧﻪ
ﻧﺘﻘﺎل إﱃ �ﺪث ��ﺎﺧّﺮ و �ﻼفم وﺗأ اﻟﻄﻮل ﺗﻘﺪّ ﳛﺪثوﱃﰲوٕاﱃ ا�اﺋﺮة ا ٔاﻟﻣﻦﯿﻂ�ﲑ ٔان �� ﳏ اﻟﻌﺮضاﻟﺘﺪو�ﺮ ﻗﻄﺮﺑﻘﺪر اﳉﻨﻮب
ﻃﺮف اﻟﺸﲈل و ﺣﺮﻛﺔ
ﺗﻘﺎﻃﻌﺎﻟﺒﯿﺎ��ﻧﻪ ﻩاٮو ﻩز وﻗﺪوﻟﯿﻜﻦ ﻗﻄﺮ ﺗﻘﺪّاﻟﺘﺪمووﺗ�ﺮأﺧّﺮ
ﺑﻄﺮفاﻟﻄﻮل ﳛﺪث ﰲ اﳌﺎرة
اﻟﻌﺮض ّ ﻣﻦ �ﲑ ٔان اﻟﻌﺮضداﺋﺮةاﳋﺎرج وﺑﻘﺪرﺟد ﻣﻦ ﻣﻦاﳉﻨﻮب اﻟﺸﲈل و ﻗﻄﻌﺔ
From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-Couple 101
ﲤﺖ اﻟﺮﺳﺎ� اﺗﻔﻖ ﻓﺮاغ اﳌﺼﻨﻒ رﻓﻊ ﷲ ﻣﺮاﺗﺒﻪ ﰲ ﻣﻌﺎرج اﻟﻘﺪس ﻣﻦ ﺗأﻟﯿﻔﻪ ٔاواﺋﻞ ﺟﲈدى
12 For details and an edition and translation of the relevant chapter from the
ااﻟٓﺧﺮة ﺳ�ﻨﺔ ۶۴۳ﳗﺮﯾﺔ ﲟﻘﺎم ﺑ�ة ﺗﻮن ﺎﺑﻟ�ﺴ�ﺘﺎن اﳌﻌﺮوف ﺑﺒﺎغ �ﺮﻛﻪ
”Ḥall, see F.J. Ragep, “Ibn al-Haytham and Eudoxus.
13 This chronology contradicts George Saliba’s contention, followed by Di
Bono and others, that the two-equal-circle version in Taḥrīr al-Majisṭī was the
first occurrence of any version of the Ṭūsī-couple. But clearly the new dating
اﻣﺎ اﺳ�ﺘﻘﺎﻣﺖ ﺣﺮﻛﺖ ﻣﺮﻛﺰ ﺗﺪو�ﺮ از ﳏﯿﻂ ﻣﺎﯾﻞ �ﺮ ﲰﺖ ﻣﺮﻛﺰش وﺑﻌﺪ از آن رﺟﻮع او ﱒ �ﺮ
of the Ḥall should put to rest this earlier proposal. Compare Saliba, “Role of
آن ﲰﺖ � ﲟﺤﯿﻂ رﺳ�ﯿﺪن ﰉ آ�ﻜﻪ ﺧﺮﰵ و اﻟﺘﯿﺎﱉ ﻻزم آﯾﺪ � �ﻠ� ﺎﺑﺳ�ﺘﺪارت ﺣﺮﰷت راﻩ
”the Almagest Commentaries.
�ﺑﺬ �ﺮ آن وﺟﻪ ﺗﻮاﻧﺪ ﺑﻮد ﻛﻪ �د ﻛﻨﲓ.
14 This comment corresponds to the Almagest, book 13, ch. 2; Ptolemy,
Ptolemy’s Almagest, 599-601.
15 Ṭūsī, Taḥrīr al-Majisṭī, fols 201a–202a:
ٔاﻗﻮل ﻫﺬا �م �ﺎرج ﻣﻦ اﻟﺼﻨﺎ�ﺔ }201ٮ{ �ﲑ ﻣﻘ�ﻊ ﰲ ﻫﺬا اﳌﻮﺿﻊ ﻓﺎ ّٕن ﻣﻦ اﻟﻮاﺟﺐ ��
ﺻﺎﺣﺐ ﻫﺬﻩ اﻟﺼﻨﺎ�ﺔ ٔان ﯾﻀﻊ دواﺋﺮ و ٔاﺟﺮاﻣ ًﺎ ذوات ﺣﺮﰷت ﻣ�ﺸﺎﲠﺔ �� ﻧﻀﺪ و�ﺮﺗ�ﺐ
ﯾﱰﻛّﺐ ﻣﻦ ﲨﯿﻌﻬﺎ ﻫﺬﻩ اﳊﺮﰷت اﶈﺴﻮﺳﺔ ا�ﺘﻠﻔﺔ ﰒ ا ّٕن ﻛﻮن ﻫﺬﻩ اﳊﺮﰷت �� ﳏﯿﻂ ا�واﺋﺮ
اﻟﺼﻐﺎر اﳌﺬﻛﻮرة ﻛﲈ ﺗﻘ�� ﺧﺮوج ٔاﻗﻄﺎر اﻟﺘﺪاو�ﺮ ﻋﻦ ﺳﻄﻮح اﳋﺎرﺟﺔ اﳌﺮاﻛﺰ ﰲ اﻟﻌﺮض ﺷﲈ ًﻻ
وﺟ�ﻮ ًﺎﺑ ﻛﺬ� ﺗﻘ�� ﺧﺮو�ﺎ ﻋﻦ ﳏﺎذاة ﻣﺮﻛﺰ اﻟﱪوج ٔاو ﻣﻮازاة ٔاﻗﻄﺎر �� ﺳﻄﺢ اﻟﱪوج
ﺑأﻋﯿﺎﳖﺎ ﰲ اﻟﻄﻮل إﻗ�ﺎ ًﻻ وٕادﺎﺑر ًا ﺑﻘﺪر ﺗ� اﻟﻌﺮوض ﺑأﻋﯿﺎﳖﺎ وذ� ﳐﺎﻟﻒ ﻟﻠﻮﺟﻮد وﻻ ﳝﻜﻦ ٔان
ﯾﻘﺎل ٕا ّن ذ� اﻟﺘﻔﺎوت ﳏﺴﻮس ﰲ اﻟﻌﺮض و�ﲑ ﳏﺴﻮس ﰲ اﻟﻄﻮل ﻟ�ﺴﺎوﳞﲈ ﰲ اﳌﻘﺪار واﻟﺒﻌﺪ
ﻣﻦ ﻣﺮﻛﺰ اﻟﱪوج ﻓﺎٕن ﺟﻌﻞ ﻗﻄﺮ ا�اﺋﺮة اﻟﺼﻐﲑة ﺑﻘﺪر ﲨﯿﻊ اﻟﻌﺮض ﰲ إ�ﺪى اﳉﻬﺘﲔ و ّ
ﺗﻮﱒ ٔا ّن
ﯾﺘﺤﺮك �� ﳏﯿﻂ داﺋﺮة ٔاﺧﺮى ﻣﺴﺎوﯾﺔ ﻟﻬﺎ ﻣﺮﻛﺰﻫﺎ ﰲ ﺳﻄﺢ اﳋﺎرج اﳌﺮﻛﺰ ﺑﻘﺪر ﻧﺼﻒ ﻣﺮﻛﺰﻫﺎ ّ
ﺣﺮﻛﺔ ﻃﺮف ﻗﻄﺮ اﻟﺘﺪو�ﺮ �� ﳏﯿﻂ ا�اﺋﺮة ا ٔاﻟوﱃ وٕاﱃ �ﻼف ��ﺎ �ﺪث ﻻاﻧﺘﻘﺎل إﱃ
اﻟﺸﲈل واﳉﻨﻮب ﺑﻘﺪر اﻟﻌﺮض ﻣﻦ �ﲑ ٔان ﳛﺪث ﰲ اﻟﻄﻮل ﺗﻘﺪّ م وﺗأﺧّﺮ وﻟﯿﻜﻦ ﻟﺒﯿﺎﻧﻪ اٮ
اﳌﺎرة ﺑﻄﺮف ﻗﻄﺮ اﻟﺘﺪو�ﺮ وﻗﺪ ﺗﻘﺎﻃﻌﺎ �� ﻩ و ﻩز ﻗﻄﻌﺔ ﻣﻦ اﳋﺎرج و ﺟد ﻣﻦ داﺋﺮة اﻟﻌﺮض ّ
ﻩم ﲨﯿﻊ اﻟﻌﺮض ﰲ اﳉﻬﺘﲔ وﻩح ﻧﺼﻔﻪ ﰲ إ�ﺪﳞﲈ و�ﺮ� �� ح ﺑﺒﻌﺪ ﻩح داﺋﺮة ﻩز و�� ﻩ
ﻣ�ﺤﺮﰷً �� داﺋﺮة ﻩز ﰲ
ﻧﺘﻮﱒ ﻃﺮف ﻗﻄﺮ اﻟﺘﺪو�ﺮ �� ﻧﻘﻄﺔ ز ّ ﺑﺒﻌﺪ حﻩ داﺋﺮة ح ط ك ل و ّ
ﻣ�ﺤﺮﰷً �� داﺋﺮة ح ط ك ل ﰲ �ﺔ ﺟ إﱃ ا ﻧﺼﻒ ﺗ� اﳊﺮﻛﺔ �ﺔ ﺟ إﱃ ٮ وﻣﺮﻛﺰ ح ّ
ﻓﻈﺎﻫﺮ ٔاﻧ ّﻪ إذا ﻗﻄﻊ ح رﺑﻌ ًﺎ وا���� إﱃ ط ﻗﻄﻊ ز ﻧﺼﻔ ًﺎ وا���� إﱃ ﻩ ﰒ إذا ﻗﻄﻊ ح رﺑﻌ ًﺎ آﺧﺮ
وا���� إﱃ ك ﻗﻄﻊ ز ﻧﺼﻔ ًﺎ آﺧﺮ وا���� }202ا ٓ{ إﱃ م وٕاذا ﻗﻄﻊ ح رﺑﻌ ًﺎ �ﻟﺜ ًﺎ وا���� إﱃ ل ﻗﻄﻊ
ز ﻧﺼﻔ ًﺎ آﺧﺮ وا���� �ﻧﯿ ًﺎ إﱃ ﻩ وٕاذا ّﰎ ح دورة �ﺎد ز إﱃ ﻣﻮﺿﻌﻪ ا ٔاﻟول ﻓﻬﻮ داﲚ ًﺎ ﯾﱰدّد ﻓ� ﺑﲔ
زم �� ﺧﻂّ ج د �ﲑ ﻣﺎﺋﻞ ﻋﻨﻪ إﱃ �� اب ﻓﻬﺬا ﺑﯿﺎن ﻫﺬا اﻟﻮﺟﻪ وﻟﻜﻦ ﯾﻠﺰم �ﻠﯿﻪ ٔان �ﻜﻮن
زﻣﺎن ﻛﻮن اﻟﻘﻄﺮ ﰲ اﻟﺸﲈل ﻣﺴﺎو ً� ﻟﺰﻣﺎن ﻛﻮﻧﻪ ﰲ اﳉﻨﻮب واﻟﻮﺟﻮد ﲞﻼف ذ� و ٔا ّﻣﺎ اﻟﻘﻮل
ﲝﺮﻛﺘﻪ �� ﳏﯿﻂ داﺋﺮة ﺣﻮل ﻧﻘﻄﺔ �ﲑ ﻣﺮﻛﺰﻫﺎ �� ﻣﺎ ذﻛﺮ ﺑﻄﻠﻤﯿﻮس ﳁﺤﺘﺎج إﱃ ﻧﻈﺮ ﳛﻘّﻘﻪ
�� ﻣﺎ ّﻣﺮ وﻧﻌﻮد إﱃ اﻟﻜ�ﺎب
وﳝﻜﻦ ٔان ﳚﻌﻞ ﻫﺬا دﻟﯿ ًﻼ �� اﻣ�ﻨﺎع اﻟﺴﻜﻮن ﺑﲔ ﺣﺮﻛﺘﲔ ﺻﺎ�ﺪة وﻫﺎﺑﻄﺔ �� ﲰﺖ ﻗﻄﺮ
263
ﻣﻦ ٔاﻗﻄﺎر ا ٔاﻟرض
�� ٮ{ �ﲑ ﻣﻘ�ﻊ ﰲ ﻫﺬا اﳌﻮﺿﻊ ﻓﺎ ّٕن ﻣﻦ اﻟﻮاﺟﺐ201} ٔاﻗﻮل ﻫﺬا �م �ﺎرج ﻣﻦ اﻟﺼﻨﺎ�ﺔ
ﺻﺎﺣﺐ ﻫﺬﻩ اﻟﺼﻨﺎ�ﺔ ٔان ﯾﻀﻊ دواﺋﺮ و ٔاﺟﺮاﻣ ًﺎ ذوات ﺣﺮﰷت ﻣ�ﺸﺎﲠﺔ �� ﻧﻀﺪ و�ﺮﺗ�ﺐ
ﯾﱰﻛّﺐ ﻣﻦ ﲨﯿﻌﻬﺎ ﻫﺬﻩ اﳊﺮﰷت اﶈﺴﻮﺳﺔ ا�ﺘﻠﻔﺔ ﰒ ا ّٕن ﻛﻮن ﻫﺬﻩ اﳊﺮﰷت �� ﳏﯿﻂ ا�واﺋﺮ
102
اﳋﺎرﺟﺔ اﳌﺮاﻛﺰ ﰲ اﻟﻌﺮض ﺷﲈ ًﻻ ٔا اﻟIslamic�� ﺧﺮوج Astronomy and Copernicus
اﻟﺼﻐﺎر اﳌﺬﻛﻮرة ﻛﲈ ﺗﻘ
ٔاﻗﻄﺎر �� ﺳﻄﺢ اﻟﱪوج وﺟ�ﻮ ًﺎﺑ ﻛﺬ� ﺗﻘ�� ﺧﺮو�ﺎ ﻋﻦ
16
إﻗ�ﺎ ًﻻ وٕادﺎﺑر ًا ﺑﻘﺪر ﺗ� اﻟﻌﺮوض ﺑأﻋﯿﺎﳖﺎ وذ� ﳐﺎﻟﻒ ﻟﻠﻮﺟﻮد وﻻ ﳝﻜﻦ ٔانinاﻟﻄﻮل
The unequal times in the Almagest occur because this motion
ﺑأﻋﯿﺎﳖﺎ ﰲ
latitude is
ﰲ اﳌﻘﺪار واﻟﺒﻌﺪwith
coordinated ﻟ�ﺴﺎوﳞﲈ ﳏﺴﻮس ﰲ اﻟﻄﻮل
the irregular motion, و�ﲑbroughtﰲ اﻟﻌﺮضabout ﺴﻮسbyﳏthe اﻟﺘﻔﺎوت �ن ذofّ ٕاthe
equant, ﯾﻘﺎل
epicycle centre on the deferent. F.J. Ragep, Na
ّ ﻣﻦ ﻣﺮﻛﺰ اﻟﱪوج ﻓﺎٕن ﺟﻌﻞ ﻗﻄﺮ ا�اﺋﺮة اﻟﺼﻐﲑة ﺑﻘﺪر ﲨﯿﻊ اﻟﻌﺮض ﰲ إ�ﺪى اﳉﻬﺘﲔ وṣī r al-D īn al- Ṭū s ī’s Memoir,
ﺗﻮﱒ ٔا ّن
vol. 2, 455.
17 ﻧﺼﻒvol.
Ibid., ﺑﻘﺪر1,اﳌﺮﻛﺰ ﯾﺘﺤﺮك �� ﳏﯿﻂ داﺋﺮة ٔاﺧﺮى ﻣﺴﺎوﯾﺔ ﻟﻬﺎ ﻣﺮﻛﺰﻫﺎ ﰲ ﺳﻄﺢ اﳋﺎرج
216–21. ّ ﻣﺮﻛﺰﻫﺎ
18 For aٕﱃfuller
ﻻاﻧﺘﻘﺎل ا account
��ﺎ �ﺪث of the �ﻼف ٔاﻟوﱃ وٕاﱃversion,
curvilinear ﯿﻂ ا�اﺋﺮة اseeﳏibid.,
�� �ﺮvol. اﻟﺘﺪو2,ﻗﻄﺮ 453–6.
ﻃﺮفItﺣﺮﻛﺔ
should be noted that the curvilinear version does not in fact produce mo-
tionاٮ on aﻧﻪgreatﻟﯿﻜﻦ ﻟﺒﯿﺎcircle ٔﺗﻘﺪّ م وﺗا
ﺧّﺮ وarc; اﻟﻄﻮلis aﰲsmall
there اﻟﻌﺮض ﻣﻦ �ﲑ ٔان
ﳛﺪثdiscrepancy resulting اﳉﻨﻮب ﺑﻘﺪر اﻟﺸﲈل و
in a narrow,
pinched figure-eight
وﻗﺪ ﺗﻘﺎﻃﻌﺎmotion. This was ةnoticed
�� ﻩ و ﻩز ﻗﻄﺮ اﻟﺘﺪو�ﺮ ﺑﻄﺮف ّ اﻟﻌﺮضbyداﺋﺮة
اﳌﺎر
on the Tadhkira, Shams al-Dīn al-Khafrī (fl. 1525 CE). But the maximum
at least
د ﻣﻦone و ﺟcommentator
ﻗﻄﻌﺔ ﻣﻦ اﳋﺎرج
و�� ﻩfrom
deviation داﺋﺮة ﻩزa great
ﺑﺒﻌﺪ ﻩحcircle�� حarc,��ﺮwhich
ٕ�ﺪﳞﲈ وoccurs
ﻧﺼﻔﻪ ﰲ ا when وﻩحusing
اﳉﻬﺘﲔtheﰲcurvilinear
ﻩم ﲨﯿﻊ اﻟﻌﺮض
versionﻩز ﰲtoداﺋﺮةdeal��with ًﻣ�ﺤﺮﰷ
ّ theزproblem
�ﺮ �� ﻧﻘﻄﺔofاﻟﺘﺪو
the ﻗﻄﺮ Moon’s ّ طكلو
ﻃﺮفprosneusis,
ﻧﺘﻮﱒ داﺋﺮة ح
is only حﻩ°ﺑﺒﻌﺪ
0.214 ,
which is about 0.87 per cent. Ibid., vol. 2, 455n55, 455n56. For an illustra-
�ﺔ ﺟ إﱃ ٮ وﻣﺮﻛﺰ ح ﻣ�ﺤﺮﰷً �� داﺋﺮة ح ط ك ل ﰲ �ﺔ ﺟ إﱃ ا ﻧﺼﻒ ﺗ� اﳊﺮﻛﺔ
tion of the deviation, see figure C26, in ibid., vol. 1, ّ 361.
19 Theﺧﺮ ٓ ح رﺑﻌ ًﺎ اof
purpose ﻗﻄﻊIbn ًﺎ وا���� إﱃ ﻩ ﰒproposal
إذاal-Haytham’s ﻗﻄﻊ ز ﻧﺼﻔwas ٕﱃ طtoا���� ا رﺑﻌ ًﺎ وaحphysical
provide ﻓﻈﺎﻫﺮ ٔاﻧ
ّﻪ إذا ﻗﻄﻊbasis
for the circular path of the epicycle apex A in Ptolemy’s latitude theory; as
{ إﱃ م وٕاذا ﻗﻄﻊ ح رﺑﻌ ًﺎ �ﻟﺜ ًﺎ وا���� إﱃ ل ﻗﻄﻊwith
far as is known, he was not concerned
ٓ ا202the } ����ا ا���� إﱃ ك ﻗﻄﻊ ز ﻧﺼﻔ ًﺎ آﺧﺮ و
resultant motion of S, which
و
traces ول ﻓﻬﻮ داﲚ ًﺎ ﯾﱰدin ا ٔاﻟEudoxus
ﻓ� ﺑﲔa“ّدhippopede” إﱃ ﻣﻮﺿﻌﻪof�ﺎد ز ح دورةtheory
Cnidus’s ( وٕاذا ّﰎas ا���� �ﻧﯿ ًﺎ ا
ٕﱃ ﻩshown ﻧﺼﻔ ًﺎ آﺧﺮ
in وfigure ز
7.9).
It�ﻜﻮن
is interesting that Regiomontanus’s version of
زم �� ﺧﻂّ ج د �ﲑ ﻣﺎﺋﻞ ﻋﻨﻪ إﱃ �� اب ﻓﻬﺬا ﺑﯿﺎن ﻫﺬا اﻟﻮﺟﻪ وﻟﻜﻦ ﯾﻠﺰم �ﻠﯿﻪ ٔان this device resulted in a
curvilinear oscillation of S along a great circle arc, something that had been
و ٔا ّﻣﺎ اﻟﻘﻮلearlier
proposed �ﲞﻼف ذ by Joseph اﻟﻮﺟﻮدibn
اﳉﻨﻮب و
Naḥmias.ﻮﻧﻪ ﰲFor �ً ﻣﺴﺎوseeاﻟﺸﲈل
ﻟﺰﻣﺎن ﻛdetails, اﻟﻘﻄﺮ ﰲchap-
Morrison, زﻣﺎن ﻛﻮن
ﳛﻘّﻘﻪthis
ter 8, ﻧﻈﺮvolume,
ﳁﺤﺘﺎج إﱃespecially
ﺑﻄﻠﻤﯿﻮسfigure
�� ﻣﺎ ذﻛﺮ 8.3.ﻣﺮﻛﺰﻫﺎ
For the �ﲑreason
ﺣﻮل ﻧﻘﻄﺔthatداﺋﺮةtheﳏﯿﻂ �� ﲝﺮﻛﺘﻪ
Eudoxan-
couple should produce a hippopede, not a curvilinear oscillation, see
Neugebauer, “On the ‘Hippopede’ of Eudoxus.” �� ﻣﺎ ّﻣﺮ وﻧﻌﻮد إﱃ اﻟﻜ�ﺎب
20 F.J. Ragep, Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī’s Memoir, vol. 1, 220–3.
21 Shīrāzī, Al-Tuḥfa al-shāhiyya, fol. 34a:
وﳝﻜﻦ ٔان ﳚﻌﻞ ﻫﺬا دﻟﯿ ًﻼ �� اﻣ�ﻨﺎع اﻟﺴﻜﻮن ﺑﲔ ﺣﺮﻛﺘﲔ ﺻﺎ�ﺪة وﻫﺎﺑﻄﺔ �� ﲰﺖ ﻗﻄﺮ
ﻣﻦ ٔاﻗﻄﺎر ا ٔاﻟرض
22 Langermann, “Quies Media,” provides an excellent summary of the quies
media question and discusses a number of Islamic thinkers, including
Shīrāzī, who dealt with it.
23 The restriction of the date will exclude a discussion of the translation into
Sanskrit of part of ʿAbd al-ʿAlī al-Birjandī’s (d. 1525–26) commentary on
Ṭūsī’s Tadhkira, the part containing the presentation of the Ṭūsī-couple.
On this translation, see Kusuba and Pingree, Arabic Astronomy in Sanskrit.
24 On the use of aṣl to translate the Greek term hypothesis, see Morrison, chap-
ter 8, this volume, note 10.
25 These works are currently extant in three codices, two in the Vatican and
one in the Biblioteca Medicea Laurenziana in Florence.
26 Edition and translation in Paschos and Sotiroudis, Schemata of the Stars,
26–53.
264
From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-Couple 103
265
104 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
tempus movebitur super lineam rectam. Tunc ponatur ultra quod perifora
qua punctus B ascenderet motu suo tantum descendat motu planete. Et pa-
tet iterum quod punctus D continue movebit in eadem linea. Ergo totum
corpus planete movebitur motu recto usque ad aliquem terminum, et
iterum poterit reverti in motu consimilli.
39 Figure 7.10 is from Droppers, “Questiones de Spera,” 287, reproduced by
Goddu, Copernicus, 481. Note that despite the use of corpus in referring to
the planet, Goddu insists that “there is no indication that Oresme was dir-
ectly concerned with the physical characteristics of the bodies or the mech-
anisms” (481). This interpretation of Oresme may be why both Droppers
and Goddu seem capable of ignoring Oresme’s clear statement that it is
the “entire body of the planet” that moves in a straight line. We should also
note here that the title of this questio is “Whether any heavenly body (corpus
celeste) is moved circularly.”
40 Kren, “Rolling Device,” 492.
41 In contrast, Goddu, Copernicus, 480, finds Kren’s reconstruction “implaus-
ible,” but this assessment seems to be based on the grounds that Ṭūsī’s
construction requires two circles whereas Oresme’s requires three. He ap-
parently is unaware of Ṭūsī’s physicalization of his geometrical device and
his explicit use of three spheres in the Tadhkira. F.J. Ragep, Naṣīr al-Dīn al-
Ṭūsī’s Memoir, vol. 1, 200–1, 350–1, vol. 2, 435–7. Kren is able to see this use
of three spheres even though she was depending, as mentioned, on an ear-
lier French translation of this passage in which Ṭūsī describes how to physic-
alize his device. Kren, “Rolling Device,” 493n8. Goddu had access to a new
translation and discussion of this passage in the Tadhkira, so his claim that
Ṭūsī does not have a three-sphere model is odd.
42 What follows is a modified version of what is described in the Tadhkira,
book 2, ch. 11, para. 4. F.J. Ragep, Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī’s Memoir, vol. 1, 200–1;
see also fig. C13, in ibid., vol. 1, 351. For a discussion of this passage, see
ibid., vol. 2, 435–8.
43 Droppers, “Questiones de Spera,” 291.
44 See Morrison, chapter 8, this volume.
45 Dobrzycki and Kremer, “Peurbach and Marāgha.”
46 Aiton, “Peurbach’s Theoricae novae planetarum,” 36, 36n118.
47 Dobrzycki and Kremer, “Peurbach and Marāgha,” 233n53.
48 Dobrzycki, “Theory of Precession,” 51.
49 In addition to the previous reference, see also Dobrzycki, “Astronomical
Aspects,” 122; and Räumer, “Johannes Werners Abhandlung.”
50 On Amico, see Swerdlow, “Aristotelian Planetary Theory”; and Di Bono,
Le sfere omocentriche.
51 Ṭūsī refers to this third as “the enclosing sphere” (al-kura al-muḥīṭa). F.J.
Ragep, Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī’s Memoir, vol. 1, 220–1. Amico calls it a “with-
standing (obsistens) sphere.” Swerdlow, “Aristotelian Planetary Theory,” 41.
266
From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-Couple 105
267
106 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
268
From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-Couple 107
269
108 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
93 George Saliba has done some interesting work on Islamic scientific manu-
scripts in Europe, but his examples are after 1500. Saliba, “Arabic Science,”
154, 159. He points to an early copy of the Tadhkira (Vatican MS ar. 319),
which was brought to Rome in 1623 as part of the Palatine collection, one
of the spoils of the Thirty Years’ War that was offered by Maximilian I of
Bavaria to Pope Gregory XV. Ibid., 159–62. But it was certainly in central
Europe by the mid-sixteenth century, where it was used and perhaps anno-
tated by Jakob Christmann (1554–1613), professor of Hebrew and Arabic
at the University of Heidelberg. Levi Della Vida, Ricerche Sulla Formazione,
329ff., esp. 332. See also Swerdlow, “Recovery of the Exact Sciences.”
94 An example would be the treatise by ʿAlī Qushjī discussed in the next
paragraph. Other possibilities include manuscripts held by the Biblioteca
Medicea Laurenziana in Florence, such as a copy of Quṭb al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī’s
Nihāyat al-idrāk (MS Orientali 110) and two copies of his Al-Tuḥfa al-
shāhiyya fī al-hayʾa (MS Orientali 116c; and MS Orientali 215). In addition
to Ṭūsī’s models, Shīrāzī in these two works deals with models of Muʾayyad
al-Dīn al-ʿUrḍī as well as his own contributions to planetary theory.
Unfortunately, we do not know at present when these manuscripts first ap-
peared in Italy.
95 F.J. Ragep, “ʿAlī Qushjī and Regiomontanus.” The diagrams found in the
1496 Venice printing of Regiomontanus’s Epitome and in the manuscripts
of Qushjī’s treatise are quite similar.
96 Independent rediscovery now seems even less likely, given that
Regiomontanus not only does not claim ownership of the proposition but
also incorrectly attributes it to Ptolemy. See Shank, chapter 4, this volume.
97 Bisaha, chapter 2, this volume, discusses Bessarion’s attitudes and his rela-
tionship to European humanist scholars.
98 This point is emphasized in Sabra, “Situating Arabic Science.”
99 For an elaboration, see F.J. Ragep, “Review of The Beginnings.” A more
global approach is taken by Van Brummelen, Mathematics of the Heavens.
100 See, for example, Dursteler, Venetians in Constantinople. Bisaha, chapter 2,
this volume, also discusses some of the complex issues involving cross-
cultural transmission during this period.
101 Leo Africanus comes to mind.
102 Such travel has been noted in the case of Moses ben Judah Galeano.
103 Swerdlow and Neugebauer, Mathematical Astronomy, part 1, 48, emphasis
added.
104 See, for example, Dannenfeldt, “Renaissance Humanists”; and Saliba,
“Arabic Science.”
105 This was even the case in the early seventeenth century. Feingold,
“Decline and Fall.”
106 Although things are changing, it is disheartening to note that Robert
Westman in his recent book The Copernican Question, a tome of 681
270
271
INTRODUCTION
330
The Two Versions of the Ṭūsī Couple 113
331
114 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
As Tüsi: states explicitly in the l;lall, the purpose of the rectilinear version
of the Tüsi: couple is to have on hand a method of varying the distance of
the epicycle center from a given point by simply having it oscillate on a straight
line . 13 The device itself consists of two circles, one having a diameter half that
of the other, with the smaller being internally tangent to the larger (see FıGURE
1). in addition to these geometrical givens, there are several physical condi
tions. The two circles move in opposite directions, each with a simple, uni
form rotation, and the smaller circle has a rotation twice that of the larger.
The result of such a configuration is that a given point will oscillate on a straight
line between extrema A and B. 14
Actually, Tüsi: does not need two motions to achieve the oscillation of his
given point along the diameter of the larger circle; he merely needs to allow
the smaller circle to "roll" inside the larger one, which would remain stationary.
To see this we will again refer to FıGURE 1; now, however, instead of both
circles rotating in place, circle Z will roll inside circle D. At the starting point,
A and E coincide; after the smaller circle has rolled along arc AG, point E
will be at a distance GE from the point of tangency G. it is clear that GE =
AG; therefore, LGZE = 2LGDA since the radius of the smaller circle is half
that of the larger. Thus mathematically, this rolling is equivalent to having
the smaller circle rotate twice as fast as the larger one in the opposite direc
tion. We may alsa, being anachronistic, find the locus of the point E by noting
that the parametric equations of DZ + ZE are
x = s cos a + s cos ( - a ) = 2 s cos a
y = s sin a + s sin (-a) = O,
which indicate that point E will oscillate on a straight line. (Note that it is
unnecessary to make any assumptions about the whereabouts of point E or
that LGDE. == LGDA.)
This sort of analysis seems to be the hasis for calling the Tüsi: couple a
"rolling device. "15 Unfortunately, such an appelation seriously misrepresents
332
The Two Versions of the Ṭūsī Couple 115
FIGURE 1
Tüsi's intentions, not to mention the entire thrust of medieval Islamic theo
retical astronomy. The TüsI couple is not simply a mathematical formula
tion; it is meant to possess a physical reality. Therefore each of the two circles
must rotate in place since the rolling of one celestial body inside another is
precluded by the absence of any void in the heavens and the stricture against
any "tearing or mending. "16
That Tüsi means the couple to have a physical reality becomes strikingly
clear in the presentation of his lunar and planetary models. 17 Instead of circles,
we now have two spheres, the Iarger of which rotates with half the speed of
the smaller; the given point E has been replaced by a spherical epicycle (see
FıcuıtE 2). The couple itself is composed of the two circles, shown with dotted
lines, that would be the resultant paths of the epicycle center if the large and
small spheres were to rotate independently of one another. 18 These two paths
are referred to by Tüsi as equators (mintaqas) though it is obvious that they
do not fit the standard definition. 19 Nevertheless as they are concentric and
coplanar with their corresponding equators, we shall refer to them as "inner
333
116 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
334
The Two Versions of the Ṭūsī Couple 117
335
118 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
E Q equant point
C center of Ptolemalc deferent
O center of World
E eplcycle center
FıGURE 4. Tüsfs planetary model.
center will be at perigee after half a rotation of the deferent (see FıGURE 3).
But since this should occur at quadrature according to Ptolemaic theory,
Tüsı must now rotate the deferent in the opposite direction. This is accom•
plished by enclosing the deferent with the inclined orb (al•falak al•ma'il),
which shares with the former the same poles and center. The inclined orb
is thus the source of the ''motion of apogee" of the Almagest. Finally the in•
clined orb is enclosed by the parecliptic orb, which has the same center but
poles that are at a distance of 5 ° from those of the deferent and inclined orbs.
Its equator, which is in the plane of the ecliptic, intersects the equator of the
inclined orb at two points called the nodes ('uqdatan or jawzahar). The
rather slow retrograde motion of the parecliptic accounts for the motion of
the nodes (approximately 19·year eyde).
336
The Two Versions of the Ṭūsī Couple 119
FIGURE 5.
For the planets, exduding Mercury, one has a somewhat different arrange
ment. 24 The deferent in this case is an eccentric orb, embedded within the
parecliptic, whose center Q is that of the equant in the Ptolemaic model, i.e.
it is at a distance 2e from the center of the World O and at a distance e from
the center C of the Ptolemaic deferent, where e is the eccentricity (see FıcuRE
4; only the "inner equators" are shown in order to simplify the illustration).
Embedded within the deferent is the large sphere of the Tüsi couple, whose
inner equator has a diameter of 2e while the inner equator of the small sphere
has a diameter e. Now in order for the distance OE from the center of the
World to the epicyde center to be R + e at apogee and R - e at perigee so
as to conform with the requirements of the Ptolemaic model where R is the
radius of the deferent (see FıcuRE 5), the epicycle center E at apogee must be
at its closest position to Q while at perigee it must be at its farthest distance.
It then easily follows that the inner equator of the deferent in this model has
a radius of R + e and that the starting position of E must be, in contrast to
that of the lunar epicycle center, at the extremum on the line of oscillation
that is nearest Q. Thus Tüsi will need, as he states, three additional spheres
for his model over what is used in the Ptolemaic planetary configuration: the
337
120 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
338
The Two Versions of the Ṭūsī Couple 121
339
122 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
large and small spheres of his couple and an "enclosing sphere" for the epicycle.
This latter, as for the lunar epicycle, is needed to keep the epicyclic apex and
perigee aligned with the point about which uniform motion occurs, in this
case the equant center Q.
The following table summarizes the parameters of the various orbs and
equators and their motions.
As for that most insidious planet Mercury, Naşir al-Din admits unquali
fied defeat: "for it is difficult to see how one can make the motion uniform
about a point in which the moved object in its motion toward and away from
it is composed of multiple motions, "25 a plaint directed at Mercury's so-called
"crank mechanism." He does, though, promise to append a solution to Al
Tadhkira if he were ever to find one; as there is no trace of such a work or
reference to it in the commentaries, Mercury would seem to have eluded him
to the end. 26
340
The Two Versions of the Ṭūsī Couple 123
Farthest Dlstance
R·e
Mld�oint between
the "Two Dlıtınces
e R·e e
R·e
Eplcycle Center Center of World l;P.icycle enter
af Mean Dlstance at Meın Dlıtance
fIGURE 6.
has shown, Tüsı is absolutely correct; the maximum difference turns out to
be approximately 8 minutes of arc, and does indeed occur at the octants. 29
in the course of his discussion, Tüsı makes the very interesting remark
that this maximum difference of 1/ 6 of a degree at the octants is "an imper
ceptible amount" (ghayr ma�süs), which gives some idea of what the director
of an observatory in the 13th century believed to be the limits of observation.
Since Tüsı also declares, this time with regard to his planetary models, that
"the distances of the epicycle center from the center of the World are the same
as resulted from the [Ptolemaic] deferent without there being a difference that
might disturb the situation of these planets, "30 it would seem appropriate to
test this daim as well.
From FıGURE 4, it is clear that the Earth-epicycle center distance in Tüsı's
planetary models will be given by
341
124 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
342
The Two Versions of the Ṭūsī Couple 125
343
126 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
C center of deferent
O center of World
P polnt of algnment
(prosneusis polnt)
E : center of eplcycle
FtGURE 8.
whose maximum absolute value is reached when L CPE = 0 °, 180 °, thus con
firming that the maximum speed of point T will indeed take place at the apogee
and perigee.
For Tüsi, this motion is a clear violation of the physical premises under
which an astronomer should work. For the epicycle, which is a solid body,
would oscillate on the diameter connecting the poles of the epicycle (i.e. the
diameter perpendicular to the plane of the paper) and would thus not com
plete the required uniform rotation. 34 The emphasis on solid movers is im
portant here. Tüsi would not accept, for example, a solution in which the
oscillation of point T were somehow replaced by a motion on a small circle
since this sort of circular motion would not have been brought about by uni
formly rotating orbs. Tüsi makes this point explicitly when he draws our at
tention to the close similarity of the prosneusis point ishkal and the difficulty
arising from Ptolemy's latitude theory as presented in the Almagest. 35 in the
case of all five planets, the endpoints of the diameters of the epicycles that
344
The Two Versions of the Ṭūsī Couple 127
1
1
1
182
____ _ .c; ____ _
FıGURE 9.
are aligned with the equant 36 will perform a revolution upon a small circle
perpendicular to the plane of the deferent. This will produce that component
of latitude called the deviation (mayi) (see FıGURE 9). 37 Mercury and Venus
are distinguished by a further latitudinal variation, called the slant (in�iriif),
whereby the endpoints of a second diameter at right angles to the first and
in the same plane will perform a similar revolution upon small circles, again
perpendicular to the deferent.
Tüsı raises three objections to Ptolemy's construction. 38 First, "it does not
take into account the configuration (hay'a) of those bodies that are the prin
ciples for these motions." Since a point in a medieval cosmological system
cannot simply move by itself, one must provide the appropriate uniformly
rotating orbs to produce motion. Second, "it compounds the difficulty that
we are expending all this effort to resolve by making the motion uniform about
a point other than the center of its revolution." This is because the endpoint
moves along the small circle with the same nonuniform motion as that of the
epicycle center on the deferent. Finally, "just as the aforementioned small circles
bring about latitudinal inclinations, they also cause inclinations to occur in
longitude ... " Unlike the first two objections, this one is not a problem of
physics (or, as some would have it, "philosophy") but in the predictive ability
345
128 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
346
The Two Versions of the Ṭūsī Couple 129
347
130 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
the oscillating apex and perigee between the small sphere and the epicycle.
As should be clear from FıGURE 11, it must move in the same direction and
with the same speed as the large sphere in order to bring the rest of the epicycle
to its proper position. (This orb is analogous to the enclosing orb (mul;ııfa)
of the rectilinear version.) The net result far the epicycle as a whole would
then be an oscillation on an axis coincident with the mean diameter, i.e. the
diameter of the epicycle in the plane of the deferent perpendicular to AB. 41
Such a series of three enclosing orbs is not only useful in resolving the
problem of the motion of the planetary epicycles in latitude, it can alsa be
used whenever an oscillation between extrema on a great circle arc is needed.
Thus as Tüsı notes, the second version of his couple may account far the os
cillation of the equator of the inclined orb of the two inferior planets in lati
tude as well as the longitudinal inclination of the diameter of the lunar epicycle
due to its alignment with the prosneusis point. Finally Tüsı remarks that his
device could even produce a trepidation of the equinoxes as well as a cyclical
change in the obliquity of the ecliptic. 42
But there are problems with the curvilinear version, some of which Tüsı
acknowledges, some of which he does not. One that seems to have escaped
him is the failure of the couple to work as advertised. The resultant locus
will not, in fact, be an arc but rather a stretched aut figure 8 on the surface
of a sphere (see FıGURE 11). 43 To see this we need only note that in spherical
triangle EA2H the exterior angle FEA2 must be less than the sum of interior
angles EHA2 and EA2H; 44 the endpoint of radius vector EAz must therefare
always extend beyond arc A1G except when 0 = n90 °, n any integer, in which
case A2 will fall on it. Nevertheless, because of the small size of the arcs of
oscillation, divergence will be slight. 45
Another remaining difficulty, one that Tüsı must regretfully admit he is
incapable of resolving, is related to objection two. 46 Because the motion of
epicyclic apex A is approximately given by AıH - AıH cos 0, 47 it is clear
that its inclination in either direction from H will be exactly equivalent in
amount and duration; the Ptolemaic theory, however, requires that this incli
nation be of longer duration in one half than the other since the motion of
point A on the small circle is coordinated with the irregular motion of the
epicycle center on the deferent. Similarly, far the case of the inclination of
the lunar epicycle due to the prosneusis point, Tüsı notes that his construc
tion will result in a motion of inclination that is symmetrical with respect
to the line joining the centers of the epicycle and the deferent whereas the
Ptolemaic model results in an asymmetrical motion of inclination48 (see above
and FıGURE 8). Undoubtedly these lingering unresolved problems, as well as
the lack of any model far Mercury, were important motivations far subse
quent generations of astronomers.
348
The Two Versions of the Ṭūsī Couple 131
One aspect of the Tüsi models that is especially perplexing is the manner
in which certain orbs may move others. 49 in particular, it is not immediately
obvious how the mu�fta, or enclosing sphere, is capable of moving the
epicycle. Because they are coaxial and concentric, and because of the lack
of friction or violent motion in the heavens, it is difficult to see how Tüsi
intends the mu�fta to cause a motion in the epicycle.
in order to deal with this specific issue, it will be useful to digress a bit
and briefly discuss the general problem of medieval celestial dynamics. Each
uniformly rotating orb, of course, is the source of a single motion, but in ad
dition it may also be capable of simultaneously moving another orb. To un
derstand how this is possible, it is important to be clear as to what precisely
is meant by the term orb (falak). Tüsi defines it as "a spherical solid bounded
by two concentric parallel surfaces," one convex, the other concave. 50 Some
orbs, though, such as epicycles, have an inner surface that degenerates to a
point; it is on this account that an orb may sometimes be a sphere. 51 in the
case of eccentrics and epicycles, there is really no dynamical problem since
these bodies are moved simply as a consequence of being contained within
the thickness of another moving orb with a different center. (See FıGURE U
in which these two possibilities are illustrated.)
On the other hand, there was a problem in understanding how one orb
could move another orb concentric to it. Part of the reason for the difficulty
arose because of a somewhat different conception of the orbs in the cos
mographical tradition exemplified by Al-Tadhkira than that found, say, in
Ptolemy's Planetary hypotheses and in the less specialized Arabic literature
such as Ibn Rushd's Talkhış ma ba' d al-tabi' a (Epitome of the metaphysics)
or the Rasa'il (Epistles) of the Ikhwan al-Şafa. 52 There the heavens are stated
to be a single living being. Hence the daily motion is simply the motion of
the whole, and the other orbs are considered parts of this whole. But in the
hay'a literature, the daily motion is caused by the ninth orb which is a discrete
orb as defined above. Thus, for example, Tüsi does not take it for granted
that the eighth orb, which contains the fixed stars, or any other orb for that
matter, will partake in some automatic way of the first motion, i.e. the daily
rotation of the heavens. The ninth orb, which shares the same center but not
the poles of the eighth, is given the awesome task of transmitting to the eighth
orb, as well as to all else in the heavens, its own daily rotation. 53 Tüsi is not
very explicit in telling us how this transmission will occur. The classical solu
tion, and the one most widely assumed in modern discussions of medieval
cosmology, would somehow attach the poles of the eighth orb into the ninth.
This is rejected by the commentators on Al-Tadhkira. Al-Sharif • Alı al-Jur
jani (d. 1413), for example, does so on the grounds that
349
132 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
350
The Two Versions of the Ṭūsī Couple 133
351
134 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
I wish to express my gratitude to Sally Palchik Ragep for drafting the dia
grams and to A. I. Sabra for commenting on various stages of this article.
They are, of course, not responsible for any remaining shortcomings.
NOTES
1. Dreyer, 269, n. 1, seems to have been the first to recognize that Copernicus employs Tusı's
construction for producing rectilinear motion.
2. Hartner 1969, 302.
3. Whence the name of the enterprise 'ilm al-hay'a, i.e. the "science of hay'a." Eventually this
came to denote astronomy in a general sense though the more specialized meaning was stili un
derstood. See, for example, Tashkubrızade, 1: 372.
4. The mest important of the early criticisms of Ptolemy occurs in Ibn al-Haytham's AI-Shu
kük 'alii Baflamyus, partially translated in Sabra 1978. George Saliha deals with two other con
temporary criticisms in his lbn Sina and Abu ·Ubayd al-Juzjanı: The problem of the Ptolemaic
equant. Al-Biruni (973-ca. 1050) is also aware of the problems inherent in physicalizing
Ptolemy's geometrical models; see, for example, his AI-Qanün al-Mas' udı, 2: 838.
5. Cf. Shams al-Din MuJ:ıammad al-Khafri (fi. early 16th c.), Bk. II, Ch. 11, ff. 189b-190a.
6. See, among others, Kennedy, 366-7; Hartner 1975, 9.
7. Tadhkira, Bk. I, Ch. 2. An edition and translation of Bk. I and Bk. II (Chapters 1-11) of Al
Tadhkira is included in my Cosmography in the Tadhkira of Naşır al-Din al-'füsı.
8. This is explicitly stated by Ni;ı:am al-Din al-Nisaburı (fi. early 14th c.), f. 10a.
9. Cf. Aristotle De Caelo, Bk. I, Ch. 3, 270b5-16, and Metaphysica, Bk. XII, Ch. 7, 1072a20-23.
10. Tadhkira, Bk. I, Ch. 2, par. 3.
11. üne finds the non-Ptolemaic models of the lfall in Ch. 3. The lfall and the R.-i Mu·ıniyya
352
The Two Versions of the Ṭūsī Couple 135
353
136 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
354
The Two Versions of the Ṭūsī Couple 137
355
138 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
Moesgaard, K. P.
1968 T he 1717 Egyptian years and the Copemican theory of precession. Centaurus,
13: 120-38.
Neugebauer, Otto
1975 A history of ancient mathematical astronomy, 3 vols. New York: Springer-Verlag.
al-Nisaburı, Ni�am al-Din l:{asan b. Mui)ammad
Tawc,II!, "al-Tadhkira." Landon, British Library MS Add. 7472.
Pedersen, Olaf
1974 A survey of the Almagest. Odense: Odense University Press.
Ragep, F. Jamil
1982 Cosmography in the Tadhkira of Naşir al-Din al-Tüsı, 2 vols. Ph.D. disserta
tion, Harvard University.
Sabra, A. I.
1978 An eleventh-century refutation of Ptolemy's planetary theory. in Studia Coper
nicana XVI, 117-31. Warsaw: Ossolineum.
1979 lbn al-Haytham's treatise: Solutions of the difficulties concerning the move
ment of iltifiif. Journal for the History of Arabic Science, 3 (Nov.): 388-422.
Saliba, George
1980 lbn Sına and Abü 'Ubayd al-Jüzjanı: The problem of the Ptolemaic equant.
Journal for the History of Arabic Science, 4: 376-403.
Tashkubrızade, Ai)mad b. Muş\afa
1968 Miftah al-sa'ada wa-mişbah al-siyada, 3 vols. Cairo: Dar al-kutub-al-i)a
ıfitha.
al-Tüsı, Naşır al-Din
Jfa/1-i mushkilıit-i Mu'ıniyya. lntroduction by Mui)ammad Taqi Danish-Pi
zhüh. Teheran: lntisharat Danishgah Tahran (no. 304 in the series), 1335 H. Sh.
Risalah-i Mu'ıniyya dar hay'a. lntroduction by Mul)ammad Taqi Danish
Pizhüh. Teheran: lntisharat Danishgah Tahran (no. 300 in the series), 1335 H.
Sh.
Al-Tadhkira fi 'ilm al-hay'a. Edition and translation of Books I and II (Chapters
1-11) in Ragep, Vol. II.
Subsequent to the writing of this paper, the article by E. S. Kennedy referred to in note 11 has
appeared as Two Persian astronomical treatises by Naşır al-Dın al-Tüsi, Centaurus, 27 (1984):
109-20.
356
The originsThe
of the Ṭūsī-couple
origins revisited
of the Ṭūsī-couple revisited
Among the many contributions by James Evans to the history of astronomy is his clear and el-
egant paper on the origin of Ptolemy’s equant.1 As has been his hallmark, he there brought his
considerable talent as a modern scientist together with his sophisticated historical sensitivity.
The result was an important contribution to the vexed problem of the origins of this problematic
device.2
The equant itself, despite its success in resolving observational issues related to the retro-
grade arcs of the planets, evoked considerable controversy among Islamic astronomers because
of the violations resulting from it of the strictures of uniformity and circularity in the heavens.
Among the devices proposed for dealing with these violations was the Ṭūsī-couple, put forth
by the famous thirteenth-century astronomer and polymath Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī (1201-1274).
Although it has been known for some time that Ṭūsī used the device in his lunar and planetary
models found in his al-Tadhkira fī ʿilm al-hayʾa (Memoir on the science of astronomy), there has
been a divergence of opinion about when Ṭūsī first proposed his new device and models. In this
paper, I present new evidence that sheds light on the first appearance of the Ṭūsī-couple.
In an earlier paper,3 I argued that Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī first announced his famous astronom-
ical device, which we now refer to as the Ṭūsī-couple, in a Persian astronomical work entitled
the Risālah-i Muʿīniyya (The Muʿīniyya treatise, named for one of Ṭūsī’s patrons), which was com-
pleted in 632/1235.4 He first presented it in the appendix to this work, which is called, among
other things, the Ḥall-i mushkilāt-i Muʿīniyya and Dhayl-i Muʿīniyya (the resolution of difficulties in
the Muʿīniyya; appendix to the Muʿīniyya). I maintained that there were compelling reasons for
believing that the Ḥall predated a second version of the couple briefly presented in Ṭūsī’s Taḥrīr
al-Majisṭī (Recension of the Almagest), which was completed in 644/1247; however, there was still
some question since no manuscript had yet been found that gave a date for the Ḥall. But thanks
to an examination of a manuscript in Tashkent, which was brought to my attention by Sergei
Tourkin, we now have a date for the Ḥall and therefore for the first publication of the Ṭūsī-cou-
ple. This new dating confirms my original chronology, but it also raises some new questions and
puzzles, which I discuss in what follows.
Before presenting this new evidence, let me briefly summarize the information we have on
the Ṭūsī-couple. The final and most complete presentation of Ṭūsī’s models occurs in al-Tadhkira
fī ʿilm al-hay’a, written in Arabic, which first appeared in 659/1261 when Ṭūsī was the director of
the Marāgha observatory that had been established under Mongol patronage in Azerbaijan. Ṭūsī
presents them in the context of criticisms of the models that had been developed by Claudius
Ptolemy in the 2nd century CE in Alexandria, Egypt, and brought forth in the latter’s Almagest
1 Evans 1984.
2 For a review of several theories on the origin of the equant, see Duke 2005.
3 Ragep 2000.
4 When separated by a slash, the first date is lunar hijrī; the second is common era. Otherwise the date is com-
mon era.
Instruments – Observations – Theories: Studies in the History of Astronomy in Honor of James Evans, ed. Alexander Jones and
Christián Carman, 2020, DOI: 10.5281/zenodo.3928498, pp. 229–237. Chapter DOI: 10.5281/zenodo.3975745. Open access distribu-
tion under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International (CC-BY) license.
140 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
230
The Origins of the Ṭūsī-Couple Revisited 141
231
142 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
Ṭūsī promises to put his solution in a separate work if the “Prince of Iran...would be so
pleased to pursue this problem,” a reference to Muʿīn al-Dīn Abū al-Shams, the son of his patron
Nāṣir al-Dīn Muḥtasham. And indeed, a solution is presented in the Ḥall-i mushkilāt-i Muʿīniyya.
The Ḥall consists of 9 chapters:
Chapter 1: On the possibility of a fixed star در �آنكه چون متام عرض كوكىب از ثوابت:1 فصل
whose colatitude is greater than the differ-
ence between the local latitude and the to-
زايدت از فضل عرض بدل بر ميل لكّى بود ممكن ابشد
tal obliquity, after having been either per- كه بعد از �آنكه ابدى الظهور اي ابدى اخلفا بوده ابشد
manently visible or permanently invisible,
becoming invisible or visible
اورا خفاىئ اي ظهورى حادث شود
Chapter 2: On why the eccentric orb was در �آنكه فكل خارج مركز هجت �آفتاب چرا بر:2 فصل
chosen for the sun over the epicycle
تدوير اختيار كرده اند
Chapter 3: On the solution of the difficulty در ح ّل شىك كه بر حركت مركز تدوير ماه:3 فصل
occurring with regard to the motion of the
center of the lunar epicycle on the circum-
بر حميط حامل و تشابه �آن حركت بر حواىل مركز عامل
ference of the deferent, and the uniformi- واردست
ty of that motion about the center of the
World
Chapter 4: On the explanation of the circuit در رشح مدار مركز تدوير مقر و چگونگی:4 فصل
of the moon’s epicycle center and the man-
ner in which the circuit of the center of the
حدوث مدار مركز فكل تدوير ماه
lunar epicycle orb comes about
Chapter 5: On the configuration of the plan- در هي�أت افالك تداوير سسيارگان بر مذهب:5 فصل
ets’ epicycle orbs according to the doctrine
of Abū ʿAlī ibn al-Haytham
ابو عىل بن الهيمث
Chapter 6: On the explanation for finding در رشح معرفت مواضع اقامت كواكب از:6 فصل
the stationary positions of the planets on
the epicycle orb
فكل تدوير
Chapter 7: On clarifying the different cir- در بيان تفاوت احوال خسوف وكسوف از:7 فصل
cumstances of lunar and solar eclipses from
the point of view of difference in latitude
هجت تفاوت عرض وغري �آن
and other matters
232
The Origins of the Ṭūsī-Couple Revisited 143
جهريه مبقام بدلة تون۶۴۳ اتفق فراغ املصنف رفع هللا مراتبه ىف معارج القدس من اتليفه اوايل جامدى الآخرة سسنه
ابلبسستان املعروف بباغ بركه
The treatise is completed, praise be to God. The author, may God elevate his stature on the
ascents to the Divine, completed its composition during the first part of Jamādā II, 643 of the
Hijra, within the town of Tūn in the garden known as Bāgh Barakah. [=late October 1245]
We should note here that Ṭūsī at this time was in the employ of the Ismāʿīlī rulers of
Qūhistān in southern Khurāsān. As stated by Farhad Daftary: “The supreme Nezārī [Ismāʿīlī]
leader, whether dāʿī or imam, selected the local chief dāʿīs to serve in the main Nezāri territories:
Kūhestān (Qohestān) in southern Khorasan and Syria. The chief dāʿī (often called moḥtašem [as
is the case here]) of the Kūhestān Nezārīs usually lived in Tūn, [in] Qāʾen, or [in] the fortress of
Moʾmenābād, near Bīrjand.”9 Tūn, today called Firdaws, lay some 80 km/50 miles west-north-
west of the main town of the region, Qāʾin.
7 For an edition, translation and discussion of this part of the Ḥall, see Ragep 2004.
8 I thank the Bīrūnī Institute for providing images of this valuable manuscript. On the side of the last page, the
text is said to have been collated with a copy that had been collated with a copy in the hand of the author (i.e. Ṭūsī)
on 4 Ramaḍān 825/late August 1422 (f. 46a). The page with the colophon and copy date is reproduced in the Appen-
dix below.
9 Daftary 1993, 6.592 (col. 1). I have added a few clarifying remarks between square brackets.
233
144 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
234
The Origins of the Ṭūsī-Couple Revisited 145
3) The criticism of Ibn al-Haytham’s latitude model that Ṭūsī gave in the Muʿīniyya is not
repeated in the Ḥall. Instead he presents Ibn al-Haytham’s model without commentary. This
seems another indication that in writing the Ḥall he still had not come up with the second,
curvilinear version of his device.
4) The model for latitude that Ṭūsī describes in the Taḥrīr al-Majisṭī is schematic at best. In
fact, it is a rather simplistic adaptation of the rectilinear Ṭūsī-couple and very different from
the curvilinear version given in the Tadhkira, which Ṭūsī presented as an adaptation of Ibn
al-Haytham’s model.13
From this we can conclude that the Ṭūsī-couple, and its applications to various planetary
models, emerged in stages and rather slowly. After coming up with the idea, apparently when
writing the Muʿīniyya, it took many years before he felt comfortable enough to present it in the
Ḥall. And at the time of writing the Ḥall, he still had not come up with the curvilinear version. A
year later he tentatively put forth a kind of adaptation of the rectilinear version for a latitude
model, but it was completely unsatisfactory since it produced straight-line motion, not the need-
ed curvilinear oscillation along a great circle arc. Fifteen years later, he would bring forth both
versions in their final form in his Arabic adaptation of the Persian Muʿīniyya, namely al-Tadhkira
fī ʿilm al-hayʾa.
i.e. 13°11' (Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī 1335 H. Sh./1956-7 CE, f. 11). It is of great historical interest that it is the Ḥall version
of Ṭūsī’s lunar model that makes it into the Byzantine Greek work of Gregory Chioniades (d. ca. 1320) entitled the
Schemata of the Stars, which would be available in Italy by the fifteenth century at the latest; see Ragep 2014, 242. For
a listing of the parameters for the lunar model in the Tadhkira, see Ragep 1993, 2.457; a comparison of parameters
between the Tadhkira and Ḥall can be found in Ragep 2017, 167.
13 Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī, Taḥrīr al-Majisṭī, Istanbul, Feyzullah MS 1360, ff. 199b-202a. This assessment of the model in
the Taḥrīr al-Majisṭī, as well as the chronology of the development of the two versions of the Ṭūsī-couple, would tend
to undermine the conclusions reached by G. Saliba 1987. A translation, edition, and analysis of the relevant parts
of the Taḥrīr can be found in Ragep 2017, 168-171 and endnote 15. The Taḥrīr version appears in various European
contexts, including Copernicus’s De revolutionibus, for which see Ragep 2017, 182-184.
235
146 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
Appendix
Figure 4. Colophon (boxed in red by current author) of Ḥall-i mushkilāt-i Muʿīniyya, Tashkent, al-Bīrūnī Institute of
Oriental Studies, MS 8990, f. 46a (original foliation). Courtesy of the Institute.
236
The Origins of the Ṭūsī-Couple Revisited 147
References
Daftary, F. 1993. “Dāʿī.” In Encyclopaedia Iranica. New York. Vol. 6, 590-593.
Duke, D. W. 2005. “Comment on the Origin of the Equant Papers by Evans, Swerdlow, and Jones.”
Journal for the History of Astronomy 36, 1-6.
Evans, J. 1984. “On the Function and the Probable Origin of Ptolemy’s Equant.” American Journal
of Physics 52, 1080-1089.
Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī. Taḥrīr al-Majisṭī. Istanbul, Feyzullah MS 1360.
Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī. 1335 H. Sh./1956-7 CE. Ḥall-i mushkilāt-i Muʿīniyya, facsimile of Tehran, Malik
3503 with an introduction by Muḥammad Taqī Dānish-Pizhūh. Tehran.
Ragep, F. J. 1987. “The Two Versions of the Ṭūsī Couple.” In D. King and G. Saliba, eds., From Def-
erent to Equant: Studies in Honor of E. S. Kennedy (vol. 500 of The Annals of the New York Academy of
Sciences). New York. 329-356.
Ragep, F. J. 1993. Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī’s Memoir on Astronomy (al-Tadhkira fī ʿilm al-hayʾa). 2 vols. New
York.
Ragep, F. J. 2000. “The Persian Context of the Ṭūsī Couple.” In N. Pourjavady and Ž. Vesel, eds.,
Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī: Philosophe et Savant du XIIIe Siècle. Tehran. 113-130.
Ragep, F. J. 2004. “Ibn al-Haytham and Eudoxus: The Revival of Homocentric Modeling in Islam.”
In C. Burnett, J. P. Hogendijk, K. Plofker and M. Yano, eds., Studies in the History of the Exact Sci-
ences in Honour of David Pingree. Leiden. 786-809.
Ragep, F. J. 2014. “New Light on Shams: The Islamic Side of Σὰμψ Πουχάρης.” In J. Pfeiffer, ed.,
Politics, Patronage, and the Transmission of Knowledge in 13th - 15th Century Tabriz. Leiden. 231-247.
Ragep, F. J. 2017. “From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-Couple.” In R. Feldhay
and F. J. Ragep, eds., Before Copernicus: The Cultures and Contexts of Scientific Learning in the Fif-
teenth Century. Montreal & Kingston. 161-197.
Ragep, F. J. and B. Hashemipour. 2006. “Juft-i Ṭūsī (the Ṭūsī-Couple).” In The Encyclopaedia of the
World of Islam (in Persian). Tehran. Vol. X, 472-475.
Saliba, G. 1987. “The Role of the Almagest Commentaries in Medieval Arabic Astronomy: A Pre-
liminary Survey of Ṭūsī’s Redaction of Ptolemy’s Almagest.” Archives internationales d’histoire des
sciences 37, 3-20.
237
Chioniades, Gregor [George]
© F. Jamil Ragep
(The Persian translation has been published as “Khiyūniyādis [Chioniades],” in Dāʾirat al-
Maʿārif-i Buzurg-i Islāmī (Iran) [The Great Islamic Encyclopaedia], vol. 23 (Tehran: Markaz-i
Dāʾirat al-Maʿārif-i Buzurg-i Islāmī, 1396/2018), 355-58.)
Chioniades, christened George, was born sometime between 1240 and 1250 CE in
Constantinople and became one of the leading figures in Byzantine astronomy.1 Little is known
about his early life and education, but in 1295 he traveled to the kingdom of Trebizond, which
was ruled at the time by Emperor John II Komnenos (reigned 1280–1297). There it is likely that
he composed notes to John of Damascus’s (d. 749 CE) Dialectics and a work entitled On the
Orthodox Faith. Trebizond would serve as a way station for the ultimate aim of his journey,
which was Īlkhānid Iran; in this he was supported by Komnenos, and later that year he arrived at
the court of Ghāzān Khān (reigned 694-703 H/1295-1304 CE) in Tabrīz. George Chrysococces
(fl. 1350) would later relate, based on the testimony of his teacher Manuel (fl. 1330s CE), that at
first Chioniades found it difficult to find a teacher of astronomy, since, according to Manuel, that
was a subject restricted to Persians only. But he persevered and apparently won favor with
Ghāzān Khān as well as with the redoubtable Rashīd al-Dīn Ṭabīb (d. 718 H/1318 CE), the
historian, physician, and sometime minister at the court of Ghāzān. Indeed, Chrysococces
informs us that “Chioniades shone in Persia, and was thought to be worthy of the King’s
1
An important source for his life is his sixteen extant letters that have been published in Jean B.
Papadopoulos, ed., Grigoríou Chioniádou tou astronómou epistolaí [in Greek, Modern] (Thessaloníki:
Panepistimio Thessaloníkis, 1929) and idem, “Une lettre de Grégoire Chioniadès, évêque de Tabriz—
Rapports entre Byzance et les Mongols de Perse,” in Mélanges Charles Diehl: Études sur l’histoire et sur
l’art de Byzance, vol. 1, Histoire (Paris: E. Leroux, 1930), 257-62. An excellent summary of what is
known of the life of Chioniades can be found in Joseph Gerard Leichter, “The Zīj as-Sanjarī of Gregory
Chioniades: Text, Translation and Greek to Arabic Glossary” (PhD diss., Brown University, 2004), 2-6.
Cf. L. G. Westerink, “La profession de foi de Grégoire Chioniadès,” Revue des études byzantines 38
(1980): 233-45; and David Pingree, “Gregory Chioniades and Palaeologan Astronomy,” Dumbarton Oaks
Papers 18 (1964): 133-60; reprinted in Pathways into the Study of Ancient Sciences: Selected Essays by
David Pingree, eds. Isabelle Pingree and John M. Steele, Transactions of the American Philosophical
Society, n.s., 104, no. 3 (Philadelphia: American Philosophical Society, 2014), 365-91. See also Maria
Mavroudi, “Exchanges with Arabic Writers During the Late Byzantine Period,” in Byzantium: Faith and
Power (1261-1557): Perspectives on Late Byzantine Art and Culture, ed. Sarah T. Brooks (New York:
Metropolitan Museum of Art, 2007), 62-75.
150 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
2 Chioniades
honour.”2 This would seem partially corroborated by the existence of a short tract by Rashīd al-
Dīn giving answers to questions posed by Chioniades on difficult physical and theological
matters, which was later translated into Greek.3 More importantly, Chioniades was granted what
he so much desired, namely instruction in astronomy. He tells us that his teacher was someone
known in Greek sources as Shams Bukharos, whom we can identify as Shams al-Dīn
Muḥammad ibn ʿAlī Khwāja al-Wābkanawī al-Munajjim (b. 652 H/1254 CE), the author of a zīj
(astronomical handbook with tables) entitled al-Zīj al-muḥaqqaq al‐sulṭānī ʿalā uṣūl al-raṣad al-
Īlkhānī (The verified zīj for the sultan based on the principles of the Īlkhānī observations) and a
work on the astrolabe; he is also most likely the author of a commentary on Naṣīr al-Dīn al-
Ṭūsī’s (d. 672 H/1274 CE) astronomical work al-Tadhkira fī ʿilm al-hayʾa entitled Tibyān
maqāṣid al-Tadhkira (Exposition of the intent of the Tadhkira).4 From November 1295 until
November 1296, Shams al-Dīn apparently dictated, in Persian, the rules for using the Zīj al-
ʿAlāʾī of ʿAbd al-Karīm al-Fahhād (fl. 1176), which Chioniades rendered into Greek as the
Persian Astronomical Composition.5 During this period he also collected a number of works that
he would subsequently translate into Greek.
By September 1301, Chioniades was back in Trebizond and had returned home to
Constantinople in April 1302. There he taught students the astronomy and medicine he had
learned while in Persia and translated, presumably from Persian into Greek, a set of recipes for
antidotes as well as a number of astronomical treatises. He also wrote a confession of faith,
perhaps to counter accusations of heresy accruing from his work in astrology and his years
2
For the full report by Chrysococces, see Raymond Mercier, “The Greek ‘Persian Syntaxis’ and the Zīj‐i
Īlkhānī,” Archives internationales d’histoire des sciences 34 (1984): 35-60, on 35-36; reproduced with
slight emendations in Leichter, “Zīj as-Sanjarī,” 3.
3
See Zeki Velidi Togan, “İlhanlı Bizans kültür münasebetlerine dair vesikalar” (“A Document
Concerning Cultural Relation Between the İlkhanide and Byzantiens” [sic]), İslâm Tetkikleri Enstitüsü
Dergisi 3 (1959–60): 315-78 (= 1-39). I owe this reference to Dimitri Gutas, “Arabic into Byzantine
Greek: Introducing a Survey of the Translations,” in Knotenpunkt Byzanz: Wissensformen und kulturelle
Wechselbeziehungen, eds. Andreas Speer and Philipp Steinkrüger (Berlin: De Gruyter, 2012), 246-62, on
258.
4
On Shams al-Dīn al-Wābkanawī and his identification with Shams Bukharos, see F. Jamil Ragep, “New
Light on Shams: The Islamic Side of Σὰμψ Πουχάρης,” in Politics, Patronage and the Transmission of
Knowledge in 13th - 15th Century Tabriz, ed. Judith Pfeiffer (Leiden; Boston: Brill, 2014), 231-47 esp.
243-45.
5
David Pingree, The Astronomical Works of Gregory Chioniades, vol. 1, The Zīj al-ʿAlāʾī (Amsterdam: J.
C. Gieben, 1985), 17-18.
Chioniades, Gregor [George] 151
Chioniades 3
among the Persians.6 Apparently sufficiently rehabilitated, he was appointed Bishop of Tabrīz in
1305 and took the name Gregory, but he may not have returned to Tabrīz until about 1310. By
1315, he was again in Trebizond, where he lived as a monk until his death around 1320.
The known astronomical works that Chioniades either translated or reworked from Islamic
sources are the following:7
1) al-Zīj al-ʿAlāʾī of ʿAbd al-Karīm al-Shīrwānī al-Fahhād (ca. 1176), via a Persian version
made by Shams al-Dīn (according to David Pingree).8
2) An abridged version of al-Zīj al-Sanjarī of ʿAbd al-Raḥmān al-Khāzinī (ca. 1120), a
Greek freedman of a judge in Marv; made after 1) and directly from the Arabic (according to
Joseph Leichter).9
3) The Īlkhānī Zīj of Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī.
4) A short Syntaxis, perhaps by Shams al-Dīn al-Bukhārī.
5) A longer Revised Canons, again perhaps by Shams al-Dīn al-Bukhārī. (Pingree takes this
to be by Chioniades, who, he claims, was attempting to show his competence in using the
tables of al-Zīj al-ʿAlāʾī.)10
6) A work called Schemata of the Stars (Περὶ τῶν σχημάτων τῶν ἀστέρων).11
7) A work on the astrolabe by Shams al-Dīn.12
8) On the Genethlialogical Computation, probably by Shams al-Dīn, which concerns the
horoscope of a certain Fakhr al-Dīn born in Tabrīz on 14 Dhū al-ḥijja 666 H (25 August
13
1268).
6
Westerink, “La profession de foi.”
7
All or some of these works are preserved in Vaticanus Graecus MS 211 (Rome), Vaticanus Graecus MS
1058 (Rome), and Laurentianus MS 28, 17 (Florence). Convenient listings (complete) are in Pingree,
Astronomical Works of Gregory Chioniades, 23-28, and Leichter, “Zīj as-Sanjarī,” 12-13 (partial,
highlighting the works attributable to Chioniades).
8
Edition and translation in Pingree, Astronomical Works of Gregory Chioniades, 36-243.
9
Leichter, “Zīj as-Sanjarī,” 19-162 (English translation), 367-567 (Greek text).
10
Pingree, Astronomical Works of Gregory Chioniades, 21-22; edition and translation, 260-333. The
work is a report by Chioniades, but it seems to be based on observations and calculations made by Shams
al-Dīn.
11
Edition and translation in E. A. Paschos and P. Sotiroudis, The Schemata of the Stars: Byzantine
Astronomy from A.D. 1300 (Singapore; River Edge, NJ: World Scientific, 1998), 26-53.
12
The Greek version of the introduction has been edited and translated into English by Elizabeth A.
Fisher, “Arabs, Latins and Persians Bearing Gifts: Greek Translations of Astrolabe Treatises, ca. 1300,”
Byzantine and Modern Greek Studies 36, no. 2 (2012): 161-77.
152 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
4 Chioniades
As for the first three zījes, one is struck by the fact that all were considerably out of date by
the 1290s. The zījes of Fahhād and Khāzinī had certainly been superseded by the Īlkhānī Zīj,
which itself had been made obsolete by the zījes of Muḥyī al-Dīn al-Maghribī (d. 1283), which,
unlike Ṭūsī’s Īlkhānī Zīj, incorporated the latest observations made at Marāgha.14 It is not clear
why these zījes were chosen, but they may have been more “elementary” in some sense. Pingree
notes that when translating al-Zīj al-ʿAlāʾī, Chioniades displays a remarkable degree of
ignorance, often transcribing Persian words into Greek when he did not understand the content.15
But Leichter (the editor and translator into English of the Greek version of the Sanjarī Zīj) has
noted an improvement in Chioniades’s knowledge, this time presumably in Arabic, when
translating the Sanjarī Zīj.16 Of considerable importance in determining how far along
Chioniades got in his apprenticeship into Islamic astronomy is whether the purported works of
Shams al-Dīn (the short Syntaxis and the longer Revised Canon), which are found in Greek
translation in some of the manuscripts, contain any of the newer material from the Marāgha and
Tabrīz observations and whether the Persian Syntaxis of Chrysococces, which he says comes
from the work of Chioniades, contains this new material. Raymond Mercier has claimed,
somewhat unconvincingly, that the Persian Syntaxis of Chrysococces was mostly derived from
the Īlkhānī Zīj, but this was disputed by Pingree, who held that there is substantial evidence that
Chrysococces used the ʿAlāʾī and Sanjarī zījes, in addition to the Īlkhānī Zīj, all of which were
translated by Chioniades.17 But neither seems to have considered that Chrysococces, and
Chioniades himself, may have used sources and observations post-dating the Īlkhānī Zīj, whether
from someone like Maghribī or from Shams al-Dīn. A fresh examination of the works attributed
to Shams al-Dīn, along with a comparison of contemporaneous works in Arabic and Persian, is
necessary in order to resolve some of these issues. The Greek translation of the astrolabe treatise
purportedly by Shams al-Dīn (no. 7) still awaits comparison with the Persian astrolabe treatise
13
Edition and translation in Pingree, Astronomical Works of Gregory Chioniades, 242-59.
14
See George Saliba, A History of Arabic Astronomy: Planetary Theories during the Golden Age of Islam
(New York: New York University Press, 1994), 163-86, 208-30.
15
Pingree, Astronomical Works of Gregory Chioniades, 18-21.
16
Leichter, “Zīj as-Sanjarī,” 11-12.
17
See Mercier, “The Greek ‘Persian Syntaxisʾ.” Pingree responded to Mercier in his “In Defence of
Gregory Chioniades,” Archives internationales d’histoire des sciences 35, nos. 114/115 (1985): 436-38.
Chioniades, Gregor [George] 153
Chioniades 5
contained in Istanbul, Topkapı, Ahmet III 3327 and attributed to Shams al-Dīn al-Wābkanawī.
The identity of Fakhr al-Dīn in no. 8 has yet to be determined.
Treatise no. 6 has attracted considerable interest since Otto Neugebauer pointed out that it
contained a diagram of the so-called Ṭūsī-couple of Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī, a device for producing
oscillating rectilinear motion from two circular motions;18 its various versions were used by Ṭūsī
in a number of ways, in particular to deal with the irregular (and thus unacceptable) motion
brought about by Ptolemy’s (fl. 140 CE) equant model. Later it was used by Copernicus (d. 1543
CE) in several of his astronomical models. The existence of such a device in a “western”
language that had clearly come from an Islamic source was evidence used by Noel Swerdlow
and Neugebauer to advocate their position that Copernicus was indebted to Islamic astronomy
for a number of his models.19 Recently it has been shown that this work by Chioniades, the
Schemata of the Stars, is derived from two Persian works of Ṭūsī, his Risāla-yi Muʿīniyya and its
appendix, the Ḥall-i mushkilāt-i Muʿīniyya.20 In particular, the versions of the Ṭūsī-couple and
the lunar model found in the Schemata are the ones found in the Ḥall and are not in either of
Ṭūsī’s later Arabic works, the Taḥrīr al-Majisṭī or al-Tadhkira fī ʿilm al-hayʾa. Another
interesting aspect of the Schemata is that Chioniades has faithfully followed the star listings in
the Muʿīniyya; in fact, he uses corrupted forms of Greek names that had entered Arabic with the
translations from Greek in the ninth century instead of their correct Greek forms. A rather
striking example of this is that Chioniades names a northern constellation κακκαοῦς rather than
the correct Greek name Κηφεύς, clearly indicating that he is simply copying the corrupted
Arabic name qayqāwus ()ﻗﻴﻘـﺎﻭﺱ, which is a simple mistake for what should have been the correct
transcription, namely ()ﻗﻴﻔــﺎﻭﺱ. Pingree notes other cases of transcription of Arabic/Persian
terminology when Chioniades did not know the meanings or equivalents in Greek.21
This raises the question of how well Chioniades knew Persian or Arabic. As previously noted,
it would seem, based on evidence compiled by Pingree and also the fact that he uses the Persian
Muʿīniyya rather than its updated Arabic version, i.e., the Tadhkira, that Chioniades and/or
Shams al-Dīn preferred using Persian over Arabic. This may well reflect the cultural interactions
18
Otto Neugebauer, A History of Ancient Mathematical Astronomy, 3 parts (Berlin; New York: Springer-
Verlag, 1975), 2:1035.
19
N. M. Swerdlow and O. Neugebauer, Mathematical Astronomy in Copernicus’s De Revolutionibus, 2
parts (New York: Springer-Verlag, 1984), 1:47-48.
20
For further details, see Ragep, “New Light on Shams,” 238-43.
21
Pingree, Astronomical Works of Gregory Chioniades, 18-21.
154 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
6 Chioniades
between the Byzantines and Iranians during this period. But Leichter, as we have seen, claims
that Chioniades may have competently translated the Zīj al-Sanjarī from Arabic, which would
indicate an improvement in his language skills from his initial work on the al-Zīj al-ʿAlāʾī.
During his lifetime, Chioniades was evidently a significant figure in the political and religious
interactions between the Byzantine and Īlkhānid realms. Though not an original or creative
scholar, his translations played an important role in the transmission of Islamic astronomy to
Byzantium and Latin Europe, and they were to influence not only later Byzantine scholars such
as George Chrysococces and Theodore Meliteniotes (d. 1393) but scholars in Latin Europe as
well.
NEW LIGHT ON SHAMS:
THE ISLAMIC SIDE OF ΣÀΜΨ ΠΟΥΧÁΡΗΣ
F. Jamil Ragep
I. Introduction
1 An excellent summary of what is known of the life of Chioniades can be found in
Joseph Gerard Leichter, “The Zīj as-Sanjarī of Gregory Chioniades: Text, Translation and
Greek to Arabic Glossary” (Unpublished Ph.D. Dissertation, Brown University, 2004), 2–6.
Cf. L.G. Westerink, “La profession de foi de Gregoire Chioniades,” Revue des études byzan-
tines 38 (1980): 233–245; and David E. Pingree, “Chioniades, Gregory,” in Oxford Dictionary
of Byzantium, ed. Alexander P. Kazhdan (New York: Oxford University Press, 2002), 422–
423. See also Maria Mavroudi, “Exchanges with Arabic Writers during the Late Byzantine
Period,” in Byzantium: Faith and Power (1261–1557): Perspectives on Late Byzantine Art and
Culture, ed. Sarah Brooks (New York: Metropolitan Museum of Art, 2007), 62–75.
156 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
King’s honor. Having gathered many treasures, and organized many subor-
dinates, he again reached Trebizond, with his many books on the subject
of astronomy. He translated these by his own lights, making a noteworthy
efffort. There are in fact other books of the Persian Syntaxis which he trans-
lated, those having certain examples with the years systematically at the
beginning. However, he handed on the Syntaxis alone, the best and most
accurate of all, as our teacher said, who appeared to be telling the truth. He
translated separately the commentary, which was taken from the Persians
by word of mouth alone. In this way, the Syntaxis, called the Handy, was
produced.2
From this account, we can gather that the Persian Syntaxis of Chrysococces
is somehow based on the work of Chioniades and that the latter went to
some city in Persia to obtain the necessary learning and materials. From
letters of Chioniades, we know that the city in question was the Mongol
capital, Tabriz.3 Furthermore, in the introduction to his translation of a
work that Pingree tells us is related to the Zīj al-ʿAlāʾī of ʿAbd al-Karīm
al-Fahhād (fl. 1176), we learn that Chioniades studied with a certain Shams
Bukharos,4 about whom the author of a recent article states: “There is
nothing known of him in Persian or Arabic sources, nor is there any
known reference to him outside the Greek work just mentioned.”5 The
purpose of this paper is to try to uncover some information about this
elusive Shams, who undertook to teach the Greek Chioniades astronomy
and provide him with valuable texts, despite whatever reservations Shams
and others in Tabriz may have had. But fijirst we will need to explore the
intellectual context of Tabriz in which this transmission took place and
the sources of some of the material Chioniades took back with him to
Byzantium.
What was the state of astronomy in and around Tabriz at the end of the
thirteenth century? Tabriz was the inheritor of the Marāgha scientifijic tra-
dition and observatory, which had been established in Azerbaijan after
2 Raymond Mercier, “The Greek ‘Persian Syntaxis’ and the Zīj-i Īlkhānī,” Archives inter-
nationales d’histoire des sciences 34 (1984): 35–36; reproduced in Leichter, “Zīj as-Sanjarī,” 3.
3 Leichter, “Zīj as-Sanjarī,” 3.
4 David Pingree, The Astronomical Works of Gregory Chioniades, vol. 1: The Zīj al-ʿAlāʾī
(Amsterdam: J.C. Grieben, 1985), 36–37.
5 Raymond Mercier, “Shams al-Dīn al-Bukhārī,” in The Biographical Encyclopedia of
Astronomers, eds. Thomas Hockey et al. (New York: Springer, 2007), 1047.
232
New Light on Shams: The Islamic Side of ΣÀΜΨ ΠΟΥΧÁΡΗΣ 157
the Mongol conquests of the 1250s. The Marāgha Observatory had been
built with the active support of the Mongol ruler Hülegü Khan, who made
the redoubtable Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī its founding director. Thanks to the
work of Aydın Sayılı and excavations carried out at the site, we know
quite a bit about this observatory, which, as far as we can determine, was
the fijirst large-scale observatory ever built and was to be the model for
similar, big-science initiatives in the centuries to come, whether in China,
in Central Asia, in India, or in Europe.6
It is not clear, however, when the Marāgha observatory ceased function-
ing as an active scientifijic institution (as opposed, say, to a tourist attrac-
tion that led Tīmūr Lang to take a detour during one of his expeditions in
order to show his grandson Ulugh Beg the remains of the observatory).7
This has considerable signifijicance as we try to reconstruct the chronology
of events that led Tabriz to become the major center of global science by
the time Chioniades arrived there in 1295.
Now this is what we can reconstruct: From what we gather from the
zīj (astronomical handbook) of a certain Shams al-Dīn al-Wābkanawī
(about whom more later), which was mostly compiled under Öljeytü
(r. 703–716/1304–1316), but not completed until sometime during the reign
of Abū Saʿīd Bahadur Khan (r. 716–736/1316–1335), the Marāgha observa-
tory seems to have ceased operations a few years (exactly how many
being unclear) after the death in 1274 of Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī. According to
Wābkanawī, the zījes of Muḥyī al-Dīn ibn Abī al-Shukr al-Maghribī used
the Marāgha observations, which Ṭūsī, for whatever reasons, had not been
able to incorporate into the Īlkhānī Zīj (completed sometime in the late
1260s). Now since Maghribī died in Marāgha in June 1283, and we have no
fijirm indications of observations or activity at the Marāgha observatory
after that date, it seems likely that we can take 1283 as the terminus ad
quem. And Wābkanawī makes it clear that the Marāgha observatory did
6 Aydın Sayılı, The Observatory in Islam and Its Place in the General History of the
Observatory (Ankara: Türk Tarih Kurumu Basımevi, 1960); and Parvīz Varjāvand, Kāvish-i
raṣadkhāna-i Marāgha (Tehran: Amīr Kabīr, 1366 H.Sh [1987 CE]).
7 This is mentioned in a letter by the eminent mathematician Jamshīd al-Kāshī, who
was a member of Ulugh Beg’s scientifijic entourage; see Edward S. Kennedy, “A Letter of
Jamshīd al-Kāshī to His Father: Scientifijic Research and Personalities at a Fifteenth Century
Court,” Orientalia 29 (1960): 196, 208–209 (reprinted in E.S. Kennedy et al., Studies in the
Islamic Exact Sciences, eds. David A. King and Mary Helen Kennedy (Beirut: American
University of Beirut, 1983), 722–744).
233
158 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
not reach its goal of a 30-year observational period, which would have
ended around 1289.8
This dating has implications for what scientifijic activity Chioniades may
have found when he came to Azerbaijan in 1295. Given the testimony of
Wābkanawī, it seems that the Marāgha observatory was no longer an
ongoing concern. But we know from Rashīd al-Dīn that Ghazan Khan vis-
ited the Marāgha observatory on numerous occasions, and in particular in
the spring of 1300 when returning from an expedition to Syria. He is said
to have shown great interest in the observatory, asked many questions
and then ordered his own observatory to be built in the extensive com-
plex of Abwāb al-Birr in Sham, a suburb of Tabriz.9 But let us consider the
dates. If there was no functioning Marāgha observatory in 1295, and the
Tabriz observatory lay in the future, what was it that brought Chioniades
to Tabriz? Here, I think, we can safely guess that Tabriz, under Ghazan or
before, had gained a justifijied reputation as a major center of scientifijic,
and in particular astronomical, learning and research even without an
observatory.
Although this period of the history of science in Islam has been some-
what downplayed (being in the shadow of the so-called Marāgha school),
there is accumulating evidence that the time in which Chioniades vis-
ited Tabriz was one of intense activity. We know, for example, that Quṭb
al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī arrived in Tabriz sometime in 1290 (or shortly thereafter)
after serving as a Mongol emissary in Egypt and as chief judge in Malaṭya
and Sivas in Anatolia, where he wrote several major works on astrono-
my.10 It is in Tabriz that he most likely wrote his Faʿalta fa-lā talum (“You
have done it so don’t impugn!”), one of the most remarkable works in the
entire history of Islamic science. In it he lambasts a certain al-Ḥimādhī,
who had dared criticize him and, adding salt to the wound, had allegedly
plagiarized large chunks of Shīrāzī’s al-Tuḥfa al-shāhiyya, an astronomical
234
New Light on Shams: The Islamic Side of ΣÀΜΨ ΠΟΥΧÁΡΗΣ 159
11 Quṭb al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī, Faʿalta fa-lā talum, Tehran, Majlis-i Shūrā MS 3944, fff. 5b, 7b,
9a.
12 Sayılı, The Observatory in Islam, 227–229.
13 On Nīsābūrī, see Robert G. Morrison, Islam and Science: The Intellectual Career of
Niẓām Al-Dīn Al-Nīsābūrī (London; New York: Routledge, 2007).
14 Sayılı, The Observatory in Islam, 230.
15 Zeki Velidi Togan, “İlhanlı Bizans kültür münasebetlerine dair vesikalar” (“A
Document concerning Cultural Relation between the İlkhanide and Byzantiens” [sic]),
İslâm Tetkikleri Enstitüsü Dergisi 3 (1959–60): 315–378 (= 1–39). I owe this reference to
Dimitri Gutas, “Arabic into Byzantine Greek: Introducing a Survey of the Translations,”
in Knotenpunkt Byzanz: Wissensformen und kulturelle Wechselbeziehungen, eds. Andreas
Speer and Philipp Steinkrüger (Berlin: De Gruyter, 2012), 258.
235
160 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
236
New Light on Shams: The Islamic Side of ΣÀΜΨ ΠΟΥΧÁΡΗΣ 161
As for the fijirst 3 zījes (astronomical handbooks with tables), one is struck
by the fact that all were considerably out of date by the 1290s. The zījes
of Fahhād and Khāzinī had certainly been superseded by the Īlkhānī Zīj,
which itself had been made obsolete by the zījes of al-Maghribī, which,
unlike Ṭūsī’s Īlkhānī Zīj, incorporated the latest observations made at
Marāgha.24 Was this because Shams al-Dīn was withholding the latest
fijindings from a potential Rūmī adversary (as implied by Chrysococces)
or was this simply a matter of Chioniades needing to learn the more
elementary material before embarking on cutting-edge research? Pingree
notes that when translating al-Zīj al-ʿAlāʾī, Chioniades shows a remarkable
degree of ignorance, often transcribing Persian words into Greek when
he didn’t understand the content.25 But Joseph Leichter (the editor and
translator of the Greek version of the Sanjarī Zīj) has noted an improve-
ment in Chioniades’s knowledge, this time presumably in Arabic, when
translating the Sanjarī zīj.26 Of considerable importance in determining
how far along Chioniades got in his apprenticeship into Islamic astron-
omy is whether the purported works of Shams al-Dīn (the short Syntaxis
and the longer Revised Canon), which are found in Greek translation in
some of the manuscripts, contain any of the newer material from the
Marāgha and Tabriz observations and whether the Persian Syntaxis of
Chrysococces, which he says comes from the work of Chioniades, contains
this new material. Raymond Mercier has claimed, somewhat unconvinc-
ingly, that the Persian Syntaxis of Chrysococces was mostly derived from
the Īlkhānī Zīj, but this was disputed by Pingree, who held that there is
substantial evidence that Chrysococces used the ʿAlāʾī and Sanjarī zījes,
22 Edition and translation in E.A. Paschos and P. Sotiroudis, The Schemata of the Stars:
Byzantine Astronomy from A.D. 1300 (Singapore; River Edge, NJ: World Scientifijic, 1998),
26–53.
23 Edition and translation in Pingree, Astronomical Works of Gregory Chioniades,
242–259.
24 See Saliba, A History of Arabic Astronomy.
25 Pingree, Astronomical Works of Gregory Chioniades, 18–21.
26 Leichter, “Zīj as-Sanjarī,” 11–12.
237
162 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
27 See Raymond Mercier, “The Greek ‘Persian Syntaxis’,” 35–60. Pingree responded to
Mercier in his “In Defence of Gregory Chioniades.”
28 Paschos and Sotiroudis refer to it as The Schemata of the Stars; Pingree and Leichter
call it a hayʾa text in their listing of works due to Chioniades.
29 On the hayʾa tradition in Islam, see F.J. Ragep, Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī’s Memoir on
Astronomy (New York: Springer-Verlag, 1993), 1: 24–53.
30 Paschos and Sotiroudis, The Schemata, 17.
31 N.M. Swerdlow and O. Neugebauer, Mathematical Astronomy in Copernicus’s De
Revolutionibus (New York: Springer-Verlag, 1984), 1: 47–48.
238
New Light on Shams: The Islamic Side of ΣÀΜΨ ΠΟΥΧÁΡΗΣ 163
ἀουάς, reflecting the Arabic [ ]).33 It is clear then that Chioniades must
Κηφεύς. (A number of other examples could be given, e.g. Βοώτης is called
239
164 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
Finally there is the case of Ṭūsī’s famous lunar model, which incorpo-
rated his Ṭūsī couple. There are signifijicant diffferences in the Schemata
with the model presented in the Tadhkira, most strikingly that the defer-
ent (ḥāmil) of the Tadhkira, in which the Ṭūsī-couple device is placed,
has been replaced by an inclined orb that incorporates the motions of the
deferent and inclined orbs of the Tadhkira models. Furthermore, from the
diagrams found in at least one manuscript of the Schemata, one can see
that the couple is rotating in the opposite sense from that in diagrams
found in manuscripts of the Tadhkira.
I was initially inclined to think that this was an adaptation by Shams
al-Bukhārī, who may have been influenced by some of the new mod-
els presented by Quṭb al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī in his work. In any event, I had
assumed that the Schemata was somehow based upon a newer, more up-
to-date hayʾa work that had been produced after Ṭūsī’s death. But follow-
ing up on a suggestion by S. Ragep, I discovered, much to my surprise, that
the Schemata is mostly a translation of fragments from another work by
Ṭūsī, namely the Risāla-yi Muʿīniyya, which he wrote in 1235, when at the
Ismaʿili court in Qūhistān, long before the coming of the Ilkhanids and the
writing of the Tadhkira.37 A few examples should sufffijice to establish this,
at least in a preliminary way:
1. From Risāla-yi Muʿīniyya, Part I, Chapter 2:38
A body is either simple or composite. A simple is that which is not made
up of bodies of diffferent natures or forms. A composite is the opposite.
Necessarily composites are composed of simples. Simples are of two types:
celestial and elemental. The celestials are all the orbs and stars. The elemen-
tals are those fourfold substances that are the basis of the world of gen-
eration and corruption, i.e., fijire, air, water and earth. The composites are
of four types: (a) that whose composition is not complete, such as clouds,
wind, shooting stars and the like. These are called upper phenomena;
37 On the Risāla-yi Muʿīniyya and its appendix, the Ḥall-i mushkilāt-i Muʿīniyya, see
Ragep, Naṣīr al-Dīn, 1: 65–70; idem, “The Persian Context of the Ṭūsī Couple,” in Naṣīr
al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī: Philosophe et Savant du XIIIe Siècle, eds. N. Pourjavady and Ž. Vesel (Tehran:
Institut français de recherche en Iran/Presses universitaires d’Iran, 2000), 113–130 ; and
idem, “The Origins of the Ṭūsī Couple Revisited,” forthcoming in a volume of conference
essays devoted to Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī, to be published by Mīrāth-i Maktūb (Tehran).
Wheeler Thackston and I are in the process of completing an edition and translation of
the Risāla-yi Muʿīniyya and Ḥall-i mushkilāt-i Muʿīniyya, which should appear in 2014.
38 Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī, Risāla-yi Muʿīniyya, facsimile of Tehran, Malik MS 3503 with an
introduction by Muḥammad Taqī Dānish-Pazhūh (Tehran: Intishārāt-i Dānishgāh-i Tihrān
(no. 300 in the series), 1335 H.Sh./1956–7 A.D.), 8; translation due to Wheeler Thackston,
Sergei Tourkin, and Jamil Ragep.
240
New Light on Shams: The Islamic Side of ΣÀΜΨ ΠΟΥΧÁΡΗΣ 165
(b) that whose composition is complete, i.e., it can remain for a period of
time and have the capacity to retain its shape or form, but it is not subject
to growth. This is called mineral; (c) that whose composition is complete
but nonetheless has the capacity to grow. This is called vegetal; (d) that
which has the capacity for growth and the capacity for perception and vol-
untary movement. This is called animal. The latter three types are called
the three engendered [kingdoms]: the fourfold elements are the mothers
of these engendered, and the celestial bodies are the fathers. The elements
and composites are called lower bodies, and the orbs and stars are called
the upper bodies.
From The Schemata of the Stars (introduction):39
The [celestial] body is divided into two [entities], simple and composite, as
is the case with the four elements, simple and composite; each of them is
thus called simple element. It became evident from what we know and com-
prehend that the sky is circular. On the other hand, the elements are four:
fijire, air, water and earth; if something is composite then it is none of these.
The entities beyond the elements are classifijied into two groups: one group
where the mixing is not perfect, so that when mixing takes place the com-
position does not survive [for a long time]; examples are air and clouds and
thunderbolts. The other group is the one in which mixing is perfect; when
mixing takes place, the composition lasts for a long time. There are three
such things; fijirst the one which is produced and cannot develop any further,
as is the case with metals; second the composed [substance] has the capac-
ity for growth, as is the case with plants; and third, the one which has the
capacity for both growth and movement, as is the case with animals. These
three are called children of three structures, and this because the four ele-
ments are called their mother. On the other hand, the sphere and the stars
are known as their father.
Although the Greek is not a perfect match for the Persian,40 it is clear that
it follows it to a great extent. And in particular, one should note the strik-
ing metaphor of the four elements being the mothers of the engendered,
while the celestial bodies are the fathers. This is something I have not
encountered in other hayʾa works, including those of Ṭūsī.
2. The listing and names of the constellations, as well as the number
of stars in The Schemata of the Stars, follows almost exactly what we fijind
241
166 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
in the Muʿīniyya.41 For example, in both the Schemata and the Muʿīniyya,
Ursa Major is listed as having 27 stars with 7 lying outside the constella-
tion. On the other hand, the Tadhkira simply lists Ursa Major, as well as
the other constellations, without providing the number of stars, while in
both Shīrāzī’s Nihāya and his al-Tuḥfa al-shāhiyya, Ursa Major has 27 stars
with 8 lying outside.42 This is what one also fijinds in the Almagest.43
3. The most decisive, and interesting, piece of evidence establishing
the relation of the Schemata and the Muʿīniyya comes from the lunar
model presented in the former. Chioniades lists 6 orbs, which difffer both
in number and content from the Tadhkira, where Ṭūsī lists 7 orbs for his
non-Ptolemaic lunar model. Furthermore, the Schemata gives 13°11′/day
for the motion of the second orb, while in the Tadhkira the equivalent
motion, resulting from the combination of the inclined and deferent orbs,
comes to 13°14′. On the other hand, in the Appendix (Dhayl or Ḥall) of the
Muʿīniyya, the lunar model given has the same 6 orbs as in the Schemata
and the second orb also moves at 13°11′/day.44
From these 3 examples, which could be supplemented by quite a few
others, one may conclude that Chioniades learned theoretical astron-
omy (ʿilm al-hayʾa) from the Risāla-yi Muʿīniyya and its Appendix. What
is remarkable about this is that when Chioniades was in Tabriz in the
1290s, the Persian Muʿīniyya and its Appendix, completed in 1235 and
1245, respectively, would have long since been superseded by the Arabic
Tadhkira, written in 1261 and containing Ṭūsī’s revisions and corrections
to his earlier works. And any competent astronomer in Azerbaijan in 1295
would have known this. Why then did Chioniades’s teacher, presumably
Shams al-Dīn al-Bukhārī, use the Muʿīniyya and its Appendix to teach
him theoretical astronomy? One obvious reason that presents itself is
that Chioniades was more comfortable dealing with a Persian text rather
than an Arabic one. And Pingree has claimed that al-Zīj al-ʿAlāʾī, originally
41 Paschos and Sotiroudis, The Schemata, 30–37; al-Ṭūsī, Risāla-yi Muʿīniyya, 19–21.
42 Ragep, Naṣīr al-Dīn, 1: 128–129; Shīrāzī, Nihāyat al-idrāk, f. 58b; Shīrāzī, al-Tuḥfa
al-shāhiyya, Istanbul, Süleymaniye Library, Turhan Valide Sultan MS 220, f. 23b.
43 Gerald J. Toomer, Ptolemy’s Almagest, translated and annotated by G.J. Toomer (New
York: Springer-Verlag, 1984), 342–343.
44 Paschos and Sotiroudis, The Schemata, 42–45. For a listing of the parameters for the
lunar model in the Tadhkira, see Ragep, Naṣīr al-Dīn, 2: 457. The sum of the lunar inclined
and deferent orbs comes to 13°14′ (24°23′/day–11°9′/day) in the Tadhkira; cf. the Ḥall,
where the equivalent motion of the inclined orb is given as the mean motion of the moon
(wasaṭ-i qamar), i.e. 13°11′ (Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī, Ḥall-i mushkilāt-i Muʿīniyya, facsimile of
Tehran, Malik MS 3503 with an introduction by Muḥammad Taqī Dānish-Pazhūh [Tehran:
Intishārāt-i Dānishgāh-i Tihrān (no. 304 in the series), 1335 H.Sh./1956–7 AD], 11).
242
New Light on Shams: The Islamic Side of ΣÀΜΨ ΠΟΥΧÁΡΗΣ 167
243
168 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
50 Our group is currently seeking to verify this; we have recently gained access to the
witness preserved in the Topkapı Museum Library.
51 Pingree, Astronomical Works of Gregory Chioniades, 16.
52 Shams al-Dīn al-Wābkanawī, al-Zīj al-muḥaqqaq, Ayasofya MS 2694, fff. 2a, 2b, 3b.
53 Shīrāzī, Faʿalta fa-lā talum, f. 14b.
54 Shīrāzī, Faʿalta fa-lā talum, f. 5a–b.
244
New Light on Shams: The Islamic Side of ΣÀΜΨ ΠΟΥΧÁΡΗΣ 169
had been safely dead for several years (since 1311). And Shams/Wābkanawī
feels safe enough in his zīj to take a swipe at the competing zīj of Shīrāzī’s
student Niẓām al-Dīn al-Nīsābūrī, who had written what Wābkanawī
considered an unusable commentary on Ṭūsī’s Īlkhānī Zīj entitled Kashf-i
ḥaqāʾiq-i Zīj-i Īlkhānī.55
It is tempting to ask at this point whether one source of the tension
between Shīrāzī and his circle on the one hand and Shams/Wābkanawī
on the other could have been the special treatment accorded Chioniades
by Ghazan Khan and Shams’s pedagogical role. This is certainly a possibil-
ity and highlighting civilizational rivalry makes a good story, especially in
these times. But this question raises issues of east-west/Muslim-Christian
competition, particularly in scientifijic matters, to a level that had not been
reached, and we are in danger thereby of reading later concerns back-
wards in time. We can say with certainty that this period of Islamic scien-
tifijic and intellectual history, during this Mongol interregnum, was a time
of enormous creativity, advance and scholarly engagement and debate.
No wonder Chioniades would be attracted to Tabriz. But the quest of a
single scholar, and his flawed transmission of outdated texts, would not
change the stark reality of the sizeable imbalance between Islamic and
“western” science at the time. Chioniades had little, if anything, to offfer
the Persians, and they in turn took little notice of his coming—at least
there is little in evidence from the historical record. Nevertheless, he had
begun a process, one that would eventually result in the ancient legend
coming true: for the “Romans” would indeed overthrow the “Persians,”
once they had consulted the practice of astronomy, whose foundation
would fijirst be taken from the Persians.
Bibliography
Comes, Mercè. “Ibn Abī al-Shukr.” In The Biographical Encyclopedia of Astronomers. Edited
by Thomas Hockey (editor-in-chief), Marvin Bolt, Katherine Bracher, Richard Jarrell,
Jordan Marché, JoAnn Palmeri, F. Jamil Ragep, Virginia Trimble, and Thomas Williams,
548–549. New York: Springer, 2007.
Dalen, Benno van. “Wābkanawī.” In The Biographical Encyclopedia of Astronomers. Edited
by Thomas Hockey (editor-in-chief), Marvin Bolt, Katherine Bracher, Richard Jarrell,
Jordan Marché, JoAnn Palmeri, F. Jamil Ragep, Virginia Trimble, and Thomas Williams,
1187–1188. New York: Springer, 2007.
245
170 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
Gutas, Dimitri. “Arabic into Byzantine Greek: Introducing a Survey of the Translations.”
In Knotenpunkt Byzanz: Wissensformen und kulturelle Wechselbeziehungen. Edited by
Andreas Speer and Philipp Steinkrüger, 246–262. Berlin: De Gruyter, 2012.
Kennedy, Edward S. “A Letter of Jamshīd al-Kāshī to His Father: Scientifijic Research and
Personalities at a Fifteenth Century Court.” Orientalia 29 (1960): 191–213. Reprinted in
E.S. Kennedy et al., Studies in the Islamic Exact Sciences. Edited by David A. King and
Mary Helen Kennedy, 722–744. Beirut: American University of Beirut, 1983.
Leichter, Joseph Gerard. “The Zīj as-Sanjarī of Gregory Chioniades: Text, Translation and
Greek to Arabic Glossary.” PhD diss., Brown University, 2004.
Mavroudi, Maria. “Exchanges with Arabic Writers during the Late Byzantine Period.” In
Byzantium: Faith and Power (1261–1557): Perspectives on Late Byzantine Art and Culture.
Edited by Sarah Brooks, 62–75. New York: Metropolitan Museum of Art, 2007.
Mercier, Raymond. “The Greek ‘Persian Syntaxis’ and the Zīj-i Īlkhānī.” Archives internatio-
nales d’histoire des sciences 34 (1984): 35–60.
——. “Shams al-Dīn al-Bukhārī.” In The Biographical Encyclopedia of Astronomers. Edited
by Thomas Hockey (editor-in-chief), Marvin Bolt, Katherine Bracher, Richard Jarrell,
Jordan Marché, JoAnn Palmeri, F. Jamil Ragep, Virginia Trimble, and Thomas Williams,
1047–1048. New York: Springer, 2007.
Morrison, Robert G. Islam and Science: The Intellectual Career of Niẓām al-Dīn al-Nīsābūrī.
London; New York: Routledge, 2007.
——. “Nīsābūrī.” In The Biographical Encyclopedia of Astronomers. Edited by Thomas
Hockey (editor-in-chief), Marvin Bolt, Katherine Bracher, Richard Jarrell, Jordan
Marché, JoAnn Palmeri, F. Jamil Ragep, Virginia Trimble, and Thomas Williams, 837.
New York: Springer, 2007.
Paschos, Emmanuel A., and Panagiotis Sotiroudis. The Schemata of the Stars: Byzantine
Astronomy from A.D. 1300. Singapore; River Edge, New Jersey: World Scientifijic, 1998.
Pingree, David E. “Gregory Chioniades and Palaeologan Astronomy.” Dumbarton Oaks
Papers 18 (1964): 133–160.
——. “In Defence of Gregory Chioniades.” Archives internationales d’histoire des sciences
35 (1985): 436–438.
——. The Astronomical Works of Gregory Chioniades. Vol. 1, The Zīj al-ʿAlāʾī. Amsterdam:
J.C. Grieben, 1985.
——. “Chioniades, Gregory.” In Oxford Dictionary of Byzantium. Edited by Alexander P.
Kazhdan, 422–423. New York: Oxford University Press, 2002.
Ragep, F. Jamil . Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī’s Memoir on Astronomy. 2 vols. New York: Springer,
1993.
——. “Shīrāzī.” In The Biographical Encyclopedia of Astronomers. Edited by Thomas Hockey
(editor-in-chief), Marvin Bolt, Katherine Bracher, Richard Jarrell, Jordan Marché, JoAnn
Palmeri, F. Jamil Ragep, Virginia Trimble, and Thomas Williams, 1054–1055. New York:
Springer, 2007.
——. “The Persian Context of the Ṭūsī Couple.” In Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī: Philosophe et Savant
du XIIIe Siècle. Edited by Nasrollah Pourjavady and Živa Vesel, 113–130. Tehran: Institut
français de recherche en Iran/Presses universitaires d’Iran, 2000.
——. “The Origins of the Ṭūsī Couple Revisited,” forthcoming in a volume of conference
essays devoted to Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī, to be published by Mīrāthi-i Maktūb (Tehran).
Saliba, George. A History of Arabic Astronomy: Planetary Theories during the Golden Age of
Islam. New York: New York University Press, 1994.
Sayılı, Aydın. The Observatory in Islam and Its Place in the General History of the Observatory.
Ankara: Türk Tarih Kurumu Basımevi, 1960.
al-Shīrāzī, Quṭb al-Dīn. al-Tuḥfa al-shāhiyya. Istanbul, Süleymaniye Library, Turhan Valide
Sultan MS 220.
——. Faʿalta fa-lā talum. Tehran, Majlis-i Shūrā, MS 3944.
——. Nihāyat al-idrāk fī dirāyat al-aflāk. Istanbul, Topkapı Sarayı Müzesi, Ahmet III MS
3333.
246
New Light on Shams: The Islamic Side of ΣÀΜΨ ΠΟΥΧÁΡΗΣ 171
247
Section III
F. Jamil Ragep
Abstract
It has long been recognized that Copernicus’ models in the Commentariolus bear a striking
resemblance to those of Ibn al-Shāṭir (14th-c. Damascus). A number of scholars have
postulated some sort of transmission but have denied that Ibn al-Shāṭir’s geocentric
models had anything to do with the heliocentric turn. Rather, the assumption has
been that they were used by Copernicus solely to resolve the irregular motions of
the planetary deferents brought on by Ptolemy’s equant. Based on proposals for direct
transformations of Ibn al-Shāṭir’s models into those of Copernicus and an alternative
reading of Copernicus’ so-called Uppsala notes, it is argued here that Ibn al-Shāṭir’s
models in fact have a “heliocentric bias” that made them particularly suitable as a basis
for the heliocentric and “quasi-homocentric” models found in the Commentariolus.
Keywords
Ibn al-Shāṭir, Copernicus, Commentariolus, De revolutionibus, Islamic astronomy,
heliocentrism, Averroism, Renaissance astronomy, homocentric astronomy
Introduction
In his classic translation of and commentary on Copernicus’ Commentariolus,1 Noel
Swerdlow provided a plausible and coherent reconstruction of Copernicus’ pathway
from Ptolemaic, geocentric planetary models to Copernican, heliocentric ones.2
Swerdlow hypothesized a conversion of Ptolemy’s epicyclic models for the planets into
eccentric models, based on propositions found in Regiomontanus’ Epitome of the
Almagest.3 This, he claimed, was the crucial step in the transformation from geocentric
to heliocentric models. This reconstruction was mainly based on an interpretation of the
so-called Uppsala notes [U] in Copernicus’ hand and the curious use of the word eccen-
tricitas found therein. As Swerdlow put it,
Corresponding author:
F. Jamil Ragep, Institute of Islamic Studies, McGill University, Morrice Hall, Room 319, 3485 McTavish
Street, Montreal, QC H3A 0E1 Canada.
Email: jamil.ragep[at]mcgill.ca
176 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
The use of the word eccentricitas in U for the sine of the maximum equation of the anomaly
shows that Copernicus was investigating the eccentric model of the second anomaly. My entire
analysis hangs on this one word.4
In his discussion, Swerdlow bifurcated Copernicus’ handling of the “first” and “sec-
ond” anomalies, the former having to do with the tropical or sidereal motion, the latter
with the synodic. Thus, the irregular motions arising from Ptolemy’s equant (falling
under the “first anomaly”) were, in this view, unrelated to the critical transformations of
the second anomaly that led to the eccentric models and whence to heliocentrism.5 In
what follows, I argue that there is an alternative, and simpler, way to reach Copernicus’
models in the Commentariolus without assuming the intermediate step of eccentric mod-
els nor the presumed, bifurcated process. This depends on assuming that (1) when
Copernicus uses the word eccentricitas, he is not referring to “eccentric models” (as
found in Regiomontanus) but rather the amount the Earth is out of center (“eccentric”) to
the Sun, i.e., the Earth–Sun distance, and (2) Copernicus does not bifurcate the process
of the geocentric-heliocentric transformation by dealing with the first and second anoma-
lies separately but rather exploits the peculiar nature of Ibn al-Shāṭir’s “heliocentrically
biased” models that allows for a more direct transformation.
396
Ibn al-Shāṭir and Copernicus: The Uppsala Notes Revisited 177
models; e is the eccentricity. Note that although Ptolemy’s mean motion is about the
equant point, his main deferent is centered at D, not E. It is this “centering on the Earth”
by Ibn al-Shāṭir, I am arguing, that is critical for the transformation to a heliocentric sys-
tem, at least insofar as Copernicus presents it in the Commentariolus.
Let us first consider Ibn al-Shāṭir’s model for the outer planets (Figure 2).12
The Earth O is at the center of a concentric orb with radius OF, rotating counterclock-
wise13 with the mean motion α . F is then the center of a “large” epicycle FG, rotating
clockwise with the mean motion α , and G is the center of a “small” epicycle GC, rotating
counterclockwise with twice the mean motion. C is the center of the Ptolemaic epicycle
CP, P being the planet. The two epicycles FG and GC, called by Ibn al-Shāṭir the deferent
(al-hāmil) and dirigent (al-mudīr), respectively, rotate uniformly and serve to account for
Ptolemy’s “first anomaly,” brought about by his eccentricities and equant E (the point
about which equal “mean” motion occurs in Ptolemy’s models). Ibn al-Shāṭir thereby
eliminates the irregular motion of Ptolemy’s deferent that moves with respect to the
equant rather than its own center (see Figure 1). As with Ptolemy’s model, the line joining
the planet P with the center of the epicycle is coordinated with the motion γ of the mean
–
Sun , so that CP is always parallel to the direction of the mean Sun from the Earth.14
There are three steps in the proposed transformation to the models of the outer planets
in the Commentariolus (Figure 3). The first step is to transpose the Ptolemaic epicycle so
that its center C is now at C′, which coincides with the center of the World O.
397
178 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
– –
The second step is to move O and along line O, O to O′ on the circumference of
– –
the transposed epicycle, and to ′ at the center of the World. Finally, P is moved paral-
– –
lel to O to P′, coinciding with the Ptolemaic epicycle center C. ′F has become the
radius of the new “deferent orb” of the planet, which Copernicus refers to as the “semi-
dyameter orbis.” Figure 4 represents the Commentariolus model.15
From an astronomical standpoint, this transformation is not that difficult to conceive,
since, as mentioned, the motion of Ptolemy’s epicycle is essentially
uuur uuur equal
uuur touuu
the
r motion
of theuuuuu
Sun around the Earth. Mathematically, we note that OF + FG + GC + CP (Figure
–r u–uur uuuur uuuur
2) = O′ ′ + ′F + F′G ′ + G ′P′ (Figure 4). The point to keep in mind is that such a simple
transformation is possible because Ibn al-Shāṭir has placed the Earth at the center of the
main deferent OF and dealt with the first anomaly not using eccentrics centered on the
apsidal line but rather with the double epicycles external to the apsidal line. In the other
models shown in Figure 1, such a direct transformation would not be possible, since one
must first transform deferents centered at H and E (for ʿUrḍī and Ṭūsī, respectively) to
ones centered on the Earth in order to reach the Commentariolus models; in other words,
one would need to transform these models into Ibn al-Shāṭir’s mathematically equivalent
models. For Ptolemy, the situation is even more complicated, since Copernicus would, in
addition to everything else, have had to deal with the irregular motion brought on by the
equant and then somehow resolve that problem and come up with Ibn al-Shāṭir’s models.
In any event, at some point, Copernicus borrowed or came up with Ibn al-Shāṭir’s mod-
els, since that is what is implied, as we shall see, by the Uppsala notes.
398
Ibn al-Shāṭir and Copernicus: The Uppsala Notes Revisited 179
Figure 3. Transformation of Ibn al-Shāṭir’s models for the outer planets into the
Commentariolus models.
399
180 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
400
Ibn al-Shāṭir and Copernicus: The Uppsala Notes Revisited 181
401
182 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
Figure 8. Transformation of Ibn al-Shāṭir’s model for Venus into the Commentariolus model.
It would be nice if we could end the story here, but Copernicus’ Commentariolus
models for the inner planets are not the same as those in De rev. The main difference is
that in the De rev models, the mean Sun and the center of the planet’s orbit (C) are dif-
ferent, whereas they are the same in the Commentariolus. Consequently, the transforma-
tion from Ibn al-Shātīr’s models, while still possible, is more complex as we see in
Figure 8.
As with the outer planets, the planetary epicycle with center C is moved so it is now
about center O. The mean Sun is also moved to the center, while the Earth is moved
along the same line to the circumference of the former deferent OF so it is now at O′. One
is left with the problem of where to place the bi-epicyclic device. Since CP is a radius of
the epicycle, which is now the main deferent of the planet in the heliocentric model,
Copernicus could have reasoned as follows. Move CP, renaming it C*P*, and maintain-
ing size and direction, so that P* coincides with F. Now move C*F, FG, GC, again main-
–
taining size and direction, so that C* coincides with ′. By simple geometry, one can
find that O′ moves with a mean motion of α in the counterclockwise direction; the mean
motion of point F′ is α + γ in the counterclockwise direction; epicycle F′ rotates α + γ
clockwise and epicycle G′ movesuuuuu 2αr counterclockwise. Using vectors, we note that
uuur uuur uuur uuur – u–uur uuuur uuuur
OF + FG + GC + CP (Figure 5) = O′ ′ + ′F′+ F′G ′ + G ′P′ (Figure 8). A similar trans-
formation is used for Mercury, but here one needs to add a Ṭūsī-couple, just as in Ibn
al-Shāṭir’s model, in order to vary the size of the planetary deferent/orbit.17
Admittedly, these complicated transformations for Mercury and Venus raise numer-
ous questions. If Copernicus had Ibn al-Shāṭir’s models when composing the
Commentariolus, why didn’t he make the simple transformation that he later did in De
revolutionibus? This question becomes particularly acute when we realize that the
402
Ibn al-Shāṭir and Copernicus: The Uppsala Notes Revisited 183
Commentariolus models for Mercury and Venus are quite difficult to use for computa-
tions as a result of the peculiar arrangement of the orbs resulting from this transforma-
tion; in fact, the equation of center can no longer be calculated from the Earth, and the
calculation of elongations becomes quite difficult (and perhaps even impossible as far as
Copernicus and his contemporaries are concerned).18 On the other hand, as we have seen,
it is indeed possible, with a bit of ingenuity, to transform Ibn al-Shāṭir’s models for the
inner planets into those in the Commentariolus without resorting to the intermediation of
Regiomontanus’ eccentric alternative. My argument is that when writing the
Commentariolus, one of Copernicus’ priorities was to have models whose main defer-
ents/orbits were centered on the mean Sun even if this made the models less practical for
calculation. This is not the case with the De rev models, where Copernicus introduced
eccentric orbs for his planetary deferents.19 I will speculate below about the reasons for
this insistence in the Commentariolus on “homocentric” deferents.
403
184 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
underlined, and in the margin, there is the number 376. Now if Copernicus were to use
the same method as with the outer planets, Mercury’s epicycle radius of 22.56, divided
by 60, would give an eccentricitas of .376, which would be 376 normed to 1000.23
However, neither 2256 nor 376 is the eccentricitas if we interpret it as being the Earth–
–
Sun distance. For in order to arrive at the radius of Mercury’s “orbis” ′F′ (i.e., 9;24) in
the lower part of the Uppsala notes, we must reduce the 1000 (corresponding to OF = 60
–
in Ibn al-Shāṭir’s model, ′O′ in the Commentariolus model) to 25: 1000/25 = 376/x ⇒ x
–
= 9;24 = ′F′. Thus, the eccentricitas for Mercury, which is the distance between the
mean Sun and Earth before that value is normed to 25, is actually 1000, which is implied
by the 376 in the margin. Thus, whether one interprets 2256 as the epicycle radius or as
the eccentricity in the eccentric model of the second anomaly, in order to arrive at an
“orbis” of 9;24 in the lower part of U, one needs to use 1000 as the “eccentricity” implied
by “proportio orbium celestium ad eccentricitatem 25 partium.” It is interesting that
Copernicus chose not to provide an eccentricitas for Venus, perhaps because of the con-
fusion regarding exactly what was the eccentricitas.
Table 1 provides derivations of all the non-crossed-out numbers in U (excluding the
Moon), assuming only that Copernicus had at his disposal Ibn al-Shāṭir’s models in some
form and that eccentricitas refers to the Earth–Sun distance resulting from the above
transformations of Ibn al-Shāṭir’s models. As mentioned (see Note 23), Copernicus’
parameters are from, or derived from, the Alphonsine tables, and, unlike Ibn al-Shāṭir
and later in De rev, he maintains a strict 3:1 relationship between r1 (the radius of first
epicycle) and r2 (the radius of second epicycle) for all the planets.
In discussions of the possible influence of Ibn al-Shāṭir on Copernicus, one important
counterargument is that their parameters are different. Swerdlow has shown that most of
the parameters in U are either directly or indirectly from the Alphonsine Tables; indeed,
the “eccentricities” are the sines of the maximum equation of the second anomaly from
those tables.26 This means that not only are the parameters different from those of Ibn
al-Shāṭir, it is also clear that they are not taken directly from the Almagest. More tell-
ingly, Copernicus adheres to a 3:1 ratio for the bi-epicyclic device for all the planets,
whereas Ibn al-Shāṭir does so only for the outer planets.27 Among other things, this
results in an exceedingly bad value for Mercury’s maximum equation of center.28
But then how do we account for the remarkable similarity between Ibn al-Shāṭir’s
models and those in the Commentariolus? One possibility is that Copernicus does not
have the text of Nihāyat al-suʾl, or has the text and can’t read it, but does have the dia-
grams. In support of this, let us look a bit more closely at the Mercury model and some
of its parameters in U.
Copernicus’ Mercury model has been a challenge to researchers, inasmuch as he talks
rather cryptically about the orbit being smaller when the Earth is at 0° and 180°, while it
is larger when the Earth is at quadratures.29 Let us examine Ibn al-Shāṭir’s diagram for
Mercury (Figure 9), which evidently illustrates Copernicus’ meaning.
As can be seen, Ibn al-Shāṭir shows the effect of the Ṭūsī-couple (the two, small inter-
secting circles in one of which Mercury is embedded) by indicating a “True Epicycle
Orb” and an “Apparent Epicycle Orb,” the latter resulting from the couple moving the
planet in a straight line toward and away from the center. At 0° and 180°, the apparent
epicycle becomes smaller (Mercury “traversing a far smaller circumference” according
404
Table 1.
Mercury Venus Mars Jupiter Saturn
– – – – – –
Eccentricitas O {1000 = O = 6000/6} {1000 = O 6583{ = O= (39.5/60)* 1917 { = O = (11.5/60)* 1083{= O = (6.5/60)*10,000}
– –
{ F= }376 { = 2256/6} = 6000/6} 10,000} 10,000} { F = 10,000}
– – –
{r = 22.56} { F = 720 = 4320/6} { F = 10,000} { F = 10,000} {r = 6.5}
{r = 43.20} {r = 39.5} {r = 11.5}
Radius of Planetary Orb based on 9;24 { = (376*25)/1000} 18{ = (720*25)/1000} 38{≈(10,000*25)/6583} 130;25 { = (10,000*25)/1917} 230 5/6
–
O = 25 {≈230.84 = (10,000*25)/1083}
r1 = 3⁄2 e {405 = 1.5*2.7*100} {180 = 1.5*1.2*100} 14{8}2{ = (1.5*5.928/60)* 777{ = (1.5*3.108/60)*10,000} 852{ = (1.5*3.408/60)*10,000}
{e = 2.7} {e = 1.2} 10,000} {e = 3.108} {e = 3.408}
– – – –
{ F = 376} { F = 720} {e = 5.928} { F = 10,000} { F = 10,000}
–
{ F= 10,000}
r2 = ½ e {135 = 0.5*2.7*100} {60 = 0.5*1.2*100} 494{ = (0.5*5.928/60)* 259 { = 0.5*3.108/60)*10,000} 284 { = 0.5*3.408/60)*10,000}
{e = 2.7} {e = 1.2} 10,000} {e = 3.108} {e = 3.408}
– – – –
{ F = 376} { F = 720} {e = 5.928} { F= 10,000} { F = 10,000}
–
{ F = 10,000}
405
r1 + r2 = 2e 600 {540}24 {240} {1976} {1036} {1136}
– – – – –
{ F = 376} { F = 720} { F = 10,000} { F = 10,000} { F = 10,000}
–
r1 = 3⁄2 e ( O = 25) 1;41¼ { = (405/6000)*25} ¾{ = (180/6000)*25} 5;34{≈5;38 = 38*1482/ 10 1/10 19 41/60 {≈19.667 =
Ibn al-Shāṭir and Copernicus: The Uppsala Notes Revisited
r: Ptolemaic epicycle radius (as given by Copernicus); e: Ptolemaic eccentricity (as given by Copernicus); r1: radius of first epicycle; r2: radius of second epicycle; {…}: reconstructed or
surmised parameter.
Numbers in bold are in U.
185
186 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
to Copernicus), while at 90° and 270°, it becomes larger (“traversing a far larger circum-
ference”).31 This would seem to indicate that Copernicus is following the illustration in
Nihāyat al-suʾl.
Turning to Mercury’s parameters, in the upper part of U, Copernicus writes 6 or 600
for r1 + r2 for Mercury. However, the “ecce” of 2256 (or 376) in conjunction with the
115.1 (or 19) for the diversitas diametrj, the displacement resulting from the Ṭūsī couple,
implies r1 + r2 = 576.32 But Copernicus uses 540 to derive the values in the lower part of
U, i.e., r1 = 1;41¼ and r2 = 0;33¾ (see Note 24). Where does this 540 come from? Looking
again at Figure 9, we can conjecture that Copernicus reasoned (incorrectly) as follows:
the largest size of the epicycle (“Apparent Epicycle Orb”) is 2256 + 115.1 = 2371.1 at
90°. Its smallest size (“Apparent Epicycle Orb”) is 2256 − 115.1 = 2140.9 at 0°. But rather
than taking the radius of the “True Epicycle Orb,” i.e., 2256 (or 376), he adopted the
“Apparent Epicycle Orb” at α = 0° as his reference epicycle, since it is the starting
point. If we take the maximum equation to occur at 90°, then the Ptolemaic eccentricity
of 6 (or 600) should be measured there with the epicycle being 2371.1. But at α = 0° ,
the ratio of the two “apparent” epicycles is 2140.9/2371.1 ≈ .9. So the sum of the eccen-
tricities (r1 + r2) should be proportionally lowered, at least according to this reasoning,
i.e., .9 × 600 = 540.33 Along with Copernicus’ description of a varying planetary “circum-
ference” (epicycle in Ibn al-Shāṭir’s model) and the explanation for 540 arising from the
diagram, I would argue that Copernicus had at his disposal something like Figure 9. In
which case, he had Ibn al-Shāṭir’s model when composing the Commentariolus. Why
then he didn’t make the simple transformation of Mercury (as well as Venus) to the De
rev model is taken up in the concluding section.
406
Ibn al-Shāṭir and Copernicus: The Uppsala Notes Revisited 187
Concluding remarks
Thanks to the recent work of Tzvi Langermann and Robert Morrison, we now know
that a certain Jewish scholar named Moses Galeano brought knowledge of Ibn
al-Shāṭir’s models to the Veneto (and environs such as Padua?) at the time Copernicus
was studying in Italy.34 And from the earlier discoveries and research of E.S. Kennedy
and his students as well as Otto Neugebauer and Noel Swerdlow, the remarkable simi-
larities between the models of Ibn al-Shāṭir (and other Islamic astronomers) with those
of Copernicus have been brought to light. Although there are still skeptics who believe
Copernicus could have come up with his models without this cross-cultural influence,
I will assume here, without further detailed proof, that Ibn al-Shāṭir’s models were
available in some form to Copernicus.35
As noted at the beginning of this paper, Swerdlow has sought to treat the reform of
the first anomaly independently of the heliocentric transformation; many (if not most)
other scholars, including Neugebauer, Kennedy, and Goldstein, have agreed with this
approach.36 André Goddu, however, has recently focused on the views of two scholars
who sought to link Copernicus’ turn to heliocentrism with his stated objective to rid
astronomy of the irregular motion of celestial orbs such as that brought on by the
equant37 – or to put it another way, to link the transformation of the second anomaly
with the “Marāgha-type” reforms of the first anomaly. The two scholars, Ludwik
Antoni Birkenmajer (1855–1929) and Curtis Wilson (1921–2012), proposed some-
what similar views on how the bi-epicyclic device somehow laid bare the possibility
for Wilson, the necessity for Birkenmajer, to replace Ptolemy’s large, unbecoming
epicycles for the outer planets with the Earth’s orbit around the Sun as shown in Figure
4 above. In some ways, this is similar to what is being proposed here, namely, the
“heliocentric bias” of the bi-epicyclic solution to the equant problem that allows a
simple, straightforward transformation to heliocentric models. Where I would differ
with Birkenmajer and Wilson (and perhaps Goddu) is that they have not provided plau-
sible pathways to the bi-epicyclic models of the Commentariolus, either in their pre-
sumed earlier geocentric or final heliocentric forms. Birkenmajer and Goddu invoke
Albert of Brudzewo, the Cracow University schoolman who criticized Peurbach’s
unthinking acceptance of the equant and also proposed a model to deal with the irregu-
lar motion brought on by Ptolemy’s lunar prosneusis point, as an important, perhaps
critical, influence on Copernicus.38 But these are slim pickings; it is a long way from
simply stating the equant problem or proposing a vague model for epicyclic oscillation
to Copernicus’ Commentariolus models.39
There is another way that I would differ from Birkenmajer and Wilson as presented
by Goddu. Their primary emphasis for Copernicus’ path to heliocentrism is on the outer
planets; in fact, Wilson states that his figure for the superior planets “cannot be easily
adapted to the case of the inferior planets,” which is true.40 On the other hand, I am
impressed with the utter simplicity of the transformation of Ibn al-Shāṭir’s Venus model
and, especially, his complex model for Mercury into the models in De revolutionibus
(Figure 6).41 More than the outer planets, this seems to show the “heliocentric bias” in its
most obvious form, and I think Ibn al-Shāṭir’s models for the inner planets may have
been influential in convincing Copernicus of the possibility of heliocentric models. But
407
188 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
this does bring up the fact, already mentioned above, that such a simple transformation
of the inner planets is not what we have in the Commentariolus (Figure 8). Given my
commitment to transmission, I would offer the following, tentative scenario. Copernicus,
for reasons to be outlined below, was attempting to find some form of a homocentric
cosmology that resolved the problem of Ptolemy’s violations of uniform circular motion,
in particular those brought about by the equants. Ibn al-Shāṭir’s models offered a com-
promise, in that they dispensed with eccentrics and all his major deferents were centered
on the Earth. The bi-epicyclic device was an uncomfortable but tolerable necessity. But
that left the Ptolemaic epicycles, which could be dispensed with by adopting heliocen-
trism. Admittedly, the latter required a bold leap, but here I think Birkenmajer and Wilson
have glimpsed an important part of Copernicus’ thinking and motivation. I would just
add that this still leaves open the possibility that Copernicus could have also been ini-
tially motivated by other factors toward heliocentrism, say Ibn al-Shāṭir’s models for the
inner planets (my preference) or some other, non-mathematical reason.42
Let me expand on the argument regarding homocentrism. As is well known, the
homocentric cosmology of the Andalusian Nūr al-Dīn al-Biṭrūjī (fl. ca. 1190) was read
and commented on in Europe from the time it became available in Latin translation in the
early thirteenth century. Coupled with the views of Averroes (1126–1198), another
Andalusian who had also advocated a return to Aristotelian homocentric orbs, one can
detect a growing interest in homocentric astronomy in fifteenth- and sixteenth-century
Europe, as well as Averroism.43 Copernicus himself brings up Calippus and Eudoxus in
his introduction to the Commentariolus, and as Swerdlow states, “What is of interest to
note about Copernicus’s remark is that he objects to the result, but not to the principle of
homocentric spheres.”44 Now there has been a tendency among both historians of Islamic
science and of astronomy to lump all the eastern Islamic, non-Ptolemaic models under
the rubric of the “Marāgha School” and to contrast them with the homocentric proposals
that came out of twelfth-century Andalusia.45 In this scenario, the main issue motivating
the former was resolving the irregularities of the equant and its siblings, while the
Andalusians were driven by “philosophical” concerns and a desire to return to a pure
Aristotelianism. But there is something fundamentally different about Ibn al-Shāṭir’s
models. They are actually centered on the Earth both mathematically and cosmologi-
cally, and they dispense with eccentrics. In a way that likely would have appealed to the
Averroists in Bologna and Padua, where Copernicus studied, Ibn al-Shāṭir’s models both
resolve a number of irregularities of Ptolemaic astronomy and at the same time, unlike
those of other members of the so-called “Marāgha School,” bring the Earth back into the
center of the universe.46 Although he is certainly not a homocentrist along the lines of
al-Biṭrūjī, he was able to achieve a successful “quasi-homocentric” system, whereas the
Andalusian Aristotelians and their followers could only tilt at windmills.
If we accept that Copernicus was, at the time of writing the Commentariolus, a “quasi-
homocentrist” along the lines of Ibn al-Shāṭir, then we can explain the puzzling models
for the inner planets. Eschewing their simple transformations that would have led to De
rev-type models with their eccentrics, he instead chose to make the centers of their main
deferents coincide with the mean Sun, i.e., the center of the Earth’s orb. However, this
created numerous problems, not the least of which was making them difficult if not unus-
able for calculation. But in the following 30 or so years, the “homocentrism” of the
408
Ibn al-Shāṭir and Copernicus: The Uppsala Notes Revisited 189
Acknowledgements
This paper would not have been possible without the insights of my student and collaborator Sajjad
Nikfahm-Khubravan; he first alerted me to the “heliocentric bias” of Ibn al-Shāṭir’s models, and
he has been my most acute and constructive critic. Robert Morrison’s comments on an earlier draft
were very helpful, especially regarding the connection of Ibn al-Shāṭir with homocentrism. An
anonymous reviewer saved me from several major blunders and generously provided advice on
how to present the transformation of Ibn al-Shāṭir’s models to Copernicus’. And as always, Sally
Ragep’s good judgment and keen editorial eye helped make this a much better paper. All remain-
ing shortcomings are, of course, my own.
Notes on Contributor
Jamil Ragep is a professor of Islamic Studies at McGill University and is currently working on
projects involving the relation of Islamic astronomy to Copernicus, science education in Islam, and
a database of Islamic scientific manuscripts.
Notes
1. N.M. Swerdlow, “The Derivation and First Draft of Copernicus’s Planetary Theory:ATranslation
of the Commentariolus with Commentary,” Proceedings of the American Philosophical
Society, 117(6), 1973, pp. 423–512, <https://www.jstor.org/stable/986461?seq=1#page_
scan_tab_contents>. A facsimile of the Uppsala notes and Swerdlow’s transcription, referred
to throughout this paper, are on pp. 428–9.
409
190 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
2. As is well-known, heliocentric in this context means “centered on the mean Sun,” not the “true
Sun.”
3. Swerdlow, “The Derivation and First Draft of Copernicus’s Planetary Theory” (see Note
1), pp. 471–8. See also N.M. Swerdlow and O. Neugebauer, Mathematical Astronomy in
Copernicus’s De Revolutionibus, 2 parts (New York: Springer-Verlag, 1984), part 1, pp. 54–
64, esp. 55–8. Dennis Duke provides animations showing this transformation from Ptolemaic
epicyclic models to eccentric models to Copernican models at <https://people.sc.fsu.
edu/~dduke/models> (25 September 2016). For the treatise by ʿAlī Qushjī that may well have
provided the basis for Regiomontanus’ propositions, see F. Jamil Ragep, “ʿAlī Qushjī and
Regiomontanus: Eccentric Transformations and Copernican Revolutions,” Journal for the
History of Astronomy, 36(4), 2005, pp. 359–71.
4. Swerdlow, “The Derivation and First Draft of Copernicus’s Planetary Theory” (see Note 1), p. 478.
5.
This [introduction in the Commentariolus of the heliocentric theory] really has nothing to
do with the principle of uniform circular motion that started Copernicus’s investigations in
the first place, but it seems likely that in the course of the intensive study of planetary theory
undertaken to solve the problem of the first anomaly, he carried out an analysis of the second
anomaly leading to his remarkable discovery.
(Swerdlow, “The Derivation and First Draft of Copernicus’s Planetary Theory” (see Note
1), p. 425). See also Swerdlow, “The Derivation and First Draft of Copernicus’s Planetary
Theory,” p. 430: “… the Maragha theory is, in any case, relevant only to the first anomaly,
not to the heliocentric theory.”
6. For the purposes of this paper, the most important is E.S. Kennedy and V. Roberts, “The
Planetary Theory of Ibn al-Shāṭir,” Isis, 50(3), 1959, pp. 227–35, reprinted E.S. Kennedy,
“Colleagues and Former Students,” in D.A. King and M.H. Kennedy (eds), Studies in the
Islamic Exact Sciences (Beirut: American University of Beirut, 1983), pp. 55–63.
7. V. Roberts, “The Solar and Lunar Theory of Ibn Ash-Shāṭir: A Pre-Copernican Copernican
Model,” Isis, 48(4), 1957, pp. 428–32, n. 2 on p. 428.
8. Although neither Swerdlow nor Neugebauer thought there was a connection between
Copernicus’ heliocentrism and his Islamic predecessors, it should be noted that both con-
sistently maintained the importance of Islamic astronomy, and in particular Ibn al-Shāṭir’s
models, for Copernicus:
The planetary models for longitude in the Commentariolus are all based upon the models of
Ibn ash-Shāṭir – although the arrangement for the inferior planets is incorrect – while those for
the superior planets in De revolutionibus use the same arrangement as ʿUrdi’s and Shīrāzī’s
model, and for the inferior planets the smaller epicycle is converted into an equivalent rotat-
ing eccentricity that constitutes a correct adaptation of Ibn ash-Shāṭir’s model. In both the
Commentariolus and De revolutionibus the lunar model is identical to Ibn ash-Shāṭir’s and
finally in both works Copernicus makes it clear that he was addressing the same physical
problems of Ptolemy’s models as his predecessors. It is obvious that with regard to these
problems, his solutions were the same.
The question therefore is not whether, but when, where, and in what form he learned of
Marāgha theory. (Swerdlow and Neugebauer, Mathematical Astronomy in Copernicus’s De
Revolutionibus (see Note 3), part 1, p. 47)
9. George Saliba has perceptively discussed the reasons for Ibn al-Shāṭir’s dismissal of eccen-
trics and justification of epicycles in several of his writings; see G. Saliba, “Critiques of
410
Ibn al-Shāṭir and Copernicus: The Uppsala Notes Revisited 191
411
192 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
412
Ibn al-Shāṭir and Copernicus: The Uppsala Notes Revisited 193
30. Figures vary greatly in the manuscripts of Ibn al-Shāṭir’s Nihāyat al-suʾl; what is represented
here is close to what one finds in Oxford, Bodleian, Marsh MS 139, f. 29a.
31. Swerdlow, “The Derivation and First Draft of Copernicus’s Planetary Theory” (see Note 1),
p. 503 for the quotations from Copernicus.
32. Swerdlow, “The Derivation and First Draft of Copernicus’s Planetary Theory” (see Note 1),
p. 507, where he derives 576(0). As he notes (pp. 508–9), Copernicus seems to have had con-
siderable problems in converting from the upper value in U for r1 + r2 to the values for the two
epicycles in the lower part.
33. This also works, of course, if one uses 376 and 19 instead of 2256 and 115.1.
34. Y.T. Langermann, “A Compendium of Renaissance Science: Taʿalumot ḥokma by Moshe
Galeano,” Aleph: Historical Studies in Science and Judaism, 7, 2007, pp. 283–318 on pp.
290–6; R. Morrison, “A Scholarly Intermediary between the Ottoman Empire and Renaissance
Europe,” Isis, 105(1), 2014, pp. 32–57.
35. A detailed argument is in preparation, which will supplement F.J. Ragep, “Copernicus and His
Islamic Predecessors: Some Historical Remarks,” History of Science, 45, 2007, pp. 65–81.
36. Swerdlow, though, does note that dealing with the irregularities related to the first anomaly
may have led Copernicus to investigate the second anomaly, which led to the heliocentric mod-
els; Swerdlow, “The Derivation and First Draft of Copernicus’s Planetary Theory” (see Note
1), p. 425. See also, Swerdlow and Neugebauer, Mathematical Astronomy in Copernicus’s De
Revolutionibus (see Note 3), part 1, p. 56:
Copernicus probably undertook an investigation of the second anomaly, and of the eccentric
model, because even with the Marāgha solution to the first anomaly, the uniform motion
of the planet on the epicycle must still be measured from the mean apogee lying on a line
directed to the equant …
For B. Goldstein’s views, see “Copernicus and the Origin of His Heliocentric System,” Journal
for the History of Astronomy, 33(3), 2002, pp. 219–35, on pp. 219–20. Goddu provides a
summary of the views of Swerdlow and Goldstein (“Ludwik Antoni Birkenmajer and Curtis
Wilson on the Origin of Nicholas Copernicus’s Heliocentrism” (see Note 15), pp. 227–8).
37. Goddu, “Ludwik Antoni Birkenmajer and Curtis Wilson on the Origin of Nicholas
Copernicus’s Heliocentrism” (see Note 15).
38. Recently, there has been something of an explosion of interest in Brudzewo. Goddu provides
a nice summary of him and the possible relation to Copernicus’ astronomy in “Ludwik Antoni
Birkenmajer and Curtis Wilson on the Origin of Nicholas Copernicus’s Heliocentrism” (see
Note 15), pp. 230–2, 236–43; for references, see n. 26 on p. 232 and passim. M. Malpangotto
makes an extended argument for the importance of Brudzewo in “The Original Motivation
for Copernicus’s Research: Albert of Brudzewo’s Commentariolum super Theoricas novas
Georgii Purbachii,” Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 70, 2016, pp. 361–411. Goddu
also extensively discussed Brudzewo in A. Goddu, Copernicus and the Aristotelian Tradition:
Education, Reading, and Philosophy in Copernicus’s Path to Heliocentrism (Leiden: Brill,
2010), for which see P. Barker and M. Vesel, “Goddu’s Copernicus: An Essay Review of
André Goddu’s Copernicus and the Aristotelian Tradition,” Aestimatio, 9, 2012, pp. 304–
36 and A. Goddu, “A Response to Peter Barker and Matjaž Vesel, ‘Goddu’s Copernicus’,”
Aestimatio, 10, 2013, pp. 248–76, esp. pp. 260–7.
39. I discuss Brudzewo’s model, and differentiate it from Copernicus’ bi-epicyclic device, in F.J.
Ragep, “From Tūn to Toruń: The Twists and Turns of the Ṭūsī-Couple,” in R. Feldhay and
F.J. Ragep (eds), Before Copernicus: The Cultures and Contexts of Scientific Learning in the
Fifteenth Century (Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2017 [exp.]).
413
194 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
40. Wilson, “Rheticus, Ravetz, and the ‘Necessity’ of Copernicus’ Innovation” (see Note 15),
p. 34, n. 25. This is cited by Goddu, “Ludwik Antoni Birkenmajer and Curtis Wilson on the
Origin of Nicholas Copernicus’s Heliocentrism” (see Note 15), p. 248, who credits Robert
Westman for bringing Wilson’s views to his attention (p. 226, n. 3).
41. For Mercury, see Swerdlow, “The Derivation and First Draft of Copernicus’s Planetary
Theory” (see Note 1), p. 502, Figure 40 and Swerdlow and Neugebauer, Mathematical
Astronomy in Copernicus’s De Revolutionibus (see Note 3), part 1, p. 410; the transformation
from Ibn al-Shāṭir’s model to the De rev model can be seen from Figure 70 (part 2, p. 657) to
Figure 73(a) (part 2, p. 658). This is discussed in detail in Nikfahm-Khubravan and Ragep,
“Ibn al-Shāṭir and Copernicus on Mercury” (see Note 17).
42. One of the factors could be the ordering of the planets, which Bernard Goldstein and Robert
Westman have both claimed as the major motivation for Copernicus; Goldstein, “Copernicus
and the Origin of His Heliocentric System” (see Note 36) and R. Westman, The Copernican
Question (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2011), esp. pp. 76–105. Another factor could
have been the question of the Earth’s possible rotation, which had been extensively discussed in
both the Latin and Islamic worlds; see F.J. Ragep, “Ṭūsī and Copernicus: The Earth’s Motion in
Context,” Science in Context, 14(1–2), 2001, pp. 145–63. On the need for a multifaceted approach
to Copernicus, see Feldhay and Ragep (eds), Before Copernicus (see Note 39), Introduction.
43. There is in fact an extensive amount of work on the subject. The importance of homocentric
astronomy, especially for Regiomontanus, has been emphasized by Michael Shank in sev-
eral articles: M.H. Shank, “The ‘Notes on al-Biṭrūjī’ Attributed to Regiomontanus: Second
Thoughts,” Journal for the History of Astronomy, 23(1), 1992, pp. 15–30; M.H. Shank,
“Regiomontanus and Homocentric Astronomy,” Journal for the History of Astronomy, 29(2),
1998, pp. 157–66. Robert Morrison has also drawn our attention to the Jewish role in dissemi-
nating homocentric astronomy in Europe: R.G. Morrison, The Light of the World: Astronomy
in al-Andalus (Berkeley; Los Angeles: University of California Press, 2016). See also the
important article by N.M. Swerdlow, “Regiomontanus’s Concentric-Sphere Models for the
Sun and the Moon,” Journal for the History of Astronomy, 30(1), 1999, pp. 1–23. Swerdlow
had earlier noted the interest in homocentric astronomy in N.M. Swerdlow, “Aristotelian
Planetary Theory in the Renaissance: Giovanni Battista Amico’s Homocentric Spheres,”
Journal for the History of Astronomy, 3(1), 1972, pp. 36–48. Homocentric astronomy in
early modern Europe is also dealt with by M. Di Bono, Le sfere omocentriche di Giovan
Battista Amico … (Genoa: Centro di Studio sulla Storia della Tecnica, 1990); E. Peruzzi, La
nave di Ermete: la cosmologia di Girolamo Fracastoro (Florence: Olschki, 1995). Goldstein
has connected the ordering of the planets, which he sees as crucial for Copernicus, to the
Averroists (“Copernicus and the Origin of His Heliocentric System” (see Note 36), p. 225).
On Averroism in early modern Europe, see A. Akasoy and G. Giglioni, Renaissance Averroism
and Its Aftermath: Arabic Philosophy in Early Modern Europe (Dordrecht: Springer, 2013).
I was intrigued to discover that “Birkenmajer concluded that Copernicus knew the Averroist
critique of Ptolemaic models, and he believed that the critique motivated Copernicus to adopt
concentric models initially.” (Goddu, “Ludwik Antoni Birkenmajer and Curtis Wilson on the
Origin of Nicholas Copernicus’s Heliocentrism” (see Note 15), p. 242).
44. Swerdlow, “The Derivation and First Draft of Copernicus’s Planetary Theory” (see Note 1),
p. 434.
45. A.I. Sabra, “The Andalusian Revolt against Ptolemaic Astronomy: Averroes and al-Biṭrūjī,”
in E. Mendelsohn (ed.), Transformation and Tradition in the Sciences: Essays in Honor of
I. Bernard Cohen (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984), pp. 133–53, reprinted
in A.I. Sabra, Optics, Astronomy and Logic: Studies in Arabic Science and Philosophy, XV
(Aldershot: Ashgate Variorum Reprints, 1994). Saliba has argued against such a dichotomiza-
tion in his “Critiques of Ptolemaic Astronomy in Islamic Spain” (see Note 9).
414
Ibn al-Shāṭir and Copernicus: The Uppsala Notes Revisited 195
46. Morrison, The Light of the World (see Note 43), p. 44, n. 165, also associates the astronomy
of Ibn al-Shāṭir with the homocentric astronomy of Ibn Naḥmias (fl. ca. 1400 c.e.), someone
who may well have been known in Renaissance Italy. Morrison, following Saliba (see Note 9
supra), notes that Ibn al-Shāṭir made a strict distinction between eccentrics, which were unac-
ceptable, and epicycles, which were possible, likening them to stars or planets that were also
embedded in the cosmos; this could well have opened the way for an Aristotelian or Averroist
to accept Ibn al-Shāṭir’s “quasi-homocentrism.” Morrison also points to Profiat Duran (d. ca.
1415) as someone who interpreted Maimonides’ doctrine of homocentricity as allowing for
epicycles (Morrison, The Light of the World, p. 16).
47. The fact that the transformations are mathematically consistent with Regiomontanus’ propo-
sitions does not entail that they were actually used by Copernicus.
48. For example, Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī in his Tadhkira states,
They placed the sun in the medial orb between the former and the latter … deeming this the
most elegant arrangement and the most excellent structure inasmuch as the six were con-
nected to it – the upper [planets] in a certain way, the lower in another and the moon in yet
another.
(F.J. Ragep, Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī’s Memoir on Astronomy (al-Tadhkira fī ʿilm al-hayʾa), 2
vols. (New York: Springer-Verlag, 1993), vol. 1, p. 110). Cf. G.J. Toomer (trans.), Ptolemy’s
Almagest (London: Duckworth, 1984), pp. 419–20 [H207]. For the Latin West, see E. Grant,
Planets, Stars, and Orbs: The Medieval Cosmos, 1200–1687 (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1994), p. 233.
415
THE MERCURY MODELS
OF IBN AL-ŠĀṬIR AND COPERNICUS
SAJJAD NIKFAHM-KHUBRAVAN
Institute of Islamic Studies, McGill University
F. JAMIL RAGEP
Institute of Islamic Studies, McGill University
1. INTRODUCTION
1
E. S. Kennedy and V. Roberts, “ The Planetary theory of Ibn al-Shāṭir ”, Isis, 50/3 (1959):
227-35 at 232-3, reprinted E. S. Kennedy, “ Colleagues and former students ”, in D. A. King
and M. H. Kennedy (ed.), Studies in the Islamic exact sciences (Beirut, 1983), p. 55-63 at
60-1.
2
Nicolas Copernic, De revolutionibus orbium coelestium (Des révolutions des orbes célestes),
3 vol., transl. M.-P. Lerner and A.-P. Segonds with the collaboration of C. Luna, I. Pantin, and
D. Savoie (Paris, 2015), vol. III, p. 394-409. Elsewhere they at least mention the similarity of
the lunar models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus but immediately cast doubt on its significance
(III, 307; see also I, 311, 354, n. 1, 553-4).
3
M. Malpangotto, “ L’Univers auquel s’est confronté Copernic: La sphère de Mercure dans
les Theoricae novae planetarum de Georg Peurbach ”, Historia mathematica, 40/3 (2013):
262-308.
4
R. S. Westman, The Copernican question: Prognostication, skepticism, and celestial order
(Berkeley, 2011), p. 531, n. 136.
2
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 199
Copernicus’ and al-Shatir’s models and the Tusi couple… The question should
be reconsidered 5 ”. A different tack is taken by Viktor Blåsjö, who insists that
similarities between models can be explained by there being “ natural ” solutions
that would lead Copernicus and Ibn al-Šāṭir to come to similar conclusions with-
out the necessity of assuming influence 6 . (More on this later.)
On the other hand, Noel Swerdlow, throughout his career, has insisted that the
similarities between Copernicus’ models and those of his Islamic predecessors
“ is so close that independent invention by Copernicus is all but impossible 7 ”.
But for Mercury (as well as for Venus) this creates something of an unacknowl-
edged conundrum for Swerdlow. Since Ibn al-Šāṭir’s Mercury model and Coper-
nicus’ in De revolutionibus are virtually the same, one must then explain why
the Commentariolus model (from some 30 years earlier) is different, not to say
flawed, if, as Swerdlow has maintained, Copernicus did have Ibn al-Šāṭir’s one
and only Mercury model when composing the Commentariolus. Swerdlow has
provided a complex scenario, most recently repeated in an article, that culminates
with the Commentariolus model 8 . But it has seemed odd to us that Copernicus
substituted a flawed model when, according to Swerdlow, he had a much better
one immediately at hand. We are also uncomfortable with the numerous ad hoc
assumptions Swerdlow needs to make in order for Copernicus to reach, over a
30-year period, essentially what he had all along. Thus part of the purpose of
this paper is to suggest an alternative account that we believe provides a more
straightforward explanation 9 . Inasmuch as Swerdlow has already offered a cri-
tique of some of the central points in this paper, we will need to respond to his
criticisms 10 .
5
A. Goddu, Copernicus and the Aristotelian tradition: Education, reading, and philosophy in
Copernicus’s path to heliocentrism (Leiden, 2010), p. 157.
6
V. Blåsjö, “ A critique of the arguments for Maragha influence on Copernicus ”, Journal for
the history of astronomy, 45/2 (2014): 183-95.
7
N. Swerdlow, “ Copernicus, Nicolaus (1473-1543) ”, in W. Applebaum (ed.), Encyclopedia
of the scientific revolution from Copernicus to Newton (New York, 2000), p. 165.
8
N. M. Swerdlow, “ The Derivation and first draft of Copernicus’s planetary theory: A transla-
tion of the Commentariolus with commentary ”, Proceedings of the American Philosophical
Society, 117/6 (1973): 423-512, esp. 471-8, 499-509. Swerdlow usefully summarizes his po-
sition in “ Copernicus’s derivation of the heliocentric theory from Regiomontanus’s eccentric
models of the second inequality of the superior and inferior planets ”, Journal for the history
of astronomy, 48/1 (2017): 33-61, esp. 33-44.
9
A preliminary attempt to deal with Copernicus’ Mercury models and their connection to that
of Ibn al-Šāṭir is in F. J. Ragep, “ Ibn al-Shāṭir and Copernicus: The Uppsala notes revisited ”,
Journal for the history of astronomy, 47/4 (2016): 395-415 at 400-6.
10
Swerdlow, “ Copernicus’s derivation of the heliocentric theory ”, p. 45-61.
3
200 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
Fig. 1. Ibn al-Šāṭir’s Mercury model in Nihāyat al-su’l. Moving the mean Sun
to F results in the “ Tychonic ” version of the De rev. model. (Not to scale ∗ .)
∗
For reasons of visualization, our figures are not to scale; in general, we use a mean motion
(α) of 35°, which entails an epicycle motion (κ) of ca. 75°. In drafting the figures, we assume
that the deferent apogee and epicycle apex are on the apsidal line when α = 0°. Darker lines
indicate the sequence of the radii of the orbs from the Earth to the planet due to the various
motions. Animations illustrating the transformation of Ibn al-Šāṭir’s models into those of
Copernicus may be found at https://islamsci.mcgill.ca/MercuryAnimations/.
4
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 201
5
202 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
Another aim of this paper is to deal with Blåsjö’s claims regarding what he
calls the “ equivalence ” of the Mercury models in the Almagest and the Com-
mentariolus, as well as his insistence that there is a “ natural ” route that goes
from Ptolemy to the more correct models in De revolutionibus that undermines
transmission. To do this, we need to provide detailed discussions of the Mercury
models of Ptolemy, in addition to those of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus. The for-
mer has been discussed competently and in detail by a number of historians 11 ,
but it will be useful to summarize a few salient points for our analysis. For
Copernicus, we have Swerdlow’s translation and study of the Commentariolus
as well as Swerdlow and Neugebauer’s lengthy study of De revolutionibus 12 ,
both being indispensable for this paper. As for Ibn al-Šāṭir’s model, there are
good presentations by E. S. Kennedy and Victor Roberts 13 , as well as by Willy
Hartner 14 ; however, their work did not delve deeply enough for the kind of com-
parisons that will allow us to see how Copernicus appropriated the work of his
predecessors. Another problem is that up until recently, there have been no pub-
lished editions or translations of Ibn al-Šāṭir’s Nihāyat al-su’l where he presents
his Mercury model 15 . So in appendices 2 and 3, we provide a translation and
critical edition of chapter 21 of part 1 of his work that deal with Mercury, based
on ten manuscripts.
11
See, for example, O. Pedersen, A survey of the Almagest, reprint of the 1974 orig. ed. with
annotation and new commentary by A. Jones (New York, 2011), p. 309-28; O. Neugebauer,
A history of ancient mathematical astronomy, 3 parts (Berlin / New York, 1975), I, 158-69;
and esp. N. Swerdlow, “ Ptolemy’s theory of the inferior planets ”, Journal for the history of
astronomy, 20/1 (1989): 29-60 at 43-59.
12
Swerdlow, “ The Derivation and first draft ”, p. 499-509; N. M. Swerdlow and O. Neugebauer,
Mathematical astronomy in Copernicus’s De revolutionibus, 2 parts (New York, 1984), I,
403-43.
13
Kennedy and Roberts, “ The Planetary theory of Ibn al-Shāṭir ”, p. 231-2.
14
W. Hartner, “ Ptolemy, Azarquiel, Ibn al-Shāṭir, and Copernicus on Mercury: A study of
parameters ”, Archives internationales d’histoire des sciences, 24/4 (1974): 5-25, reprinted
in W. Hartner, Oriens-Occidens: Ausgewählte Schriften zur Wissenschafts- und Kul-
turgeschichte: Festschrift zum 60. Geburtstag, ed. Y. Maeyama, 2 vol. (Hildesheim: Olms,
1968-1984), vol. II p. 292-312.
15
G. Saliba does give an English translation of the Saturn chapter in his “ Arabic astronomy and
Copernicus ”, Zeitschrift für Geschichte der Arabisch-Islamischen Wissenschaften, 1 (1984):
73-87 at 81-2, reprinted in G. Saliba, A history of Arabic astronomy: Planetary theories
during the golden age of Islam (New York, 1994), p. 291-305 at 299-300. E. Penchèvre has
recently published an edition and French translation of part 1, ch. 25 of Nihāyat al-su’l, which
deals with the latitude theory for Venus and Mercury (“ Vénus selon Ibn al-Šāṭir ”, Arabic
sciences and philosophy, 26/2 (2016): 185-214 at 202-14). Penchèvre has also put online an
edition, French translation, and commentary of the Nihāyat al-su’l at arXiv.org (https://
arxiv.org/abs/1709.04965: “ La Nihāya al-sūl fī taṣḥīḥ al-’uṣūl d’Ibn al-Šāṭir: Édition,
traduction et commentaire ”; accessed 27 February 2018).
6
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 203
7
204 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
Ptolemy found Mercury to be the most problematic planet he had to deal with,
in part because of the difficulties involved in viewing a planet whose maximum
elongation from the Sun is about 28°, in part because of several unfortunate as-
sumptions 16 . Our purpose here, however, is not to critique Ptolemy’s method-
ology or observations but simply to present his model, both as it appears in the
mathematical-schematic version in the Almagest and in the physical, solid-sphere
versions of the Islamic hay’a and Latin theorica traditions. As is well known,
the origins of the latter are to be found in Ptolemy’s Planetary hypotheses, which
was the basis of the hay’a tradition and from it the Latin theoricae (the Planetary
hypotheses not being available in Europe in the medieval period).
The model for Mercury as presented in the Almagest is represented in fig-
ure 3 17 .
There are several things that make Mercury distinctive:
1) Unlike the case of the other four “ vacillating ” planets (i. e., the ones that
exhibit retrogradation), the center of equal motion E is placed closer to the world
center O, while the deferent center N, which maintains equal distance R to the
epicycle center C, is usually (except once in a cycle) farther away. For the other
planets, the order of centers (toward the apogee) is O-N-E.
2) Distinctive among the vacillating planets, but similar to what was done for
the Moon, the deferent center is not fixed but moves on a small circle, coinciding
with E once every cycle.
3) The result of this configuration is that the epicycle center is not closest
to the Earth at 180°, as it is for the other vacillating planets, but at two places,
±120°, which fulfills his empirical conditions (figure 4 18 ).
So far, we have only discussed the model as presented in the Almagest. But
in a hay’a work, as later in Peurbach’s Theoricae, the plane geometrical models
of the Almagest are transformed into full-fledged spherical models in which cir-
cles were made into uniformly rotating orbs – fully spherical epicycles that do
not surround the Earth or concentric and eccentric hollowed-out spheres that do
surround the Earth. Thus a typical hay’a illustration for Mercury would appear
as figure 5 19 .
16
For some of these assumptions, see Swerdlow, “ Ptolemy’s theory of the inferior planets ”,
p. 43-59.
17
Figure 3 is a modified version of fig. 11 in Swerdlow, “ Ptolemy’s theory of the inferior plan-
ets ”, p. 50.
18
Figure 4 is a modified version of fig. 13 in Swerdlow, “ Ptolemy’s theory of the inferior plan-
ets ”, p. 52.
19
Figure 5 is adapted from S. P. Ragep, Jaghmīnī’s Mulakhkhaṣ: An Islamic introduction to
Ptolemaic astronomy (New York, 2016), figure 4, p. 96.
8
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 205
Chart 1. Ptolemy’s Almagest parameters for Mercury (see fig. 3) (plus / minus
indicates sequential / counter-sequential zodiacal motion).
There are several points that should be noted. First, Mercury, unlike the mod-
els for the upper planets and Venus, has four rather than three orbs (not counting
the planet itself). The three orbs in common are the parecliptic (responsible for
the motion of the apogee), the deferent (the basis for the mean zodiacal motion),
and the epicycle (the source for the synodic motion). But in addition, Mercury
has a dirigent (mudīr) that causes the deferent center to move on a circle that
brings it closer and farther away from the world center. Another feature of the
model is that a point on the deferent, and in particular the epicycle center (which
is located in the deferent), cuts equal angles in equal times not with respect to the
deferent center (as one would expect based on the principle of uniform circular
motion in the celestial region), but with respect to the equant point, which is lo-
cated mid-way between the world center and dirigent center on the apsidal line.
There are thus 4 critical points on the apsidal line (this at the initial position,
i. e., when the epicycle center is at apogee): the world center, the equant point,
the dirigent center, and the deferent center. For Ptolemy in the Almagest, the
distance between the world center and equant point is 3 parts where the distance
from the deferent center to epicycle center is 60 parts; likewise, the distance
from the equant point to the dirigent center is 3 parts and the distance from the
dirigent center to the deferent center is 3 parts. The upshot of this arrangement
and the stipulated motions for the orbs is that the epicycle center will trace an
oval-shaped figure in which the nearest approach to the world center (and the
Earth) occurs at about 120° and 240°, whereas the farthest distance is, as one
would expect, at 0°. (Figure 6 shows how this was illustrated in Ṭūsī’s Taḏkira;
note in particular the explicit designation of the nearest distances at the trines.
For the parameters see chart 1.)
9
206 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
α: mean motion
γ: motion of epicycle (Ptolemaic)
A: apogee
B: point opposite apogee
C: epicycle center
E: equant point (about which equal motion of the epicycle center occurs)
M: center of circle about which the deferent center moves
N: deferent / eccentric center
O: world center
P: planet
R: radius of deferent
⊙: mean Sun
Fig. 3. Ptolemy’s Mercury model.
10
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 207
20
20
From this period we have Ibn al-Haytham’s remarkable work Al-Šukūk ‘alā Baṭlamyūs
From this about
(“ Doubts periodPtolemy
we have ”), Ibn
A. I.al-Haytham’s
Sabra and N. remarkable
Shehaby (ed.) work Al-Šukūk
(Cairo, 1971;‘alā
2nd Baṭlamyūs
ed., Cairo,
(“ Doubts
1996) about
as well as Ptolemy ”), A.
the treatise by I.Abū
Sabra and N.
‘Ubayd Shehaby an
al-Jūzjānī, (ed.) (Cairo,of1971;
associate 2nd ed.,
Ibn Sīnā (for Cairo,
which
1996)
see G. Saliba, “ Ibn Sīnā and Abū ‘Ubayd al-Jūzjānī: The problem of the Ptolemaic(for
as well as the treatise by Abū ‘Ubayd al-Jūzjānī, an associate of Ibn Sīnā which
equant ”,
see G. Saliba,
Journal for the“history
Ibn Sīnā ofand Abūscience,
Arabic ‘Ubayd4al-Jūzjānī: The problem
(1980): 376-403, of the
reprinted Ptolemaic
in G. Saliba, A equant ”,
history
Journal
of Arabicfor the historyp.of85-112).
astronomy, Arabic science, 4 (1980): 376-403, reprinted in G. Saliba, A history
21 of
ForArabic astronomy,
a summary, see G.p. Saliba,
85-112).“ Arabic planetary theories after the eleventh century AD ”,
21
ForR.a Rashed
in summary, seeEncyclopedia
(ed.), G. Saliba, “ Arabic planetary
of the history theoriesscience,
of Arabic after the3 eleventh century
vol. (London, AD ”,
1996), I,
in R. Rashed
58-127. On the (ed.), Encyclopedia ”ofinthe
“ Eudoxan-couple history
Islam, seeofF. Arabic
J. Ragep,science, 3 vol. (London,
“ Ibn al-Haytham 1996), I,
and Eudoxus:
58-127. Onof
The revival thehomocentric
“ Eudoxan-couple
modeling ” ininIslam,
Islamsee
”, inF.C.J.Burnett
Ragep, et“ Ibn al-Haytham
al. (ed.), Studiesand Eudoxus:
in the history
The revival
of the exactofsciences
homocentric modeling
in honour in Islam
of David ”, in C.
Pingree Burnett2004),
(Leiden, et al. (ed.), Studies An
p. 786-809. in the history
overview
of
of the
the exact sciencesand
Ṭūsī-couple in its
honour of David Pingree
cross-cultural (Leiden,
transmission can 2004),
be found p. 786-809. An overview
in F. J. Ragep, “ From
of
Tūn to Toruń: The twists and turns of the Ṭūsī-couple ”, in R. Feldhay and F. J. Ragep“ From
the Ṭūsī-couple and its cross-cultural transmission can be found in F. J. Ragep, (ed.),
Tūn to Toruń:
Before The twists
Copernicus: and turnsand
The cultures of the Ṭūsī-couple
contexts ”, in R.
of scientific Feldhayinand
learning the F. J. Ragep
fifteenth (ed.),
century
11
Before Copernicus:
(Montreal, 2017), p. The cultures and contexts of scientific learning in the fifteenth century
161-97.
(Montreal, 2017), p. 161-97.
208 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
12
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 209
13
210 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
that required uniform circular motion in the heavens. As such, devices such as
the equant were replaced by combinations of uniformly rotating orbs. Now the
reason we say that it is an eastern Islamicate phenomenon, contingent on cer-
tain intellectual and possibly social and religious trends, is that other examples
we have of criticisms of Ptolemy took different approaches. For example, Pro-
clus in his Hypotyposis is highly critical of Ptolemy’s eccentric and epicyclic
models but offers no criticism of the equant and has nothing to offer in the way
of alternatives 22 . In the western Islamic world, in particular in twelfth-century
al-Andalus, one has a quite dissimilar set of criticisms leading to the homocen-
tric alternative of al-Biṭrūjī that is mostly rejected in the Islamic East 23 . Pre-
Copernican alternatives in Europe are either of a far different sort (e. g., those
of the fourteenth-century Jewish scholar Levi ben Gerson 24 ) or are based on al-
ternatives that clearly can be traced to Islamic precedents (such as those of Ibn
Naḥmias, Regiomontanus, and Giovanni Battista Amico 25 ). For this reason,
Copernicus’ criticism of the equant in the introduction to the Commentariolus,
and his models meant to rectify it, are strikingly innovative within a European
context 26 .
22
Proclus, Procli Diadochi Hypotyposis astronomicarum positionum, ed. C. Manitius (Leipzig,
1909; reprint, Stuttgart, 1974). For a well-informed analysis of Proclus’ attitude toward as-
tronomy (and an important corrective to Pierre Duhem’s discussion in his Σώζειν τὰ φαι-
νόμενα), see G. E. R. Lloyd, “ Saving the appearances ”, Classical quarterly, 28/1 (1978):
202-22, esp. 204-11 (reprinted with new introduction in G. E. R. Lloyd, Methods and prob-
lems in Greek science [Cambridge, 1991], p. 248-77).
23
A. I. Sabra, “ The Andalusian revolt against Ptolemaic astronomy: Averroes and al-Biṭrūjī ”,
in E. Mendelsohn (ed.), Transformation and tradition in the sciences: Essays in honor of
I. Bernard Cohen (Cambridge, 1984), p. 133-53, reprinted in A. I. Sabra, Optics, astronomy
and logic: Studies in Arabic science and philosophy, XV (Aldershot, 1994).
24
B. R. Goldstein, The Astronomy of Levi Ben Gerson (1288-1344): A critical edition of chap-
ters 1-20 with translation and commentary (New York, 1985).
25
On Ibn Naḥmias, see R. G. Morrison, The Light of the world: Astronomy in al-Andalus
(Berkeley, 2016). On Regiomontanus, see N. Swerdlow, “ Regiomontanus’s concentric-
sphere models for the Sun and Moon ”, Journal for the history of astronomy, 30/1 (1999):
1-23; M. H. Shank, “ The ‘ Notes on al-Biṭrūjī ’ attributed to Regiomontanus: Second
thoughts ”, Journal for the history of astronomy, 23/1 (1992): 15-30; and M. H. Shank,
“ Regiomontanus and homocentric astronomy ”, Journal for the history of astronomy, 29/2
(1998): 157-66. For Amico, see N. Swerdlow, “ Aristotelian planetary theory in the Renais-
sance: Giovanni Battista Amico’s homocentric spheres ”, Journal for the history of astron-
omy, 3/1 (1972): 36-48; and M. di Bono, “ Copernicus, Amico, Fracastoro, and Ṭūsī’s device:
Observations on the use and transmission of a model ”, Journal for the history of astronomy,
26/2 (1995): 133-54. See also R. Morrison, “ A scholarly intermediary between the Ottoman
Empire and Renaissance Europe ”, Isis, 105/1 (2014): 32-57.
26
Alternatively, Michela Malpangotto has argued that the original motivation for Coperni-
cus’ criticism of the equant and his research leading to heliocentrism came from Albert of
Brudzewo (d. ca. 1497); “ The Original motivation for Copernicus’s research: Albert of
14
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 211
On the other hand, Ibn al-Šāṭir is the inheritor of a long tradition of Islamic
criticisms of Ptolemy and of the alternatives these gave rise to. Unfortunately,
these alternatives are still referred to by the generic term “ Marāgha ” even though
there are few if any models that can be attributed to the years of operation of the
Mongol-sponsored Marāgha Observatory (roughly 1260-83); most of the theo-
retical work of Mu’ayyid al-Dīn al-‘Urḍī (d. ca. 1266) and Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī
(1201-74) predates their time at the Observatory, and the major astronomical
works of Quṭb al-Dīn al-Šīrāzī (d. 1311) were written after he left Marāgha. And
we know that there were alternative models long before Marāgha gained promi-
nence as a Mongol capital, and these models continued to be proposed centuries
afterwards 27 . So we need to see Ibn al-Šāṭir in the fourteenth century as one
of a series of astronomers, spanning six or more centuries, who worked to find
models that provided results comparable to those of Ptolemy while adhering to
the accepted celestial physics.
Ibn al-Šāṭir, the long-time chief muezzin (ra’īs al-mu’aḏḏinīn) and time-
keeper (muwaqqit) at the Umayyad Mosque in Damascus, was distinctive for
a number of reasons 28 . Unlike his “ Marāgha ” predecessors, he rejected ec-
centrics, so attempted to base his alternatives on concentrics (orbs whose center
was the Earth) and epicycles. He also made strong claims that his work was
based on new observations. Unfortunately, his major work in which he claims
to have explained the observational basis for his new models, Ta‘līq al-arṣād
(“ Explanation of the observations ”), is lost to us. What we have is a kind of
summary account of his models, contained in a hay’a work entitled Nihāyat al-
su’l fī taṣḥīḥ al-uṣūl (“ The culmination of inquiry into correcting the hypothe-
ses ”). The Mercury model is presented in chapter 21 of part 1; our translation
and edition are in appendices 2 and 3.
Brudzewo’s Commentariolum super Theoricas novas Georgii Purbachii ”, Archive for his-
tory of exact sciences, 70/4 (2016): 361-411. Though Brudzewo, and earlier Henry of Hesse,
do indeed point out the problems related to the equant, it is not entirely clear that this is done
with the same motivation of Islamic astronomers who put in place a program for reforming the
Ptolemaic system. As Edith Sylla has put it, in response to Malpangotto’s contentions regard-
ing the equant: “ Contrary to Malpangotto, I think that Peurbach and Brudzewo both accept
the idea that there are some physical orbs uniformly rotating and other, purely mathemati-
cal methods that do not correspond to bodies. Brudzewo is not disappointed with Peurbach
but is elucidating positions with which Peurbach would have agreed ”. E. Sylla, “ The Sta-
tus of astronomy as a science in fifteenth-century Cracow: Ibn al-Haytham, Peurbach, and
Copernicus ”, in Feldhay and Ragep, Before Copernicus, p. 45-78 at 78.
27
For a critique of “ Marāgha ” as a shorthand for this long tradition, see S. P. Ragep and
F. J. Ragep, “ The ‘ Marāgha school ’: The myth and its prequel ”, forthcoming.
28
For an overview of his life and works, see S. Nikfahm-Khubravan and F. J. Ragep, “ Ibn al-
Shāṭir ”, Encyclopaedia of Islam, 3rd ed., forthcoming.
15
212 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
The model itself consists of seven solid orbs 29 (see figure 7): 1) the par-
ecliptic [r0 ]; 2) the inclined [r1 ]; 3) the deferent [r2 ]; 4) the dirigent [r3 ]; 5)
the epicycle [r4 ]; 6) the enclosing [r5 ]; 7) the maintaining [r6 ]. r0 , r1 , . . . des-
ignate the radii of the orbs in the schematic version (figure 10); their values
are given in chart 2. This allows radii of the “ schematic ” equators to be consid-
ered, somewhat anachronistically, as linked, uniformly rotating vectors 30 . These
radii, determined by the planetary parameters, are of the “ inner equators ” (in-
dicated in dashed lines in figure 8) of the solid orbs, which are parallel to the
“ outer equators ” on the surface of the orb. (For a further explanation of these
“ inner equators ”, see Ragep, Ṭūsī’s Memoir on astronomy, II, 435-6, as well as
I, 350-3, fig. C11-C15 for examples.)
Since the parecliptic only causes the slow motion of the apogee (one degree
per 60 years 31 ), we will ignore it in the subsequent analysis. The combination
of the inclined, deferent, and dirigent will result in the apex of the epicycle being
displaced by 2α; thus in figure 9, which is a schematic version of figure 7, we
note that the epicyclic apex A, which for Ptolemy is on the line from the equant
through the epicycle center, has shifted from A0 to A1 when α = 90°. The
enclosing and maintaining orbs will therefore also be 90° from the Ptolemaic
“ reference apex ” A0 of the epicycle. Practically, this means that the epicycle’s
daily motion for Ibn al-Šāṭir (as also for Copernicus in De revolutionibus) is
≈ 2; 7° (κ) rather than ≈ 3; 6° (γ) as it was for Ptolemy. Ibn al-Šāṭir refers
to the sum of his epicycle’s motion (κ) plus the mean motion of center (α) as
the “ proper ” [khāṣṣa] motion of the epicycle, which is the motion of anomaly
(γ = κ + α) in the Ptolemaic model.
The final two orbs, the enclosing and maintaining, form a Ṭūsī-couple: in
the schematic model (figure 9) they are the same size but in the full, solid-sphere
29
Solid here refers to the substance of the orbs, whereby other bodies are precluded from moving
through them. Of course, another solid body can be embedded within a solid orb; e. g., an
epicycle is embedded within a deferent orb, each rotating with its own motion. As one can
see in figure 7, all of Ibn al-Šāṭir’s orbs (except for the planet itself) contain one or more orbs
embedded within them.
30
Kennedy and Roberts, “ The Planetary theory of Ibn al-Shāṭir ”, p. 231, fig. 2.
31
Earlier in the Nihāya, Ibn al-Šāṭir cites 1°/100 years (Ptolemy) as well as 1°/ 66 2/3 years and
1°/70 years (the “ Moderns ”) as possible values for precession (part I, ch. 3 and ch. 5), which
one would expect to be equivalent to the motion of apogee. In fact, in Al-Zīj al-jadīd, Ibn al-
Šāṭir tells us that the motion of the apogees for all the planets is 1°/60 years, whereas the
precessional motion is 1°/70 years. He claims the proof can be found in his Ta‘līq al-arṣād,
which unfortunately is not extant. See Leiden ms. Or. 65, f. 49b.
16
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 213
17
214 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
Fig. 8. “ Inner equators ” (in dashed lines) of the solid orbs. (Not to scale.)
18
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 215
C: epicycle center
F: deferent center
O: world center
Q: transposed Ptolemaic equant
A0 : (Apex)0
A1 : (Apex)1
19
216 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
version (figure 7) they are in the ratio of 2:1 32 . Because Mercury is embedded in
the maintaining orb, it will oscillate on a straight line toward and away from the
center of the epicycle. Note that the line (OF) connecting the world center and
the deferent center is in the direction of the mean Sun, a point of considerable
importance to which we shall return.
Let us now turn to the parameters. For the outer planets, Ibn al-Šāṭir seems
to have adopted the Ptolemaic eccentricities e and then made the deferent radius
r2 = 3e/2 and the dirigent radius r3 = e/2 33 ; the ratio r2 : r3 is then 3.
For Venus, however, the ratio r2 : r3 ≈ 3.9 rather than 3 34 . For Mercury,
the ratio is r2 : r3 ≈ 4.45 35 . One of the consequences for Mercury is that
this results in considerably different amounts for the extremal distances. For
Ptolemy, at apogee the distance between the world center and epicycle center
is 69; at 180°, it is 57. For Ibn al-Šāṭir the corresponding distances are 65 and
55. We cannot give a satisfactory reason for these differences 36 , which result in
different elongations, as we will discuss below.
Chart 2 provides a list of Ibn al-Šāṭir’s various schematic orbs (the “ inner
equators ” or non-physicalized versions) for Mercury, their sizes and their mo-
tions, and a comparison with Copernicus’ values (in both the Commentariolus
and De rev.). For Copernicus, we follow Kennedy and Roberts in designating his
orbs by vectors and norming r1 to 60. Positive values for motions of orbs are in
the sequence of the signs with respect to the apogee or epicyclic apex; negative
values are counter-sequential 37 .
32
Although mathematically equivalent, the equal-circle model (presented by Copernicus in De
revolutionibus in III.4 and by Ṭūsī in his Taḥrīr al-Majisṭī ) is distinct from the 2:1 model
(used in the Commentariolus and in Ṭūsī’s Taḏkira); see also note †† in chart 2 below. The
importance of distinguishing them for understanding the historical relationship between the
various models had already been pointed to by M. di Bono, “ Copernicus, Amico, Fracastoro
and Ṭūsī’s device ”; see also Ragep, “ From Tūn to Toruń ”.
33
As explained by Kennedy and Roberts, this is so that r2 − r3 = e and r2 + r3 = 2e, the
two conditions needed to satisfy the necessary distances at apogee, perigee and quadratures
(“ The Planetary theory of Ibn al-Shāṭir ”, p. 230).
34
r2 = 1; 41 and r3 = 0; 26.
35
r2 = 4; 5 and r3 = 0; 55.
36
To quote Kennedy and Roberts (referring to Venus): “ We are at a loss to explain these new
constants ”. Kennedy and Roberts, “ The Planetary theory of Ibn al-Shāṭir ”, p. 231; their chart
on p. 230 conveniently lists the parameters for r2 , r3 , and r4 for all the planets. One might
speculate, as does Hartner, that Ibn al-Šāṭir is basing himself on new observations, but this
must remain speculation as long as we do not have Ta‘līq al-arṣād. Cf. Hartner, “ Ptolemy,
Azarquiel, Ibn al-Shāṭir, and Copernicus on Mercury ”, p. 24-5; repr. p. 311-12. For a recent
attempt to reconstruct Ibn al-Šāṭir’s observations for Mercury, cf. Penchèvre, “ La Nihāya
al-sūl ”, p. 492-3.
37
Cf. Kennedy and Roberts, “ The Planetary theory of Ibn al-Shāṭir ”, p. 230.
20
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 217
∗
In book I, ch. 7 of Nihāyat al-su’l, the value is given as 0; 59, 8, 9, 51, 46, 57, 32, 3°. This is
the Sun’s tropical mean motion.
†
This is based on the value Copernicus gives for the Sun’s sidereal year, “ 365 days, 6 hours,
and about 1/6 of an hour ”. In his copy of the 1515 Almagest, Copernicus gives the year
as 365; 15, 24, 45, which translates to a daily motion of 0; 59, 8, 11, 16, 12°; see Swerdlow,
“ The Derivation and first draft ”, p. 451-4.
‡
This is sidereal.
§
Although the value is given initially as 1/2 plus 1/3 of a degree, i. e., as 0; 50 parts, the amount
that is used later in the calculations is 0; 55 parts.
¶
This is exactly 1/3 of the deferent; Copernicus gives a slightly different value, 1; 21, 36 [0; 34
using R = 25], but this is rounded. Swerdlow more precisely derives 1; 411/4 and 0; 333/4
[R = 25] from the Uppsala manuscript; see Swerdlow, “ The Derivation and first draft ”,
p. 509.
‖
All the manuscripts have 2; 18, 14, 2°, which is incorrect.
∗∗
Because of the particular way in which Copernicus places his orbs, this is equal to the motion
of Ptolemy’s epicycle (≈ 3; 6°/day) plus the motion of center (≈ 0; 59°/day). Note that for
Ibn al-Šāṭir and for Copernicus in De rev., the orb’s own rotation is the motion of Ptolemy’s
epicycle (≈ 3; 6°/day) minus the motion of center (≈ 0; 59°/day).
††
In the Commentariolus, Copernicus describes a spherical version of the rectilinear Ṭūsī-
couple, which is what Ibn al-Šāṭir uses in the solid-sphere version of his Mercury model
(figure 7); for ease of comparison, we have transformed this for r5 and r6 into the mathemati-
cally equivalent equal-circle version of the Ṭūsī-couple (figure 9). Note that Copernicus states
that the motions of r5 and r6 are completed in a tropical year rather than a sidereal year, an-
other indication that the Commentariolus model was originally geocentric; Swerdlow, “ The
Derivation and first draft ”, p. 503, 505.
In figure 10, we see the complete schematic model of Mercury when α = 35°
(about 35.5 days). Note that the planet P has moved about 145° (2α + κ) from a
fixed reference point A on the epicyclic diameter parallel to the apsidal line 38 ,
about 110° (α + κ) from A0 , the initial position of the epicycle apex, and about
75° (κ) from A1 , the transposed position of the epicycle apex. From Ibn al-Šāṭir’s
parameters, we can calculate the sidereal period to be 87.97 days, the synodic
period to be 115.88 days, the latter the same as Ptolemy’s. Ibn al-Šāṭir differenti-
ates between what he calls the true epicycle, i. e., a reference epicycle whose size
is invariable, and an apparent epicycle, whose size is constantly changing due to
the effect of the Ṭūsī-couple, which brings the planet toward and away from the
epicycle center. (See figure T1 [appendix 2: Translation] for his illustration.)
We will have more to say about the true and apparent epicycles below.
How well does Ibn al-Šāṭir’s model replicate Ptolemy’s results, in particular
for the maximum elongations? Ibn al-Šāṭir’s maximum elongations ∆ can be
obtained from the following formula 39 :
r4 − 2 · r5 · cos(2α)
sin(∆) = [ ]1/2 .
r12 + r22 + r32 + 2 · r1 · (r2 + r3 ) · cos(α) + 2 · r2 · r3 · cos(2α)
At the critical centrum values of 0°, 90°, and 180°, we find that Ibn al-Šāṭir’s
values are somewhat different from those of Ptolemy. Note the differences in
chart 3 40 .
On the other hand, Ibn al-Šāṭir’s value for greatest maximum elongation
(23; 53, 48 at 117; 51°) is remarkably close to Ptolemy’s (23; 53, 20 at 120; 28°).
That Ibn al-Šāṭir’s greatest elongation occurs near 117; 50, whereas Ptolemy’s
is around 120; 30, is due to the equation of center (≈ 2; 40); recall that uniform
motion of center for Ptolemy is about the equant, whereas it is about the Earth for
Ibn al-Šāṭir. From the Earth, the two models would thus predict almost the same
maximum elongation at the same distance from the apogee. It would seem that
Ibn al-Šāṭir attempted to match Ptolemy’s greatest maximum elongation while
being less concerned about the values for 0°, 90°, and 180° (see chart 4). It is not
38
We ignore here the motion of the apsidal line due to the parecliptic.
39
The numerator is the apparent radius of the epicycle (the true radius modified by the cou-
ple). The denominator is the distance of the center of the epicycle from the Earth. This
latter distance formula can also be found in Hartner, “ Ptolemy, Azarquiel, Ibn al-Shāṭir, and
Copernicus on Mercury ”, p. 10; repr. p. 297.
40
These values are different from those reported by Hartner, because he took r3 = 0; 50,
whereas we are using 0;55 based on textual evidence (Hartner, “ Ptolemy, Azarquiel, Ibn
al-Shāṭir, and Copernicus on Mercury ”, p. 23; repr. p. 310); see also note § in chart 2 above.
For our calculations, we used a modern calculator; the differences using Ibn al-Šāṭir’s sine
table would be insignificant.
22
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 219
Centrum Elongation
Ibn al-Šāṭir Ptolemy and De rev.
0 19; 28, 16 19; 03
90 23; 24, 17 23; 15
180 23; 11, 59 23; 15
41
It is worth mentioning here that Copernicus in De revolutionibus was somewhat more suc-
cessful in duplicating Ptolemy’s maximum elongations at 0°, 90°, and 180° as indicated in
our chart 3 (cf. Swerdlow and Neugebauer, Mathematical astronomy in Copernicus’s De rev-
olutionibus, I, 420). Since the Mercury model there is mathematically and astronomically
equivalent to Ibn al-Šāṭir’s model, we must conclude that either Ibn al-Šāṭir was unable to
figure out how to adjust his parameters to achieve equivalence with Ptolemy (which seems
unlikely), or he chose, for some reason, not to do so.
24
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 221
25
222 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
Fig. 11. Transformation of Ibn al-Šāṭir’s Mercury model to the De rev. model.
models; rather, he does not think they are sufficient to explain Copernicus’ var-
ious models nor his transition to a heliocentric cosmos. He insists instead that
Copernicus was also dependent on Regiomontanus’ alternative eccentric models.
Blåsjö’s arguments about “ naturalness ” are generally lacking in historical evi-
dence, but he does point to an illuminating mistake in Swerdlow’s understanding
of the Mercury model that will figure in our own analysis. We deal with Blåsjö’s
other arguments regarding Mercury in appendix 1. As for Swerdlow’s criticisms
of Ragep’s claims in “ Ibn al-Shāṭir and Copernicus ”, which are central to this
paper as well, we take them up in the subsequent discussion.
There is an important caveat to our argument regarding Copernicus’ simple
transformation of Ibn al-Šāṭir’s Mercury model: this only works for De revolu-
tionibus. In the earlier Commentariolus, the Mercury model exhibits a number of
differences with the De rev. model, the most important being that the mean Sun
and the center of Mercury’s orb / orbit are coincident in the earlier work. Since
we believe, like Swerdlow, that Copernicus had Ibn al-Šāṭir’s Mercury model
when writing the Commentariolus, we need to show how one might get to the lat-
ter from the former. We begin with a geocentric transformation of Ibn al-Šāṭir’s
model (figure 12), using a simplified version that dispenses with the Ṭūsī-couple.
(Thus it is similar to, but not exactly the same as, the Venus model.) In order to
show the transformation more clearly, we again make α = 35°, κ ≈ 75°, both
motions starting at A.
The transformation consists of the following steps: 1) transpose the epicycle
so that its center C is now at F; 2) transpose the double epicycle FGC along line
FF′ , which is parallel and equal to CP. Note that O and P are not moved, and they
retain the same relationship as before. However, P is no longer on the epicycle.
Using vectors, we can see that we have made the following transformation,
which has preserved both distance and direction between the Earth and the planet:
−→ −→ −→ − → −−→ −−→ −−→ −→
OF + FG + GC + CP = OC′ + C′ F′ + F′ G′ + G′ P. Using the symbols for the
radii of the orbs from chart 2, we have − →r1 + −
→
r2 + −→
r3 + −→
r4 = −→
r1 + −→
r4 + −
→
r2 + −
→
r3 .
It is then simple to transform this adaptation of Ibn al-Šāṭir’s geocentric model
into the heliocentric model of the Commentariolus (figure 13). Copernicus rec-
ognized the need to add a Ṭūsī-couple to vary the size of the epicycle, which has
now become Mercury’s deferent orb around the Sun. It may not be coincidental
that Copernicus follows our reconstruction, first presenting the model without
the couple (as in figure 12) and then justifying and adding the couple. In the
Commentariolus model, as well as in Ibn al-Šāṭir’s and De rev.’s models, the
purpose of the couple is to vary the size of the epicycle or Mercury’s orbit; we
will have more to say about this below. However, unlike Ibn al-Šāṭir’s model as
well as the De rev. model, the Ṭūsī-couple produces this effect in the Commen-
tariolus by bringing the center of the orb F′ , rather than the planet, away from
27
224 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
28
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 225
42
Ragep, “ Ibn al-Shāṭir and Copernicus ”, p. 408-9.
30
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 227
Fig. 14. The Mercury model in the Commentariolus (adapted from Swerdlow,
“ The Derivation and first draft ”, fig. 39, p. 501) ∗ .
∗
Note that the mean motion α and the starting point of F are different from our figures 12
and 13.
and then rotating it through 360° to find the greatest maximum elongation for
any centrum.
But even if we grant “ mathematical equivalence ” in theory, the fact remains
that Copernicus was unable to derive parameters that would make the Commen-
tariolus model “ work ”. That Copernicus himself would have found using his
model computationally challenging is made clear from the values that it gener-
ates. For example, the maximum equation of center is considerably off from that
of Ptolemy, as also from Ibn al-Šāṭir and the De rev. model, as we see in chart 5.
The maximum elongations tell a similar, though less dramatic, tale (see chart 6).
Part of the problem in the Commentariolus is that Copernicus retains the 3:1
ratio of the deferent to dirigent epicycles from the outer planets and fails to ad-
31
228 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
just it as is done by both Ibn al-Šāṭir and the later Copernicus in De rev. 43 . So
Copernicus here was either not interested or incapable of testing his parameters
(in contrast to what he does in De rev.) 44 . For the equation of center this is par-
ticularly striking, since he should have been able to derive the quantity. For the
maximum elongation, we very much doubt that he or any of his contemporaries
could have derived the value without an extraordinary amount of effort. We are
thus left with a model that is deeply flawed and almost impossible to test.
When Copernicus came to work seriously on what would become De rev-
olutionibus, the inadequacies of his earlier models must have become all too
apparent, which led him to abandon his earlier attempts to exclude eccentrics
and have a single center for each planetary system. Copernicus was still work-
ing on Mercury, perhaps as late as 1539, when Rheticus arrived on the scene 45 .
As Swerdlow has shown, Copernicus had first come up with a model different
from the standard De rev. model. This can be established from the text of his
holograph and its crossed-out parts, i. e., without the corrections in the margin
43
From chart 2, we find that the ratio for Mercury is 4.45 for Ibn al-Šāṭir and 3.49 for De rev.
44
Swerdlow also notes a number of calculation errors (“ The Derivation and first draft ”, p. 509).
45
N. Swerdlow, “ Copernicus’s four models of Mercury ”, in O. Gingerich and J. Dobrzycki
(ed.), Studia Copernicana XIII (Colloquia Copernicana, III): Astronomy of Copernicus and
its background: Proceedings of the joint symposium of the IAU and IUHPS, co-sponsored
by the IAHS, Torun, 1973 (Warsaw, 1975), p. 141-55 at 155 and n. 8. Based on the fact that
the “ standard ” model is described in the Narratio prima, Swerdlow concludes that it was in
place by 1539, but whether this occurred before or after Rheticus’ arrival seems to us an open
question.
32
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 229
on f. 176. This original model, which Swerdlow dubs the “ deviant ” version, is
basically the same as the standard model (figure 11) but has the planet move on
the circumference of a circle rather than its diameter. In other words, Coperni-
cus uses something like the small circles employed by Ptolemy for his latitude
theory in book XIII of the Almagest rather than a Ṭūsī-couple device 46 .
It is not clear why he might have been experimenting with the small circles
(perhaps he thought them simpler than the Ṭūsī-couple?) but in any event this
“ deviant ” model 47 exhibits a mostly “ correct ” transformation of Ibn al-Šāṭir’s
model. Now it is of great historical interest that Copernicus reinstated eccentric-
ities in De revolutionibus. Copernicus himself offers an explanation, at least a
partial one, by citing changes in the eccentricities of Mars and Venus since the
time of Ptolemy that have resulted from the motion of the mean Sun (i. e., the
center of the Earth’s orbit) with respect to the orbit of the center of the epicycle
carrying the planet 48 . Swerdlow and Neugebauer explain Copernicus’ justifica-
tion with careful analysis, but there seems to us to be another factor that may be
at work. Could it be that Copernicus somehow realized that the Commentari-
olus model for the inner planets did not work? Once he tried to do the sort of
derivation of the parameters from Ptolemy’s observations for Venus and Mer-
cury that he does in V.21-22 and V.27, he would have discovered that he could
not obtain suitable elongations using his earlier model. For one thing, as we
have mentioned, it is exceedingly difficult to compute the elongations for the
Commentariolus models since the planets Venus and Mercury are not usually on
their circle around the Sun (i. e., r4 ). It thus seems plausible that once Coper-
nicus started the process of actually deriving parameters from observations, he
would have realized that he needed a new model. Such a model, namely Ibn al-
Šāṭir’s, was already at hand and quite easily transformed into the De rev. model,
which was much more amenable to computation.
46
Swerdlow and Neugebauer, Mathematical astronomy in Copernicus’s De revolutionibus, II,
fig. 73, p. 658.
47
The terminology is Swerdlow’s; see his “ Copernicus’s four models of Mercury ”, p. 142.
48
Swerdlow and Neugebauer, Mathematical astronomy in Copernicus’s De revolutionibus, I,
299-300; see also I, 356 sqq. (for Mars) and I, 384 sqq. (for Venus).
49
N. Swerdlow, “ Copernicus’s derivation of the heliocentric theory ”, p. 34 and passim.
33
230 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
Mercury model is virtually identical to the De rev. model, and Swerdlow has
claimed that Copernicus had Ibn al-Šāṭir’s models when writing the Commen-
tariolus, and in particular the Mercury model 50 , it would seem incumbent on
him to explain why Copernicus was unable or unwilling to make the simple
transformation ca. 1510 that he would make in 1543. To explore Swerdlow’s
reasoning a bit further, we have reconstructed, as best we can, the steps that he
claims Copernicus took that would eventually lead to what he calls the standard
De rev. model:
1) Copernicus first seeks to resolve the problem of irregular motion brought
on by Ptolemy’s equant (“ first anomaly ”) with the solution offered by Ibn al-
Šāṭir’s models 51 ; 2) he then is motivated to explore the “ second anomaly ” (i. e.,
the one related to the planet’s synodic motion) 52 ; 3) this leads him to transform
Ptolemy’s epicyclic models into eccentric ones, based on propositions in Re-
giomontanus’ Epitome of the Almagest 53 ; 4) because, geocentrically, this leads
to an unacceptable penetration of solid orbs, Copernicus is compelled to opt for
a heliocentric system 54 ; 5) Copernicus then incorporates Ibn al-Šāṭir’s devices
into the simple models (i. e., ones that do not deal with the first anomaly) that
he came up with in 3) and 4) 55 ; 6) because of the problem in the transforma-
50
“ Since [the Commentariolus’s Mercury model] is Ibn ash-Šāṭir’s model, this is further evi-
dence, and perhaps the best evidence, that Copernicus was in fact copying without full under-
standing from some other source, and this source would be an as yet unknown transmission to
the west of Ibn ash-Shāṭir’s planetary theory ”. Swerdlow, “ The Derivation and first draft ”,
p. 504.
51
“ [Copernicus’] original concern was the first, not the second, anomaly because it was in the
representation of the first anomaly that Ptolemy’s model violated the uniform and circular
motion permitted to the rotation of a sphere … My own inclination is to suspect … [that] the
identity with the earlier planetary theory [of Ibn al-Šāṭir] of Copernicus’s models for the Moon
and the first anomaly of the planets and the variation of the radius of Mercury’s orbit and the
generation of rectilinear motion by two circular motions seems too remarkable a series of
coincidences to admit the possibility of independent discovery. ” Swerdlow, “ The Derivation
and first draft ”, p. 467, 469 (italics in original; clarifying words in brackets added by current
authors).
52
“ It seems likely that in the course of the intensive study of planetary theory undertaken to
solve the problem of the first anomaly, he carried out an analysis of the second anomaly
leading to his remarkable discovery. ” Swerdlow, “ The Derivation and first draft ”, p. 425. See
also Swerdlow and Neugebauer, Mathematical astronomy in Copernicus’s De revolutionibus,
I, 56 and our comments below.
53
Swerdlow, “ The Derivation and first draft ”, p. 471-8.
54
Swerdlow, “ The Derivation and first draft ”, p. 477.
55
This is nowhere stated as such. We are led to this conclusion since Swerdlow’s entire discus-
sion of the transformation from epicyclic to eccentric models involves orbs in which the first
anomaly does not play a role. See Swerdlow, “ The Derivation and first draft ”, fig. 17-22,
p. 472-7. At some point, these “ eccentric ” models would need to be supplied with devices
34
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 231
tion from geocentric eccentric to heliocentric models, Venus and Mercury have
serious deficiencies that make them similar to but significantly different from
Ibn al-Šāṭir’s models 56 ; 7) by the time of writing De revolutionibus, Coperni-
cus modified the Commentariolus model so that it “ worked ” computationally,
ending up with a correct heliocentric version of Ibn al-Šāṭir’s model 57 .
In essence, Swerdlow is asking us to believe that Copernicus had the “ correct ”
Mercury model all along, at least the one he eventually set forth in De rev., but de-
cided not to use it, instead taking this complicated, not to say convoluted, detour.
According to Swerdlow in his original study of the Commentariolus, Coperni-
cus did not fully understand Ibn al-Šāṭir’s Mercury model 58 . But as Blåsjö has
recently shown, and as we will discuss below, Swerdlow based his assessment
on a misunderstanding of what Copernicus was saying regarding the behavior of
the Mercury model.
Furthermore, Swerdlow’s suggestion that somehow the problems with the
first anomaly spurred Copernicus to explore the second anomaly is doubtful.
Here is what he and Neugebauer say about this alleged problem:
Copernicus probably undertook an investigation of the second anomaly, and of the
eccentric model, because even with the Marāgha solution to the first anomaly, the
uniform motion of the planet on the epicycle must still be measured from the mean
apogee lying on a line directed to the equant (see fig. 5.53 for Venus). Thus, techni-
cally there is still a violation of uniform circular motion, or in physical terms, of the
uniform rotation of the epicyclic sphere 59 .
But this is really a non-problem as Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī pointed out:
the [difficulty for the Moon] that was mentioned as arising on account of the anomaly
in alignment is not present [for Mercury] because the alignment [of its epicycle di-
ameter] is toward the point with respect to which the uniformity of motion occurs 60 .
Even if somehow one thought this was a problem with Ptolemy’s model, it is
35
232 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
certainly not with Ibn al-Šāṭir’s model as one can see by examining figure 7
(Ibn al-Šāṭir’s solid-orb version) and chart 2, where all the orbs are rotating uni-
formly. Would Copernicus not have understood this? This seems unlikely: the
deft way Copernicus handles the transformation of Ibn al-Šāṭir’s Mercury model
in the Commentariolus, as well as his well-advised adoption of the actual model
in De rev., bespeaks of someone quite at home with the astronomical traditions
to which he was heir. This then makes Swerdlow’s claim for Copernicus’ mo-
tivation for investigating the second anomaly, and the move toward eccentric
models, dubious at best.
Let us now turn to some specific points Swerdlow has brought up in favor of
his “ Regiomontanus detour ” 61 . At the base of his entire reconstruction, the
only concrete evidence he has, is the claim that eccentricitas in the Uppsala
notes refers to the radius of the eccentric in the transformation of the epicycles
in Ptolemy’s planetary models. After listing the values for the eccentricitas of
Mars, Jupiter, Saturn, and Mercury, Swerdlow has this to say:
These numbers directly give the proportion of the radius of the epicycle to the radius
of the eccentric where the radius of the eccentric is 10000. Copernicus, however,
calls the number for each planet an eccentricitas. The substitution of an eccentricity
for the epicyclic radius can refer only to the eccentric model for the second anomaly
mentioned briefly by Ptolemy in Almagest XII, 1 (Manitius 2, 268-269); it is this
alternate model that leads directly to the heliocentric theory 62 .
The consistent use of 10000 in the alternative models is what one would ex-
pect if Swerdlow’s reconstruction were correct. But in fact, this is only true for
Mars, Jupiter, and Saturn. For Mercury, the listed eccentricitas value in the Up-
psala notes is 2250 (later changed to 2256) indicating a radius of 6000. It is true
that in the margin one finds 376, but this is not labeled as “ the ” eccentricitas
and in any case is based on a radius of 1000, not 10000. If Copernicus is de-
veloping alternative eccentric models, why would he use different radii for his
norms? Indeed later, when discussing Mercury, Swerdlow recognizes this and
then gives an alternative explanation, saying that “ Copernicus was using sine ta-
bles normed to a radius of 6000 or 60000 … It is possible that Copernicus used
sines normed to 60000 for all the planets, and then divided by 6 to produce the
numbers in U ” 63 . All this is odd and, to us, unconvincing. Why would Coperni-
cus change norms if he is consistently transforming Ptolemy’s epicycle models
61
For a recent summary of Swerdlow’s position, see his “ Copernicus’s derivation of the helio-
centric theory ”. For an alternative to Swerdlow’s reconstruction and a re-evaluation of the
critical Uppsala notes, see Ragep, “ Ibn al-Shāṭir and Copernicus ”, which contains a fuller
exposition of the following.
62
Swerdlow, “ The Derivation and first draft ”, p. 471.
63
Swerdlow, “ The Derivation and first draft ”, p. 505.
36
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 233
to eccentric ones? It is much more plausible to see the numbers listed with the
label eccentricitas simply as part of a series of steps in the heliocentric transfor-
mation of Ibn al-Šāṭir’s models. This is most clearly illustrated with Mercury’s
parameters in the upper part of the Uppsala notes. It would appear that Coper-
nicus, for the eccentricitas, originally wrote 2250, which is Ptolemy’s epicycle
radius normed to 6000 (or 60000 / 10 if we were to accept that the “ original ”
number was 60000). But at some point, Copernicus changed the 0 of 2250 to a
6, which is consistent with the 376 (2256 / 6) in the margin. The explanation for
this is provided by Swerdlow in his derivation of what Copernicus called the di-
versitas diametrj, which is the displacement resulting from the Ṭūsī-couple. As
Swerdlow shows, this displacement, given as 1151 in the Uppsala notes, comes
from a mean epicycle radius of 22560 64 . It would seem that Copernicus origi-
nally took Ptolemy’s radius of 2250 and then changed it so it would be consistent
with the diversitas diametrj of 1151. This slight modification of the eccentrici-
tas, though mathematically insignificant, does, we think, provide a window for
understanding Copernicus’ use of eccentricitas as well as his procedures in the
Uppsala notes. Our suggestion is that eccentricitas simply meant the eccentric-
ity, or off-centeredness from the mean Sun, of either the Earth (for the outer
planets) or the main deferent (r4 ) of the planet itself (for the inner planets) af-
ter the transformation of Ibn al-Šāṭir’s models into their heliocentric versions
in the Commentariolus. For both the outer and inner planets, the values for the
eccentricitas in the upper part of the Uppsala notes are equivalent to the radii of
Ptolemy’s epicycles (except for the slightly revised value for Mercury). We can
see what this looks like for the outer planets in figure 15.
Taking Mars as our example, we find in the Uppsala notes that the Ptolemaic
epicycle of 39.5 (or 3950 with a deferent radius OF of 6000) has been changed
to 6583, normed to 10000. This now, in our reconstruction, represents the ra-
dius of the Earth’s “ orbit ” around the Sun in figure 15. In the instructional note
separating the upper and lower parts of the Uppsala notes, Copernicus writes:
“ proportio orbium celestium ad eccentricitatem 25 partium ” (the proportion
of the celestial orb to an eccentricity of 25 parts). In other words, Coperni-
cus wishes to provide a unified “ solar system ” based on an eccentricitas of 25,
which is the Earth-Sun distance in the unified system, that then allows for a sim-
ple calculation of the “ semidyameter orbis ”, or radius ⊙′ F of the celestial orb
for each planet. For the outer planets, this is straightforward: in the case of Mars,
64
Swerdlow, “ The Derivation and first draft ”, p. 508.
37
234 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
Fig. 15. Transformation of Ibn al-Šāṭir’s models for the outer planets into the
Commentariolus models (primed letters / symbols indicate location after the
transformation).
38
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 235
65
A. Goddu has asserted that “ Ragep claims that the eccentricitas for each planet is the Earth –
mean Sun distance and, hence, 10000 (or 1000 in the case of Mercury) is the eccentricitas
for each planet. ” (“ Birkenmajer’s Copernicus: Historical context, original insights, and con-
tributions to current debates”, Science in context, 31 (2018): 189-222 at 210.) But clearly
Goddu did not understand Ragep’s argument in “ Ibn al-Shāṭir and Copernicus ”, repeated
here, where 6583 is explicitly given as the eccentricitas for Mars. His other comments re-
garding the ultimate origin of Copernicus’ numbers for the eccentricitates in U (the Alfonsine
tables) and the use of the genitive (eccentricitas martis 6583) are not particularly relevant to
the discussion. The latter point ignores the fact that a Latin genitive (as in other languages)
can be used in different ways; thus, it could just as well mean “ the eccentricity of Mars is
6583 ” as “ the eccentricity for Mars is 6583 ”, i. e., in the case of Mars’ planetary model.
66
Some of the following repeats points made in Ragep, “ Ibn al-Shāṭir and Copernicus ”.
67
Swerdlow, “ The Derivation and first draft ”, p. 504.
39
236 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
This misunderstanding must mean that Copernicus did not know the relation of the
model to Mercury’s apparent motion. Thus it could hardly be his own invention for,
if it were, he would certainly have described its fundamental purpose rather than
write the absurd statement that Mercury “ appears ” to move in a larger orbit when
the earth is 90° from the apsidal line. The only alternative, therefore, is that he copied
it without fully understanding what it was really about. Since it is Ibn ash-Shāṭir’s
model, this is further evidence, and perhaps the best evidence, that Copernicus was
in fact copying without full understanding from some other source, and this source
would be an as yet unknown transmission to the west of Ibn ash-Shāṭir’s planetary
theory 68 .
While we concur that this is Ibn al-Šāṭir’s Mercury model, which, as stated
above, leads to unacknowledged problems with Swerdlow’s analysis, we do not
agree that Copernicus did not understand the model. Part of Swerdlow’s argu-
ment is that “ Copernicus apparently does not realize that the model was de-
signed, not to give Mercury a larger orbit (read epicycle) when the earth (read
center of the epicycle) is 90° from the apsidal line, but to produce the greatest
elongations when the earth (center of the epicycle) is ±120° from the aphelion
(apogee) 69 ”. But as Blåsjö has pointed out, there is a plausible way to read what
Copernicus is saying that shows he was aware that the simple double-epicycle
model (see our figure 12) would not work for Mercury without an adjustment,
i. e., the introduction of the Ṭūsī-couple device. Nevertheless, it is curious that
Copernicus only refers to the situation with reference to the apsis and quadratures
and not at ±120° as in the Almagest and also in De revolutionibus. Blåsjö thinks
that it was not necessary for Copernicus to mention the maximum elongations at
the trines “ since his intended readership would of course be very familiar with
Ptolemaic theory and realize at once that this corollary carries over directly in-
sofar as the two theories are equivalent 70 ”. But as we will argue in appendix 1,
it is highly unlikely that Copernicus’ “ intended readership ”, or anyone else for
that matter, would have seen the greatest elongations at the trines as somehow
a “ corollary ” to the effect of the Ṭūsī-couple. Blåsjö also wishes us to believe
that by showing that Swerdlow misunderstood what Copernicus was saying, this
somehow disproves Swerdlow’s conclusion that Copernicus was copying Ibn al-
Šāṭir’s model. Although this is an unwarranted leap on Blåsjö’s part, his analysis
does provide a key to showing an even stronger connection between Ibn al-Šāṭir
and Copernicus.
Indeed, given the overwhelming evidence of the similarities, and in several
cases the virtual identity, of Copernicus’ and Ibn al-Šāṭir’s models, we are led to
68
Swerdlow, “ The Derivation and first draft ”, p. 504.
69
Ibid.
70
Blåsjö, “ A critique of the arguments for Maragha influence on Copernicus ”, p. 193.
40
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 237
conclude that Copernicus knew of his predecessor’s models in some form. But
in which form? Because Copernicus does not use Ibn al-Šāṭir’s parameters, and
in fact makes some ill-advised choices, we think it much more likely that he had
diagrams but not Ibn al-Šāṭir’s text. The case of the variable size of the circum-
ference of Mercury’s orbit is revealing. Looking at the “ schematic ” diagram in
Ibn al-Šāṭir’s Nihāyat al-su’l (figure T1 in the translation, appendix 2), one is
struck by how perfectly it depicts what Copernicus describes. In his diagram,
Ibn al-Šāṭir has shown both the “ apparent epicycle orb ” on which is the planet
and the “ true epicycle orb ”, which is the “ reference ” epicycle orb without the
effect of the Ṭūsī-couple. (See also figure 10 above.) Even though Ibn al-Šāṭir,
as we have seen, was aware of the importance of the nearest distances occurring
at the trines 71 , he did not feel the need to indicate this on his diagram; his pur-
pose was to show the effect of the Ṭūsī-couple on the model, which causes the
epicycle to “ shrink ” at 0° and 180°, and “ expand ” at 90° and 270°. Bearing
this in mind, and with a view to Ibn al-Šāṭir’s diagram, let us quote Copernicus:
But this combination of circles, although adequate to the other planets, is not ad-
equate to Mercury because, when the Earth is in the views of the apsis mentioned
above [i.e, at 0° and 180°], the planet appears to move by traversing a far smaller
circumference, and on the other hand, when the Earth is at quadratures [to the apsis],
[i.e., at 90° and 270°], by traversing a far larger circumference than the proportion
of the circles just given permits. Since, however, no other anomaly in longitude is
seen to arise from this, it seems suitable that it take place on account of some kind of
approach [toward] and withdrawal from the center of the sphere on a straight line 72 .
It would seem that Copernicus was following Ibn al-Šāṭir to a “ + ”.
Ibn al-Šāṭir’s diagram also helps explain another, heretofore puzzling aspect
of the Uppsala notes 73 . In the upper part of the Uppsala notes for Mercury,
Copernicus writes 6 or 600 for r1 + r2 . However, the “ ecce ” of 2256 (or 376)
in conjunction with the 115.1 (or 19) for the diversitas diametrj, the displace-
ment resulting from the Ṭūsī couple, implies r1 + r2 = 576 74 . But Copernicus
uses 540 to derive the values in the lower part of U, i. e., r1 = 1; 41 1/4 and
r2 = 0; 33 3/4. Regarding this, Swerdlow says: “ I do not know why Copernicus
had these problems 75 ”. However, looking again at fig. T1, we can conjecture
71
See the above discussion of Ibn al-Šāṭir’s values for the maximum elongations, which are
remarkably close to Ptolemy’s near 120°.
72
Swerdlow, “ The Derivation and first draft ”, p. 503 (Swerdlow’s translation; italics are from
the current authors).
73
The following is taken from Ragep, “ Ibn al-Shāṭir and Copernicus ”.
74
Swerdlow, “ The Derivation and first draft ”, p. 507, where he derives 576(0). As he notes
(p. 508-9), Copernicus seems to have had considerable problems in converting from the upper
value in U for r1 + r2 to the values for the two epicycles in the lower part.
75
Swerdlow, “ The Derivation and first draft ”, p. 509.
41
238 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
that Copernicus reasoned (incorrectly) as follows: the largest size of the epicy-
cle (“ apparent epicycle orb ”) is 2256 + 115.1 = 2371.1 at 90°. Its smallest
size (“ apparent epicycle orb ”) is 2256 − 115.1 = 2140.9 at 0°. But rather
than taking the radius of the “ true epicycle orb ”, i. e., 2256 (or 376), he adopted
the “ apparent epicycle orb ” at α = 0° as his reference epicycle, since it is
the starting point. If we take the maximum equation to occur at 90°, then the
Ptolemaic eccentricity of 6 (or 600) should be measured there with the epicy-
cle being 2371.1. But at α = 0°, the ratio of the two “ apparent ” epicycles is
2140.9/2371.1 ≈ 0.9. So the sum of the eccentricities (r1 + r2 ) should be pro-
portionally lowered, at least according to this reasoning, i. e., 0.9×600 = 540 76 .
Along with Copernicus’ description of a varying planetary “ circumference ”
(epicycle in Ibn al-Šāṭir’s model) and the explanation for 540 arising from the
diagram, we would argue that Copernicus had at his disposal something like
fig. A1 / T1. This is the sense in which we can say that Copernicus had Ibn al-
Šāṭir’s Mercury model when composing the Commentariolus and later De rev.
7. CONCLUSION
The remarkable similarity between Ibn al-Šāṭir’s Mercury model and that in
De rev. should long ago have settled the question of whether Copernicus was
dependent on his Islamic predecessor. Although Swerdlow has championed a
connection between Islamic astronomy and Copernicus, his interjection of a Re-
giomontanus detour has, we believe, considerably muddied the waters and inhib-
ited the simple conclusion that Copernicus built his system almost exclusively on
the foundation of Ibn al-Šāṭir’s models. Blåsjö’s arguments for Copernicus’ inde-
pendence from Islamic influence, based on the elusive concept of “ naturalness ”,
would have very different models be classified as equivalent (see appendix 1).
As argued elsewhere, Ibn al-Šāṭir’s models are fundamentally different not only
from those of Ptolemy but also from his “ Marāgha ” predecessors 77 . Because of
the “ heliocentric bias ” brought about by a rejection of eccentrics and by making
the Earth the actual center of motion, Ibn al-Šāṭir’s models considerably facili-
tated Copernicus’ transition from an Earth-centered to a Sun-centered cosmol-
ogy. There was a wide array of non-Ptolemaic Mercury models that were devel-
oped after Naṣīr al-Dīn al-Ṭūsī admitted that this complex model had defeated
him 78 : Quṭb al-Dīn al-Šīrāzī claims to have invented nine different Mercury
76
This also works, of course, if one uses 376 and 19 instead of 2256 and 115.1.
77
Ragep, “ Ibn al-Shāṭir and Copernicus ”, p. 396-7, 408.
78
Ragep, Ṭūsī’s Memoir on astronomy, I, 208.
42
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 239
APPENDIX 1
THE ISSUE OF EQUIVALENCE AND “ NATURAL ” SOLUTIONS
79
Quṭb al-Dīn al-Šīrāzī, Fa‘alta fa-lā talum, Majlis-i šūrā ms. 3944, f. 7b. For an analysis
of some of these models, see Amir-Mohammad Gamini, “ Quṭb al-Dīn al-Shīrāzī and the
development of non-Ptolemaic planetary modeling in the 13th century ”, Arabic sciences and
philosophy, 27/2 (2017): 165-203.
80
G. Saliba, “ A sixteenth-century Arabic critique of Ptolemaic astronomy: The work of Shams
al-Dīn al-Khafrī ”, Journal for the history of astronomy, 25/1 (1994): 15-38.
81
B. R. Goldstein (ed. and transl.), Al-Biṭrūjī: On the principles of astronomy, 2 vol. (New
Haven, CT, 1971), I, 140-2, II, 375-85.
82
Malpangotto, “ L’univers auquel s’est confronté Copernic ”.
83
Blåsjö, “ A critique of the arguments for Maragha influence on Copernicus ”, p. 183.
84
On this point, see Saliba, “ A sixteenth-century Arabic critique of Ptolemaic astronomy ”.
43
240 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
Copernicus himself over his lifetime came up with different models for Mercury
(four according to Swerdlow); which of these is supposed to count as “ natural ”?
Part of the problem with Blåsjö’s approach is that he is far too willing to dis-
miss differences between models as irrelevant, especially physical differences,
as long as there is what he takes to be mathematical equivalence. But Blåsjö’s
reductionism leads to a number of untoward conclusions, not least because his
notion of mathematical equivalence is itself problematic. To explore this a bit
further, let us turn to his claims regarding the nearest distance issue for Mer-
cury. As we have seen, Swerdlow takes Copernicus’ silence on the matter in the
Commentariolus to mean that he did not fully understand his own model. In re-
sponse, Blåsjö uses his notion of “ equivalence ” to assert that “ There is no need
for Copernicus to mention this since his intended readership would of course be
very familiar with Ptolemaic theory and realize at once that this corollary car-
ries over directly insofar as the two theories [that of Ptolemy and Copernicus] are
equivalent 85 ”. Setting aside the dubious notion of an “ intended readership ” in
1510 that would be experts on one of the most difficult problems of Ptolemaic
astronomy, it is clear from our above discussion of maximum elongation and
the equation of center that it is simply wrong to claim that the Commentariolus
model is equivalent to those of Ptolemy, Ibn al-Šāṭir, and De rev., if one means
by “ equivalent ” that they can produce equivalent results. One might be able
to somehow adjust the parameters in the Commentariolus to reach results that
would be closer to those of the other models, but Copernicus clearly did not do
this. Nor is it at all likely that he tested the Commentariolus model to see if it
was equivalent. The fact that the value for the equation of center is so far off is
a clear indication of this (chart 5 above).
In short, the fact that the Mercury model in the Commentariolus was not
only impractical but also exceedingly difficult to test undermines Blåsjö’s claim
that finding the maximum elongations at 0, ±90, and 180° “ eliminates the need
for Copernicus to address the issue ” of maximal elongation at ±120°, since
somehow this latter is a corollary of the former. Furthermore, this requires us to
believe that Copernicus understood this property of Ptolemy’s model, something
that is certainly not self-evident inasmuch as there is some doubt that Copernicus
even had a copy of the Almagest when he wrote the Commentariolus 86 .
Let us turn to the question of whether Blåsjö might nevertheless be correct
in asserting that the maximal elongations at ±120° are somehow “ a corollary ”
that are only derived after the model has been determined by observations for
the 0°, ±90°, 180° cases that Ptolemy brings forth. Mathematically speaking,
85
Blåsjö, “ A critique of the arguments for Maragha influence on Copernicus ”, p. 193.
86
Swerdlow, “ The Derivation and first draft ”, p. 426.
44
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 241
there is some truth to this: since the shape of the curve described by C in figure 6
above is an oval, rather close to an ellipse 87 , it would naturally follow that once
one has the major and minor axes the other positions fall into place. But this
bit of anachronistic reasoning has little bearing on the way in which Ptolemy
most likely proceeded; for even after fixing his parameters using observations
at 0°, ±90°, 180°, he still had to confirm that the model actually predicted the
observations for ±120°. That it does is hardly a “ corollary ”; indeed, Swerdlow
has convincingly argued that it was neither mathematical necessity nor observa-
tional precision that results in the model being in accord with the observations
at ±120°. Rather, the model itself most likely was constructed to account for
observations that seemed to show (erroneously as it turned out) that elongations
at ±120° were greater than those at 180°. Swerdlow is then led to conclude “ that
some, perhaps most [of the observations], were [then altered] ” to take into ac-
count the theoretical model with its two perigees 88 . It is unlikely that anyone
before Swerdlow (other than Ptolemy himself) understood this, at least not in
the analytical detail that Swerdlow brings to the task. So the original motivation
for Ptolemy’s model, and alleged curve-fitting, does not in itself count against
Blåsjö’s speculation about why Copernicus does not feel the need to explain that
his model in the Commentariolus accounts for Ptolemy’s reported elongations
at the trines. It is at least conceivable that he had analyzed the model in the
Almagest and understood that fixing the parameters for 0°, ±90°, 180° would
achieve his desired result. But this is doubtful for several reasons. For one,
almost everyone before Copernicus who had any understanding of the model
did remark on the two perigees and understood that this was fundamental to the
model 89 . That Copernicus does not do so is thus odd. Furthermore, for us to
87
W. Hartner, “ The Mercury horoscope of Marcantonio Michel of Venice: A study in the his-
tory of Renaissance astrology and astronomy ”, Vistas in astronomy, 1 (1955): 84-138 at
109-22, reprinted in W. Hartner, Oriens-Occidens, I, 440-95 at 465-78.
88
Swerdlow, “ Ptolemy’s theory of the inferior planets ”, p. 51-4 (quotation is on p. 54). This
brief summary can hardly do justice to Swerdlow’s incisive and compelling explanation of
Ptolemy’s Mercury model and its origins. Although hardly conclusive, it is noteworthy that
Ptolemy presents the observations establishing the need for two perigees (IX.8) before de-
riving the distances between the centers and the radius of the small circle (IX.9). Once he
has the parameters, he then “ proves ” that the model will produce the needed two perigees, a
result that Swerdlow remarks may seem like “ luck ” but is much more likely a consequence
of “ adjusting ” the observations and model in advance [G. J. Toomer (transl.), Ptolemy’s Al-
magest (London, 1984), p. 453-60].
89
This is quite explicit, for example, in Ṭūsī’s Taḏkira (Ragep, Ṭūsī’s Memoir on astronomy,
I, 168-9 and 176-7 [fig. T9]), a work well known to Ibn al-Šāṭir. Because Ibn al-Šāṭir is so
familiar with his predecessors (including Ṭūsī), he evidently does not feel the need to discuss
the two perigees in his chapter on Mercury (see appendices 2-3); however, he does indicate
that he is aware of Ptolemy’s Mercury model having the perigees at points other than 180°
45
242 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
accept that Copernicus could consider the perigees at ±120° a corollary, one
would need to show that he had sufficient understanding of Ptolemy’s model so
that his own could replicate its parameters and output. But as we have seen,
this is far from the case, at least at the time of the composition of the Com-
mentariolus. Thus to believe Blåsjö’s main contention, one needs to assume
that Copernicus when writing the Commentariolus: a) would not mention the
most prominent aspect of Mercury’s model because this was a “ corollary ” to
Ptolemy’s “ equivalent ” model; and also assume, b) that Copernicus would put
forth a model that did not produce equivalent results. Needless to say, we find
this untenable. On the other hand, by the time he composed De revolutionibus,
Copernicus not only does not ignore the perigees at ±120°, he in fact adjusts the
parameters of the model to account for them (something obviously not done in
the Commentariolus) and achieves a result fairly close to Ptolemy’s 90 . But this
was done many years later and has no bearing on Blåsjö’s contention, which is
focused on the earlier Commentariolus.
APPENDIX 2 (TRANSLATION)
IBN AL-ŠĀṬIR’S NIHĀYAT AL-SU’L, BOOK I, CHAPTER 21
in his introductory remarks in Nihāyat al-su’l, which deal with difficulties of the Ptolemaic
models (Oxford, Bodleian, Marsh ms. 139, f. 3b and Penchèvre, “ La Nihāya al-sūl ”, p. 40-1).
90
See above and Swerdlow and Neugebauer, Mathematical astronomy in Copernicus’s De rev-
olutionibus, I, 422-4.
91
Both opinions, as it turns out, are due to Ptolemy: the variable inclination of the inclined orb
is presented in the Almagest; a fixed inclination of 1/6 degree is in the Planetary hypotheses.
See Neugebauer, A history of ancient mathematical astronomy, II, 909.
92
Later the value that is used is 55 minutes.
46
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 243
the dirigent. We conceive of a fifth orb whose center is on the dirigent equator,
its radius being 22 parts, 46 minutes of those parts; it is called the epicycle orb.
We conceive of a sixth orb whose center is on the epicycle equator, its radius be-
ing 33 minutes; it is called the enclosing [orb] 93 . We conceive of a seventh orb
whose center is on [the equator of] the enclosing [orb], its radius being equal to
the radius of the enclosing [orb], namely 33 minutes; it is called the maintaining
[orb] and Mercury is embedded on the equator of this orb.
As for the motions: the parecliptic moves on the two ecliptic poles sequen-
tially, one degree every sixty years, this being the same as the motion of the
apogees 94 . The inclined moves sequentially equal to Mercury’s motion of cen-
ter, which is equal to the Sun’s [motion] of center. It is in a nychthemeron
0; 59, 8, 10. As for the deferent, it moves counter-sequentially in its uppermost
part, this also being equal to Mercury’s motion of center 95 . As for the epicycle
orb, it moves sequentially in its uppermost part in the amount of the excess of
Mercury’s proper motion over its motion of center, it being in a nychthemeron
2; 18, 14, 2 96 ; it is a simple motion.
As for Mercury’s proper motion, it is a simple motion that is compound be-
cause it is in the amount of the motion of this epicycle, which is 2; 18, 14, 2
plus the motion of Mercury’s center, which is 0; 59, 8, 10. This is [simple?]
because the two motions are in the same direction, so the separation of the
planet from the apex is in the amount of the sum of the two motions, namely
3; 6, 24, 10, 1, 38, 37, 28, 42, which is the compounded proper motion of Mer-
cury, and it is uniform with respect to the epicycle center.
What will clarify this further is that when the inclined moves a quarter revo-
lution, and the deferent moves a quarter revolution, and the dirigent moves a half
revolution, the apex, which is the starting point of its proper motion, will shift
a quarter revolution sequentially. However, by observation it is found to shift
sequentially equal to the proper motion of Mercury, namely 3; 6, 24, 10. Thus
the motion of the epicycle about its center sequentially is in the amount of the
excess of this proper [motion] over the motion of center, since they are both in
the same direction. This has thus been clarified 97 .
93
MS L adds “ and the containing [shāmil] ”. This term is used later in this chapter for the
enclosing orb.
94
Note that Ibn al-Šāṭir differentiates the motion of the apogees from the precessional motion.
See note 31.
95
The following is implied from what follows but is missing in all the manuscripts: <The diri-
gent moves sequentially in its uppermost part, this being equal to twice Mercury’s motion of
center.>
96
3; 6, 24, 10, 1, 38, 37, 28, 42° − 0; 59, 8, 10° = 2; 7, 16, 0°, not 2; 18, 14, 2°. We do not
know the source of this error, but it is attested in all the manuscripts. Note that it is repeated
in the following paragraph.
97
For further clarification, see above, figure 9 and the accompanying explanation.
47
244 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
As for the enclosing [orb], it moves sequentially in its uppermost part equal
to twice Mercury’s motion of center, which is daily 1; 58, 16, 20. As for the
maintaining [orb], it moves counter-sequentially in its uppermost part 4 times
Mercury’s motion of center, which is daily 3; 56, 32, 39.
So Mercury remains on the line extending from the epicycle center to the
center of the enclosing [orb], approaching and moving away from the epicycle
center, it being on the line and not departing from it. When the epicycle center
is at the apogee or perigee, Mercury will be at its nearest distance to its epicycle
center; this nearest [distance] is called the epicycle’s apparent radius, and it is
21 1/3 parts 98 . And when the center is three signs [away], Mercury will be at
its farthest distance from the center of the epicycle, namely 23°52′ 99 . Thus the
farthest distance of Mercury from the center of the world is 86 2/3 100 and its
nearest [distance] 33 1/3 101 ; however, Mercury does not come near the nearest
distance of its solid orbs, according to what we have explained before in another
venue 102 .
As for the sizes of the solid orbs: the radius of the deferent sphere is 28; 52 103 ;
the radius of the dirigent sphere is 24; 47 104 ; the radius of the epicycle sphere is
23; 52 105 ; the radius of the enclosing sphere is 1; 6; and the radius of the main-
taining sphere is 0; 33. All are with parts whereby the radius of the parecliptic
is 60 parts. So the farthest distance of the parecliptic is 88 [parts] and 52 min-
utes 106 . Above that is the thickness of the parecliptic; let us assume it to be fully
complete at 89; 30. And the nearest [distance] of its orbs is 31; 8 107 but it is less
than that due to the conjunction of the orb, so we assume it to be 31; 0. 108 And
God is all-knowing.
98
This should be 212/3: 22; 46 − 1; 6 = 21; 40p .
99
22; 46 + 1; 6 = 23; 52p .
100
60 + 4; 5 + 0; 55 + 21; 40 = 86; 40p .
101
60 − (4; 5 + 0; 55 + 21; 40) = 33; 20p .
102
With reference to figure 6, one can see that the planet never reaches the “ nearest distance ”
of the solid orbs, which is the point of tangency between the deferent and the concave surface
of the inclined orb. “ Another venue / place ” probably refers to another work.
103
0; 33 + 0; 33 + 22; 46 + 0; 55 + 4; 05 = 28; 52.
104
0; 33 + 0; 33 + 22; 46 + 0; 55 = 24; 47.
105
0; 33 + 0; 33 + 22; 46 = 23; 52.
106
60 + 28; 52 = 88; 52.
107
60 − 28; 52 = 31; 8.
108
This notion of conjunction [ittiṣāl] seems to be peculiar to Ibn al-Šāṭir. The idea is that the
orb on which is the nearest distance (in this case the inclined) needs extra thickness. Thus the
“ nearest distance ” will be less than what has been calculated thus far. He also applies this
for the other planets, explaining it first for Saturn at the end of chapter 12, where he calls it
iḫlāṭ rather than ittiṣāl. There is also a scholium [tanbīh] at the end of chapter 19 on Venus
that explains how to transform the schematic circles into solid orbs that gives instructions for
adding the ittiṣāl.
48
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 245
[Fig. T1.] This is the illustration of the orbs of Mercury according to which the
centers of the complete spheres are as pictured in a plane for the apogee, the
perigee and the mean distances.
49
246 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
[Fig. T2.] This is the illustration of Mercury’s solid orbs, which are complete
spheres, as pictured in a plane for the apogee, the perigee and the mean
distances.
50
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 247
ب
B ( ): Oxford, Bodleian, Marsh ms. 290 [f. 29a, line 7 – f. 30a, line 3]
ح
H ( ): Oxford, Bodleian, Huntington ms. 547 [f. 40b, line 8 – f. 41b, line 4]
د
D ( ): Oxford, Bodleian, Marsh ms. 501 [f. 30b, line 4 – f. 31b, line 1]
س
S ( ): Tehran, Sipahsalar ms. 598 [page 38, line 7 – page 40, line 4]; copy
date: 935/1528
ف
F ( ): Jerusalem, Khālidiyya ms. 992 [f. 26b, line 5 – f. 27b, line 12]
ق
Q ( ): Istanbul, Süleymaniye, Kadızade Mehmed Ef. ms. 339 [f. 30b, line
16 – f. 33a, line 7]; copy date: 751/1350
گ
G ( ): Mashhad, Guharshad ms. 1409 [f. 49b, line 7 – f. 51b, line 5]; copy
date: 1275/1858
ل
L ( ): Leiden, Leiden University ms. Or 194 [f. 46b, line 12 – f. 48b, line 1]
م
M ( ): Oxford, Bodleian, Marsh ms. 139 [f. 28a, line 3 – f. 29a, line 1]; copy
date: 768/1366
ی
Y ( ): Balıkesir, Balıkesir İl Halk Kütüphanesi, Dursunbey ms. 54 [page 40,
line 10 – page 42, line 4]; copy date: 1075/1664
An analysis of these copies has revealed that Ibn al-Šāṭir originally wrote the
first part of Nihāyat al-su’l (“ On the configuration of the heavens ”) without a
clear intention to add other parts. However, at the end of ms. F, Q, and M, Ibn
al-Šāṭir indicates that he will add a second part that would include planetary
“ equations ” (ta‘dīlāt). This part seems never to have been written and might
have been superseded by his Zīj. It would seem that subsequently he decided to
add a different part 2, this one dealing with the configuration of the Earth (hay’at
al-arḍ). Most of our manuscript witnesses contain this part 2. That being the
case, Ibn al-Šāṭir, or a copyist, then changed the explicit that we find in ms. F, Q,
and M, so that it now reads in our other manuscript witnesses that the second part
is on the configuration of the Earth and a third part would be on “ equations ”.
But like the original promise of a second part on equations, this third one was,
as far as we can tell, also never written.
None of the manuscripts are free of errors, and there are real problems (as
mentioned in the notes to the translation) with several of the parameters. It would
109
One more copy of the Nihāya is Cairo, Dār al-kutub, Taymūr Riyāḍa, ms. 154, which is
incomplete and does not include the chapter on Mercury. (See: David A. King, Fihris al-
maḫṭūṭāt al-‘ilmiyya al-maḥfūẓa bi-dār al-kutub al-miṣriyya, vol. 2 [Cairo, 1986], p. 35.)
51
248 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
seem, based on our experience with this chapter, that the textual tradition of
Nihāyat al-su’l became corrupt at a fairly early stage. Ms. B, H, and M are
arguably the best witnesses; ms. Q, which one might have expected to be reliable
based on its date and provenance, turned out to be corrupt in a number of places.
Of the Iranian manuscripts, ms. G was copied from ms. S, which itself is not
particularly useful.
Apparatus conventions
م، ل، ق، نتو ّهم[ ح٣ . هيئة[ –ف١ . د، ح، ب:٢١ الباب الحادي والعشرون[ الباب١
. ف: گ = تتوهم، س: د )متغ ّير من » فيتوهم «( = فيتوهم: ی = فنتوهم، ب:= يتوهم
ی = د )متغ ّير من، گ، س، ب: م = ويتوهم، ل، ق، ونتو ّهم[ ح٣ . و ُيس ّمى الممثّل[ –ل٣
نصف وربع٤ .(« مائل[ )فوق السطر في ح مع رمز » صح٤ . ف:» ويتوهم «( = وتتوهم
. د: انه+ [قولٍ ٥ .( عند ا��ٔوج إلى جهة الجنوب[ )في هامش ق٥–٤ . د:درجة[ مه دقيقة
د: ی = ٮٮ دقيٯه، ح: سدس جزء[ سدس جزؤ٥ .( درجه )مشطوب في م+ [ سدس٥
. ل: جزء+ = (« » سدس « في الهامش مع رمز » خ+)
52
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 249
صح .وسطح المائل يقاطع سطح الممثّل على نقطتين متقابلتين ،تس ّمی وهو ا��ٔ ّ
متقابلتين ،تس ّمی
المائل نقطتينعلى منطقة على مركزه فلكاًل ثالثاً
سطحمالممثّ المائلالذنب.
يقاطع ونتو ّه وسطحخری
صحرأ.س وا��ٔ اوهو ا��ٔ
ٕحداهما ّال
المائل
ون نصفعلىقطرمنطقة
المائل ستّ ثالثاًبهامركزهفلكاًالتيالذنب.دقائقونتو ّهبا�م�ٔجزاء
خریوخمس قطرهأ أسربعةوا�أ�ٔجزاء
ٕحداهما الر
اونصف
المائل ستّون
ونصف منطقة قطر
الحامل على نصف التي بها دقائقاً ربا��ٔابعاًجزاءمركزه
وخمسم فلك قطره ّم أیربعة أجز
الحاملاء .ونتو ّه ونصف و ُيس
جزءاً،
ونصف
مركزه على الحامل
منطقةخامساًعلى فلكاً ونتو ّهويمسمفلكیاً رابعاً
المدير.مركزهونتو ّهم نصف ّم وثیُلثالحامل. قطرهاً ،و ُيس
جزء
درجة]![ّ ُ ، ٥
مركزه على
تلك ربعونخامساً
دقيقة من فلكاً
وست وأ المدير.
جزءاً ونتو ّه ّم وعشرون اثنانس ّمی
درجة]![ ،و ُي
ونصف قطره المديروثُلث منطقةنصف قطره ٥
تلك
منطقةمنالتدوير
علىدقيقة وست وأ
مركزهربعون وعشرونفلكاًجزءاًسادساً ّ اثنان ونتو ّهم فلك قطره
التدوير. المدير ّمىونصف منطقةاء ،و ُيس
ا��ٔجز
التدوير المحيطاً .ونتو
مركزه ّهمعلىفلكاًمنطقة
سابعاً مركزه فلكاً سادس دقيقة،ونتوو ّهُيمس ّمىالتدوير.
ث���فلكوث��ثون قطرهس ّمى ا��ٔجز
ونصفاء ،و ُي
سابعاًدقيقة،
مركزه ث���فلكاًوث��ثون قطر المحيط
المحي� .وهوونتو ّهم نصفس ّمى دقيقة ،و ُي
وث��ثون مثل
ونصف قطره المحي� ث��� ونصف قطره على
الفلك.وهو ث��� وث��ثون دقيقة، المحي� قطرهذا منطقة نصف مركوزمثلعلى وعطاردقطره
الحافظونصف على ّمىالمحي� و ُيس ١٠
و ُيس ّمى الحافظ وعطارد مركوز على منطقة هذا الفلك. ١٠
١سطح[ لسطح :س ،گ ١ .الممثّل[ )فوق السطر في ل( ١ .متقابلتين[ متقابلين :ل.
ل. متقابلتين[= متقابلين:
احدهما :ل، ل(.ف ١،ق ،گ السطر د،في س، )فوقب ،ح، الممثّل[
ٕحداهما[ گ.ل ٢ ١.ا س ،ف، لسطح :ب،
ی[ يسمی: سطح[
١١تس ّم
احدهما :ل،
ويتوهم: ق ،م = گ= ق،(«، س»،ف،
ويتوهم د ،من ب،د ح،
)متغ ّير ٕحداهما[ ح،
ب ٢ .ا ٢ونتو ّهم[ ا��خر :ل.
ب ،ف، يسمی:
خری[ و ی.ی[ ٢وا��ٔ
١م،تس ّم
ويتوهم:
گ( ٣ .أربعة ق ،م = «( ،في ويتوهم
)بياض في »س(، )محجوب من
ح ،د )متغ ّير ب٢ .ل.ونتوّ ٢هم[
مركزه[ ا��خر:ٮٮوهم:
خری[ وی =
ف ،گ، ب،ی.س ٢ ،وا��ٔ م،
گ(.س ٣،أگ.
ربعة الفلك: )بياض في
ح( = + )مشطوبفيفيس(، قطر):محجوب قطر[+ ٢مركزه[ ٮٮوهم ٣ :ل.دقائق[ید =ه :د.
ف ،گ، وخمس ب،اء س، أجز
س،س ّمگ.
ی[ الفلكُ ٤ :ي
ستون :ل. ح( == + فيا :د)مشطوبجزوقطر:جزءاً[ ٦٠ الميل :ق.قطر[+٤–٣ستّون
٣ دقائق[ف د=ه :د.
الممثل: وخمس أ٣جزاء
المائل[
ی[
«(،ل.قُ ٤ ،يل،س ّمم = ستون: جزءاًد[ ٦٠
)متغ ّيرجزومنا» :د =
ويتوهم ونتو ّهستّم[ون ح،
٣المائل[ الممثل :ف = الميل :ق٤–٣ ٤ .
+الفلك :س ،گ = تسمی :م.
«(،ی[ق+،ل ،م =
الفلك: ويتوهمو ُيس ّم
دقيقه »:د٥ .درجة[)متغن ّير من نصف ّه وثُم[لثح ،د
تسمی:ی.م ٥.ونتو
٤
ف ،گ، الفلك:ب،س،س،گ = +ويتوهم:
گ،ی[ی =+الفلك:
تتوهم: د .س،و ُيس ّم
٥
دقيقه:ب،درجة[= نويتوهم: نصف وثُ
ويتوهملث«( ،م ی.ر من »
٥
گ)،متغيّس،م[ف،ح ،د
ب ،ونتو ّهگ٥ . ويتوهم:
س،
تتوهم:
وست= وأربعون گ ،ی ّ س ،جزءاً اثنان ب،
وعشرون ی .ويتوهم:
٦ «(،ا :م =
ويتوهمجزو
ل .من »جزءاً[
٦ وىىوهم):متغيّر
وىتوهم:ونتو ّهقم[= ح ،د
٥ س= ،گ. ف
ربعون
م[ وست وأ
ونتو ّه ٧ جزءاً مّ . وتسمی:وعشرون
اثنان ّمى[ ٦
گ .و ُيس
٧ س،ا :ی. وىىوهم:زاء[ل +.جزءاً[
المذكورة :جزو ٦
وىتوهم:مو:ق د =.ا��ٔج
٧ ف=
دقيقة[ كٮ
م[ ف =م .ونتو
وىتوهمّ :ه ق ٧ وتسمی:
گ.گ ،و ُيیس ّم=ى[وتتوهم:
٧
س،س، المذكورة:ب،
«(،اء[م =+ويتوهم: ويتوهم�ٔجز
من »د .ا�
٧ كٮر مو: دقيقة[ )متغيّ
ح ،د
وىتوهم :ق
ی. ف،فق == ثلثه: وتتوهم:
ثلث =:ح، گ ،ی ب ،س،ث���[ ٨ ويتوهم:گ.فلك :س، «( ،م = )متغيّرل.من » ويتوهم
منطقة[ + ٧ =ح ،د
وىىوهم:
ی.
)مشطوب(. درجة :قق = ثلثه: ثلث+ =:ح ،ف، ث���[ یف ،ق ،ل، ٨ وثلثون:س،ح،گ. منطقة[م =+فلك: ل .س ،گ،
٧
وىىوهم :ب،=٨وث��ثون[
)مشطوب(.
الشامل المحيطق[ +و السطر(٨ +.درجة:
فوق ی = ق ،ل، ف،ق « رمز »)يوجد ح، لحـ م =:٠دوثلثون: دقيقة[گ،
ب ،س، وث��ثون[وث��ثون
٨ث���
الشامل
ق، ويتوهم +و«(، المحيط[ السطر(.
)متغ ّير ٨من » رمز » ٨قونتو« ّهم[فوقح ،د )يوجد ی.دقيقة[ معلحـرمز »:٠دنخـ «(،وث��ثونالهامش
ث���ل )في أ٨يضا:
«( ،ق،
مثل[ ق٩ . من »ف،ويتوهم على[د )+متغيّر
منطقة: م[ ح، ونتو ّه ٩
وتتوهم٨ :ف.«( ،ی. گ،نخـی = ب ،معس،رمز »الهامش يضا= :ل )في
ويتوهم: أل ،م
وثلثون :مثل[
ح، ويتوهم :ب ،س ،گ ،ی = وتتوهم :ف ٩ ٩.على[ +منطقة :ف ،ق٩ .
ی ٩ .ث���[ ثلث :ح ،ف ،ق ،م ،ی .وث��ثون[ ب ،س ،گ = ميل:م = ل،
وث��ثون[د .ب ،س ،گ = وثلثون :ح، ی٩ ٠.دقيقه: دقيقة[م ،لحـ
وث��ثون ق،
ث���ح ،ف، ثلث: ميل :ق،ی.ل ٩،م،ث���[
ی٩ . ف،
ف ،ق ،ل ،م ،ی .ث��� وث��ثون دقيقة[ لحـ ٠دقيقه :د. ٩
53
250 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
وأ ّما الحركات ف ٕا ّن الممثّل يتح ّرك على قطبي البروج إلى التوالي في ك ّل ستّين
سنة درجة وذلك مثل حركة ا��ٔوجات .وأ ّما المائل ف ٕانّه يتح ّرك إلى التوالي مثل
حركة مركز عطارد وهو مثل مركز الشمس وهو في اليوم بليلته ٠نط ح ى.
وأ ّما الحامل ف ٕانّه يتح ّرك في أع��ه إلى خ��ف التوالي مثل حركة مركز عطارد
٥ أيضاً .وأما فلك التدوير ف ٕانّه يتح ّرك في أع��ه إلى التوالي بقدر فضل حركة
خاصة عطارد على حركة مركزه وهو في اليوم بليلته ٠ب يح يد ب]![ وهو ّ
حركة بسيطة.
وأما حركة خاصة عطارد ف ٕانّها بسيطة مركّبة ��ٔنّها بقدر حركة هذا التدوير
التي هي ٠ب يح يد ب]![ مع حركة مركز عطارد التي هي ٠نط ح ى،
١٠ وذلك لكون الحركتين إلى جهة واحدة ،فيحصل مفارقة الكوكب للذروة بقدر
مجموع الحركتين وهي ٠جـ و كد ى ا لح لز كح مب ،وهي حركة خاصة
عطارد المركّبة وهي مستوية عند مركز التدوير.
١قطبي[ +فلك :س ،گ ١ .ستّين[ :٦٠د ٢ .سنة[ –ل ٢ .درجة[ +واحدة :س،
گ ٣ .وهو[ فهو :ف ،ق ٣ .وهو في اليوم بليلته ٠نط ح ى[ +مط نٮ )فوق السطر في
د( = وهو ٠نط ح ى في اليوم بليلته :س = وهو ٠ ٠نط ح ى في اليوم بليلته :گ.
٤حركة[ حركت :ی ٥ .فلك[ –س– ،گ ٥ .أع��ه[ عله :گ ٥ .إلى[ +خ��ف :ب
)فوق السطر( ،ل ،ی ٦ .وهو )ا��ٔ ّول([ ب ،ح ،د ،ل ،م ،ی = –س– ،گ = وهي :ف،
ق ٠ ٦ .ب يح يد ب[ ٠ب نح يد ب :ب ،ی = +لعله ٠ٮ و ٮو ٠ط نا لط نو لط:
م )في الهامش( ٦ .وهو )الثاني([ وهذه :ف ،ق ،م ٨ .خاصة[ –فٔ�� ٨ .نّها[ ٠ +ب
يح يد ب :س ،گ ٩ .التي هي ٠ب يح يد ب[ ح ،د ،ق ،م = التي هي ٠ب نح
يد ب :ب ،ل ،ی = –س– ،گ ٩ .حركة[ حركت :ی ٩ .هي[ +في اليوم بليلته :س،
گ ١٠ .لكون[ الكون :گ ١٠ .فيحصل[ فتحصل :ف ،ق ١٠ .مفارقة[ مفارقت :ی.
١٠الكوكب[ )في هامش ق( ٠ ١١ .جـ و كد ى ا لح لز كح مب[ ح ،د ،ق ،م = كد
ی ا لح لز مب :ب )ويوجد » ٠حـ و « في الهامش( = ٠جـ و كد ی ا لح لز كح مب ٠
:٠س = ٠جـ و كه ی ا لح لو كح مب :٠ ٠گ = ٠جـ و كد ى ا لح لز يح مب:
ل = ٠جـ و كد ی ا ىح لر لح مب :ی ١١ .حركة[ حركت :ی ١٢ .المركّبة[ المركب:
ی.
54
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 251
ومما يزيد ذلك إيضاحاً أنّه إذا تح ّرك المائل ربع دائرة وتح ّرك الحامل ربع
الخاصة
ّ دائرة وتح ّرك المدير نصف دائرة ،انتقلت الذروة التي هي مبتدأ حركته
ربع دائرة إلى التوالي .و إنّما وجدت بالرصد أنّها منتقلة إلى التوالي مثل حركة
خاصة عطارد التي هي ٠جـ و كد ى ،فيكون حركة التدوير حول مركزه إلى ّ
الخاصة علی حركة المركز لكونهما إلى جهة واحدة. ّ التوالي بقدر فضل هذه ٥
١ذلك[ ذالك :د ،س ٢–١ .وتح ّرك الحامل ربع دائرة[ –ب– ،ل– ،ی ٢ .مبتدأ[ ح ،س،
گ = مثل :ب ،ل ،ی = مبدأ :د ،ف ،ق = منند :م ٢ .حركته[ ل = حركة :ب،
ح ،د ،ف ،ق ،م = الحركة :س ،گ = ىحركت :ی ٣ .وجدت[ وجد :ف ،ق ،م.
٣بالرصد[ بارصادنا :ی ٣ .منتقلة[ ننقلىه :ب = منتقلت :ی ٣ .حركة[ حركت :ی.
٠ ٤جـ و كد ى[ ب ،د ،ق ،ل ،م = ٠ج و كد ی ا :ح = ٠ج و كد ی ب :س ،گ.
٤فيكون[ فتكون :د ،ق ،م ٤ .حركة[ حركت :ی ٤ .حول[ حركة :ب ،ل = حركت :ی.
٥بقدر[ بقد :م ٥ .التوالي بقدر فضل[ التوالي بعد :ب )» بعد « متغيّر إلى » بقدر «( ،ل.
٥هذه[ )» هذه « متغيّر إلى » حركة « في ب( = +الحركة) :مشطوب في ق( ٥ .علی[
)مشطوب في ب( = عند :د )» على « في هامش د مع رمز » خ «( ٥ .حركة[ وحركة:
الخاصة على حركة المركز[ بقدر حركت الخاصة و ّ ب = +هذا :ف ٥ .بقدر فضل هذه
حركت المركز :ی ٥ .لكونهما[ لكونها :س ،گ ٦ .ذلك[ –ل– ،ی ٧ .الشامل[ +وهو
المحيط :س ،گ ٧ .التوالي[ –ی ٧ .حركة[ –ی ٨ .ا نح يو ك[ ل ) » +ا ٮح ٠ٮح
ك « في هامش ل مع رمز » ٮحـ «( ،ی = ا نح يح ك :ب )» يح « متغيّر إلى » يو «(
= ا يح ٠يح ك :ح ،د ،ف ،ق = ا يح ٠يح ك بليلته :س ،گ = ا نح ٠يح ك :م.
٨الحافظ[ ب ،ح ،س ،گ = الحافظة :د ،ف ،ق ،ل ،م ،ی ٨ .ف ٕانّه[ ح ،س ،گ =
فانها :ب ،د ،ف ،ق ،ل ،م ،ی ٨ .يتح ّرك[ تتحرك :د ،ق ،م ٩ .مركز[ –ی ٩ .وهي[
وهو :ی ٩ .اليوم جـ نو لب لط[ ی = اليوم ج نو لو لط :ب )» لو « متغيّر إلى » لب «(،
د ،ف ،ق ،م = ج نو لز لط :٠ ٠ح = اليوم بليلته ج نو لز لط :س = اليوم بليلته ج نو
لو لط :گ = اليوم جـ نو لز لط :ل.
55
252 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
الخط الخارج من مركز التدوير إلى مركز الشامل ،يقرب ّ ف�� يزال عطارد على
الخط غير خارج عنه .و إذا كان مركز التدوير ّ من مركز التدوير ويبعد وهو على
في ا��ٔوج أو الحضيض كان عطارد في أقرب قربه من مركز تدويره ،ويس ّمى هذا
القرب نصف قطر التدوير المرئي وهو أحد وعشرون جزءاً وثُلث]![ جزء .و إذا
٥ كان المركز ث��ثة بروج كان عطارد في أبعد بعده من مركز التدوير وهو ث���
وعشرون درجة واثنتان وخمسون دقيقة .فيكون أبعد بعد عطارد من مركز العالم
ستّة وثمانون وثُلثين وأقرب قربه ث��ثة وث��ثون وثُلث ،إ�ّ� أ ّن عطارد �� يقرب إلى
الم�سمة على ما أوضحنا قبل في غير هذا الموضع. ّ أقرب قرب أف��كه
١عطارد[ عطار :ح ٢ .و إذا[ اذا :ف ،ق ٣ .أو[ ب ،ف ،ق ،ل ،م ،ی = و :ح،
د ،س ،گ ٣ .تدويره[ تدوير عطارد :ف ،ق ٤ .نصف[ –ف ٤ .التدوير[ –ل ٤ .المرئي[
المرى :ب ،ف ،ق ،م ،ی ٤ .أحد[ احدي :س ،گ ٤ .جزءاً[ جزواً :س ،گ ،م ،ی.
٤أحد وعشرون جزءاً وثُلث جزء[ كا ك :د ٥ .ث��ثة[ ق = ث��� :ب ،ح ،د ،س ،ف ،گ،
ل ،م = ثلث :ی ٦–٥ .ث��� وعشرون درجة واثنتان وخمسون دقيقة[ ك�� ن� :د )يوجد رمز
» ق « فوق السطر( ٥ .ث���[ ثلث :ح ،ف ،ق ،ی ٦ .وعشرون[ عشرون :ف ٦ .درجة[
جزواً :س ،گ ٦ .واثنتان[ ف ،ق = واثنان :ب ،ح ،س ،گ ،ل ،م ،ی ٧ .ستّة[ ست:
س ،گ ٧ .ستّة وثمانون وثُلثين[ فو م :د ٧ .وثُلثين[ ف ،ق = وثلثي :ب ،ح ،س ،گ،
ل ،م ،ی ٧ .قربه[ � ث��� وعشرون جزوا واثنان خمسون دقيقه فيكون ابعد بعد عطارد من
مركز العالم ست وثمانون وثلثين واقرب قربه :گ ٧ .ث��ثة[ ب )مت�يّر من » ث��� «( ،ل،
م = ث��� :س ،گ = ثلثة :ح ،ف ،ق ،ی ٧ .وث��ثون[ ب = وثلثين :ح ،ف ،ق =
وث��ثين :س ،گ ،م = وثلثون :ل ٧ .ث��ثة وث��ثون وثُلث[ لج ك :د ٧ .وثُلث[ ح ،س ،گ
= وثلثا :ب ،ف ،ق ،ل ،م ،ی [�� ٧ .ب ،د ،ف ،ق ،ل ،م ،ی = ا�� :ح ،س ،گ.
٧يقرب[ ب ،ح ،د ،س ،گ ،ل = ىقرب :ق = بقرب :م ٨ .قرب[ قربه :ق = –ل.
٨في غير هذا الموضع[ ح ،د ،س ،گ = في غير موضع :ب ،ف ،ق ،ل ،م ،ی ٨ .هذا[
)فوق السطر في ح(.
56
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 253
المجسمة ف ٕا ّن نصف قطر كرة الحامل كح نب؛ ونصف ّ وأما أقدار ا��ٔف���
قطر كرة المدير كد مز؛ ونصف قطر كرة التدوير كجـ نب؛ ونصف قطر كرة
الشامل ا و؛ ونصف قطر كرة الحافظ ٠لجـ ،الجميع با��ٔجزاء التي بها نصف
قطر الممثّل ستّون جزءاً .فيكون أبعد بعد الممثّل ثمانية وثمانين واثنتين وخمسين
دقيقة .وفوق ذلك سمك الممثّل ولنفرضه تت ّمة فط ل ،وأقرب قرب أف��كه ٥
١ا��ٔف���[ اف��كه :ب ١ .قطر كرة[ ب ،ق ،ل ،م = قطره :ح = قطر :د ،س ،گ.
١كح نب[ كح ىٮ :ب ،ح ،د ،س ،ف ،ق ،گ ،ل ،م ،ی ٢–١ .ونصف قطر كرة المدير
كد مز؛ ونصف قطر كرة التدوير كجـ نب[ ونصف قطر كرة التدوير كجـ نب ونصف قطر كرة
المدير كد مز :د ٢ .كجـ نب[ ب ،ح ،س ،ف ،ق ،ل ،م ،ی = كح نٮ :گ ٢ .كرة
)ا��ٔ ّول([ +التدوير) :مشطوب في ل( ٢ .كد مز[ ب ،ح ،ف ،ق ،ل ،م ،ی = كد مب:
س ،گ ٣ .ا و[ ا ز :ب ،ل ،ی ٠ ٣ .لجـ[ ح ،س ،ف ،ق ،گ ،م = ا ٠لج:
ب )متغيّر من » ا و لج «( ،ل ،ی = ٠لج :٠د ٤ .ستّون[ :٦٠د = ستين :ف،
ق ٤ .جزءاً[ جزوا :د ،س ،گ ،م ٤ .فيكون[ فكون :ق ٤ .الممثّل )الثاني([ ل )ويوجد
» المائل « في هامش ل مع رمز » ٮح «( ٥–٤ .ثمانية وثمانين واثنتين وخمسين دقيقة[ فح
نٮ :د )يوجد رمز » ق « فوق السطر( ،س ،گ = +واقرب قربه) :مشطوب في هامش
ح( ٤ .وثمانين[ +درجة) :في هامش ل( ٤ .واثنتين[ ح ،م = اثىين :ب = واسنتين :ف
= واىىىىن :ق = واىىىن :ل = –ی ٥ .وفوق ذلك[ وفوقه :ی ٥ .الممثّل[ للمىل :م.
٥ولنفرضه[ ولتفرضه :ف ٥ .تت ّمة[ –د ٥ .فط ل[ ب ،ف ،ق ،ل ،م ،ی = نط ل :ح ،د،
س ،گ ٦ .وأق ّل من ذلك[ –ب = +نصف قطر الكوكب) :مشطوب في ق( ٦ .باتّصال[
واتصال :ف ٦ .فنفرضه[ ونفرضه :س ،گ :�� [٠ �� ٦ .ب ٦ .والله أعلم[ –ب– ،د،
–ف– ،ق.
57
254 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
][Fig. A1.
صورة أف��� عطارد على أنّ�ا مراك� ا��ٔكر التا ّمة على حسب ما يتص ّور على
البسيط في ا��ٔو� وال��ي� والب��ين ا��ٔوسطين.
١صورة[ وهذه صورة :ح ،د ،س ،گ ٢–١ .التا ّمة على حسب ما يتص ّور على البسيط في
ا��ٔو� وال��ي� والب��ين ا��ٔوسطين[ ح ،س ،گ = –ب = +فتامله :د = التامة على
حسب ما نفع على البسيط :ف = التا ّمة على حسب ما تقع على البسيط :ق = التا ّمة على
حسب ما يتص ّور :ل = التا ّمة على حسب ما يتص ّور على البسيط :م = التامت علی حسب
ما يتصور في البسيط :ی.
58
The Mercury Models of Ibn al-Šāṭir and Copernicus 255
][Fig. A2.
Ibn al-Shir
Ibn al-Shir (b. probably 705/1306,
d. 777/1375–6) was one of the most
important astronomers of pre-modern
Islam, writing on a variety of topics
and producing one of the most innova-
tive astronomical systems prior to the
advances of early modern Europe. His full
name is Al al-Dn Ab l-asan Al b.
Ibrhm b. Muammad b. al-Humm Ab
Muammad b. Ibrhm b. assn b. Abd
al-Ramn b. Thbit al-Anr al-Aws.
Sources do not agree about his birth
date, but the one reported by al-afad
(15 Shabn 705/2 March 1306), who
met Ibn al-Shir, seems the most reliable
(al-afad, 20:302).
Ibn al-Shir was born in Damascus. His
father died when he was six, after which
he was raised by a cousin on his father’s
side, who was married to Ibn al-Shir’s
258 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
maternal aunt. His stepfather’s name was who later became a timekeeper at al-Azhar
Al b. Ibrhm b. Ysuf b. al-Shir, who Mosque in Cairo and was the grandfather
was known as Ibn al-Shir, whence the of Sib al-Mridn (d. c.900/1495), stud-
name under which our Ibn al-Shir came ied under him (King, Analog computer,
to be known. His stepfather taught him 219–20 n. 2).
the art of ivory inlaying (tam), so he
became known as al-Muaim. He appar- 1. I b n al -Sh ir and as t ronomy
ently earned a good living and lived in a Ibn al-Shir was firmly within the Hel-
fine house in the Bb al-Fards quarter lenistic traditions of astronomy and their
of Damascus (Ibn ajar, 1:116; al-afad, continuation in the Islamic world, and he
20:302; cf. al-Maqrz, 2:526). had access to many of the works of his
According to al-afad (20:302), Ibn predecessors in these traditions. At some
al-Shir studied the mathematical sci- point, Ibn al-Shir decided to test Ptol-
ences with his stepfather, Al b. Ibrhm. emy’s (fl. c.140 C.E.) observations. This
Later, in 719/1319, he travelled to Cairo led him to write a work titled Nihyat
and Alexandria to further his studies (Ibn al-ghyt f aml al-falakiyyt (“The culmi-
ajar, 1:116; cf. al-Maqrz, 2:526). Dur- nation of goals regarding astronomical
ing this period, Egypt was home to several operations”), which is not extant, but is
prominent scientists working in astron- based, according to Ibn al-Shir in his
omy, especially involving instruments al-Zj al-jadd, on Ptolemy’s models in the
and practical applications (King, Astron- Almagest. Later, basing himself on alterna-
omy, 531, 534–5). Amongst these was tives to Ptolemy’s models, he wrote Talq
Ibn al-Sarrj (d. after 748/1347–8), with al-ard, not extant, in which he estab-
whom Ibn al-Shir corresponded and lished his new models based on his own
exchanged treatises regarding an instru- observations (al-afad, 20:306). The tra-
ment known as al-rub al-mujanna, which dition of alternatives to Ptolemy’s models
Ibn al-Sarrj invented and Ibn al-Shir dates back at least to Ibn al-Haytham
modified. Ibn al-Shir’s treatise is not (d. c.431/1040); this tradition found fault
extant, but Shams al-Dn Muammad b. with Ptolemy’s violations of the accepted
Ab l-Fat al-f al-Mir (fl. c.900/1495) physics that demanded uniform circular
summarised it in one of his treatises (Cha- motions in the heavens resulting from
rette, 15 n. 63; al-afad, 20:307). the rotations of spherical orbs (Saliba,
Ibn al-Shir was the long-time chief 134–70). Later astronomers in this tradi-
muezzin (ras al-muadhdhinn) and time- tion usually listed several problems with
keeper (muwaqqit) at the Umayyad Mosque Ptolemaic models, ten of which were cited
in Damascus (al-afad, 20:302). His roles by al-afad as well known. He went on
at the Umayyad Mosque secured his fame, to say that Ibn al-Shir supplemented
and his works, as indicated by ownership this list with an additional nineteen prob-
notes, were esteemed by later generations lems and claimed that he had solved them
of timekeepers (e.g., Tehran, Sepahslr, all in his Talq al-ard. Al-afad notes,
MS 598, fol. 1a). Although Ibn al-Shir however, that Ibn al-Shir wrote two
never occupied a formal teaching position, monographs, Maqla f qurb falak al-burj
Jaml al-Dn al-Mridn (d. 809/1406–7), min muaddil al-nahr and Maqla f arakat
68
Ibn al-Shāṭir 259
al-iqbl wa-l-idbr, in which he denied the 682/1283); and Qub al-Dn al-Shrz
existence of two of the ten well known (d. 710/1311).
problems, namely, the variability of the Although Ibn al-Shir is often included
obliquity of the ecliptic in the Maqla f in the so-called Margha School (Margha
qurb, and variable precession in the Maqla was the site of a famous observatory) of
f arakat (al-afad, 20:304–6). al-Ur, al-s, and al-Shrz, his mod-
Ibn al-Shir later presented his new els differ fundamentally, inasmuch as he
models in Nihyat al-sul f ta al-ul insists on making the Earth both the math-
(“The culmination of inquiry into correct- ematical and cosmological centre of the
ing the hypotheses”) but without the full Universe. This is accomplished by dispens-
derivations found in Talq al-ard. The ing with eccentric orbs (ones surrounding
Nihyat al-sul is in the genre of haya basa the Earth but with different centres) and
(simplified theoretical astronomy, i.e., using only Earth-centred orbs and epicy-
presented mostly without the geometrical cles (orbs that do not surround the Earth).
derivations). Most of the extant manu- This seems to be a compromise system
scripts comprise an introduction and two that solves Ptolemy’s violations using epi-
additional parts: one on the configuration cycles rather than eccentrics while making
of the celestial realm (hayat al-sam) and the Earth the primary mathematical cen-
one on the configuration of the Earth, that tre. This “quasi-homocentric” cosmology
is, the sublunary realm (hayat al-ar). An may well owe something to the works of
additional part on the calculation of plan- sixth/twelfth-century Andalusians such as
etary equation tables (promised in some Ibn Rushd and al-Birj, who sought to
manuscript copies) seems never to have return to the pure homocentric system of
been written; he probably decided instead Aristotle (Ragep, 408). Unlike the astron-
to write al-Zj al-jadd, several copies of omy of al-Birj, however, Ibn al-Shir’s
which are extant. This zj (an astronomical models can faithfully reproduce Ptolemy’s
handbook with tables) is innovative (thus mathematical results, which generally rep-
jadd, new); in it, the new models of Nihyat resent celestial motions accurately.
al-sul were used instead of the standard With the exception of al-Zj al-jadd, Ibn
Ptolemaic models. Al-afad mentions a al-Shir’s works had less influence than
zj written by Ibn al-Shir for Sayf al-Dn one might expect. The manuscript tradi-
Tankiz (d. 740/1340), the Damascus- tion of his works is spotty; many works are
based viceroy of Syria, whence it is called lost, and important works, such as Nihyat
al-Zj al-Sayf. In the Nihyat al-sul and al-sul, are replete with copyists’ errors.
al-Zj al-jadd, Ibn al-Shir refers to works Nevertheless, references to him and his
by Ptolemy; Ibn al-Haytham; Jbir b. work are not uncommon in Islamic lands,
Afla (fl. first half of the sixth/twelfth cen- and there is strong evidence that he was
tury); Ibn Rushd (Averroës, d. 595/1198); known in other cultural contexts.
al-Birj (Alpetragius, fl. 586/1190, in We know that Shams al-Dn al-Mir
al-Andalus; Ibn al-Shir incorrectly calls and Taq al-Dn Ibn Marf al-Rid (d.
him al-Majr); Muayyad al-Dn al-Ur 993/1585), two prominent astronomers
(d. c.664/1266); Nar al-Dn al-s (d. of the early modern period, owned cop-
672/1274); Muy l-Dn al-Maghrib (d. ies of Nihyat al-sul (Oxford, Bodleian
69
260 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
70
Ibn al-Shāṭir 261
universal quadrant”), exists; see King, Ibn al-Shir also wrote several works
Fihris, 2:543). on instruments that were invented before
3) Al-mamarrt al-fqiyya (“Horizon him: 1) al-Ishrt al-imdiyya f l-mawqt
transits”) (apparently not extant). al-shariyya (“Fundamental indications on
4) Al-rub al-mujanna (“The ‘winged’ legally sanctioned timekeeping”), or Risla
quadrant”), which is probably the modi- f l-amal bi-l-uturlb wa-rub al-muqanart
fied version of the instrument invented by wa-l-rub al-mujayyab (“Treatise on the use
Ibn al-Sarrj, mentioned by Shams al-Dn of the astrolabe, the almucantar quad-
al-Mir. rant, and the sine quadrant”); 2)
5) Al-la al-jmia (“The universal instru- al-mughayyab f l-amal bi-l-rub al-mujayyab
ment”), described in al-Ashia al-lmia (“Elucidation of the obscure regarding
f l-amal bi-l-jmia (“Shining rays on the the use of the sine quadrant”); 3) Kashf
use of the universal [instrument]”). Ab al-mughayyab f l-isb bi-l-rub al-mujayyab
Al al-Marrkush (d. c.700/1300) is (“Uncovering the obscure regarding cal-
mentioned in this treatise. Taq al-Dn culation with the sine quadrant”); 4) al-
al-Rid’s al-Thimr al-ynia min quf al-la Zubd al-mar f l-amal bi-l-jayb bi-ghayr mur
al-jmia (“Ripe fruits from the harvest of (“The manifest essence on the use of the
the universal instrument”) was inspired by sine quadrant without the muri [string cal-
it; King, Fihris, 2:533). culator]”).
6) andq al-yawqt (“Box of gems/sap- We are fortunate to have several
phires”), a multi-purpose instrument in instruments made by Ibn al-Shir: 1) an
which a magnetic compass was fitted in astrolabe, bearing the date 726/1326, cur-
order to align it in the cardinal directions, rently held by the Observatoire National,
described in Tashl al-mawqt f l-amal Paris (Mayer, 42); 2) an exemplar of his
bi-andq al-yawqt (“Facilitating timekeep- al-la al-jmia (“Universal instrument”)
ing by using the box of gems”), which is made in 738/1338 and dedicated to
not extant; on the instrument itself, see Shaykh Al b. Muammad al-Darband,
Janin and King, 190). in the Museum of Islamic Art, Cairo
7) Al-rub al-Al (“The Al quad- (Mayer, 40); 3) another exemplar of al-la
rant”), described in al-Risla f l-rub al-jmia, bearing the same year and dedi-
al-Al (“Treatise on the Al quadrant”; catee, in Bibliothèque Nationale, Paris
Schmalzl, 100). (Mayer, 41); 4) an exemplar of his origi-
8) Al-murabbaa (“The square instru- nal instrument, the andq al-yawqt (“Box
ment”), attributed to Ibn al-Shir by Ibn of sapphires”), dated 767/1366, recently
al-Ar (King, Survey, 62–3). A certain located in Aleppo (present location and
Ibn al-Ghuzl composed in 779/1377–8 situation unknown; Reich and Wiet, 195;
a treatise based on a work by Ibn al-Shir Janin and King, 187); it was dedicated to
dealing with al-murabbaa (Charette, 17). Mankal-Bugh, the viceroy of Aleppo (d.
King suggests that Ibn al-Shir is the 774/1372–3); 5) fragments of his sundial,
author of the anonymous treatise in Cairo dated 773/1371–2 and constructed for
that is about the same instrument. the Umayyad Mosque in Damascus, pre-
9) Al-rub al-kmil (“The perfect quad- served in the National Museum, Damas-
rant”), described in Rislat al-rub al-kmil cus; a replica of it was made in about
(“Treatise on the perfect quadrant”). 1873 by a certain Shaykh Muammad
71
262 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
al-anw (d. 1886) and placed in the Archives Internationales d’Histoire des Sciences 24
Umayyad Mosque (Badrn, 365; King, (1974), 219–42; David A. King, The astron-
omy of the Mamluks, Isis 74 (1983), 531–55;
Ibn al-Shir, 361). David A. King, Fihris al-makht al-ilmiyya
al-mafa bi-Dr al-kutub al-miriyya, 2 vols.,
3. O th e r wo r k s by I bn Cairo 1981–6; David A. King, Ibn al-Shir,
al -Sh i r in Charles Coulston Gillispie (ed.), Diction-
ary of scientific biography (New York 1975),
Three works on mathematics are 12:357–64; David A. King, A survey of the
attributed to Ibn al-Shir, but there is no scientific manuscripts in the Egyptian National
known copy: al-Mal f ab al-ul (on Library, Winona Lake IN 1986; Y. Tzvi
geometry), Kitb f l-misa (on surveying), Langermann, A compendium of renaissance
science. Taalumot okmah by Moses Galeano,
and Kitb f l-isb (on arithmetic). There Aleph. Historical Studies in Science and Judaism 7
are also several works that have been (2007), 285–318; Rudolf Mach, Catalogue of
attributed to Ibn al-Shir but are uncor- Arabic manuscripts (Yahuda section) in the Gar-
roborated, including A5-A9, A16, A19, rett collection, Princeton University Library, Princ-
eton 1977; L. A. Mayer, Islamic astrolabists
A21-A25, A28, A30-A32, and A34-A35 and their works, Geneva 1956; Robert Mor-
(Rosenfeld and hsanolu, 254–6). rison, A scholarly intermediary between the
Ottoman empire and renaissance Europe,
Isis 105 (2014), 32–57; F. Jamil Ragep, Ibn
Bibl io g ra ph y al-Shir and Copernicus. The Uppsala
notes revisited, Journal for the History of Astron-
Sources omy 47 (2016), 395–415; Sigismund Reich
Abd al-Qdir b. Amad Badrn, Mundamat and Gaston Wiet, Un astrolabe Syrien du
al-all wa-musmarat al-khayl, Beirut 1985; XIVe siècle, BIFAO 38 (1939), 195–202;
Ibn ajar al-Asqaln, Inb al-ghumr bi-abn Victor Roberts, The solar and lunar the-
al-umr, ed. asan abash, vol. 1, Cairo ory of Ibn ash-Shir. A pre-Copernican
1969; al-Maqrz, Durar al-uqd al-farda Copernican model, Isis 48 (1957), 428–
f tarjim al-ayn al-mufda, ed. Mamd 32; Boris A. Rosenfeld and Ekmeleddin
al-Jall, 2 vols., Beirut 2002; al-afad, hsanolu, Mathematicians, astronomers and
al-Wf bi-l-wafayt, ed. Amad uay, vol. other scholars of Islamic civilization and their
20, Beirut 2007; Taq al-Dn Ibn Marf works (7th–19th c.), Istanbul 2003; George
al-Rid, Sidrat muntah l-afkr f malakt al- Saliba, Islamic science and the making of the
falak al-dawwr, Istanbul, Nuruosmaniye European renaissance, Cambridge MA 2007;
Library, MS 2930. Peter Schmalzl, Zur Geschichte des Quadranten
bei den Arabern, Munich 1929 (partial repr.
Studies Kennedy and Ghanem, 27–35); Noel M.
Abbs Azzw, Ibn al-Shir al-Dimashq, Swerdlow and Otto Neugebauer, Mathemati-
riy wa-falak, al-Majalla, Sijill al-Thaqfa cal astronomy in Copernicus’s De revolutionibus,
al-Rafa 27 (1959), 51–5; François Charette, New York 1984.
Mathematical instrumentation in fourteenth-century
Egypt and Syria. The illustrated treatise of Najm Sajjad Nikfahm-Khubravan
al-Dn al-Mir, Leiden 2003; Louis Janin F. Jamil Ragep
and David A. King, Ibn al-Shir’s andq
al-yawqt, Journal for the History of Arabic Sci-
ence 1 (1977), 187–256; Edward S. Kennedy
and Imad Ghanem, The life & work of Ibn
al-Shir, an Arab astronomer of the fourteenth cen-
tury, Aleppo 1976; Edward S. Kennedy and
Victor Roberts, The planetary theory of Ibn
al-Shir, Isis 50 (1959), 227–35; David A.
King, An analog computer for solving prob-
lems of spherical astronomy. The shakkzya
quadrant of Jaml al-Dn al-Mridn,
72
Section IV
360
Alī Qushjī and Regiomontanus: Eccentric Transformations and Copernican Revolutions
C
267
361
2005JHA....36..3
268 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
362
Alī Qushjī and Regiomontanus: Eccentric Transformations and Copernican Revolutions
C
269
363
2005JHA....36..3
270 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
364
Alī Qushjī and Regiomontanus: Eccentric Transformations and Copernican Revolutions
C
271
365
272 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
366
Alī Qushjī and Regiomontanus: Eccentric Transformations and Copernican Revolutions
C
273
367
2005JHA....36..3
274 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
368
Alī Qushjī and Regiomontanus: Eccentric Transformations and Copernican Revolutions
C
275
369
2005JHA....36..3
276 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
370
Alī Qushjī and Regiomontanus: Eccentric Transformations and Copernican Revolutions
C
277
371
Tūsı̄ and Copernicus: The Earth’s Motion in Context* ˙
F. Jamil Ragep
University of Oklahoma
Argument
1. Introduction
In recent years, there has been considerable discussion regarding the possible
influence of late medieval Islamic astronomy1 on the work of Copernicus and other
Renaissance astronomers. For the most part, this influence has been presumed to be
limited to mathematical models and, perhaps, to criticism of Greek astronomy that
had led to these models. The story can be recapitulated as follows: Islamic
astronomers, beginning with Ibn al-Haytham in the eleventh century, faulted a
number of Ptolemy’s models on the grounds that they produced irregular motion,
which was a violation of the ancient principle that all celestial motion must be
uniform and circular. Beginning in the thirteenth century, this led to the proposal of
alternative models by several Islamic astronomers, dubbed collectively the Marāgha
School, whose purpose was to replace certain suspect Ptolemaic models and devices
(such as the equant) using various combinations of uniformly rotating orbs.
Copernicus, somehow aware of this late tradition of non-Ptolemaic astronomy, began
* I wish to thank Steven Livesey, Sally Ragep, A. I. Sabra, and Julio Samsó for helpful suggestions. It should
be noted that several of the texts discussed in this article are only available in manuscript and have yet to be
edited or translated. This will, I hope, be rectified in a forthcoming publication.
1
“Late” medieval astronomy refers here to the period beginning in the early thirteenth century. This is after
the main translation movement from Arabic into Latin had occurred.
280 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
his work to reform astronomy under its influence. Eventually, in dealing with aspects
of planetary motion for which he had no Islamic precedent (in particular the motion
of certain epicycles that produce “the second anomaly”), he was led to transform his
system from a geocentric to a heliocentric one.2
Since medieval Islamic astronomy remained geocentric, it has been assumed that
the reasons for Copernicus’s decision to embrace a heliocentric cosmology and put
the Earth in motion are to be found within a European context. There is, however,
some tantalizing evidence that links Copernicus’s discussion of the Earth’s motion
with a long and increasingly sophisticated discussion of the Earth’s possible rotation
that occurred amongst a number of Islamic astronomers and philosopher/
theologians. In what follows, I will discuss the evidence linking Copernicus to this
Islamic tradition, indicate some of the main issues that animated this debate in Islam,
and speculate about the possible implications of this debate for Copernican
astronomy.
2. The Evidence
Then what should we say about the clouds and other things suspended in the air in
whatever way or things that fall down or conversely things that rise up to the upper
regions? [We would say] that not only the earth with the watery element conjoined with
it moves in this way, but also not a small part of the air and whatever in the same way
has a natural connection (cognatio) to the earth. Either the nearby air, mixed with the
matter of earth or water, should conform to (sequatur) the same nature as the earth, or
the motion of the air, which has been acquired by the contiguity of the earth,
2
Admittedly this is a grossly simplified version of a fuller and much more careful exposition that one may find
in Swerdlow and Neugebauer 1984, esp. part 1, 41–64. Although there are parts of this story that need
revision, I will leave that for another occasion.
146
Tūsī and Copernicus: The Earth’s Motion in Context 281
Let us compare this with a passage from Nası̄r al-Dı̄n al-Tūsı̄’s Tadhkira, a work on
˙
theoretical astronomy (hay a), whose first edition ˙
was completed in 1261. This
passage occurs in Book II, chapter 1, which is concerned with establishing the
general cosmology of the celestial realm according to Ptolemaic principles. As such
Tūsı̄ wishes to prove that the Earth is at rest. But unlike the other “proofs” in this
˙
chapter that for the most part follow Ptolemy’s recourse to observational evidence for
establishing such things as the sphericity of the heavens and Earth, Tūsı̄ here rejects
Ptolemy’s empirical approach in a manner strikingly similar to˙ that taken by
Copernicus:
It is not possible to attribute the primary motion to the Earth. This is not, however,
because of what has been maintained, namely that this would cause an object thrown up
in the air not to fall to its original position but instead it would necessarily fall to the west
of it, or that this would cause the motion of whatever leaves the [Earth], such as an arrow
or a bird, in the direction of the [Earth’s] motion to be slower, while in the direction
opposite to it to be faster. For the part of the air adjacent to the [Earth] could conceivably
conform (yushāyiu) to the Earth’s motion along with whatever is joined to it, just as the
aether [(here) = upper level of air] conforms (yushāyiu) to the orb as evidenced by the
comets, which move with its motion. Rather, it is on account of the [Earth] having a
principle of rectilinear inclination that it is precluded from moving naturally with a
circular motion. (Ragep 1993, vol. 1, 106–107)
What originally struck me about these two passages was the use of comets by both
Tūsı̄ and Copernicus to bolster their case for the view that the Earth might be
˙
moving but we would not be able to tell this simply by observing objects that
occurred or were thrown in the air. But in examining the texts more closely, I became
aware of other similarities, such as the use of the concept of “following” or
“conforming” used by both men to describe what occurs in the lower as well as the
3
I owe this fairly literal translation to my colleague Steven Livesey, who also helped me gain a deeper
understanding of the passage. He is, of course, absolved of any shortcomings and peculiarities in the
interpretation.
147
282 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
upper atmosphere (sequi in Latin and yushāyiu in Arabic).4 I also saw that the structure
of the argument itself – making the case for objects in the lower air conforming to
the Earth’s motion and then bringing forth comets to somehow clinch the matter –
was similar in both cases. Though highly suggestive, these passages alone are not
decisive in proving influence or transmission. For one thing, it has been known for
some time that similar discussions concerning the possibility of the Earth’s motion
exist in the medieval European scholastic tradition. Here an understanding of the
intellectual contexts in each case can not only help elucidate similarities and
differences of corresponding passages but also help answer questions regarding
influence and transmission.
In what follows, I will attempt to deal with some of these contexts by examining
three issues: (1) the use of comets to bolster the case for the Earth’s rotation; (2) the
problem of observational tests; and (3) the debate over the use of natural philosophical
premises in mathematical astronomy.
3. The Use of Comets to Bolster the Case for the Earth’s Rotation
As mentioned above, one of the most striking similarities between the passages by
Tūsı̄ and Copernicus is the appeal to comets. Both use them to provide an analogous
˙ that would make plausible the notion that the air, and whatever is in it, might
case
participate in the Earth’s rotation. To follow this argument, one must first understand
the underlying Aristotelian doctrine regarding comets. According to Aristotle, comets
are a sublunar phenomenon and, as such, one might thereby assume that they would
not participate in the daily rotation of the Universe. But Aristotle maintained in the
Meteorology that the “outermost part of the terrestrial world which falls below the
circular motion. . . and a great part of the air that is continuous with it below is
carried round the earth by the motion of the circular revolution.” Aristotle then
proceeded to relate this to the production of comets, which he, and most medieval
writers, took to occur in the upper atmosphere. Indeed it is presumably comets that
led him to conclude that the upper atmosphere was somehow a party to the daily
motion (Aristotle 1984, Meteorology I.vii, esp. 344a5–23). From the point of view of
Tūsı̄ and Copernicus, the fact that Aristotle could argue that the upper part of the
˙
atmosphere could participate in – or “conform” to – the daily motion of the orbs
provided a physical justification for the idea that the lower atmosphere – that is, the
air – could follow the motion of a rotating Earth if the orbs were not the source of
the daily motion. It is worth noting here that Aristotle’s theory of comets was well-
known, and widely accepted, in both medieval Islam and Christendom. This is nicely
illustrated by a passage from Albertus Magnus’s (ca. 1193–1280) commentary on
Aristotle’s Meteorology in which he cites both Avicenna (Ibn Sı̄nā: 980–1037) and
4
E. Rosen in his translation (1978, 16) uses “conform” in the first instance, “accompany” in the other.
148
Tūsī and Copernicus: The Earth’s Motion in Context 283
5
For the English translation, see Thorndike 1950, 68; repr. Grant 1974, 544. The source of Albert’s reference
to Ibn Sı̄nā’s view may be from the latter’s book on meteorology in the Shifā (1965, 73–74), where a similar
but not exact passage may be found. Albert’s more extensive quotation is from al-Ghazālı̄’s Logica et philosophia
(1506, Liber II, Trac. III, Spec. iiii; for the original Arabic see idem 1960–1, 343).
6
I make no claim to having gone through all the possible European medieval sources. But I find no references
to any such discussion in Thorndike 1923–1958, Hellman 1944, Thorndike 1950, Jervis 1985, or Grant 1994.
If such a discussion existed, it also escaped the keen gaze of Pierre Duhem.
149
284 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
of the most famous and widely read, that of al-Sayyid al-Sharı̄f al-Jurjānı̄
(1339–1413), who was sympathetic to Shı̄rāzı̄’s position on comets but who also
noted its irrelevance when judging whether or not the air might be in conformity
with the Earth’s motion (Jurjānı̄, f. 20a-b).
This issue was also discussed by Alı̄ al-Qūshjı̄ (d. 1474), who played a prominent
intellectual role in the court of the Timurid Prince Ulugh Beg in Samarqand and was
later invited to establish a school devoted to the sciences by the Ottoman Sultan
Mehmet the Conqueror in the newly Islamized city of Constantinople. Writing in his
commentary on Tūsı̄’s theological work, Tajrı̄d al-aqā id, Qūshjı̄ disputed Shı̄rāzı̄’s
˙ motion of the comets in conformity with the orbs by citing the
dismissal of the daily
comet of 837 hijra ( = 1433 A.D.), which he claimed to have personally observed. As
he says:
From what we have witnessed, there is clear proof that the sphere of fire (kurat al-athı̄r)
moves with the daily motion. But it is said [viz. by Shı̄rāzı̄] that if this were the case then
the motion of comets would be parallel to the celestial equator; however, this is not so
since sometimes they [move] north from the equator, sometimes south from it. There is,
though, nothing to this [objection by Shı̄rāzı̄]. For according to what we have witnessed,
they do indeed move thusly with their proper motion. But all the planets move this way
– they move with the daily motion while they have their own proper motions, which
may sometimes be to the north of the equator, sometimes south. (Qūshjı̄ 1890, 194)7
This dispute regarding the relevance of the cometary evidence continues into the
sixteenth century. Abd al-Alı̄ al-Bı̄rjandı̄, who died in 1525 or 1526 (and thus was
a contemporary of Copernicus), was yet another commentator on the Tadhkira who
brought up this controversy.8 He noted that the question of the conformity of air to
the Earth’s motion would not depend on whether or not the comets moved with the
orb since this was only brought up by Tūsı̄ as a supporting argument whose
resolution would not be decisive one way or˙ another (Bı̄rjandı̄, f. 37b).
The point that needs to be stressed here is that this question regarding comets and
their relevance for the problem of the Earth’s rotation was hotly debated for a number
of centuries in the Islamic world. Though Oresme’s argumentation is clearly similar,
he does not use comets directly. As far as I have been able to tell, Copernicus was the
first person in Europe to discuss this matter in a way that so closely follows (or
parallels) the Islamic tradition. Here again, understanding the context (and tradition)
of the debate within each cultural context is important, I believe, for indicating the
7
Though he does not mention Shı̄rāzı̄ by name, the quotation is taken directly from the Tuhfa and would have
˙
been readily recognized by many of Qūshjı̄’s readers. The comet of 1433 was described by the Italian Paolo
Toscanelli (Jervis 1985, 56–58).
8
It is worth noting that though Bı̄rjandı̄ was Iranian, he, along with a number of other Sunnı̄ intellectuals,
fled the new Shı̄ı̄ regime of Shah Ismāı̄l and went to areas controlled by the Ottomans. Bı̄rjandı̄ himself went
to the Ottoman cities of Trebizond and later Istanbul, where contact with European scholars, either directly
or indirectly, would have presumably been easier (Ihsanoǧlu et al. 1997, vol. 1, 101).
150
Tūsī and Copernicus: The Earth’s Motion in Context 285
most likely lines of transmission and influence. In the next two sections, we turn to
other aspects of the intellectual and historical contexts that underlie the arguments of
Tūsı̄ and Copernicus.
˙
9
Unfortunately, as noted above, the vast majority of these texts have not been edited or translated.
10
Though Bı̄rūnı̄ names the followers of the Hindu astronomer Āryabhata as holding that the Earth is in
motion in both his India (1887, 139; 1888, 276) and Qānūn (1954–56, vol.˙ 1, 49), the “unnamed person” is
probably not of Indian origin since he is said to be a distinguished scholar of “ilm al-haya”, which no doubt
indicates an Islamic personage. Cf. S. Pines (1956), who came to the same conclusion.
151
286 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
calculate), he claims that an object such as an arrow shot with a violent (i.e. forced)
motion eastward would have its motion combined with that of the air traveling with
the great speed of the Earth while one shot westward would resist it; thus one should
be able to tell the difference if the Earth’s motion existed (Bı̄rūnı̄ 1954–56, vol. 1,
51–53).11
After Tūsı̄, the question was taken up with renewed vigor, in large part because of
the above˙ passage from the Tadhkira. Once again his student, Qutb al-Dı̄n al-Shı̄rāzı̄,
took a contrary stance, in this case claiming that if the air conformed ˙ to the motion
of the Earth, then a large and a small rock thrown, say, along the meridian should
return to Earth at different locations since the air would move the larger less than the
smaller. In general he seems to have agreed with Ptolemy that observation could
determine the question of the Earth’s rotation.12 (We will return to the significance
of this stance below.)
Shı̄rāzı̄’s position, however, was itself soon under attack. Nizām al-Dı̄n al-Nı̄sābūrı̄
(writing in 1311) and the noted theologian/scientist al-Sharı̄f ˙ al-Jurjānı̄ (in 1409)
both criticized Shı̄rāzı̄ on the matter of the two rocks; they held that they would in
fact have the same quantity of motion as that of the rotating Earth. Hence they
upheld Tūsı̄’s view that this conceivable motion of the Earth could not be decided on
empirical ˙ grounds.13
This discourse became increasingly sophisticated as various writers attempted to
understand the implications of a rotating Earth and to analyze such ideas as the
“conformity” of the air, and things in the air, with a rotation of the Earth. Al-Qūshjı̄,
for example, attempted to counter Shı̄rāzı̄ by claiming that “what is intended by
conformity of the air is its conformity [with a rotating Earth] along with all that is in
it whether it be a rock or something else, whether small or large” (Qūshjı̄ 1890, 195).
Earlier, Jurjānı̄ had dealt with the notion of “conformity” by invoking the important
distinction between accidental and forced motion. “There would be no difference
between the moving [by the air] of the two rocks by an accidental motion since it
would be in the amount of the [air’s] proper motion whether the accidentally moved
thing were small or big. Any difference between them would only be in the forced
motion” (Jurjānı̄, f. 20b).14 Bı̄rjandı̄ elucidated this further by stating that one may
argue against Shı̄rāzı̄ as follows: “the small or large rock will fall to the Earth along the
11
In order to make sense of the argument, one should change the text on page 52, line 9 from miat alf (one
hundred thousand) to the variant bi-thalāthat ālāf (three thousand).
12
Shı̄rāzı̄’s discussion can be found in maqāla II, bāb 1, fasl 4 (ff. 46a–47b) of his Nihāyat al-idrāk fı̄ dirāyat al-
aflāk, which was completed in 1281, and in bāb II, fasl 4 ˙(Mosul MS, ff. 15a–18a = London MS, ff. 9b–11a)
of his al-Tuhfa al-shāhiyya fı̄ al-haya, which appeared ˙in 1284. This section of the Nihāya was translated into
˙
German by E. Wiedemann 1912.
13
In both cases, the discussion occurs in the context of their commentaries on the above-cited passage from
Tūsı̄’s Tadhkira, i.e. Bk. II, Ch. 1, Para. 6. Cf. Ragep 1993, vol. 2, 384; for information on these
˙
commentaries, see ibid., vol. 1, 60, 62. Most of the other commentators on this passage also sided with
Tūsı̄.
˙ This passage is also quoted by Bı̄rjandı̄, f. 37a.
14
152
Tūsī and Copernicus: The Earth’s Motion in Context 287
path of a line that is perpendicular to the plane (sath) of the horizon; this is witnessed
by experience (tajriba). And this perpendicular is away˙˙ from the tangent point of the
Earth’s sphere and the plane of the perceived (hissı̄) horizon. This point moves with
the motion of the Earth and thus there will be no ˙ difference in place of fall of the two
rocks” (Bı̄rjandı̄, f. 37a). Thus Bı̄rjandı̄ makes the case with a concept very close to
what would later be called circular inertia.15
This question of observational tests is of central importance in the work of two
fourteenth-century Frenchmen, namely Jean Buridan and Nicole Oresme, the latter
of whom has been mentioned previously. In his Quaestiones on Aristotle’s De Caelo,
Buridan (ca. 1300–1358), philosopher and sometime rector of the University of Paris,
maintained that there is an observation that negates the possibility of the Earth’s
rotation. This would be an arrow shot straight upward which should, if the Earth
were rotating, not return to the same point from which it was projected since “the
violent impetus of the arrow in ascending would resist the lateral motion of the air
so that it would not be moved as much as the air.” This would then counter the
supporters of the Earth’s rotation who had claimed that “the air, moved with the
Earth, carries the arrow, although the arrow appears to us to be moved simply in a
straight line motion because it is being carried along with us.”16 As can be seen, both
Buridan’s position and that of his antagonist is quite close to what we have seen above
in Bı̄rūnı̄’s Qānūn. Like Bı̄rūnı̄, Buridan holds that an observation can settle the
matter.
A very different perspective is presented by Oresme.17 He holds that no observation
can be decisive since given the scenario outlined by Buridan, in which an arrow or
stone is thrown up into the air, such an object would participate in the Earth’s
hypothetical rotation; thus just as various motions inside a ship would “seem exactly
the same as those when the ship is at rest,” so one could not tell from the action of
the arrow whether or not the Earth were rotating (Oresme 1968, 524–525; trans.
repr. Grant 1974, 505). Oresme thus holds a view that is virtually identical with that
of Tūsı̄ and many (but not all) of Tūsı̄’s Islamic successors as well as Copernicus. But
˙
Oresme argues a further position˙ that puts him at considerable odds with Tūsı̄,
namely that “no argument is conclusive,”18 that is, that neither observations˙ nor
rational arguments from natural philosophy nor even theological arguments could
conclusively show that the Earth was – or was not – moving. On the other hand, Tūsı̄
and many of his followers were willing to accept the proofs of natural philosophy˙ on
this matter, which observation and mathematical astronomy, they maintained, could
15
This is not the place to compare Bı̄rjandı̄’s view with those of early modern European scientists such as
Galileo, but one hopes such a comparison will not be dismissed out of hand.
16
Translation due to M. Clagett 1959, 596; repr. Grant 1974, 502.
17
As my colleague Steve Livesey pointed out to me, one should keep in mind that Oresme was professionally
a theologian whereas Buridan was a philosopher mainly concerned with the works of Aristotle. We will return
to the possible significance of this difference below.
18
Oresme 1968, 520–521; trans. repr. Grant 1974, 504. Since this is the main point Oresme is making, it is
repeated several times throughout the passage.
153
288 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
19
Much of the literature on this problem has portrayed the two sides as being on the one hand mathematical
and instrumentalist (interested only in “saving the phenomena”) and on the other physicalist and realist
(interested in the “true” nature of the universe). There have been a number of correctives to this view in recent
years – especially as regards ancient authors – and it has become increasingly clear that physical considerations
were of concern even to someone like Ptolemy or the writers of astronomical tables (zı̄jes). Cf. Ragep 1993,
vol. 1, 24–53, where one may also find references to other discussions of this problem; for how a zı̄j writer
such as al-Battānı̄ (ca. 858–929) was influenced by physics in dealing with questions of mathematical
astronomy, see Ragep 1996, 267–303.
20
Tūsı̄ does not put the matter as explicitly as stated here, but this was the universal understanding of the
˙
passage, which is quoted in section 2 above.
154
Tūsī and Copernicus: The Earth’s Motion in Context 289
Though this issue became much more explicit and important for Tūsı̄ and his
successors, it certainly predates him. In his work on the astrolabe, written ˙ sometime
before 1000 A.D., Bı̄rūnı̄ implies that the question of the rotation of the Earth cannot
be decided by observation and, somewhat surprisingly, declares that this is a difficult
matter whose “resolution should be entrusted (mawkūl) to the Natural Philoso-
phers.”21 But in his later work, al-Qānūn al-masūdı̄, completed in 1030, he claims, as
we have seen, that there is an observational test. One way to interpret Bı̄rūnı̄’s change
of position is to see him as having become more closely tied to a mathematical
approach to astronomical problems and less sympathetic to a philosophical
encroachment upon science. Indeed, in the Qānūn he tells us that for these matters
mathematical investigation is more appropriate than that of natural philosophy since
the latter is “persuasive” (iqnāı̄) (Bı̄rūnı̄ 1954–56, vol. 1, 49) and thus does not attain
certitude.22 One is tempted to view this change in Bı̄rūnı̄ as somehow a reaction to
his contemporary and long-term rival Ibn Sı̄nā, who at about the same time Bı̄rūnı̄
was writing the Qānūn was completing his summary of the Almagest, which would
become part of his monumental Shifā . There, contrary to Bı̄rūnı̄, he seems to dispute
Ptolemy’s reliance on observational tests by stating that “his [i.e. Ptolemy’s]
amazement at their portrayal of something of this heaviness [viz. the Earth] having
such a fast motion … is not something one should put much stock in for it would
only be amazing if they had made it move by compulsion and it were not in its natural
place whereby it had an inclination by nature for another motion.” Ibn Sı̄nā ends the
discussion by stating that “we have shown the impossibility of this motion in the
section on Natural Philosophy” (Ibn Sı̄nā 1980, 25–26).23 This gives a clear indication
that he, unlike Bı̄rūnı̄, thinks the best basis for proving that the Earth does not move
is through the rationalist procedures of Natural Philosophy rather than the
observational tests of mathematical astronomy.
Once again, this debate is given new life and intensity by Tūsı̄’s Tadhkira, and the
˙
main players will be familiar from the above discussion of observational tests. As we
shall see, this is not coincidental. Shı̄rāzı̄ once more gets the ball rolling. In a way that
hearkens back to Bı̄rūnı̄, he insists, as we have seen, that observation can determine
the Earth’s state of rest. And lurking behind this assertion, again like Bı̄rūnı̄, is the
need to establish the science of astronomy (i.e. ilm al- hay a) without recourse to
natural philosophy. Shı̄rāzı̄ calls upon the Ancients for support:
21
This work, Istı̄āb al-wujūh al-mumkina fı̄ sanat al-asturlāb, is unedited, but the above passage may be found
˙
in the Persian edition of Bı̄rūnı̄’s al-Tafhı̄m (1367 ˙ 297).
H. Sh.,
22
This difficult passage is far from clear, but the interpretation given here is reinforced elsewhere in the Qānūn
(vol. 1, 27) where Bı̄rūnı̄ tells us that Ptolemy’s physical proofs for the sphericity of the heavens are persuasive
(iqnāı̄), not necessary (darūrı̄). He also chides Ptolemy for mixing natural philosophy and metaphysics with
astronomy in the latter’s˙ Planetary Hypotheses (Bı̄rūnı̄ 1954–56, vol. 2, 634–635; for a translation, see Ragep
1993, vol. 1, 40).
23
Ibn Sı̄nā is most likely referring here to chapter 7 of his De Caelo, which forms part of the Shifā (Ibn Sı̄nā
1969).
155
290 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
If one asks: why did the Ancients [probably Ptolemy] disprove the Earth’s motion toward
the East with what you have stated and they did not disprove it by [resorting to] its having
the principle of rectilinear inclination and thus is prevented by nature from moving
circularly? We answer: This is: (1) either because it does not follow from a denial of a
natural circular motion of the Earth that one reaches the desired end since it is possible
that it might move in a circle by compulsion; or (2) because this proof is natural
philosophical not mathematical and they [i.e. the Ancients] avoided using non-
[mathematics] in their inquiries. For this reason, to establish the circularity of the simple
[elements] they relied upon matters based upon observation and testing (al-rasad wa-’l-
itibār) and not upon that which is bound to natural [philosophy] – for example, ˙ that a
form other than a sphere would entail a dissimilarity of parts. (Shı̄rāzı̄, Tuhfa, Mosul MS,
f. 17b = London MS, f. 11a) ˙
The reason for this aversion to natural philosophy is made explicit by Shı̄rāzı̄ in his
introduction to the Nihāya. There he paraphrases a famous and controversial passage
from the introduction of Ptolemy’s Almagest: “Astronomy is the noblest of the
sciences… its proofs are secure – being of number and geometry – about which there
can be no doubt unlike the proofs in physics and theology” (Shı̄rāzı̄, Nihāya, preface,
f. 34b).24
Despite this skepticism, Shı̄rāzı̄ still retained, as had Tūsı̄, sections on the natural
philosophical principles needed in astronomy both in his˙Nihāya and in the Tuhfa. But
in the next century Qūshjı̄ would take the bold step of declaring that astronomy ˙ does
not depend upon natural philosophy and metaphysics and can dispense with them. In
his commentary on Tūsı̄’s theological work, the Tajrı̄d al-aqā id, Qūshjı̄, responding
to attacks by certain˙ theologians who had attempted to discredit astronomy by
associating it with astrology and Aristotelian natural philosophy and metaphysics,
claimed:
That which is stated in the science of astronomy (ilm al-haya) does not depend upon
physical (tabı̄iyya) and theological (ilāhiyya) premises (muqaddamāt). The common
practice of˙ authors to introduce their books with them is by way of following the
philosophers; this, however, is not something necessary and it is indeed possible to
establish [this science] without basing it upon them. For of what is stated in [this science]:
(1) some things are geometrical premises which are not open to doubt; (2) others are
suppositions (muqaddamāt hadsiyya) as we have stated; (3) others are premises determined
by (yahkumu bihā) the mind ˙ (al- aql) in accordance with the apprehension (al-akhdh) of
what is˙ most suitable and appropriate; … and (4) other premises that they state are
indefinite (alā sabı̄l al-taraddud), there being no final determination (al-jazm). Thus they
say that the irregular speed in the sun’s motion is either due to an eccentric or to an
epicyclic hypothesis without there being a definitive decision for one or the other.
(Qūshjı̄ 1890, 187)25
24
For the comparable passage in the Almagest, see Toomer 1984, 36.
25
A lengthy section from Qūshjı̄ that contains this passage is quoted by al-Tahānawı̄ (1862, vol. 1, 48–49). For
a translation of the entire passage see Ragep 2001, appendix.
156
˙
Tūsī and Copernicus: The Earth’s Motion in Context 291
It is worth noting that Qūshjı̄ was true to his principles; in his elementary hay a
work Risāla dar ilm-i haya, he took the highly unusual step of dispensing with a
section on natural philosophy with which almost all other similar treatises began.26
What this has to do with the Earth’s rotation becomes clear later in his
commentary when Qūshjı̄ deals with Shı̄rāzı̄’s views. He first states that “it is not
established that what has a principle of rectilinear inclination is prevented from
[having] a circular motion,” which is in answer to the view that the Earth cannot
rotate since its natural motion is rectilinear. Secondly, as we have seen above, he
counters Shı̄rāzı̄ by asserting that the “conformity of the air [with a rotating Earth]
would be its conformity along with all that is in it, whether it be a rock or something
else, whether small or large.” He then ends with a startling conclusion: “Thus nothing
false (fāsid) follows [from the assumption of a rotating Earth]” (Qūshjı̄ 1890, 195).
Qūshjı̄’s conclusion needs to be taken in context with his earlier discussion of the
premises of astronomy. By rejecting the need for Aristotelian natural philosophy, he
has made the determination of the Earth’s rotation (or lack thereof) dependent upon
observational evidence. But contrary to Shı̄rāzı̄, he insists that such evidence is not to
be had since the possibility of the “conformity” of the air with such a rotation makes
the two-rock experiment irrelevant. This leaves him in the rather surprising position
of being apparently an agnostic as regards this question. His position is therefore quite
close to that of Copernicus; given a more compelling physics – one based upon his
four types of premises and in conformity with observational evidence – he would
seem prepared to accept a rotation of the Earth. This makes him almost unique
among medieval astronomers and philosophers.27
It should therefore not surprise us that other astronomers would find such a
position intolerable. Bı̄rjandı̄ for one paraphrases the above passage from Qūshjı̄
(regarding the premises of astronomy),28 and then gives his response:
This is contestable. For many of the questions of this science are based upon the orbs
being simple [bodies], the impossibility of [their] being penetrated and so on, which are
based upon the two sciences [i.e. natural philosophy and metaphysics]. The restriction to
what he has stated is unacceptable, as will become clear in the investigations of this book.
(Bı̄rjandı̄, f. 7a–7b)
Exactly how this will become clear is made clear when we reach Bı̄rjandı̄’s
discussion of the possible rotation of the Earth. As we have seen, Bı̄rjandı̄, like Qūshjı̄,
26
This work was originally in Persian and, given the evidence of the extant manuscripts, quite popular. It was
translated by Qūshjı̄ himself into Arabic and dedicated to Mehmet, the Conqueror (Fātih) of Constantinople,
˙ et al. 1997, vol. 1,
whence it was called al-Risāla al-fathiyya. Cf. Haidarzadeh 1997, 24, 30–32, 41; Ihsanoǧlu
27–35; and Pingree 1996, 474. ˙
27
Other possibilities (as indicated above) are Bı̄rūnı̄’s “unnamed astronomer” and the “followers of
Āryabhata”.
28 ˙
Curiously, Bı̄rjandı̄ does not mention Qūshjı̄ by name but simply refers to him as “one of the eminent
scholars” (bad al-afādil).
˙ ˙
157
292 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
argued against the view that observations could determine whether or not the Earth
rotates. But unlike Qūshjı̄, he was willing to depend upon the standard Aristotelian
natural philosophy to decide the issue. In reacting to Shı̄rāzı̄’s explanation (cited
above) of why the ancient astronomers did not use Natural Philosophy to prove the
Earth’s state of rest, Bı̄rjandı̄ reasserts his previous position: “As mentioned above,
natural philosophy is among the principles of astronomy (hay a), so it is not improper
to determine a question of astronomy with premises that are proven in natural
philosophy” (Bı̄rjandı̄, f. 38a).
Later in this chapter, Bı̄rjandı̄ again brought the issue of the use of Natural
Philosophy in astronomy to the question of the Earth’s rotation. He admits that, in
general, Natural Philosophy strives to prove the “why” of nature (the “reasoned fact”)
whereas astronomy simply proves the fact of a thing. However, “the proof of the lack
of rotational motion of the Earth is. . .of the ‘reasoned fact’ (limmı̄)” (Bı̄rjandı̄, f.
39b).29 Whereas Shı̄rāzı̄, as well as Qūshjı̄, wished to avoid such a conclusion,
Bı̄rjandı̄, following Tūsı̄, is willing to accept that astronomy must on occasion defer
to Natural Philosophy. ˙
We can now return to a comparison with Buridan and Oresme. Buridan notes that
some astronomers hold that since either hypothesis (a stationary or a rotating Earth)
can save the appearances, they “posit the method which is more pleasing to them”
(Clagett 1959, 595; repr. Grant 1974, 501). Underlying this position is a certain view,
which he reports but also seems to agree with, namely “that it suffices astronomers
that they posit a method by which appearances are saved, whether or not it is so in
actuality” (ibid.).30 Buridan thus takes for himself the role of determining the actual
nature of things, in this case whether or not the Earth moves. He therefore must do
this as a natural philosopher, not as an astronomer, which in any event is evident since
his discussion occurs within the context of Aristotle’s De Caelo, a part of the Natural
Philosophy corpus. This then is in marked contrast to several of the Islamic writers we
have been dealing with who took it upon themselves, in an astronomical context and
as astronomers, to determine by factual (innı̄) proofs mainly based on empirical
evidence whether or not the Earth moved. Even astronomers such as Tūsı̄ and
Bı̄rjandı̄, who were willing to defer to Natural Philosophy in this one case, ˙ were
nevertheless careful to delineate those matters in which the astronomer can
determine the true state of affairs (by mathematics and observations) from those very
few he cannot. This simply is not an issue for Buridan; by claiming that astronomers
are not interested in reality, he as natural philosopher can use both observational facts
29
For a discussion of the significance of the fact/reasoned fact dichotomy for distinguishing astronomy from
natural philosophy, see Ragep 1993, vol. 1, 38–41 and vol. 2, 386–388.
30
This extreme version of the “saving the phenomena” thesis is, in fact, something of a distortion of what the
ancient Greek astronomers actually did. Someone like Ptolemy, for example, was quite obviously interested
in the reality of his system as is made clear not only from his cosmological Planetary Hypotheses but also from
his more mathematical Almagest. Islamic astronomers were, for the most part, also considerably interested in
the physical reality of their models. Cf. Lloyd 1991 and Ragep 1990.
158
Tūsī and Copernicus: The Earth’s Motion in Context 293
(the domain held closely by Islamic astronomers) as well as rational arguments (the
traditional realm of the natural philosophers).31
A more striking comparison can be made with Oresme. Since his purpose is to
show that “no argument is conclusive” in determining whether it is the Earth or the
heavens that move, he obviously does not believe that astronomy can be put on an
absolute foundation, whether by astronomical, physical or metaphysical arguments.
One might compare this attitude with that of Qūshjı̄, who also allows for some
uncertainty in the premises of astronomy, but the context is quite different. Qūshjı̄,
like all the Islamic writers mentioned in this paper, was committed to the importance
of astronomy not only as a way to reach truth but also as a way to glorify God.32
Many, if not most, Islamic astronomers would agree with Shı̄rāzı̄ that the
mathematical science of astronomy was the most sure way to obtain knowledge of
cosmological matters, i.e. God’s creation. Despite Oresme’s incisive and subtle
argumentation, which cannot but elicit our admiration, Oresme’s purpose in this
passage from Le Livre du ciel et du monde is not to establish the foundation of
astronomy. If anything, it is the exact opposite. At the end of the passage he tells us
his exercise can “serve as a valuable means of refuting and checking those who would
like to impugn our faith by argument” (Oresme 1968, 538–539; trans. repr. Grant
1974, 510). However one interprets this, it is clear that Oresme believes the lesson to
be drawn is theological rather than astronomical or physical.33
The point that needs to be made here is that, despite their brilliance, Buridan and
Oresme were simply not arguing within an astronomical context, at least as it was
understood in Islam and as it would later be understood in Europe. The question of
31
The use of observations to support propositions in natural philosophy, rather than to prove them (which
ideally should be done using rational arguments rather than observational evidence), goes back to Aristotle
himself, who in De Caelo states at one point that “our theory [of the unchanging aether] seems to confirm
experience and to be confirmed by it” (I.3, 270b4–5). That Buridan’s decisive argument is based upon
observations rather than a priori premises perhaps indicates a continuing overlap (and confusion) of natural
philosophy and astronomy (which both Bı̄rūnı̄ and Qūshjı̄ deplore), but it does not in itself make Buridan’s
argumentation “astronomical” any more than Ptolemy’s occasional recourse to “physical” arguments makes
the Almagest a work of natural philosophy. But one should not draw too fine a line; the main point that I wish
to make here is that Buridan is arguing in the mode of a natural philosopher and using whatever arguments
seem appropriate.
32
Qūshjı̄ 1890, 187: “Whoever contemplates the shadows on the surfaces of sundials will bear witness that this
is due to something wondrous and will praise the [astronomers] with the most laudatory praise.” A similar
sentiment was expressed by al-Sharı̄f al-Jurjānı̄ in his commentary on the Mawāqif, a famous theological work
by al-Ījı̄; cf. Sabra 1994, 39–40 and Ragep 2001.
33
E. Grant has interpreted this to mean that “by showing that it was impossible to know which alternative is
really true, Oresme, the theologian, succeeded in using reason to confound reason” (1974, 510, note 61). E.
Sylla has taken a somewhat different view and argued, rightly in my opinion, that Oresme was not seeking
to “humble reason” but rather to establish that an apparently “unreasonable” tenet, whether the Earth’s
rotation or one of the articles of Christian faith, “may in fact be quite defensible by rational argument” (1991,
217–218). Grant has defended his interpretation against that of Sylla and insisted that “Buridan arrived at his
conclusion on the basis of rational argument and the senses” whereas Oresme “decided the issue on the basis
of scripture and faith” (1994, 647). But whichever interpretation is correct, it should be clear that Oresme
was not writing to establish the proper premises of astronomy.
159
294 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
the proper foundation of astronomy would therefore not arise. On the other hand,
the Islamic writers quoted above were struggling with just this question since they
identified themselves so closely with the mathematical traditions they had inherited
from antiquity.34 For this reason, I believe it is easier, and more natural, to associate
Copernicus’s argumentation with his Islamic astronomical predecessors rather than
with his European scholastic ones. Though admittedly Copernicus’s arguments were
not conclusive but “make it more likely that the earth moves than that it is at rest”
(Rosen 1978, 17), it is noteworthy that just such an alternative was made theoretically
possible by Qūshjı̄, who opened up the possibility of the Earth’s rotation if a coherent
(but not necessarily proven) alternative to Aristotelian physics could be put forth. In
view of his theoretical position, Qūshjı̄ for one might well have found Copernicus’s
alternative, that the whole Earth could have a circular natural motion different from
the rectilinear motion of its parts (Rosen 1978, 17), compelling.35 This simply does
not seem to be an actual possibility that could be maintained by either Buridan or
Oresme.
6. Conclusion
In seeking to understand the possible connection between the passages in Tūsı̄’s
˙
Tadhkira and Copernicus’s De Revolutionibus, it is crucial to understand the intellectual
contexts in which those passages were produced. As we have seen, the Islamic
discussion regarding the possible rotation of the Earth spans more than 600 years. Tūsı̄
is one of a large number of astronomers, philosophers, and theologians who dealt ˙
with this issue in increasingly sophisticated terms as each generation added new
insights into the problem. Thus someone like Bı̄rjandı̄, writing in the sixteenth
century, could quote and react to many of the main players, including Tūsı̄, Shı̄rāzı̄,
˙ As we have
Jurjānı̄, and Qūshjı̄, who themselves were well aware of their predecessors.
seen, the latest members of this debate, Qūshjı̄ and Bı̄rjandı̄, had already anticipated
the main lines of argument that would animate the debate in Europe that began with
Copernicus’s bold assertion of a rotating Earth, an assertion that Qūshjı̄ had
tentatively suggested in the previous generation.
None of this, of course, proves that Copernicus was indebted to his Islamic
predecessors and contemporaries on this point. What it does show is that one of the
crucial arguments used by him had already been debated extensively in the adjoining
cultural area. And furthermore, it had been debated as part of an ongoing astronomical
debate and not simply as a scholastic, philosophical, or theological exercise as was the
case in fourteenth-century Europe. Indeed, the question of the Earth’s rotation
34
This is true even when they were writing in a theological context as Qūshjı̄ was in the remarks quoted
above. In other parts of the Sharh Tajrı̄d, he was at some pains to defend astronomy from those theologians who
would disparage it (Ragep 2001). ˙
35
We should recall that Qūshjı̄ also raised the possibility that something could have both a rectilinear
inclination and a natural circular motion (see above).
160
Tūsī and Copernicus: The Earth’s Motion in Context 295
References
Aristotle. 1984. The Complete Works of Aristotle, 2 vols. Edited by J. Barnes. Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Al-Bı̄rjandı̄, Abd al-Alı̄ b. Muhammad b. Husayn. Sharh al-Tadhkira, Cambridge, Harvard College
Library, Houghton MS Arabic ˙4285. ˙ ˙
Al-Bı̄rūnı̄, Abū Rayhān Muhammad b. Ahmad. 1887. Kitāb fı̄ tahqı̄q mā li-’l-Hind. Edited by C. Edward
Sachau as Alberuni’s ˙
˙ India:˙ An Account ˙ of the Religion, Philosophy, Literature, Geography, Chronology,
Astronomy, Customs, Laws and Astrology of India About A. D. 1030. London: Trübner.
Al-Bı̄rūnı̄, Abū Rayhān Muhammad b. Ahmad. [1888] 1910. Alberuni’s India, 2 vols. Translated with
notes by C. Edward ˙ Sachau.
˙ [London: Trübner]
˙ London: K. Paul, Trench, Trübner.
Al-Bı̄rūnı̄, Abū Rayhān Muhammad b. Ahmad. 1954–1956. al-Qānūn al-masūdı̄, 3 vols. Hyderabad:
˙ uthmāniyya.
Dāirat al-maārif al- ˙ ˙
Al-Bı̄rūnı̄, Abū Rayhān Muhammad b. Ahmad. 1367 H.Sh./1988. Al-Tafhı̄m li-awāil sināat al-tanjı̄m.
˙ by Jalāl
Persian version edited ˙ ı̄, 4th edition. Tehran: Nashr-i Humā. ˙
˙ al-Dı̄n Humā
36
Obviously it is not possible to deal with this complex question in a footnote, but the following literature
gives tantalizing hints of continuing transmission and influence of Islamic science during the late medieval and
early modern periods. For the possible influence of Ibn al-Nafı̄s’s (Damascus, thirteenth century) discovery
of pulmonary circulation on Michael Servetus (Spain, sixteenth century), see Meyerhof 1935. For some
compelling evidence of the influence of Islamic mathematics from the circle of the Marāgha observatory
(thirteenth century) upon Levi ben Gerson (France, fourteenth century), see Lévy 1992. Another indication
of the importance of Jewish scholars in the transmission of Islamic science to early modern Europe is given
by Y. Tzvi Langermann, who has discovered Jewish writers, including Mordecai Finzi (Italy, fifteenth century),
who knew of the Tūsı̄ couple; see Langermann 1996, 34–35. Another article that investigates the possibility
˙
that “Marāgha” astronomy was known in fifteenth-century Europe is Dobrzycki and Kremer 1996. Further
evidence that Tūsı̄’s Tadhkira was known during this period is provided by the Latin annotations found in an
˙ of the work currently in the Vatican (ar. 319). And finally, the question of the influence of
Arabic manuscript
late Islamic observatories upon those of early modern Europe is explored by Sayili 1960, esp. chaps. 9–10.
161
296 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
Clagett, Marshall. 1959. The Science of Mechanics in the Middle Ages. Madison: University of Wisconsin
Press.
Copernicus, Nicholas. 1543. De Revolutionibus orbium coelestium. Nuremberg: Apud Ioh. Petreium.
Dobrzycki, Jerzy and Richard L. Kremer. 1996. “Peurbach and Marāgha Astronomy? The Ephemerides
of Johannes Angelus and Their Implications.” Journal for the History of Astronomy 27:187–237.
Al-Ghazālı̄, Abū Hāmid Muhammad ibn Muhammad. 1506. Logica et philosophia Algazelis Arabis.Venice:
P. Liechtenstein. ˙ Facsimile ˙ reproduction with
˙ introduction by C. H. Lohr, Frankfurt am Main:
Minerva, 1969.
Al-Ghazālı̄, Abū Hāmid Muhammad ibn Muhammad. 1960–1. Maqāsid al-falāsifa. Edited by Sulaymān
Dunyā. Cairo: Dār˙ al-ma ārif.˙ ˙ ˙
Grant, Edward. 1994. Planets, Stars, and Orbs: The Medieval Cosmos 1200–1687. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Grant, Edward, ed. 1974. A Source Book in Medieval Science. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Haidarzadeh, Tofigh. 1997. “The Astronomical Works of Alı̄ Qūshjı̄” (in Turkish). M.A. thesis, Istanbul
University.
Hellman, C. Doris. 1944. The Comet of 1577: Its Place in the History of Astronomy. New York: Columbia
University Press.
Ibn Sı̄nā, Abū Alı̄ al-Husayn b. Abd Allāh. 1965 (or 1964?). Al-Shifā . Al-Maādin wa-’l-āthār
al-alawiyya (part 5 of ˙Natural Philosophy). Edited by Abd al-Halı̄m Muntasir, Saı̄d Zāyid, and
˙ ˙
Abdallāh Ismāı̄l. Cairo: al-Haya al-āmma li-shuūn al-matābi al-amı̄riyya.
˙
Ibn Sı̄nā, Abū Alı̄ al-Husayn b. Abd Allāh. 1969. Al-Shifā . Al-Samā wa-’l-ālam (part 2 of Natural
Philosophy). Edited by ˙ Mahmūd Qāsim. Cairo: Dār al-kātib al- arabı̄ li-’l-tibā a wa-’l-nashr.
Ibn Sı̄nā, Abū Alı̄ al-Husayn˙ b. Abd Allāh. 1980. Al-Shifā . Ilm al-hay a (part
˙ 4 of Mathematics [al-
˙
Riyādiyyāt]). Edited by Muhammad Madwar and Imām Ibrāhı̄m Ahmad. Cairo: al-Haya al-misriyya
˙
al-āmma li-’l-kitāb. ˙ ˙ ˙
Ihsanoǧlu, Ekmeleddin, et al. 1997. Osmanlı Astronomi Literatürü Tarihi, 2 vols. Istanbul: IRCICA.
Jervis, Jane. 1985. Cometary Theory in Fifteenth-Century Europe. Studia Copernicana, vol. 26. Dordrecht:
D. Reidel.
Al-Jurjānı̄, al-Sayyid al-Sharı̄f. Sharh al-Tadhkira, Damascus, Zāhiriyya MS 3117.
Langermann, Y. Tzvi. 1996. “Medieval ˙ Hebrew Texts on˙ the Quadrature of the Lune.” Historia
Mathematica 23:31–53.
Lévy, Tony. 1992. “Gersonide, commentateur d’Euclide: traduction annotée de ses gloses sur les
Éléments.” In Studies on Gersonides: A Fourteenth-Century Jewish Philosopher-Scientist, edited by G.
Freudenthal, 83–147. Leiden: E. J. Brill.
Lloyd, Geoffrey E. R. 1991. “Saving the Appearances.” In idem, Methods and Problems in Greek Science,
248–277. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Originally appeared (without the introduction)
in Classical Quarterly 28 (1978):202–222.
Meyerhof, Max. 1935. “Ibn al-Nafı̄s (XIIIth century) and His Theory of the Lesser Circulation.” Isis
23:100–120.
Oresme, Nicole. 1968. Le Livre du ciel et du monde. Edited by A. D. Menut and A. J. Denomy. Translated
with an introduction by A. D. Menut. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.
Pines, Shlomo. 1956. “La théorie de la rotation de la terre à l’époque d’al-Bı̄rūnı̄.” Journal Asiatique
244:301–306. Reprinted, 1986, in The Collected Works of Shlomo Pines, vol. II. Jerusalem and Leiden.
Pingree, David 1996. “Indian Reception of Muslim Versions of Ptolemaic Astronomy.” In Tradition,
Transmission, Transformation, edited by F. J. and S. P. Ragep, 471–485. Leiden: E. J. Brill.
Al-Qūshjı̄, Alı̄ b. Muhammad. 1890 (?). Sharh Tajrı̄d al-aqā ı̄d. Tehran.
Ragep, F. Jamil. 1990. ˙“Duhem, the Arabs, and˙ the History of Cosmology.” Synthese 83:201–214.
Ragep, F. Jamil. 1993. Nası̄r al-Dı̄n al-Tūsı̄’s Memoir on Astronomy (al-Tadhkira fı̄ ilm al- hay a), 2 vols.
New York: Springer-Verlag. ˙ ˙
Ragep, F. Jamil. 1996. “Al-Battānı̄, Cosmology, and the Early History of Trepidation in Islam.” In From
Baghdad to Barcelona. Essays on the History of the Islamic Exact Sciences in Honour of Prof. Juan Vernet,
162
Tūsī and Copernicus: The Earth’s Motion in Context 297
163
F. Jamil Ragep - 9789047412441
Downloaded from Brill.com11/17/2021 08:16:24PM
via McGill University
300 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
787
F. Jamil Ragep - 9789047412441
Downloaded from Brill.com11/17/2021 08:16:24PM
via McGill University
Ibn al-Haytham and Eudoxus: The Revival of Homocentric Modeling in Islam 301
788
F. Jamil Ragep - 9789047412441
Downloaded from Brill.com11/17/2021 08:16:24PM
via McGill University
302 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
789
F. Jamil Ragep - 9789047412441
Downloaded from Brill.com11/17/2021 08:16:24PM
via McGill University
Ibn al-Haytham and Eudoxus: The Revival of Homocentric Modeling in Islam 303
790
F. Jamil Ragep - 9789047412441
Downloaded from Brill.com11/17/2021 08:16:24PM
via McGill University
304 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
791
F. Jamil Ragep - 9789047412441
Downloaded from Brill.com11/17/2021 08:16:24PM
via McGill University
Ibn al-Haytham and Eudoxus: The Revival of Homocentric Modeling in Islam 305
792
F. Jamil Ragep - 9789047412441
Downloaded from Brill.com11/17/2021 08:16:24PM
via McGill University
306 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
793
F. Jamil Ragep - 9789047412441
Downloaded from Brill.com11/17/2021 08:16:24PM
via McGill University
Ibn al-Haytham and Eudoxus: The Revival of Homocentric Modeling in Islam 307
794
F. Jamil Ragep - 9789047412441
Downloaded from Brill.com11/17/2021 08:16:24PM
via McGill University
308 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
795
F. Jamil Ragep - 9789047412441
Downloaded from Brill.com11/17/2021 08:16:24PM
via McGill University
Ibn al-Haytham and Eudoxus: The Revival of Homocentric Modeling in Islam 309
796
F. Jamil Ragep - 9789047412441
Downloaded from Brill.com11/17/2021 08:16:24PM
via McGill University
310 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
797
F. Jamil Ragep - 9789047412441
Downloaded from Brill.com11/17/2021 08:16:24PM
via McGill University
Ibn al-Haytham and Eudoxus: The Revival of Homocentric Modeling in Islam 311
798
F. Jamil Ragep - 9789047412441
Downloaded from Brill.com11/17/2021 08:16:24PM
via McGill University
312 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
799
F. Jamil Ragep - 9789047412441
Downloaded from Brill.com11/17/2021 08:16:24PM
via McGill University
Ibn al-Haytham and Eudoxus: The Revival of Homocentric Modeling in Islam 313
800
F. Jamil Ragep - 9789047412441
Downloaded from Brill.com11/17/2021 08:16:24PM
via McGill University
314 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
801
F. Jamil Ragep - 9789047412441
Downloaded from Brill.com11/17/2021 08:16:24PM
via McGill University
Ibn al-Haytham and Eudoxus: The Revival of Homocentric Modeling in Islam 315
802
F. Jamil Ragep - 9789047412441
Downloaded from Brill.com11/17/2021 08:16:24PM
via McGill University
316 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
803
F. Jamil Ragep - 9789047412441
Downloaded from Brill.com11/17/2021 08:16:24PM
via McGill University
Ibn al-Haytham and Eudoxus: The Revival of Homocentric Modeling in Islam 317
804
F. Jamil Ragep - 9789047412441
Downloaded from Brill.com11/17/2021 08:16:24PM
via McGill University
318 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
805
F. Jamil Ragep - 9789047412441
Downloaded from Brill.com11/17/2021 08:16:24PM
via McGill University
Ibn al-Haytham and Eudoxus: The Revival of Homocentric Modeling in Islam 319
806
F. Jamil Ragep - 9789047412441
Downloaded from Brill.com11/17/2021 08:16:24PM
via McGill University
320 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
807
F. Jamil Ragep - 9789047412441
Downloaded from Brill.com11/17/2021 08:16:24PM
via McGill University
Ibn al-Haytham and Eudoxus: The Revival of Homocentric Modeling in Islam 321
808
F. Jamil Ragep - 9789047412441
Downloaded from Brill.com11/17/2021 08:16:24PM
via McGill University
322 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
809
F. Jamil Ragep - 9789047412441
Downloaded from Brill.com11/17/2021 08:16:24PM
via McGill University
324 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
268
Al-Battānī, Cosmology, and the Early History of Trepidation in Islam 325
269
326 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
270
Al-Battānī, Cosmology, and the Early History of Trepidation in Islam 327
271
328 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
272
Al-Battānī, Cosmology, and the Early History of Trepidation in Islam 329
273
330 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
274
Al-Battānī, Cosmology, and the Early History of Trepidation in Islam 331
275
332 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
276
Al-Battānī, Cosmology, and the Early History of Trepidation in Islam 333
277
334 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
278
Al-Battānī, Cosmology, and the Early History of Trepidation in Islam 335
279
336 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
280
Al-Battānī, Cosmology, and the Early History of Trepidation in Islam 337
281
338 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
282
Al-Battānī, Cosmology, and the Early History of Trepidation in Islam 339
283
340 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
284
Al-Battānī, Cosmology, and the Early History of Trepidation in Islam 341
285
342 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
286
Al-Battānī, Cosmology, and the Early History of Trepidation in Islam 343
287
344 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
288
Al-Battānī, Cosmology, and the Early History of Trepidation in Islam 345
289
346 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
290
Al-Battānī, Cosmology, and the Early History of Trepidation in Islam 347
291
348 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
292
Al-Battānī, Cosmology, and the Early History of Trepidation in Islam 349
293
350 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
294
Al-Battānī, Cosmology, and the Early History of Trepidation in Islam 351
295
352 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
296
Al-Battānī, Cosmology, and the Early History of Trepidation in Islam 353
297
354 Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
298
Index for Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus 355
INDEX
Andalusia, 9, 15, 107, 188, 194, 210, 131, 136, 137, 138, 139, 144, 145, 147,
259, 304 149, 150, 151, 152, 153, 154, 155, 156,
158, 159, 160, 161, 162, 163, 166, 167,
Andalusian Revolt, 9, 15, 194, 210
170, 191, 194, 202, 207, 210, 239, 247,
Angelus, Johannes, 17, 84, 296 262, 269, 276, 277, 279, 282, 283, 291,
animal, 26, 133, 165 295, 300, 303, 304, 321, 323, 327, 328,
329, 330, 332, 336, 340, 342, 348, 352,
anomaly, anomalies, xii, xiii, 5, 133,
353
176, 177, 178, 183, 184, 187, 189, 190,
191, 192, 193, 212, 230, 231, 232, 237, Arabs, 7, 31, 109, 151, 159, 296
265, 267, 269, 270, 271, 277, 280 Archimedes, 46
anomaly, first, xii, 5, 133, 176, 177, 178, Aristarchuses; Aristarchus, 18, 30, 54,
187, 190, 191, 193, 230, 231 135, 320,
anomaly, second, xii, 5, 176, 183, 184, Aristotelian, x, 9, 10, 11, 14, 16, 22, 25,
187, 190, 192, 193, 230, 231, 232, 265, 267, 31, 32, 34, 38, 100, 104, 106, 107, 109,
269, 280 113, 133, 176, 188, 191, 193, 194, 195,
Antares, 47 199, 210, 226, 239, 267, 269, 282, 283,
290, 291, 292, 294, 295, 304
Antiquity, xiv, 30, 43, 45, 47, 48, 55,
288, 294, 329 Aristotle, xiii, 10, 23, 26, 30, 31, 35, 45,
46, 71, 75, 134, 137, 259, 267, 282, 283,
Antiquity, late, 55
287, 288, 292, 293, 295, 303, 304, 305
apex; apices, 72, 81, 102, 116, 117, 122,
Arkand, 335
124, 128, 129, 130, 134, 191, 200, 212,
215, 216, 218, 219, 243, 267, 270, 271, arrangement, 6, 41, 71, 119, 129, 183,
301, 302, 315, 316, 317, 318, 319 190, 195, 205, 303
apogee, 69, 89, 98, 99, 118, 119, 121, Āryabhaṭa, 285, 291
122, 125, 126, 132, 193, 200, 204, 205, Ashʿarite, 25, 26, 27, 28, 33,
206, 209, 212, 216, 218, 219, 231, 236,
al-Ashiʿʿa al-lāmiʿa fī l-ʿamal bi-l-jāmiʿa,
242, 244, 245, 246, 270, 271, 277, 317,
261
323, 342
aṣl; device, x, xi, xii, 3, 4, 5, 6, 8, 9,
apologetics, 21
12,15, 16, 17, 18, 35, 51, 63, 64, 66, 67,
appropriate judgments, 24 68, 70, 72, 76, 79, 84, 85, 86, 87, 88, 89,
appropriation, 14, 21, 26, 54 93, 95, 97, 98, 102, 103, 104, 109, 114,
130, 139, 145, 153, 163, 164, 182, 184,
ʿaql, 290
187, 188, 191, 193, 207, 210, 216, 229,
Arabic, ix, 6, 15, 16, 17, 19, 21, 24, 25, 230, 236, 268, 279, 283, 304, 331
27, 28, 32, 33, 34, 53, 59, 64, 67, 77, 78,
Assyrian, 47
84, 89, 91, 94, 95, 96, 102, 107, 108, 113,
astral science, 24
Index for Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus 357
astrolabe, 150, 151, 152, 161, 167, 260, astronomy, mathematical, x, xi, xii, 16,
261, 262, 289, 329, 353 19, 24, 105, 107, 108, 138, 153, 162, 171,
190, 192, 193, 194, 202, 220, 229, 230,
astrologer, 53, 79, 82, 325, 333, 334
231, 242, 262, 276, 282, 287, 288, 289,
astrology, 24, 25, 31, 33, 150, 160, 241, 297, 321, 324, 348, 353, 354
275, 276, 295, 330, 333, 352
astronomy, non-Ptolemaic, 269
astronomer, 156, 158, 167, 169, 170
astronomy, Ptolemaic, 4, 8, 13, 15, 24,
astronomia, 24 27, 35, 63, 99, 133, 188, 191, 194, 204,
astronomy, v, vi, ix, x, xi, xii, xiii, xiv, 210, 239, 240, 276, 296, 304, 348
xv, xvi, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9, 10, 11, 13, 14, astronomy, Renaissance , 175
15, 16, 17, 18, 19, 21, 22, 23, 24, 25, 26,
Athens, 299
27, 28, 29, 30, 31, 32, 33, 34, 35, 37, 39,
53, 54, 55, 46, 57, 58, 59, 63, 64, 66, 84, Augustus, 326, 327, 338, 349
85, 86, 90, 91, 97, 98, 99, 102, 103, 105,
Averroism, 175, 188, 194
107, 108, 111, 113, 115, 116, 133, 134,
137, 138, 139, 147, 149, 150, 151, 152, Averroist, 98, 109, 194, 195
153, 154, 155, 156, 158, 159, 160, 161, Avignon, 91
162, 166, 169, 170, 171, 175, 187, 188,
Avner de Burgos; Alfonso de
189, 190, 191, 192, 193, 194, 195, 199,
Valladolid, 79, 92
202, 203, 204, 207, 209, 210, 211, 212,
220, 222, 228, 229, 230, 231, 238, 239, Azerbaijan, 139, 156, 158, 159, 166, 168
240, 241, 242, 258, 259, 260, 262, 265,
al-Azhar, 29, 258
266, 267, 269, 275, 276, 279, 280, 281,
282, 287, 288, 289, 290, 291, 292, 293,
294, 295, 296, 297, 299, 304, 305, 315, B
320, 321, 323, 324, 330, 334, 336, 340,
348, 352, 353, 354 Babylonian, 45, 47, 97, 327, 330, 331,
342, 350, 352
astronomy, Byzantine, 91, 149, 151,
161, 170 Bāgh Barakah, 66
De caelo, 10, 23, 30, 31, 134, 137, 287, direct motion, 270, 271, 277, 325
289, 292, 293
dirigent; mudīr, 67, 69, 177, 205, 208,
De motibus corporum coelestium, 85 209, 212, 216, 217, 219, 227, 243
De motu octavae sphaerae; De motu Dobrzycki, Jerzy, 7, 84, 137, 296
octave spere, 84, 323
double epicycle device, 207
De revolutionibus, xii, xiii, xiv, 3, 6, 7, 8,
double epicycle model, 225
11, 15, 16, 18, 32, 34, 35, 85, 86, 88, 99,
105, 145, 153, 162, 171, 175, 180, 181, Dreyer, J. L. E., x, 3, 15, 137
182, 187, 189, 190, 192, 193, 194, 197, Droppers, Garrett, 79
198, 199, 201, 202, 212, 216, 220, 223,
Duran, Profiat, 195
228, 229, 230, 231, 236, 242, 262, 275,
279, 280, 294, 296, 297, 324, 354 E
deferent; ḥāmil, 4, 5, 6, 8, 15, 41, 65, 67, Earth (the body), x, xiii, 3, 4, 5, 7, 9, 10,
68, 69, 79, 80, 81, 82, 83, 102, 103, 111, 11, 27, 30, 32, 34, 36, 37, 39, 44, 46, 47,
112, 113, 117, 118, 119, 121, 122, 123, 51, 54, 57, 58, 107, 117, 123, 176, 177,
124, 126, 127, 128, 129, 130, 132, 136, 178, 180, 182, 183, 184, 188, 189, 191,
140, 142, 143, 144, 147, 163, 164, 166, 197, 200, 203, 204, 205, 211, 218, 220,
175, 176, 177, 178, 180, 181, 182, 183, 223, 225, 226, 233, 235, 237, 238, 247,
188, 200, 204, 205, 206, 208, 209, 212, 259, 279, 280, 281, 282, 285, 286, 287,
215, 216, 217, 219, 223, 225, 226, 227, 288, 289, 290, 291, 292, 293, 294
233, 242, 243, 244, 267, 270, 271, 277,
earth (the element), xiii, 11, 29, 30, 164,
301, 316, 318, 319
165, 192, 235, 236, 280, 281, 282, 294
degree, 7, 16, 23, 32, 45, 46, 47, 51, 86,
Earth’s immobility/statis, 11
122, 123, 144, 152, 161, 212, 217, 242,
243, 333, 349, 351 Earth’s rotation, 13, 18, 34, 267, 269,
276, 279, 280, 282, 284, 286, 287, 288,
demonstration, 25, 37, 85
291, 292, 293, 294
depression, 334, 335
eccentric, xii, 5, 13, 41, 72, 93, 119, 122,
deviation, 4, 86, 102, 122, 127, 129, 133, 132, 142, 163, 175, 176, 183, 184, 189,
136, 221, 301, 316 190, 192, 193, 199, 204, 206, 210, 223,
230, 231, 232, 233, 235, 259, 265, 267,
devices, mathematical, 63
268, 269, 270, 271, 276, 277, 290, 302,
Dialectics, 149 304, 315, 316, 317, 343
diameter, 4, 5, 72, 75, 77, 112, 114, 117, eccentric hypothesis, 267, 269, 270,
119, 124, 126, 127, 130, 185, 218, 229, 271, 277
231, 315, 316, 317, 319
eccentricitas, 175, 176, 183, 184, 192,
dictionary; dictionaries, 31, 155, 170, 232, 233, 235,
262, 297, 321, 352, 353
Index for Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus 361
eccentricity; eccentricities, 6, 119, 120, Epitome of the Almagest, xiii, 13, 175,
122, 135, 176, 177, 183, 184, 185, 186, 265
190, 192, 216, 229, 231, 235, 238, 232,
equant, xii, 4, 5, 8, 9, 15, 17, 18, 64, 65,
233, 235, 238
98, 102, 109, 118, 119, 122, 123, 127,
eclipse, 26, 27, 34, 37, 39 134, 138, 139, 147, 153, 175, 176, 177,
178, 180, 187, 188, 193, 205, 206, 207,
ecliptic, xiii, 4, 43, 50, 51, 57, 65, 71, 85,
208, 210, 211, 212, 215, 218, 219, 226,
118, 130, 243, 259, 303, 323, 327, 328,
230, 231, 239, 275, 279, 300, 301, 304,
330, 331, 332, 333, 335, 337, 338, 340,
316, 317, 318
341, 345, 346, 349
equation, 125, 143, 176, 183, 184, 186,
Egypt, 28, 139, 158, 258, 262
218, 226, 227, 228, 238, 240, 259, 270,
element, xiii, 11, 32, 165, 280, 348 271, 277
Elements, 7, 87, 91, 144, 296, 333 equator, 116, 118, 119, 120, 121, 130,
Elements of Astrology, 330, 333, 352 135, 242, 243, 271, 277, 283, 284, 315,
317, 319
elevation, 334, 335
equinox; equinoxes, xiii, 48, 49, 70,
elongation, 41, 122, 197, 204, 218, 220,
130, 323, 325, 326, 327, 329, 330, 331,
226, 227, 228, 240, 270
332, 342, 347, 354
enclosing orb; al-muḥīṭa, 69, 81, 130,
Eratosthenes, 44, 45, 46, 47, 51, 52, 57,
133, 243 ; 69, 104, 117
58
enclosing sphere; kura muḥīṭa, 67, 81,
essence, 4, 10, 25, 28, 30, 80, 231, 261
104, 116, 117, 120, 121, 122, 131, 133,
244 essentialism, 21, 22
epicycle, epicyclic; al-tadwīr, xii, 4, 5, 6, Euclid, 7, 52, 87, 91, 107, 144, 296
65, 67, 69, 71, 72, 73, 74, 75, 77, 79, 80, Eudoxan-couple, 74, 76, 78, 84, 89, 90,
81, 82, 83, 84, 88, 98, 100, 102, 112, 113, 92, 98, 207
114, 115, 116, 117, 118, 119, 120, 122, 123,
Eudoxus, xiii, 15, 101, 102, 103, 136,
124, 125, 126, 127, 128, 129, 130, 131,
147, 188, 207, 299, 301, 303, 304
132, 133, 136, 140, 142, 143, 163, 176,
177, 178, 180, 182, 183, 184, 185, 186, Eurocentric, 28, 95
190, 191, 192, 193, 200, 204, 205, 206,
Europe, v, vi, ix, xiii, xiv, 4, 8, 9, 13, 14,
207, 212, 215, 216, 217, 218, 219, 223,
22, 29, 35, 75, 78, 79, 84, 88, 91, 93, 95,
225, 226, 231, 232, 233, 235, 236, 237,
96, 99, 105, 108, 154, 157, 188, 193, 194,
238, 243, 244, 265, 267, 270, 271, 276,
204, 210, 257, 262, 265, 269, 279, 283,
277, 301, 302, 303, 315, 316, 317, 318
284, 288, 293, 294, 295, 296, 299
epicyclic hypothesis, 41, 267, 270, 271,
European science, 36
290
362 Index for Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
ḥiss, 41, 287 Ibn Naḥmias, Joseph, 12, 64, 84, 92,
102, 195, 210
history of science, xv, 4, 7, 12, 16, 17,
21, 28, 70, 77, 97, 107, 158, 193, 268, Ibn Rushd; Averroes, 9, 15, 131, 188,
275, 295 194, 210, 259
Ibn al-Shāṭir, ʿAlāʾ al-Dīn al-Awsī;
364 Index for Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
Shāṭir; Ibn al-Šāṭir, xi, xii, 23, 197, 198, Indian Group, 52
199, 200, 202, 203, 207, 211, 212, 213,
inertia, 36, 287
215, 216, 217, 218, 219, 220, 221, 222,
223, 224, 225, 226, 227, 228, 229, 230, innate principle, 31
231, 232, 233, 234, 235, 236, 237, 238, inner equators, 80, 116, 212, 214, 215,
239, 240, 241, 242, 243, 247 216
Ibn Sīnā, Abū ʿAlī; Avicenna, 4, 15, 24, innī; quia; fact, 6, 7, 8, 10, 11, 30, 31, 32,
28, 51, 52, 55, 58, 134, 138, 207, 282 35, 36, 39, 46, 48, 51, 68, 70, 73, 75, 81,
Ibn Ṭufayl, 9 86, 89, 92, 97, 98, 102,103, 111, 112, 130,
143, 144, 145, 152, 153, 156, 161, 175,
Ibn Yūnus, 47, 338
183, 187, 188, 189, 194, 195, 198, 212,
Ibrāhīm ibn Sinān, 323, 346, 358 227, 228, 230, 232, 235, 236, 237, 240,
242, 266, 267, 282, 286, 292, 293, 301,
Īḍāḥ al-mughayyab fī l-ʿamal bi-l-rubʿ
302, 316, 329, 330, 341
al-mujayyab, 261
innovation, 7, 95, 191, 194, 329
Iḥtimālāt, 39
instrument, 25, 50, 133, 258, 261
al-Ījī, ʿAḍud al-Dīn; Ījī, 27
instrumentalism, instrumentalist, 26,
Ikhtiyārāt-i Muẓaffarī, 94
23, 24, 28, 29, 35, 288, 331
ilāhiyya, 290
irāda, 27
Īlkhānid, 67, 91, 96, 149, 150, 154, 159,
Iran, 11, 28, 33, 58, 63, 65, 67, 89, 91,
164, 171
96, 107, 113, 142, 144, 149, 164, 167,
ʿilm; ʿulūm, x, 64, 67, 107, 144, 145, 170, 299, 300
147, 150, 166, 194, 195
Iranians, 154
ʿilm al-nujūm; science of the stars, 24
irregularity; irregularities, 8, 34, 37,
imaginary things; umūr mawhūma, 27 39, 41, 97, 109, 188, 193, 260, 301, 318
impulse , 281 Irshād al-qāṣid, 300
imtiḥān, 53 Isḥāq; Isḥāq ibn Ḥunayn; Isḥāq b.
inclination, 85, 125, 127, 128, 129, 130, Ḥunayn, 48, 53, 330, 332, 338, 339
189, 230, 242, 281, 289, 290, 291, 294, al-Ishārāt al-ʿimādiyya fī l-mawāqīt al-
315, 316, 318, 319 sharʿiyya; 261
inclined orb (māʾil), 68, 69, 74, 78, 117, al-Ishārāt wa-al-tanbīhāt, 144
118, 121, 130, 136, 144, 164, 166, 176,
ishkālāt, 111, 113, 114, 124, 140
183, 219, 242, 244, 316, 319
Isis, 111, 198
India, 157, 159, 285, 295, 335, 354
Islam, v, vi, ix, x, xi, xii, xiii, xiv, 4, 11,
Indian Circle, 143
14, 15, 17, 19, 21, 22, 23, 24, 25, 26, 28,
Index for Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus 365
33, 36, 54, 55, 58, 84, 92, 95, 97, 98, 99, Jones, Alexander, 50, 57, 139, 202, 330,
136, 137, 147, 150, 152, 155, 157, 158, 352
159, 162, 170, 171, 189, 191, 202, 207,
Judeo-Arabic, 84
211, 257, 260, 269, 275, 276, 279, 280,
282, 285, 288, 293, 296, 297, 299, 301, Jupiter, 120, 124, 135, 183, 185, 232, 265
303, 304, 305 Jurjān, 52
Islamdom, 299 Jurjānī; al-Jurjānī, al-Sharīf; al-Sayyid
Islamic civilization, 7, 17, 22, 23, 36, al-Sharīf ʿAlī ibn Muḥammad ibn ʿAlī
262 al-Ḥusaynī al-Jurjānī; al-Sayyid al-
Sharīf al-Jurjānī, 29, 94, 131, 137, 266,
Islamic East, 4, 35, 210
284, 293, 296
Islamic jurisprudence; uṣūl al-fiqh, 55
al-Jūzjānī, ʿAbd al-Wāḥid; Jūzjānī,
Islamic science, vi, vii, ix, x, xi, xii, xiii, al-Jūzjānī, Abū ʿUbayd, 4, 15, 51, 134,
xiv, 7, 16, 22, 25, 36, 55, 95, 106, 144, 138, 207
158, 188, 191, 262, 295, 331
Islamic world, 6, 8, 9, 14, 21, 36, 43, 96,
K
98, 207, 210, 258, 265, 275, 283, 284
kalām, 26, 27, 29, 57
Islamist, 7, 36
Kansas, 47
Ismaʿili court, 164
Kashf al-mughayyab fī l-ḥisāb bi-l-rubʿ
Ismāʿīlī governor, 65, 300
al-mujayyab, 261
iʿtabara, 53
Kashf-i ḥaqāʾiq-i Zīj-i Īlkhānī, 169
Italy, 6, 78, 87, 91, 92, 99, 108, 145, 187,
Kāshī, Jamshīd al-Kāshī, 157, 266, 276
195, 260, 266, 276, 295
Kashmir, 159
ithbāt, 31, 37
Kennedy, E. S., 162, 176, 187, 190, 191,
iʿtibār, 53, 290
192, 198, 202, 212, 275, 276, 304, 321,
ʿiyān, 34, 41 335, 352
Kepler, 7, 15, 16, 31, 137
J al-Khafrī, Shams al-Dīn; Shams al-Dīn
Muḥammad ibn Aḥmad al-Khafrī, 4,
al-Jaghmīnī, Sharaf al-Dīn Maḥmūd,
17, 35, 75, 94, 102, 134, 136, 137, 239
162
al-Kharaqī; al-Khiraqī; Khiraqī, 162,
Jewish, 79, 84, 92, 96, 187, 194, 210,
300, 318
260, 295, 296
khāṣṣa, 212
Jewish intermediaries, 92, 96
John of Damascus, 149
366 Index for Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
Khāzinī; ʿAbd al-Raḥmān al-Khāzinī, latitude, x, xi, xiii, 45, 47, 50, 51, 65, 70,
151, 152, 160, 161 72, 73, 74, 78, 85, 89, 102, 107, 112, 126,
127, 128, 130, 136, 142, 143, 202, 229,
Khujandī, 51, 52
300, 301
Khurāsān, 66, 143
latitude model, 4, 71, 86, 140, 145, 303
Khwārazmī, 337
latitude, planetary, xi, xiii, 4
Kindī; al-Kindī, 55
law, 23, 26, 37, 55, 112, 295
King, David, 21, 22, 23, 25, 275
Le Livre du ciel et du monde, 283, 293,
Kitāb al-manāẓir, 53 296
Kitāb al-qirānāt, 336 Leichter, Joseph, 107, 151, 161
Kitāb fī al-hayʾa, 347 Lerner, Michel-Pierre, 105, 198
Kitāb fī ḥarakāt al-shams, 323, 346, 352 Lévy, Tony, 91, 107, 296
Kitāb fī ʿilal al-zījāt, 334, 335, 352 The Light of the World, 84, 194, 195
Kitāb fī l-ḥisāb, 262 limmī; propter quid; reasoned fact
Kitāb fī l-misāḥa, 262 10, 31, 292
Kitāb-i Maʿrifat-i usṭurlāb-i shamālī, 167 logic, 16, 21, 25, 88, 97, 98, 105, 109,
194, 210
Komnenos; John II Komnenos, 149,
155 Logica et philosophia, 283, 296
Kremer, Richard, 7, 17, 18, 84, 99, 104, longitude, 6, 52, 65, 71, 72, 85, 127,
109, 295, 296 128, 129, 136, 140, 190, 226, 237, 301,
318, 323, 325, 326, 327, 337
Kren, Claudia, 79, 80, 81, 82, 103, 104
longitude model, 86, 112, 189
Kugler, Franz, 97
longitudinal motion, ix, 71, 140
Kuhn, Thomas, 54
Lutheran, 35
L
M
Langermann, Tzvi, 57, 79, 92, 96, 102,
103, 107, 187, 193, 260, 262, 295, 296, mabdaʾ, 39
299, 321, 337 madrasa, 33, 266
Latin, vii, 3, 5, 6, 28, 53, 75, 78, 84, 91, al-Maghribī, Muḥyī al-Dīn; Muḥyī
95, 98, 103, 109, 154, 188, 189, 194, 204, l-Dīn al-Maghribī; Muḥyī al-Dīn ibn
235, 276, 279, 282, 283, 295, 297, 321, Abī al-Shukr al-Maghribī; Maghribī
323, 324, 327, 328, 330, 336, 348 107, 152, 157, 158, 161,169
Latin West, 7, 91, 97, 98, 99, 106, 195, 305
Index for Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus 367
Maqāla fī qurb falak al-burūj min mean motion, 68, 144, 166, 176, 177,
muʿaddil al-nahār, 258, 259 180, 182, 197, 200, 203, 206, 212, 217,
227, 267, 270, 271, 277, 350
Marāgha, 6, 7, 15, 17, 33, 74, 84, 86,
104, 105, 109, 113, 152, 156, 161, 171, mean Sun, 177, 180, 181, 182, 183, 184,
187, 190, 192, 193, 211, 231, 236, 238, 188, 190, 192, 200, 206, 216, 220, 223,
239, 240, 259, 295, 296 226, 229, 233, 235, 270, 271, 277
Marāgha Observatory, 113, 139, 157, measurement, 44, 45, 46, 51, 57, 58,
158, 168, 295 260, 351
Mehmed II; Mehmet the Conqueror 111, 117, 122, 134, 144, 145, 153, 163,
34, 95, 96, 284, 291 164, 166, 190, 198
Meliteniotes, Theodore, 154 model, mathematical, x, 3, 4, 8, 13, 17,
112, 275, 279, 330, 340
Mercier, Raymond, 150, 152, 156, 161,
162, 170 model, planetary, xi, 4, 6, 23, 64, 67,
68, 78, 82, 87, 97, 115, 118, 120, 123,
Mercury, xii, 13, 41, 65, 66, 87, 93, 107,
139, 145, 175, 176, 190, 198, 232, 235,
119, 122, 127, 130, 135, 144, 180, 182,
239, 260, 267, 302
183, 184, 185, 186, 187, 191, 192, 194,
197, 198, 199, 200, 201, 202, 203, 204, models, non-Ptolemaic, 96, 113, 134
205, 206, 207, 208, 211, 213, 215, 216,
modeling, homocentric, xii, xiii, 15,
217, 218, 219, 220, 222, 223, 224, 225,
147, 207, 299, 301, 303, 304, 305
226, 227, 228, 229, 230, 231, 232, 233,
235, 236, 237, 238, 239, 240, 241, 242, models, Ptolemaic, 7, 18, 96, 99, 109,
243, 244, 245, 247, 265, 267, 269, 275, 113, 122, 134, 140, 188, 194, 242, 258,
276 259, 279
Mesopotamia, 47 monolithic, 29
motion, irregular, xii, 5, 9, 65, 74, 87, mutakallim, theologian, 14, 25, 55
97, 99, 102, 111, 113, 130, 140, 143, 175,
Muʿtazilite, 26
176, 177, 178, 187, 230, 279, 300, 301,
316
motion, longitudinal, xi, 71, 140 N
motion, natural, 26, 32, 112, 285, 291, Nabonassar, 49, 341, 350
294 al-Nafʿ al-ʿāmm fī l-ʿamal bi-l-rubʿ al-
motion, oscillating straight-line, 66 tāmm, 260
Muslim, 15, 23, 25, 26, 27, 28, 35, 55, al-Nīsābūrī, Niẓām al-Dīn; Ḥasan ibn
57, 95, 96, 113, 167, 169, 296, 324 Muḥammad ibn al-Ḥusayn Niẓām al-
Dīn al-Aʿraj al-Nīsābūrī, 94, 159
al-Muṭaʿʿim, 258
370 Index for Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
nodes, 118, 122 281, 283, 284, 303, 315, 316, 317, 318,
319, 327, 328, 329, 330, 331, 333, 334,
normal science, 17, 54
335, 337, 338, 340, 341, 342, 343, 345,
Nuzhat al-sāmiʿ fī l-ʿamal bi-l-rubʿ al- 346, 349, 351
jāmiʿ, 260
orbit, 85, 86, 182, 184, 187, 192, 220,
223, 229, 230, 233, 235, 236, 237
O Oresme, Nicole 18, 67, 79, 92, 283, 287
obliquity, 51, 52, 53, 54, 57, 74, 85, 86, oscillation, xi, 4, 5, 64, 82, 85, 89, 102,
130, 142, 259, 323 112, 113, 114, 116, 119, 122, 124, 126,
obliquity, total, 142 130, 136, 140, 187, 300, 323, 327
observation, x, xiv, 4, 10, 11, 16, 29, 30, oscillation, curvilinear, xi, 64, 70, 73,
31, 32, 33, 34, 36, 43, 44, 45, 46, 48, 49, 85, 99, 102, 140, 145, 300
51, 52, 53, 54, 56, 64, 123, 124, 139, 144, oscillation, rectilinear, xi, 64, 72, 113,
150, 151, 152, 157, 158, 160, 161, 162, 122
167, 168, 191, 204, 210, 211, 216, 220,
oscillation, straight-line, 92
229, 240, 241, 242, 243, 258, 260, 267,
277, 285, 286, 287, 288, 289, 290, 292, oscillatory trepidation motion, 48, 49
293, 335, 339, 340, 346, 347, 348, 350,
Osiander, Andreas, 35
351
Ottomans, 11, 27, 33, 93, 96, 275, 284
Observatoire National, 261
occasionalism, 22, 288, 293
P
Öljeytü, 157, 167, 168
Padua, 18, 91, 187, 188
omnipotence, 22
Palmyra, 47
Omnipotent, 27, 37, 39
parallelism, vi, 14
On the Genethlialogical Computation, 151
parecliptic; mumaththal, 41, 68, 69, 117,
On the Orthodox Faith, 149
118, 119, 121, 205, 208, 212, 217, 218,
On the Sphere of the World, 79 242, 243, 244
oppositions, 41 Paris, 15, 23, 33, 58, 59, 137, 149, 198,
261, 287, 352, 353
orb, 4, 32, 37, 41, 48, 49, 51, 67, 68, 69,
74, 78, 81, 82, 86, 100, 106, 111, 116, Paschos, E.A., 16, 102, 103, 151, 161,
117, 118, 119, 121, 129, 130, 131, 133, 162, 163, 165, 166, 170
136, 140, 142, 144, 164, 166, 176, 177,
Penchèvre, E., 202, 216, 242
178, 183, 184, 185, 186, 188, 195, 212,
213, 216, 217, 219, 220, 223, 226, 232, perception, 17, 21, 34, 41, 165
233, 237, 238, 242, 243, 244, 260, 270, perigee, 116, 118, 119, 122, 124, 125,
Index for Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus 371
126, 128, 129, 130, 191, 209, 216, 241, 149, 150, 151, 156, 160, 207, 276, 299,
242, 244, 245, 246, 270, 277, 301, 302, 352
315, 316, 317, 318, 319
Pius II; Aeneas Silvius Piccolomini, 95
Persia, 90, 149, 150, 155, 156, 266, 333
planet, xi, xii, xiii, 5, 8, 79, 80, 81, 82,
Persian, xi, xv, xvi, 14, 16, 27, 28, 30, 83, 104, 116, 122, 128, 132, 177, 178,
34, 65, 67, 77, 78, 89, 90, 94, 100, 107, 182, 184, 191, 193, 200, 204, 205, 206,
113, 137, 138, 139, 145, 147, 149, 150, 212, 218, 219, 223, 226, 229, 231, 232,
151, 152, 153, 155, 156, 160, 161, 162, 233, 235, 237, 243, 244, 270, 271, 301,
163, 164, 165, 166, 167, 170, 289, 291, 315
295, 299, 300, 301, 304, 305, 321
planet, inferior, 6, 112, 130, 187, 190,
Persian Astronomical Composition, 150 199, 202, 204, 241
Persian Tables, 14 planet, outer, 5, 67, 80, 177, 178, 179,
180, 182, 184, 187, 212, 216, 222, 227,
Peurbach, Georg, 84, 198, 266
233, 234, 265
philosophy, 32, 33, 34, 36, 37, 55, 58,
planet, superior, 6, 187, 190
64, 127, 193, 194, 199, 202, 210, 239,
266, 276, 295, 296, 297, 353 planet, upper, 65, 140, 205, 235, 267,
277, 315, 319
philosophy, Greek, 27, 28
planet, wandering, 315
philosophy, natural, x, 9, 14, 22, 24, 25,
29, 31, 32, 33, 34, 35, 63, 107, 287, 288, Planetary Hypotheses, 24, 31, 65, 111,
289, 290, 291, 292, 293, 296 131, 136, 137, 140, 204, 242, 289, 292,
303, 315
physical laws, 112
plants, 113, 165
physicalization, 104, 329
Plato, 23, 54, 136, 168
physicalized rectilinear version, 66,
68, 80, 81, 83, 86 pole, 70, 79, 85, 118, 126, 129, 131, 133,
135, 141, 242, 243, 316, 317, 318, 319,
physicist, 10, 21, 30, 47
331
physics, 3, 9, 10, 11, 14, 22, 23, 24, 29,
Pope, 93, 95, 108
30, 31, 32, 33, 34, 35, 65, 71, 107, 112,
127, 134, 140, 147, 207, 211, 258, 267, Posidonius, 46
269, 288, 290, 291, 294, 295, 328
Posterior analytics, 10, 31
Physics, Aristotle’s; Aristotelian
precession, xiii, xiv, 48, 49, 50, 51, 74,
physics, 10, 11, 14, 30, 32, 34, 267, 269,
84, 85, 86, 104, 138, 212, 259, 323, 324,
294, 295
328, 331, 332, 333, 334, 335, 336, 338,
Physis, 111, 137 339, 340, 341, 342, 343, 345, 346, 347,
349, 353, 354,
Pingree, David, 15, 35, 91, 103, 147,
372 Index for Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
qayqāwus, 153, 163 Rashīd al-Dīn Ṭabīb, 149, 150, 158, 159
quadrant, 260, 261, 262, 317, 318 reality, physical, 111, 115, 292
Risālah dar ʿilm-i hayʾa; Risāla dar ʿilm-i Sabra, A. I., 15, 17, 18, 21, 23, 25, 26,
hayʾa, 34, 291 27, 35, 43, 53, 57, 59, 108, 134, 136, 137,
138, 194, 207, 210, 279, 293, 297, 299,
al-Risāla lil-rubʿ al-tāmm; Risāla fī
300, 303, 315, 321
l-ʿamal bi-l-rubʿ al-tāmm al-mawḍūʿ li-
mawāqīt al-Islām, 260, Saccheri, Giovanni, 91
sphere, small, 69, 70, 116, 117, 119, 120, Syene, Aswan, 45, 50
128, 129, 130, 136 Syntaxis, 107, 150, 151, 152, 156, 160,
stade, 46, 47, 57 161, 162, 170
stars, 16, 18, 24, 25, 30, 37, 48, 53, 78, Syria, 28, 47, 107, 143, 158, 259, 262,
102, 103, 131, 145, 151, 153, 161, 162, 324
163, 164, 165, 166, 170, 195, 281, 296, System, Tychonic, 5
323, 327, 328, 329, 331, 332, 333, 337,
338, 340, 341, 342, 345, 347, 348, 349,
350, 351 T
sublunar region, 32, 112, 259, 282, 337 ṭabīʿiyya, 39, 290
376 Index for Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
Tabrīz; Tabriz, 74, 89, 91, 147, 149, 150, testing, 44, 46, 53, 54, 55, 228, 290
151, 152, 156, 157, 158, 159, 160, 161,
Thābit ibn Qurra; Thābit, ix, 15, 23, 48,
162, 166, 168, 169
53, 58, 84, 320, 323, 330, 332, 333, 335,
Tabriz observatory, 158 338, 339, 340, 342, 345, 352, 353
al-Tabṣira fī ʿilm al-hayʾa, 318 theologian, x, 10, 14, 25, 26, 27, 28, 29,
35, 55, 280, 286, 287, 288, 290, 293, 294
al-Tadhkira fī ʿilm al-hayʾa (Memoir on
Astronomy); Tadhkira, x, 15, 58, 66, 67, theology, 9, 21, 24, 30, 33, 34, 39, 290,
94, 111, 138, 139, 145, 147, 150, 162, 297
195, 209, 277, 296, 301, 321, 323, 333,
Theon, 16, 324, 325, 326, 327, 328, 329,
353
330, 331, 332, 333, 334, 335, 336, 337,
Tahānawī; Muḥammad Aʿlā al- 338, 339, 340, 354
Tahānawī, 31, 37, 290, 297
Theoricae novae planetarum, 84, 104, 198
Taḥrīr, Recension, xi, 71, 84, 139, 144
al-Thimār al-yāniʿa min quṭūf al-āla al-
Taḥrīr al-Majisṭī (Recension of the jāmiʿa, 261
Almagest), 71, 94, 101, 144, 147
three-sphere curvilinear version, 64,
tajriba, 53, 287 73, 85, 86, 99
tajribiyya, 34 thubūt, 27, 37, 39
Tajrīd al-ʿaqāʾid; Tajrīd, 27, 33, 34, 37, Tibet, 159
266, 284, 290, 294, 296
Tibyān maqāṣid al-Tadhkira, 150
Takmīl al-Tadhkira, 94
time-keeper, 3, 23, 176, 211, 258
al-Takmila fī sharḥ al-Tadhkira, 94
timekeeping, 23, 260, 261
Taʿlīq al-arṣād, 211, 212, 216, 258, 259
Timurid, 10, 33, 266, 284
talismans, 334, 349
Tīmūr Lang, 157, 266
al-Ṭanṭāwī, Shaykh Muḥammad, 262
Toledo, 84
al-Tanūkhī, Muḥammad ibn Ismāʿīl ,
tools, mathematical, x, 4 , 10, 15, 27
335
Toomer, Gerald, 18, 23, 166, 171, 195,
taqdīr, 27
241, 265, 275, 276, 285, 290, 297, 301,
Taqī al-Dīn ibn Maʿrūf al-Rāṣid, 259, 318, 321, 331, 347, 353, 354
262
Toruń, xi, 63, 99, 147, 193, 207, 216, 228
Tashīl al-mawāqīt fī l-ʿamal bi-ṣandūq
Toscanelli, Paolo, 284
al-yawāqīt, 261
Tourkin, Sergei, 139, 164
Tashkent, 66, 100, 139, 143, 146
tradition, vi, ix, 4, 5, 7, 8, 9, 11, 13, 14,
Tawḍīḥ al-Tadhkira, 94, 138
Index for Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus 377
15, 17, 18, 19, 21, 23, 24, 26, 28, 29, 34, Turkestan, 266
35, 98, 106, 111, 131, 136, 156, 162, 193,
Turkish nations, 159
194, 199, 204, 210, 211, 232, 248, 258,
259, 260, 269, 275, 279, 280, 282, 283, al-Turkistānī, Jamāl al-Dīn, 159
284, 288, 294, 296, 318, 324, 340, 342 al-Ṭūsī; Naṣīr al-Dīn Ṭūsī; Naṣīr al-
transit, Venus, 51 Dīn, x, xi, 3, 4, 17, 22, 24, 63, 90, 94,
100, 102, 104, 105, 106, 137, 138, 139,
translation, Arabic, ix, 91, 136, 330
147, 150, 157, 162, 164, 170, 171, 195,
translation, Latin, ix, 53, 188, 283, 323, 209, 211, 231, 238, 277, 321
327, 328, 336, 348
Ṭūsī-couple, x, xi, 63, 64, 66, 68, 72, 75,
transmission, vii,x, xiv, 6, 7, 8, 11, 13, 78, 79, 81, 83, 84, 85, 86, 89, 91, 92, 98,
14, 16, 18, 19, 21, 23, 35, 63, 64, 65, 67, 100, 102, 105, 109, 139, 147, 162, 163,
68, 70, 74, 75, 76, 77, 78, 79, 84, 86, 88, 168, 207, 212, 218, 223, 233, 236, 237
89, 90, 91, 92, 93, 95, 96, 97, 99, 105,
Ṭūsī-couple, curvilinear, 5, 141
106, 109, 131, 147, 150, 154, 156, 163,
169, 175, 188, 197, 198, 202, 207, 210, Ṭūsī-couple, rectilinear, 5, 68, 79, 145,
222, 230, 236, 269, 276, 279, 282, 285, 217
295, 296, 299 Ṭūsī’s device, x, xi, 3, 8, 16, 79, 86, 216
Transoxiana, 266 two-equal-circle version, 64, 73, 85,
Trebizond, 16, 90, 93, 149, 150, 151, 86, 101
155, 156, 160, 275, 284 two-sphere curvilinear version, 64, 86
trepidation, xiii, xiv, 49, 58, 74, 84, 85, two-unequal-circle version, 64
130, 137, 296, 304, 305, 320, 323, 324,
“Tychonic” version of the De rev.
325, 327, 328, 329, 330, 331, 332, 333,
model, 200
334, 335, 336, 337, 338, 339, 340, 341,
342, 343, 344, 347, 348, 349, 350, 353,
354
U
trepidational variation, 85
al-ʿUbaydī, Jalāl al-Dīn Faḍl Allāh, 94,
trigonometry, x, 95 159, 295
trines, 41, 197, 205, 236, 237, 241 al-ʿUbaydī, Shams al-Dīn, 168
Tuḥfat al-sāmiʿ fī l-ʿamal bi-l-rubʿ al- Ulugh Beg, 10, 33, 157, 266, 269, 275,
jāmiʿ, 260 276, 284
al-Tuḥfa al-shāhiyya fī al-hayʾa; Al-Tuḥfa ʿUmar b. Daʾūd al-Fārisī, 94
al-shāhiyya; Tuḥfa, 33, 74, 94, 102, 108,
Umayyad Mosque, 3, 23, 176, 211, 258,
158, 166, 170, 283
261, 262
Tūn, xi, 63, 66, 99, 100, 143, 147, 193,
uniform velocity, 8
207, 216
378 Index for Islamic Astronomy and Copernicus
uniformity, 10, 111, 139, 142, 231, 301, version, rectilinear, x, xi, 6, 64, 65, 66,
341 67, 68, 70, 80, 81, 83, 86, 90, 114, 130,
140, 143, 145, 300
universe, x, xiii, 17, 27, 28, 29, 35, 55,
59, 111, 113, 162, 188, 191, 259, 280, Veselovsky, I. N.; Ivan Nikolayevich
282, 288 Veselovsky, 7, 17, 86, 87, 105
University of Paris, 287 Vienna, 13, 14, 19, 93, 95
Unmūdhaj al-ʿulūm, 107
Uppsala, 217, 262 W
Uppsala University, 265 Wābkanawī; al-Wābkanawī; Shams
al-Dīn al-Bukhārī; Shams al-Dīn
Uppsala Notes, 100, 109, 175, 178, 179,
Muḥammad ibn ʿAlī Khwāja al-
183, 184, 189, 199, 232, 233, 235, 237
Wābkanawī al-Munajjim; Shams
ʿUrḍī; Muʾayyad al-Dīn al-ʿUrḍī, 4, 6, Bukharos; Shams al-Din al-
9, 97, 108, 178, 180, 190, 211, 259 Wābkanawī; Shams al-Dīn, 78, 89,
ʿUrḍī lemma, 4, 97, 207 150, 151, 153, 156, 157, 158, 160, 164,
166, 167, 168, 169, 170, 171
Ursa Major, 163, 166
Waḍʿ gharīb, 39
Uyghur, 159
water, 37, 164, 165, 238, 280
Uzbekistan, 100, 143
Werner, Johann, 84, 85, 104
Wilson, Curtis, 187, 191, 193, 194
V
wind, 164, 281
variation, latitudinal, 4, 71, 127, 301
wisdom , 29, 35
Vatican, xi, 6 , 90, 91, 102, 103, 108,
151, 160, 162, 163, 295 wondrous creation, 29, 35
Z
al-Zarqallu; al-Zarqāllu; Zarqāllu;
Zarqālī, 15, 320, 324, 332, 333, 334, 336,
337, 347
Zīj, 161, 162, 166, 167, 168, 169, 170,
171, 212, 247, 260, 324, 352, 354
Zīj al-ʿAlāʾī; ʿAlāʾī, 150, 151, 152, 154,
156, 160, 161, 166, 170
al-Zīj al-jadīd, 23, 212, 259, 260
al-Zīj al-muḥaqqaq al-sulṭānī ʿalā uṣūl
al-raṣad al-Īlkhānī, 150, 158, 167, 168,
169, 170, 171
al-Zīj al-Sanjarī; Sanjarī zījes; Sanjarī zīj,
151, 152, 154, 160, 161, 167
al-Zīj al-Sayfī, 259,
al-Zīj al-sulṭānī, 168
Zīj-i Īlkhānī; Īlkhānī Zīj, 150, 151, 152,
157, 160, 161, 162, 169
zodiac, xii, 53, 331
zodiacal orb, 242
al-Zubd al-marʾī fī l-ʿamal bi-l-jayb bi-
ghayr murī, 261
Bringing together fifteen articles that have been published by F. Jamil
Ragep over the last four decades, this volume offers fresh insights and
a deeper understanding of how Islamic astronomical and scientific
traditions influenced the emergence of the Copernican heliocentric
system. These articles not only provide new technical and content-
based evidence regarding the Islamic background to Copernicus, but
also highlight the importance of studying scientific and historical
contexts in which Islamic astronomy could find its way into medieval
and early modern European intellectual and cultural settings. Raising
new questions and contributing solid research through the examination
of various Islamic, Latin, and Greek scientific texts, Ragep’s articles will
be useful for anyone interested in engaging in the study of the Islamic-
Copernicus connection from a broader multicultural perspective.
ISBN: 978-625-8352-02-3