Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

Lecture Waisel

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 7

Informed Consent:

The Core of Pediatric Bioethics


David B. Waisel, MD
Children‟s Hospital Boston, Harvard Medical School, USA

The Informed Consent Process for Pediatric Patients


The core of medical ethics is self-determination. Physicians facilitate self-
determination by honoring the process of informed consent, by explaining to the patient
the risks, benefits and alternatives to the procedure, and by obtaining from the patient an
active, voluntary, informed authorization to perform a specific plan.
In pediatrics, although parents traditionally act as the surrogate decision-makers
for their children, surrogate consent does not fulfill the spirit of informed consent, which
requires the patient to authorize the treatment. To acknowledge this distinction, the
American Academy of Pediatrics has suggested that the proper role for the surrogate
decision-maker is to provide informed permission, which has the same elements as
informed consent but acknowledges that the parent is authorizing treatment for their
child.1
For pediatric patients, the „rule of sevens,‟ provides a rough age-based guideline
for approaching various decision-making abilities of children. The “rule of sevens”
views children age 7 and under as incapable of decision-making capacity, children
between the ages of 8 and 14 as unlikely to have decision-making capacity, and children
over age 14 as presumed to have decision-making capacity.

The Best Interests Standard for Infants, Toddlers, Younger Children and Children
Unable to Participate in the Informed Consent Process
Parents and physicians use the concept of best interests to guide decision-making
about health care for children unable to participate in the decision-making process. This
standard requires the decision-maker to select the care which is objectively the best.
Using this standard, then, requires determining (1) who will make the decision and (2)
what is the best care. The difficulties arise in assuming that there is always one best
choice, because if there is, it should not matter who makes the decision.
In today‟s heterogeneous and multicultural society, parents are given extensive
leeway in determining what is in a child‟s best interests, particularly in complex
decisions about informed consent, end-of-life issues and confidentiality. Traditionally,
parents who are present and capable of participating in the decision-making process are
well-suited to be the primary decision-makers for their children. This is in part due to
society‟s respect for the concept of the family, and the assumption that parents care
greatly for their children. And although we can never know what a child would decide if
he were capable of participating in the decision-making process, it is reasonable to
assume that a child will incorporate some of the parents‟ values as he grows and
matures, making the values of the parents a good first approximation for the future
values of the child.2
Informed Assent for School-age Children and Young Adolescents
Children between ages 7 and 14 should participate in decision-making to the
extent their development permits. Participation should increase as children mature.
School-age children are developing decision-making capacity, so
anesthesiologists should seek both informed permission from the parent and assent and
participatory decision-making from the child. School-age children are capable of using
logic and reason, but they tend to be more rigid and absolute in applying rules. Older
school-age children begin to develop the flexibility to understand motives and different
situations. Such situations may include whether to sedate a 6 year old prior to an
inhalation induction, to use an inhalation or intravenous induction of anesthesia in an 8
year old and to place an epidural for postoperative analgesia in a 12 year old.

Informed Assent for Older Adolescents


Anesthesiologists should try to fulfill the ethical requirements of consent while
obtaining assent from older adolescents. Adolescents have the ability to use abstract
thought, apply complex reasoning, foresee outcomes, understand probability and
evaluate multiple options. These abilities do not necessarily translate into good decision-
making, because adolescents may be limited by insufficient emotional development. The
extent to which adolescents may make decisions is related to the age of the patient, the
maturity of the patient, the ability to articulate their reasons and the risks of making a
poor decision. Lower risk decisions that do not foreclose future possibilities (e.g.
delaying elective surgery) may be more appropriate to honor than decisions that limit the
future, such as potentially life-saving decisions.
Pro forma solicitations of opinions are harmful. The American Academy of
Pediatrics speaks directly to this point, emphasizing “no one should solicit a patient‟s
views without intending to weigh them seriously. In situations in which the patient will
have to receive medical care despite his or her objection, the patient should be told that
fact and should not be deceived.” 1

Emancipated Minor Status and Mature Minor Doctrine


Some adolescents have the legal right to consent to treatment. Emancipated
minors have the ability to give legal informed consent for all healthcare matters.
Emancipated minor status is generally awarded to adolescents who are married, parents,
in the military, economically independent and may include adolescents who are
pregnant. Mature minors are legally and ethically capable of giving informed consent in
specific situations as determined by a court. The mature minor doctrine generally
requires adolescents to be older than 13 years old, and tends to permit less hazardous
decisions at a younger age and more hazardous decisions as the adolescent nears
majority.
Table: Elements of Consent and Assent as Defined by the American Academy of
Pediatrics Committee on Bioethics1

Consent
1. Adequate provision of information including the nature of the ailment or
condition, the nature of the proposed diagnostic steps or treatment and the
probability of their success; the existence and nature of the risks involved; and
the existence, potential benefits, and risks of recommended alternative treatments
(including the choice of no treatment)
2. Assessment of the patient‟s understanding of the above information
3. Assessment, if only tacit, of the capacity of the patient or surrogate to make the
necessary decisions.
4. Assurance, insofar as it is possible, that the patient has the freedom to choose
among the medial alternatives without coercion or manipulation

Assent
1. Helping the patient achieve a developmentally appropriate awareness of the
nature of his or her condition.
2. Telling the patient what he or she can expect with tests and treatment.
3. Making a clinical assessment of the patient‟s understanding of the situation
and the factors influencing how he or she is responding (including whether there
is inappropriate pressure to accept testing or therapy).
4. Soliciting an expression of the patient‟s willingness to accept the proposed care.

Table: Approaches to Pediatric Consent

This broad outline should be viewed as a guide. Specific circumstances always must be
taken into consideration. When children are in the upper range of an age bracket, limited
or full inclusion of a higher technique, such as the use of assent for a six year old, may
be appropriate.

Age Decision-making Capacity Technique


Under 7 years None Best Interests Standard
Ages 7 – 13 years Developing Informed Permission
Informed Assent
Ages 14 years and older Mostly developed Informed Assent
Informed Permission
Mature Minor Developed, as legally Informed Consent
determined by a judge
Emancipated Minor Developed, as determined Informed Consent
by a situation
Resolving Disagreements: Informed Refusal by Parents and Adolescents
The requirements to achieve informed refusal for a procedure are similar to the
requirements for informed consent in that the decision-makers should be substantially
well-versed about the risks, benefits and alternatives before declining. When parents
refuse what caregivers believe is necessary care for a minor who cannot participate in the
decision-making process, caregivers may use the best interests standard as guide.
One way to decide what is in the best interests of the child is to define what
choices fall outside of the range of acceptable decision-making. The continuum between
unacceptable and acceptable treatment in the practice of anesthesiology provides clear
extremes, but an ambiguous gray zone. For example, it is nearly always considered
unacceptable undertreatment for Jehovah‟s Witnesses to refuse a life-sustaining blood
transfusion for their child. On the other hand, parents may decline to have an epidural
placed in their child for postoperative pain management, depriving the child of an
optimal source of pain control. This is not considered unacceptable undertreatment, in
part because the harm is limited by other adequate methods of pain control.
Anesthesiologists may best determine the appropriateness of a treatment by
considering the amount of harm to the child, the likelihood of success and the overall
risk-to-benefit ratio.3 Anesthesiologists challenging inappropriate health care may
benefit from inviting other clinicians to review the proposed plan and to engage the
parent in discussion.4 Pursuing legal actions to redress questionable health care decisions
has significant familial and social ramifications. If all other methods fail, and
anesthesiologists believe the desired therapy is outside the bounds of acceptable
treatment, they should report the situation to proper child welfare authorities.
This situation is more complicated when the minor expresses significant
decision-making capacity and refuses a nonemergent procedure. Anesthesiologists
should respect the right of pediatric patients not to assent to a procedure, and should go
out of their way to avoid coercing or forcibly making the minor have the procedure.
Achieving the patient‟s assent may necessitate further discussions with the patient,
parents, and other providers, and such discussions may best take place away from the
operating room. In cases where the parent and child disagree, clinicians should seek the
assistance of others experienced in conflict resolution to help resolve the dispute with a
minimum of rancor.
Disagreements about appropriate therapy may be more relevant in end-of-life
care. Decision-making for a child near the end of life should be based on the best
interests of the child. Given improvement in medicine, clinicians should be aware that it
is often hard to predict success in very young children. Further, parents tend to be very
involved in the care of their children and pediatric doctors may feel a need to “protect”
their patients. When both parents and clinicians are invested in the child‟s well-being,
there is a greater possibility of disagreements causing conflict, particularly given the
difficulty in defining beneficial and burdensome outcomes. The guidelines from the
American Academy of Pediatrics consider benefits to include prolongation of life under
certain circumstances, improved quality of life (such as reduction of pain or the ability to
leave the hospital), and increased enjoyment of life. Burdens may include intractable
pain and suffering, disability, and events that cause a decrement in the quality of life, as
viewed by the child and parents.5 A useful approach to resolving conflicts has been
proposed by the President's Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine
and Biomedical and Behavioral Research.2 In short, only if a therapy is clearly
beneficial (as in blood transfusion for anemia) may clinicians override parental
preferences, and even then, out of respect, the appropriateness of the treatment and the
process of decision-making should undergo an external review, which will often be
medical, ethical or legal in nature.

Table: Suggested Grid for Resolving Disputes about Appropriate Care 2,6

Parents prefer to Parents prefer to


accept treatment forego treatment
Physicians consider Provide treatment
Treat
treatment clearly beneficial during review process
Physicians consider
treatment to be of
Treat Forego
ambiguous or uncertain
benefit
Physicians consider Provide treatment
Forego
treatment to be inadvisable during review process
Physicians consider
Review Forego
treatment to be futile

Special Situations in Pediatric Informed Consent


The Pediatric Patient and Abortion
Even though pediatric patients who are pregnant may be considered emancipated,
many states require some form of parental involvement such as parental consent or
notification prior to an elective abortion in an adolescent. If a state requires parental
involvement, the ability of the minor to circumvent this regulation by seeking relief from
a judge, known as judicial bypass, must be available. Requirements and enforcement of
statutes vary from state to state.7 The need for parental involvement in minor abortions is
not always legally straightforward and it may be best to consult with hospital counsel in
determining these issues. Although this is clearly an area in which honorable people
disagree, it is worth noting that both the American Academy of Pediatrics and the
American Medical Association have issued statements affirming the rights of
adolescents to confidentiality when contemplating an abortion.7,8

Confidentiality for Adolescents


The obligation to maintain confidentiality requires physicians to protect patient
information from unauthorized and unnecessary disclosure. Confidentiality is necessary
for the development of a patient-physician relationship that supports an open and
uncensored flow of information and concerns. A trusting alliance is particularly
important in the care of adolescents who are more likely to defer needed treatment
because they are concerned about confidentiality.9 Emancipated and mature minors have
a right to complete confidentiality. For other adolescents, if the knowledge is of minimal
harm to the health of the patient, physicians should encourage the patient to be forthright
with parents but respect their decision not to be. If, on the other hand, withholding the
information may result in serious harm to the patient, the physician is ethically justified
in notifying the parents.9 Possible exceptions to the principle of confidentiality are
notifications required by law such as reporting statutes, parental notification, and when a
patient makes a credible threat to harm another person.
The quality of the information obtained in the preoperative interview may be
directly affected by the adolescent‟s trust of the anesthesiologist. The anesthesiologist
can enhance this trust by interviewing the adolescent in private, acknowledging the
adolescent‟s concerns about confidentiality and following through on any promises
made. Inadvertent breeches of confidentiality are as harmful as intentional ones, and
anesthesiologists should be aware that many disclosures take place unwittingly in public
spaces or social situations.

Emergency Care
Anesthesiologists will need to perform emergent anesthetics for minors who do
not have parents available to give legal consent or informed permission. In an emergency
situation, the presumption is that necessary therapy is desirable and should be given.10 It
is reasonable to attempt to contact the parents or surrogate, but questions about
reimbursements should not hold up necessary treatment.10 Emergencies include
problems that could cause death, disability and the increased risk of future
complications.
This situation becomes more complex when a minor near majority refuses assent
for emergency care that the parent desires. The right of the minor to refuse treatment
turns on the minor‟s decision-making capacity and the resulting harm from the refusal of
care.1 If the harm is significant, and the patient‟s rationale is decidedly short term or
filled with misunderstanding, it is necessary to question the minor‟s decision-making
capacity. At this point one may revert to asking what is in the best interests of the minor.

The Impaired Parent


Parents may have impaired judgments and may be unable to fulfill surrogate
responsibilities regarding informed permission, and they may be disruptive or dangerous.
Caregivers should focus on the safety of the child, the impaired parent, and others, such
as patients, parents and employees in the area, comply with reporting mandates and
protect patient confidentiality.11 As a general rule, caregivers should use the least
restrictive means to decrease the risk from the impaired parent. Caregivers may wish to
postpone routine treatment until legal consent can be obtained from an unimpaired
parent. Anesthesiologists will have to weight the benefits of waiting with the risk that
impaired parents may be less reliable and, for example, may not return for future visits.
In this case, it may be in the child‟s best interests to proceed with a routine procedure in
the situation of an impaired parent unable to give legal consent. Anesthesiologists may
wish to consult legal and risk management colleagues for guidance.
General References
Waisel DB, Truog RD, Todres ID. Ethical issues in pediatric anesthesiology.
In: Cote CJ, Lerman J, Todres ID, eds. A Practice of Anesthesia
for Infants and Children, 4th ed. Philadelphia: W.B. Saunders, in press

Waisel DB. Ethical and legal considerations in pediatric anesthesia. In: Holzman RS,
Mancuso TJ, Polaner DM, eds. A Practical Approach to Pediatric Anesthesia.
Philadelphia: Lippincott Williams & Williams; 2008. p. 71-8

References
1. Committee on Bioethics, American Academy of Pediatrics: Informed consent,
parental permission, and assent in pediatric practice. Pediatrics 1995; 95: 314-7
2. President's Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and
Biomedical and Behavioral Research. Deciding to Forgo Life-Sustaining Treatment:
Ethical, Medical and Legal Issues in Treatment Decisions. Washington, DC, U.S.
Government Printing Office, 1983
3. McMenamin JP, Buckel JC: Children as patients, Legal Medicine, 3rd Edition. Edited
by Sanbar SS, Gibofsky A, Firestone MH, LeBlang TR, Liang BA, Snyder JW. St.
Louis, Mosby, Inc., 2001, pp 369-381
4. Anderson B, Hall B: Parents' perceptions of decision making for children. J Law Med
Ethics 1995; 23: 15-9
5. Committee on Bioethics, American Academy of Pediatrics: Guidelines on forgoing
life-sustaining medical treatment. Pediatrics 1994; 93: 532-6
6. Consensus statement of the Society of Critical Care Medicine's Ethics Committee
regarding futile and other possibly inadvisable treatments. Crit Care Med 1997; 25: 887-
91
7. Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs, American Medical Association: Mandatory
parental consent to abortion. JAMA1993; 269: 82-6
8. Committee on Adolescence, American Academy of Pediatrics: The adolescent's right
to confidential care when considering abortion. Pediatrics 1996; 97: 746-51
9. Council on Scientific Affairs, American Medical Association: Confidential health
services for adolescents. JAMA 1993; 269: 1420-4
10. Consent for emergency medical services for children and adolescents. Pediatrics
2003; 111: 703-6
11. Fraser JJ, Jr., McAbee GN: Dealing with the parent whose judgment is impaired by
alcohol or drugs: legal and ethical considerations. Pediatrics 2004; 114: 869-73

You might also like