Randall Peerenboom
Randall Peerenboom
Randall Peerenboom
Randall Peerenboom
and legal scholars debate endlessly the relationship between rule of law,
democracy, human rights and constitutionalism, Focusing their lens a little more
narrowly, neoinstitutionalists inquire into the institutions needed to implement
rule of law, whether that be an independent judiciary and legal profession, a
systems of checks and balances or a particular form of separation of powers.
No single approach will satisfy everyone. Each produces its own insights, and
has its own drawbacks. However, if we are to have meaningful discussions with
others with different backgrounds, it may help to begin with some definitions and
a provisional conceptual framework to clarify whether we are all talking about
the same thing, and, if not, how and why we differ. Fortunately, despite the many
debates over rule of law and its contested nature, there is a fairly well-accepted
conceptual or analytical framework that at least clarifies some of the terms and
disputes, though without resolving many important related but oftentimes
somewhat broader issues.
There is general agreement not only about these criteria, but that these criteria
cannot be perfectly realized, and may even in some cases be.in tension with each
other. While marginal deviations are acceptable, legal systems that fall far short
are likely to be dysfunctional. Of course, a thin theory requires more than just
these elements. A fully articulated thin theory would also specify the goals and
purposes of the system as well as its institutions, rules, practices and outcomes.
Typical candidates for the more limited normative purposes served by thin
theories of rule of law include:4
• ensuring stability, and preventing anarchy and Hobbesian war of all against
all;
• securing government in accordance with law by limiting arbitrariness on the
part of the government;
• enhancing predictability, which allows people to plan their affairs and hence
promotes both individual freedom and economic development;
• providing a fair mechanism for the resolution of disputes;
• bolstering the legitimacy of the government.
States may agree on these broad goals and yet interpret or weigh them differently,
leading to significant variations in their legal regimes. For instance, a greater
emphasis on stability rather than individual freedom may result in some states
limiting civil society, freedom of association and speech (see Chapters 4, 6 and
7). Moreover, in periods of rapid economic or social transformation, some of
these goals, such as predictability, may be sacrificed for other important social
values.
A variety of institutions and processes are also required. The promulgation of
law assumes a legislature and the government machinery necessary to make the
laws publicly available. Congruence of laws on the books and actual practice
assumes institutions for implementing and enforcing laws. While informal means
of enforcing laws may be possible in some contexts, modern societies must also
rely on formal means such as courts and administrative bodies. Furthermore, if
the law is to guide behavior and provide certainty and predictability, laws must
be applied and enforced in a reasonable way that does not defeat people’s
expectations. This implies normative and practical limits on the decision-makers
who interpret and apply the laws and principles of due process or natural justice
such as access to impartial tribunals, a chance to present evidence and rules of
evidence. One must also look beyond the traditional branches of government to
the legal profession, civil society, private actors who increasingly take on
government functions, and the military, which in many countries continues to be
a force capable of undermining the legal system and rule of law.
In contrast to thin versions of rule of law, thick or substantive conceptions
begin with the basic elements of a thin conception but then incorporate elements
of political morality such as particular economic arrangements (free-market
capitalism, central planning, “Asian developmental state” or other varieties of
4 RANDALL PEERENBOOM
there are democratic elections in Singapore and Malaysia, both countries are
frequently characterized as non-liberal, soft-authoritarian regimes. Several other
countries are in the process of consolidating democracy But even many of the
democratic regimes show signs of being less liberal than their Western
counterparts. Some countries remain politically unstable and torn by ethnic
strife, resulting in various restrictions on individual liberties. Many are
confronting widespread poverty and the social ills that follow from it. Worried
about meeting the basic needs of sustenance, expansive social welfare programs
seem a distant pipedream.
In striking contrast to the many volumes on rule of law in the Western
literature, relatively little work has been done on clarifying alternative
conceptions of rule of law in other parts of the world, including Asia.8 What
emerges from the following country studies is a rich portrait of diverse
conceptions of rule of law both across the region and within individual countries,
from liberal views to authoritarian views, from top-down statist views to the
bottom-up perspectives of oppressed individuals seeking to harness the power of
rule of law to redress individual instances of injustice and the broad-ranging
systemic problems that empower a few at the expense of the many.
If rule of law is the rule of the good law then to explain its nature is to
propound a complete social philosophy. But if so the term lacks any useful
function. We have no need to be converted to the rule of law just in order
to believe that good should triumph. A non-democratic legal system, based
on the denial of human rights, of extensive poverty, on racial segregation,
sexual inequalities, and religious persecution may, in principle, conform to
the requirements of the rule of law better than any of the legal systems of
the more enlightened Western democracies.9
As a practical matter, much of the moral force behind rule of law and its
enduring importance as a political ideal today is predicated on the ability to use
rule of law as a benchmark to condemn or praise particular rules, decisions,
practices and legal systems. But all too often, rule of law is simply invoked to
criticize whatever law, practice or outcome does not coincide with one’s own
political beliefs. For example, in Singapore liberal critics of the government’s
conservative policies have invoked rule of law to object to the lack of “adequate”
workers’ rights legislation, limitations on the right of peaceful demonstration,
and a regulatory framework that restricts the freedom of the local press. Contrast
such complaints with the following. A law provides that contractors must have
five years of experience and meet various other requirements to obtain a license;
VARIETIES OF RULE OF LAW 7
legal aid system; exchanges to strengthen the securities regulatory system and
the administrative law system; seminars on electronic commerce, corporate law,
and the enforcement of arbitral awards and court judgments; and even a
symposium to discuss the legal aspects of protecting human rights, including
issues such as China’s legal responsibilities under international rights
agreements, the rights of criminal defendants and the legal protection of religious
freedom.
As discussions of contentious criminal law issues show, relying on a thin rule
of law as a benchmark to assess a legal system does not allow one to completely
avoid all substantive issues of the type that must be addressed by advocates of a
thick theory of rule of law. It merely reduces the range of issues where such
substantive values will be relevant and hence the scope of possible conflict.
Although the features of a thin rule of law are common to all rule of law
systems, they will vary to some extent in the way they are interpreted and
implemented depending on substantive political views and values. For instance,
socialists and liberals may agree that one of the purposes of a thin rule of law is
to protect individual rights and interests but disagree about what those rights and
interests are. Or they may agree that rule of law requires that laws be made by an
entity with the authority to make laws but disagree as to whether members of
that entity must be democratically elected. Accordingly, legal systems that meet
the standards of a thin rule of law will still diverge to some extent with respect to
purposes, institutions, rules and outcomes due to the different contexts in which
they are embedded.
One of the dangers of eliding rule of law with an open-ended concept like
justice is that it tends to produce confusion, and eventually disillusionment. As
Vitit Muntarbhorn (Chapter 11) explains:
The Thai term for the rule of law is “Luck Nititham” implying a precept of
law based upon a sense of justice and virtue—not an easy notion to grasp
in a concrete sense. There is thus a kind of mythification of the term as a
linchpin of our society, when in reality it is steeped in popular
incomprehension rather than comprehension. This mythification dilutes the
impact of the notion of the rule of law, precisely because the distance
between people and the notion itself is often extreme—and that gap results
in what can be described as the rule of lore.
Simply put, there is little agreement over what justice is. As Upendra Baxi
(Chapter 10) reminds us:
the “good” that triumphs, as a “complete social philosophy,” may be, and
indeed has often been, defined in ways that perpetuate states of Radical
Evil. Complete social philosophies have justified, and remain capable of
justifying, varieties of violent social exclusion.
VARIETIES OF RULE OF LAW 9
Given the fact of pluralism,11 thick conceptions of rule of law must confront the
issue of whose good, whose justice? Liberals, Socialists, Communitarians, Neo-
authoritarians, Soft Authoritarians, New Conservatives, Old Conservatives,
Buddhists, Daoists, Neo-Confucians and New Confucians all differ in their
visions of the good life and on what is considered just, and hence what rule of
law requires. By incorporating particular conceptions of the economy, political
order or human rights into rule of law, thick conceptions decrease the likelihood
that an overlapping consensus will emerge as to its meaning. Conversely,
limiting the concept of rule of law to the requirements of a thin theory makes it
possible to avoid getting mired in never-ending debates about the superiority of
the various political theories all contending for the throne of justice.
The more concrete, practical downside of conflating rule of law with justice is
that it gives rise to unrealistic expectations of rule of law. No legal system to date
has produced a perfectly just society, and none ever will. People should not
expect a legal system or rule of law to address all social ills. You may win a
lawsuit, but if the other party is insolvent, no legal system will be able to enforce
the judgment for you. Regardless of whether abortion is allowed or prohibited,
some people will find the outcome unbearable. When the legal system falls short
of one’s particular conception of what is just, it is then criticized, leading to a
backlash against rule of law as an empty concept or, worse yet, a mask of
oppression.
On the other hand, thick theories have their advantages as well. Articulating
different thick conceptions makes it possible to relate political and economic
problems to law, legal institutions and particular conceptions of legal systems.
By highlighting differences in viewpoints across a range of issues, thick theories
bring out more clearly what is really at stake in many disputes. Moreover, activists
and legal reformers in repressive regimes generally prefer thick theories because
they allow them to discuss certain controversial political issues. For instance, in
China, legal reformers have used a broad conception of rule of law as a means of
discussing democracy, separation of powers and human rights issues.
As a matter of legal sociology, it seems most people object to the normative
deficiencies of a thin rule of law, and are unwilling to describe states such as
Nazi Germany or apartheid South Africa as rule of law states.12 Whatever the
merits of this view, conceiving rule of law in thin terms will mean that rule of
law will give way to other important values in some instances, and many of the
most important public issues will be debated in terms other than rule of law.
Where laws are deeply unjust, citizens will engage in civil disobedience or seek
to overthrow the ruling regime. Similarly, if rule of law is narrowly conceived to
curtail all discretion, then rule of law and its virtues of predictability and
certainty will sometimes give way to considerations of equity and the desire for a
context-specific and just outcome.
In sum, the choice of thin or thick theories depends on one’s purpose.
Investors seeking a basis for assessing legal system risk may be better served by
a rule of law index that closely approximates the standards of a thin theory.
10 RANDALL PEERENBOOM
able to argue that his acts violate rule of law, a powerful objection in any setting,
but particularly in the case of a president in a newly democratic state who made
his name by opposing the abuse of law for political purposes by the prior
authoritarian regime.