Philosophy of Education by Paul Ernest
Philosophy of Education by Paul Ernest
Philosophy of Education by Paul Ernest
OF MATHEMATICS
EDUCATION?
Paul Ernest
<P.Ernest@ex.ac.uk>
Moving beyond the first word, there is the more substantive question of the reference of
the term ‘philosophy of mathematics education’. There is a narrow sense that can be
applied in interpreting the words ‘philosophy’ and ‘mathematics education’. The
philosophy of some area or activity can be understood as its aims or rationale.
Mathematics education understood in its simplest and most concrete sense concerns the
activity or practice of teaching mathematics. So the narrowest sense of ‘philosophy of
mathematics education’ concerns the aims or rationale behind the practice of teaching
mathematics. ‘What is the purpose of teaching and learning mathematics?’ is an
important question. I have added learning to it because learning is inseparable from
teaching. Although they can be conceived of separately, in practice a teacher
presupposes one or more learners. Only in pathological situations can one have teaching
without learning, although of course the converse does not hold. Informal learning is
often self directed and takes place without explicit teaching.
Returning to the question of the aims of teaching mathematics it is important to note that
aims, goals, purposes, rationales, etc, do not exist in a vacuum. They belong to people,
whether individuals or social groups. Indeed since the teaching of mathematics is a
widespread and highly organised social activity, and even allowing for the possibility of
divergent multiple aims and goals among different persons, ultimately these aims, goals,
purposes, rationales, and so on, need to be related to social groups and society in general.
Aims are expressions of values, and thus the educational and social values of society or
some part of it are implicated in this enquiry. In addition, the aims discussed so far are
for the teaching of mathematics, so the aims and values centrally concern mathematics
and its role and purposes in education and society.
In his essay on the subject of the philosophy of mathematics education Stephen Brown
(1995) asks a very pertinent question by posing a trichotomy. Is the philosophical focus
or dimension:
education
Each of these three possible ‘applications’ of philosophy to mathematics education
represents a different focus, and might very well foreground different issues and
problems. However, Figure 1, of course, raises more questions than it answers. It
illustrates that applications can be made either of philosophy or of two special branches
of it. However what is such an application? The diagram might be taken to suggest that
there are substantive bodies of knowledge and applicational activities connecting them,
whereas philosophy, mathematics education and other domains of knowledge
encompass processes of enquiry and practice, personal knowledge, and as well as
published knowledge representations. They are not simply substantial entities in
themselves, but complex relationships and interactions between persons, society, social
structures, knowledge representations and communicative (and other) practices.
At the very least, this suggests that the philosophy of mathematics education should not
only attend to the philosophy of mathematics. Stephen Brown (1995) suggests that it
should also look to the philosophy of Schwab's other commonplaces of teaching: the
learner, the teacher, and the milieu or society. So we also have the philosophy of learning
(mathematics), the philosophy of teaching (mathematics) and the philosophy of the
milieu or society (with respect to mathematics and mathematics education) as further
elements to consider.
Looking at each of these four commonplaces in turn, a number of questions can be posed,
as issues for the philosophy of mathematics education to address, including the
following.
1. WHAT IS MATHEMATICS?
What is mathematics, and how can its unique characteristics be accommodated in a
philosophy? Can mathematics be accounted for both as a body of knowledge and a social
domain of enquiry? Does this lead to tensions? What philosophies of mathematics have
been developed? What features of mathematics do they pick out as significant? What is
their impact on the teaching and learning of mathematics? What is the rationale for
picking out certain elements of mathematics for schooling? How can (and should)
mathematics be conceptualised and transformed for educational purposes? What values
and goals are involved? Is mathematics value-laden or value-free? How do
mathematicians work and create new mathematical knowledge? What are the methods,
aesthetics and values of mathematicians? How does history of mathematics relate to the
philosophy of mathematics? Is mathematics changing as new methods and information
and communication technologies emerge?
This already has begun to pose questions relating to the next area of
SOCIETY?
How also does mathematics education relate to society? What are the aims of
mathematics education (i.e., the aims of mathematics teaching)? Are these aims valid?
Whose aims are they? For whom? Based on which values? Who gains and who loses?
How do the social, cultural and historical contexts relate to mathematics, the aims of
teaching, and the teaching and learning
of mathematics? What values underpin different sets of aims? How does mathematics
contribute to the overall goals of society and education? What is the role of the teaching
and learning of mathematics in promoting or hindering social justice conceived in terms
of gender, race, class, ability and critical citizenship? Is anti-racist mathematics
education possible and what does it mean? How is mathematics viewed and perceived in
society? What impact does this have on education? What is the relationship between
mathematics and society? What functions does it perform? Which of these functions are
intended and visible? Which functions are unintended or invisible? To what extent do
mathematical metaphors (e.g., profit and loss balance sheet) permeate social thinking?
What is their philosophical significance? To whom is mathematics accountable?
What assumptions, possibly implicit, underpin views of learning mathematics? Are these
assumptions valid? Which epistemologies and learning theories are assumed? How can
the social context of learning be accommodated? What are constructivist, social
constructivist and other theories of learning mathematics? Do they have any impact on
classroom practice? What elements of learning mathematics are valuable? How can they
be and should they be assessed? What feedback loops do different forms of assessment
create, impacting on the processes of teaching and learning of mathematics? What is the
role of the learner? What powers of the learner are or could be developed by learning
mathematics? How does the identity of the learner change and develop through learning
mathematics? Does learning mathematics impact on the whole person for good or for ill?
How is the future mathematician and the future citizen formed through learning
mathematics? How important are affective dimensions including attitudes, beliefs and
values in learning mathematics? What is mathematical ability and how can it be
fostered? Is mathematics accessible to all?
One further set of questions for the philosophy of mathematics education goes beyond
Schwab's four commonplaces of teaching, which were primarily about the nature of the
(mathematics) curriculum. This further set concerns the status of mathematics education
as a field of knowledge and coming to know in it.
5. WHAT IS THE STATUS OF MATHEMATICS EDUCATION AS
KNOWLEDGE FIELD?
These five sets of questions encompass, in my view, most of what is important for the
philosophy of mathematics education to consider and explore. These sets are not wholly
discrete, as various areas of overlap reveal. Nor are the questions systematically derived.
Rather they originate from ‘brainstorming’, and other thinkers would probably add
further questions or even further sets of questions, and might background some of the
issues raised above. Hence no claim for either completeness or even complete relevance
[2]
can be made for them. Some of the questions are not essentially philosophical, in that
they can also be addressed and explored in ways that foreground other disciplinary
perspectives, such as sociology. However, in my view, when such questions are
approached philosophically, they become part of the business of the philosophy of
mathematics education. And often to exclude certain questions ab initio is to adopt and
promote a particular philosophical position, i.e., a particular philosophy of mathematics
education.
Of course the question of what and where are the boundaries between philosophy,
sociology, anthropology, psychology is yet another area of philosophical enquiry, and
one that is much disputed. The traditional clear-cut ‘division of labour’, i.e., marking out
of discipline boundaries has been challenged by poststructural, postmodern, and other
philosophies and theories about knowledge. This is an issue that impacts particularly on
the fifth set of questions listed above.
1. Philosophy of Mathematics
As one of the oldest sciences, and as the paradigm of certain and cumulative knowledge,
mathematics and its philosophy seems an unlikely area for controversy. But currently the
so-
called ‘Science Wars’ are raging, mostly in USA, but also in other English-speaking
countries, about philosophical views of science and mathematics. Although primarily
ignited between realist and social constructivist or science studies accounts of the nature
of science, the heated debate has also spilled over into the domain of mathematics.
Foundationalists and absolutists, on the one hand, want to maintain that mathematics is
certain, cumulative and untouched by social interests or developments beyond the
normal patterns of historical growth. Fallibilists, humanists, relativists and social
constructivists, on the other hand, have been arguing that mathematics is through and
through historical and social, and that there are cultural limitations to its claims of
certainty, universality and absoluteness. This controversy can become very heated and
even emotionally charged, as correspondence in the American Mathematical Monthly
and Mathematical Intelligencer illustrates. Barnard and Saunders (1994) illustrate the
negative reaction of some British mathematicians to the claims of fallibilism in
philosophy of mathematics.
The aims of mathematics education can be a hotly contested area, especially when new
curricula are being developed or disseminated through a national or regional education
system. In Ernest (1991) I identified the aims of five different groups contesting the
nature and aims of the British (for England Wales) National Curriculum in mathematics,
during the late 1980s and early 1990s. In summary, these five groups and their aims were
as follows:
These aims are best understood as part of an overall ideological framework that includes
views of knowledge, values, society, human nature as well as education. In Britain, the
contestation between these groups was largely behind the scenes, although sometimes it
spilled over into the public arena when interest groups sought to gain public support for
their positions. My analysis suggested that the first three interest groups formed a
powerful and largely victorious alliance in 1980s and 1990s Britain. This forced the aims
of group 4 (Progressive Educators) to be compromised and filtered through those of
group 2 (Technological Pragmatist) in order to have an impact on the curriculum. The
aims of group 5 (Public Educators) were eliminated in this struggle, and had no impact at
all. Similar struggles and contestations have been noted in other countries too.
Since then, yet further controversy has erupted between different versions of
constructivism, most notably radical constructivism versus social constructivism (Ernest
1994a), as well as powerful critiques of constructivism learning theory both within
science and mathematics education, and from without.
4. Mathematics Teaching
The teaching of mathematics is also an area in which there can be heated and
controversial clashes of philosophy or ideologies. Among the ‘hot’ areas and issues are
the following
4. Mathematics and culture – should traditional mathematics with its formal tasks and
problems be the basis of the curriculum, or should it be presented in realistic, authentic,
or ethnomathematical contexts?
Each of these issues and oppositions has been the basis of heated debate and contestation
world wide, and rests on philosophical issues and assumptions.
by Gage (1989). Such conflicts have been manifested by ‘gatekeepers’ choosing what
papers to accept for conferences and journals, and what projects to fund; and thus have
involved the exercise of power, of considerable significance for researchers in
mathematics education. Although most researchers are by now aware of the validity of
both approaches and styles, when conducted properly, nevertheless conflicts in personal
judgements about such validity still arise periodically.
This brief and selective account of controversies in mathematics education research does
not really indicate the strength of feelings involved. Conflicts sparked by philosophical
controversies around philosophies of mathematics, the aims, learning theories, teaching
approaches, and research paradigms in mathematics education continue to arise. Often
this occurs when opponents fail to realise it is their underlying philosophies, assumptions
and ideologies that are in conflict, not their overt proposals or claims. An awareness of
the multi
dimensional philosophical issues and assumptions underpinning research in mathematics
education, something that the philosophy of mathematics education can bring, can help
to forestall, minimise and sometimes resolve such conflicts and misunderstandings.
One of the central issues for the philosophy of mathematics education is the link
between philosophies of mathematics and mathematical practices. A widespread claim is
that there is a strong if complex link between philosophy and pedagogy. As Steiner
(1987: 8) says “all more or less elaborated conceptions, epistemologies, methodologies,
philosophies of mathematics (in the large or in part) contain - often in an implicit way -
ideas, orientations or germs for theories on the teaching and learning of mathematics.”
However, in the past few decades a new wave of ‘fallibilist’ philosophies of mathematics
has been gaining ground, and these propose a different and opposing image of
mathematics as human, corrigible, historical and changing (Davis and Hersh 1980,
Ernest 1994b, Lakatos 1976, Tymoczko 1986). Fallibilism views mathematics as the
outcome of social processes. Mathematical knowledge is understood to be eternally open
to revision, both in terms of its proofs and its concepts. Consequently this view embraces
the practices of mathematicians, its history and applications, the place of mathematics in
human culture, including issues of values and education as legitimate philosophical
concerns. The fallibilist view does not reject the role of logic and structure in
mathematics, just the notion that there is a unique, fixed and permanently enduring
hierarchical structure. Instead it accepts the view that mathematics is made up of many
overlapping structures which, over the course of history, grow, dissolve, and then grow
anew, like trees in a forest (Steen 1988).
Fallibilism does reject the absolutist image of mathematics as a body of pure and perfect
abstract knowledge which exists in a superhuman, objective realm (Davis 1972). Instead
mathematics is associated with sets of social practices, each with its history, persons,
institutions and social locations, symbolic forms, purposes and power relations. Thus
academic research mathematics is one such practice (or rather a multiplicity of shifting,
interconnected practices). Likewise each of ethnomathematics and school mathematics is
a distinct set of such practices. They are intimately bound up together, because the
symbolic productions of one practice is recontextualised and reproduced in another
(Dowling 1988).
Two philosophical views of mathematics have been described. Which of them reflects
the image of mathematics in school? It must be said that the experience some learners
have from their years of schooling confirms the absolutist image of mathematics as cold,
absolute and inhuman. It is far from uncommon for teachers and others and the
experience of learning itself to confirm this view. Such an image is often, but not always,
associated with negative attitudes to mathematics. A counterexample arose in my
research on student teacher’s attitudes and beliefs about mathematics. I found a subgroup
of mathematics specialists who combined absolutist conceptions of the subject with very
positive attitudes to mathematics and its teaching. However amongst non-mathematics-
specialist future primary school teachers I found a loose correlation between fallibilist
conceptions and positive attitudes to mathematics and its teaching (Ernest 1988, 1989b).
Thus the connections even just between beliefs and attitudes to mathematics are complex
and multifaceted.
Research on children’s attitudes towards mathematics in the past two decades shows
fairly widespread liking of the school subject, certainly in the years of elementary
schooling (Assessment of Performance Unit 1985). In the later years of schooling
attitudes in general become more neutral, although extreme negative attitudes are
relatively rare. Presumably this downturn in attitudes is due to such things as
adolescence, peer-attitudes, the impact of competitive examinations, not to mention the
image of mathematics conveyed in and out of school.
An important issue for education is the relationship between mathematics and values,
especially since the popular image of mathematics is clearly value-laden. The feminist
researcher Gilligan (1982) has offered a theory of values, distinguishing stereotypically
feminine values (termed ‘connected’), from stereotypically masculine values (termed
‘separated’). The ‘connected’ position is based on and valorises relationships,
connections, empathy, caring, feelings and intuition, and tends to holistic and human-
centred in its concerns. The ‘separated’ position valorises rules, abstraction,
objectification, impersonality, unfeelingness, dispassionate reason and analysis, and
tends to be atomistic and thing-centred in focus.
Although we are one species and male/female differences are not as profound as our
commonalities, reviews of empirical evidence suggest that there are significant
differences by late adolescence and adulthood (Larrabee 1993), and girls are more likely
to be empathetic than boys in exhibiting emotional reactions to another’s feelings
(Hoffman 1977). Likewise, separated values have come to dominate many institutions
and structures, including mathematics and science, especially in Anglophone and
Protestant countries. Many people have come to feel that mathematics is cold, hard,
uncaring, impersonal, rule-driven, fixed and stereotypically masculine. Evidently there is
a strong parallel between the absolutist conception of mathematics, the negative popular
view of mathematics, and separated values. Likewise, a second parallel exists between
the fallibilist conception of mathematics, connected values and the humanistic image of
mathematics promoted by modern progressive mathematics education as accessible,
personally relevant and creative (Cockcroft 1982, NCTM 2000).
The second parallel can be used to improve accessibility and the public image of
mathematics, although it should also be recognised that the absolutist image of
mathematics attracts some people to it. Many mathematicians and others love
mathematics for its absolutist features. It is both consistent and common for teachers and
mathematicians to hold an absolutist view of mathematics as neutral and value free, but
to regard mathematics teaching as necessitating the adoption of humanistic, connected
values. This raises again the issue of the relationship between philosophies of
mathematics, values and teaching.
🡻 🡮⬃ 🡻
Separated Values ⬃ 🡮 Connected Values 🡻 ⇩
(‘crossing
over’) 🡫🡻
Separated
Mathematics
Classroom practice
Humanistic
compliance’)
(‘strategic
Mathematics
Classroom practice
This, subject to the constraints and opportunities afforded by social context of schooling,
often results in separated mathematics classroom practice. Likewise, a fallibilist
philosophy of mathematics combined with connected values can give rise to a connected
view of school mathematics. Subject to the same constraints, this can result in a
humanistic mathematics classroom practice. These two possible sets of relations are
shown by bold vertical arrows. They represent the most straightforward relationships
between philosophies, values and mathematics classroom practices.
Finally, it is possible for the various constraints of the social context of schooling to be
so powerful that a teacher with connected values and a humanistic view of school
mathematics is forced into ‘strategic compliance’ (Lacey 1977), resulting in a separated
mathematics classroom practice. This is indicated in Figure 2 by the bold and thin arrows
deviating left towards the separated classroom practice following the impact of the social
context. This practice may originate with either an absolutist philosophy (thin arrows), or
a fallibilist philosophy (bold arrows), but in both cases ‘crosses over’. Empirical research
has confirmed that teachers with very distinct personal philosophies of mathematics
(absolutist and fallibilist) have been constrained by the social context of schooling to
teach in a traditional, separated way (Lerman 1986).
I suggest that values as well as beliefs and philosophies play a key role in determining
the underlying images and philosophies embodied in mathematics classroom practice.
This is not surprising, since such values are realised in the type of teacher-pupil
relations, the degree of competitiveness, the extent of negative weight placed on errors,
the degree of public humiliation experienced in consequence of failure, and other such
factors which powerfully impact on learners’ attitudes, self-esteem and images of
mathematics.
Much work in the philosophy of mathematics education pertains to exploring the link
between the philosophies of mathematics implicit in teachers' beliefs, in texts and the
mathematics curriculum, in systems and practices of mathematical assessment and in
mathematics classroom practices and ethos, and the results with learners. While much
progress has been made in illuminating such influences, it is clear that the relationships
are complex and non
deterministic.
One concern that is illuminated by this enquiry is the relatively weak link between the
philosophy of education and mathematics education. This is a relationship that needs to
be more actively explored and developed. Like mathematics, mathematics education has
too much of a tendency to isolate it from adjacent areas of knowledge and enquiry. How
often, for example, do we look to developments in science education? The philosophy of
mathematics
education is one approach that should facilitate the building of links with other areas of
knowledge and research. This essay suggests a number of directions in which we could
turn our gaze to begin to do this.
References
Ausubel, D. P. (1968) Educational Psychology, a cognitive view, New York: Holt, Rinehart and
Winston.
Barnard, T. and Saunders, P. (1994) ‘Is school mathematics in crisis?’, The Guardian, 28
December 1994: 18.
Buerk, D. (1982) An Experience with Some Able Women Who Avoid Mathematics, For the Learning
of Mathematics, Vol. 3, No. 2: 19-24.
Cockcroft, W. H., Chair, (1982) Mathematics Counts, London: Her Majesty's Stationery
Office.
Cooney, T. J. (1988) The Issue of Reform, Mathematics Teacher, Vol. 80: 352-363.
Davis, P. J. (1972) Fidelity in Mathematical Discourse: Is One and One Really Two?
American Mathematical Monthly, Vol. 79, No. 3: 252-263.
Dowling, P. (1988) The Contextualising of Mathematics: Towards a Theoretical Map, in Harris, M. Ed.
Schools, Mathematics and Work, London, Falmer, 1991: 93-120.
Ernest, P. (1988) The Attitudes and Practices of Student Teachers of Primary School
Mathematics, in A. Borbas (Ed.) Proceedings of PME-12, Veszprem, Hungary, Vol. 1: 288-
295.
Ernest, P. (1989a) The Impact of Beliefs on the Teaching of Mathematics, in Ernest, P. Ed.
Mathematics Teaching: The State of the Art, London, Falmer Press, 1989: 249-254.
Paris. Ernest, P. (1991) The Philosophy of Mathematics Education, London: Falmer Press.
Ernest, P. Ed. (1994b) Mathematics, Education and Philosophy: An International Perspective, London:
Falmer Press.
Gage, N. L. (1989) The Paradigm Wars and Their Aftermath: A 'Historical' Sketch of
Research on Teaching Since 1989, Teachers College Record, Vol. 91, No. 2: 135-150.
Hersh, R. (1979) Some Proposals for Reviving the Philosophy of Mathematics, Advances in
Mathematics, Vol. 31: 31-50.
Kilpartrick, J and Sierpinska, A., Eds. (1998) Mathematics Education as a Research Domain,
Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Lacey, C. (1977) The Socialization of Teachers, London: Methuen.
Lerman, S. (1986) Alternative Views of the Nature of Mathematics and their Possible Influence
on the Teaching of Mathematics, unpublished Ph.D. Thesis, King's College, University of
London.
Maxwell, J. (1989) ‘Mathephobia’, in Ernest, P. Ed. Mathematics Teaching: The State of the Art,
London, Falmer Press, 1989: 221-226.
NCTM (2000) Principles and Standards for School Mathematics, Reston, Virginia:
National Council of Teachers of Mathematics.
Riley, R. W. (1998) ‘The State of Mathematics Education: Building a Strong Foundation
for the 21st Century’, Conference of American Mathematical Society and Mathematical
Association of America, Thursday, January 8, 1998.
Schwab, J. J. (1961) 'Education and the Structure of the Disciplines' in Westbury, I. and
Wilkof, N. J., Eds., Science, Curriculum and Liberal Education: Selected Essays of
Joseph J. Schwab, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1978, 229-272.
Kluwer. Steen, L. A. (1988) The Science of Patterns, Science, Vol. 240, No. 4852: 611-616.
(Ernest 1991)
[2]
For example, it is possible to imagine an approach to the philosophy of mathematics education that is
primarily historical, rather than falling under the five areas of investigation listed above. This might
consider Plato’s ideas about mathematics and its teaching and learning, as well as those of Pythagoras,
Euclid, the Babylonians, ancient Egyptians, Pacioli, Robert Recorde, Descartes, and other medieval and
modern mathematicians and movements. For virtually all mathematics texts and books throughout history
have an educational purpose and function, and for many this is their prime purpose. Through such aims
they must embody a mathematical pedagogy and thus a philosophy of mathematics education. Howson’s
(1982) historical approach embodies elements of such an enquiry although it is not philosophically
intended. As Steiner (1987: 8) says “Concepts for the teaching and learning of mathematics - more
specifically: goals and objectives (taxonomies), syllabi, textbooks, curricula … carry with them or even
rest upon (often in an implicit way) particular philosophical and epistemological views of mathematics."
For simplicity I have not mentioned yet another approach termed the critical-theoretic or critical
[3]
research, paradigm which focuses on social change for social justice rather than validatory or
exploratory research.
In this section I illustrate one way of conceptualising this complex range of relationships. I do not
[4]
claim to offer a definitive account. By their nature, all such accounts depend on the orientation of the
author and are undoubtedly contestable, if not questionable.