Leijonhufvud, A. Information and Coordination Cap. 9 y 10
Leijonhufvud, A. Information and Coordination Cap. 9 y 10
Leijonhufvud, A. Information and Coordination Cap. 9 y 10
AND COORDINATION
Essays in Macroeconomic Theory
AXEL LEIJONHUFVUD
l. INTRODUCTION
One approach to the problem of the microeconomic founda-
tions of macro-economics takes the frame and the components
of standard "neoclassical" theory as the given starting point.
One asks what can be used and what needs modification for
purposes of representing the movement of a macro-system
through time and into a future that is in sorne respects un-
knowable. The aim is to define and, if possible, solve the analyt-
ical problems that emerge at the levels of individual conceptual
experiments, market experiments, and general equilibrium ex-
periments. I have pursued this approach in other recent
papers 1 but am running into diminishing returns.
An alternative approach is to start from the other end with
sorne "applied" problem, preferably one of such importance
that no macroeconomist can really afford to dodge it, and con-
sider the difficulties that arise in trying to handle it in a "rea-
sonable" way with standard micro-theoretical tools. From this
viewpoint we get a different critica] angle on the problems
requiring solution if micro- and macro-theory are to be made to
mesh. This is the approach taken in this paper.
T he "practica!" macro-question to be considered here is that
of the social costs and consequences of inflation. A new view of
the welfare costs of inflation has emerged in the last ten or fif-
* I am thankful to Armen Alchian, Roben Clower, Ben Klein, John McCall and Sidney
Afriat for comments and obliged to d eclare them free from responsibility. Financia!
support of the Liberty Fund is gratefully acknowledged.
l. Leijonhufvud (1974, 1974-5).
227
INFORMATION AND COORDINATION
228
COSTS ANO CONSEQ UENCES OF INFLATION
229
INFORMATION ANO COORDINATION
230
COSTS AND CONSEQUENCES OF INFLATION
231
INFORMATION AND COORDINATION
232
COSTS ANO CONSEQUENCES OF INFLATION
233
INFORMATION ANO COORDINATION
234
COSTS AND CONSEQUENCES OF INFLATION
235
INFORMATION ANO COORDINATION
than has yet gone into social benefit-cost analysis. If, then, re-
peated rounds of gradually improved social cost calculations for
inflation keep repeating the answer that it is relatively trivial, it
gives one pause to note that the law is helpless to assure justice
in inflations.
Because of this impotence of the law, inflations tend to accel-
erate the secular tendency of most Western countries to rnove
away from the Rule of Law toward Rule by Men. Associated
therewith, we expect to observe a tendency for the dominant
popular conception of social justice in democratic societies to
shift from Equality under the Law towards Income Equality.
The first of these conceptions focuses on the evenhanded appli-
cation of the rules governing social and economic activities irre-
spective of the identities of individuals and of the social status
they occupy, etc. The second focuses on the ex post real outcome
of individual economic activity. 16
The two linked tendencies are, of course, subject to divergent
value j udgments. Sorne would cheer them on, others wish that
they could be braked, halted, or even reversed. Here we are
concerned to argue only that the strength of these tendencies
will be associated with inflation and, consequently, that this as-
sociation should be considered in assessing the consequences of
inflation. One note might be added to this: namely, that infla-
tions, even as they speed up the process, are likely to make or-
derly and coherent evolution in the d irections indicated more
difficult to achieve.
The law is help less to assure that a just real outcome is re-
stored to contracts concluded in nominal terms. That is so for
rather simple reasons. The expectations about the rate of infla-
tion in prospect 17 that th e two parties originally held cannot be
16. I n o rder to get on with the topic, this paragraph had better be left as is--patently
inadequate. Two references to cover my escape: Hayek (1973) and Rawls (1971). Toe
basic o pposition between Hayek's emphasis on "spontaneous orders" and Rawls's
equally evident "constmctivism" need not, as fa r as 1 can see, p roduce a clash in the
context of th is section (Chap ter 10 would be another matter-but there I will avoid the
issue).
17. He1·e and elsewhere we make use of "the rate of inAation" as if bo th parties to a con-
tract would define inAation, with regard to their own best economic interests, in terms
of money-price changes of sh-ictly identical composite baskets.
This fudge seems unavoidable if we are to go ahead with the arg ument. But-<:ould
this condition ever be exactly fulfilled (while leaving room for gains from trade between
236
COSTS ANO CONSEQUENCES OF INFLATION
237
INFORMATION AND COORDINATION
238
COSTS AND CONSEQUENCES OF INFLATION
239
INFORMATION AND COORDINATION
22. T he actual economic "game" that people find themselves "playing" has vast arrays
of the pay-off matrix" blan k ex ante. Entire dimensions of the ouLcome space are left
unspecified (also in the probabilistic sense). WhaL Lhe parties will know about most of
the "blan ks" of the matrix, however, is that, if that is where they find Lhemselves ending
up, Lhe courts will adjudicate: i.e., will provide an ex post definition of what Lhe rules
should have been understood to have been. They will expect, moreover, thaL sucl1 a
ruling will most often, tho ugh not invariably, "make sense" to them. More importantly,
they know that they will not end up deadlocked in an irreconcilable conflict.
One of Lhe d imensions of the matrix should be reserved for drnnges in the value of
money. Along that d imension, the above observations do noL hold.
240
COSTS AND CONSEQUENCES OF INFLATION
241
INFORMATION AND COORDINATION
struggling to establish their own coinage as a dominant money. Lending the powers of
the law to the enforcement of prívate agreements concluded in comracling units that
do not correspond to the payment unit of government issued legal tender would entail
a self-imposed constraint on the sovereign's ability to rely on inílationary finance in a
pinch. But in Finland the prohibition is recen!, having been imposed following the
abandonment of the celebrated Finnish experiment with indexation.
25. Cf. B. Klein ( 1976).
26. Such short-term employment contract.s will not be affected by the capital gains
provisions of tax-law. It may be lhat it is chieíly the tax law that inhibits the develop-
ment of longer term index contract markets. I doubl, however, that this could be the
whole story.
242
COSTS ANO CONSEQUENCES OF INFLATION
243
INFORMATION ANO COORDINATION
244
COSTS AND CONSEQUENCES OF INFLATION
31. !bid.
245
INFORMATION AND COORDINATION
246
COSTS AND CONSEQUENCES OF INFLATION
IV A
Being efficient and competitive at the production a nd distribu-
tion of "real" goods and services becomes less important to the
real outcome of socio-economic activity. Forecasting inflation
and coping with its consequences become more important.
People will r eallocate their effort and ingenuity accordingly.
The relative significance of two types of capacity for adapta-
tion to changing conditions has changed. The product de-
signer who can come up with a marginally improved or more
attractive product, the p roductio n manager who in a good year
is capable of increasing the product per man hour by a per cent
or two, the vice president of sales who might reduce the real
cost of distribution by sorne similar amount, etc., have ali be-
come less important to the stable functioning and/or survival of
the organisations to whi ch they belong. Other functions requir-
ing different talents h ave increased in importance: the vice
president of finance with a tale nt for so adjusting the balance
sheet as to minimise the real incidence of an unpredictable
inflation ra te is an example. But the "wise gu y" who can do a
good job at second-guessing th e m onetary authorities sorne
moves ahead is the one wh o really counts. Smart assessment of
the risks generated by the política! game comes to outweigh
sound judgement of "ordinary" business risks. Other roles will
247
INFORMATION AND COORDINATION
248
COSTS AND CONSEQUENCES OF INFLATION
ing union activism. 33 In any case, we should note that the asso-
ciation between high inflation and union activism, out of which
has been conjured the inflation theory most "popular" in sorne
other countries, is observable also in the United States. Unions
will not only bargain harder and more frequently, they will also
Jobby more energetically and continuously in Washington and
¡0 State capitals. This brings us to our second set of observa-
tions about the behavioural adaptations that we expect to find.
IV B
People will rely relatively less on private contracts and relatively
more on political compacts in trying to ensure for themselves a
reliable frame for their economic lives.
Inflation, and particularly a ragged inflation , renders prívate
agreements less reliable in their outcome. Inflation also renders
prívate agreements less "agreeable"-shall we call it?- in the
simple sense that the fact that both parties initially entered into
an agreement "voluntary" carries much less of a guarantee that
it can be carried out amicably and without rancour than is the
case in a regime of stable prices. 34
The "economic interest" of individuals goes beyond consum-
ing food, clothing, shelter, health care, entertainment, and so
on. We all strive to control our fates, to shape our lives, and to
gain sorne sphere of relative autonomy in the midst of a world
which "in the large" is quite beyond our control. Most of us are
conscious that the trouble with unemployment and with pov-
erty lies less in the reduced size of the "consumption basket"-
which at other times and in other places has allowed people to
live contentedly and with dignity-than in the loss of control
and autonomy in this sense that individuals experience. Were
it otherwise, a programme of adequate hand-outs could eradi-
cate the social problem-a barbarous presumption.
33. While this should be to our advantage in trying to understand the processes in
which we are caught up, it is one that we squander by simply going witch-hunting
among big business and food-chain middlemen, etc., instead. The natural sciences have
got rid of "animism" ali the way clown through primary school but "social animism" still
is a far, far way from fall ing into general disrepute.
34. Cf. Hicks (1970): . .. direct economic loss and (very often) loss oftemper as well."
249
INFORMATION ANO COORDINATION
35. In less developed countries, a slowing down or reve1·sal of the movement out of the
"subsistence sector" and into the "market economy" may be the more feasible adapta-
tion. In highly developed industrial economies, to withdraw into economic activities the
outcomes of which are largely not contingent u pon what others do will not be a relevant
option for any significant number of people. It is ignored here. The process of eco-
nomic development is not reversible-which is not to say that a developed economy
could not unravel and come apart at the seams.
250
COSTS ANO CONSEQUENCES OF INFLATION
251
INFORMATION ANO COORDINATION
252
COSTS AND CONSEQUENCES OF INFLATION
253
INFORMATION ANO COORDINATION
254
COSTS ANO CONSEQUENCES OF INFLATION
255
INFORMATION AND COORDINATION
256
COSTS AND CONSEQUENCES OF INFLATION
257
INFORMATION ANO COORDINATION
258
COSTS AND CONSEQUENCES OF INFLATION
Scale-economies will affect who does and who <loes not try hard
to do so. Traders expecting to transact large quantities will in-
vest considerable resources in keeping track of prices. (Still, one
would not expect a 10-20 percent inftation to be "enough" to
call forth inftation-trading specialists in large numbers--die Gu-
laschbaronen are not yet prominent amongst us). Most house-
holds will not try to maintain their stock of price-information at
tbe "quality" they normally desire-even as they spend more ef-
fort at it. If beef prices go up in every odd-numbered week and
potatoes every even week, sensible beef-and-potato eaters will
resign themselves to a constant proportions diet that is non-
optimal every week-and curse the statisticians who assert their
real income is unaffected by it ali.
Perhaps that sort of thing is not important. But another
proposition, I feel, is: Transactors will not be able to sort out the rele-
vant "real" price signals from the relative price changes due to these
iriflationary leads and lags. How could they? Messages of changes
in "real scarcities" come in through a cacaphony of noises sig-
nifying nothing . . . and "sound" no different. To assume that
agents generally possess the independent information required
to filter the significant messages from the noise would, I think,
amount to assuming knowledge so comprehensive that reliance
on market prices for information should have been unneces-
sary in the first place. Sorne adjustments in resource allocation
that are needed will not be made. Sorne will be made that
should not have been. Between the omissions and commissions,
the vector of effective excess demands is distorted and the
"hunt" for the G.E. solution vector goes off on false trails.
Transactors will gradually lose all firm conception of where
the equilibrium neighbourhood for relative prices lies. Setting
prices and determining reservation wages becomes a more dif-
ficu lt problem-and also a problem that no longer "makes
sense" in the way it used to. We may safely assume that, even in
more stable times imposing less pressing short-run information
requirements, agents have not been used to consider the prob-
lem in n dimensions. Rather, your own past price was used as
the main "precedent'' to be revised in the light of new informa-
tion on changes in demand and on developments in a relative
small set of markets-for the main inputs and substitute prod-
259
INFORMATION AND COORDINATION
260
COSTS AND CONSEQUENCES OF INFLATION
261
INFORMATION AND COORDINATION
262
COSTS ANO CONSEQUENCES OF INFLATION
50. E.g., the type of process we adduce in explaining to students why refraining from
"destabilising speculation" has survival-value in commodity markets.
5 1. Klein (1974).
263
INFORMATION ANO COORDINATION
2. From the mid 1930s through to the early 1960s or so, "ra-
tional expectations" (for Americans) might have been to
count on the monetary authorities to revert to a zero rate of
change "as soon as feasible."
3. Klein refers to the situation of recent years as one of a
"purely fiduciary standard." This is a fair description-but
how would one describe the operating "rules" that would
govern the "probability distributions" of future price levels?
I would not even try. 52 My impression is that the interna-
tional monetary "system" has for sorne time been in a period of
unstructured experimentation and "innovation." Whether this
will converge to a stable institutional arrangement and, if so,
what it will be like seems obscure indeed-if for no other rea-
sons than that those doing the innovating do not understand
what they are tampering with or know what their criteria of
design should be.
In the United States, a transactor might listen to those econo-
mists who argue that policy should not be employed to reduce
inflation, but at most to stabilise it. If he believes they rule the
world, he will get unity as the lower bound to the elasticity of
his price-level expectations.53 Another transactor, looking back
over the past ten years, might be more impressed with the fact
that the Fed will still, whenever unemployment is "tolerable,"
listen to Congressional complaints of "high" (nominal) interest
52. The type of "uncertainty" envisaged in most standard economic models of deci-
sion-making under uncertainty may be illustrated by a game of dice. We know the
properties of the mechanism generating the probability distribulion of outcomes. If the
agent does not know it-tbe dice may be biased, say-a Bayesian learning model may
still be used to model his adaptive behaviour. For most economic decisions, the game of
chess may, however, be the better source of appropriate metaphors. Here we cannot
exhaustively specify ali tbe possible alternalive future positions in a game. Con-
sequently, the "actuaria! calculus" cannot be applied to the decision-problems of the
game (cf. also p. 240 and footnote 22 above).
Consider then major business decisions, the outcomes of which are crucially depen-
dent u pon the future rate of inflation, and which have to be made in a setting where no
rules, ultimately constraining the rate of money creation, are accepted as "constitu-
tionally binding" by the legislature and monetary authorities. Observed inflation rates
are not "drawn" from a probability distribution generated by a law-abiding mechanism.
T he appropriate metaphor fo r this case, 1 suggest, is that of playing "chess" in Lhe pres-
ence of an official who has and uses tl1e power arbitrarily to change tl1e rules-i.e., a
man who may interrupt at move 14 with the announcement: "From now on bishops
move like rooks and vice versa . . . and 1'11 be back with more later."
53. Cf. again, Davidson a nd Kregel ( 1975).
264
COSTS AND CONSEQUENCES OF INFLATION
265
INFORMATION AND COORDINATION
266
COSTS AND CONSEQUENCES OF INFLATION
267
INFORMATION AND COORDINATION
266
COSTS AND CONSEQUENCES OF INFLATION
269
CHAPTER TEN
lnflation and the Economists:
Critique
11
Five times the American public has been promised a campaign
to end inflation:
l. the "Art of Central Banking" credit crunch of 1966;
2. the "Keynesian" tax surcharge;
3. the "monetarist" crunch of 1969-70;
4. the price freeze of autumn 1971 plus the price control
"stages";
5. the 1974 biggest crunch of them all.
Rounds (2) and (4), in one sense, should not count. They were
interludes during which the monetary system was stoked up for
a resumption of worse inflation. In another sense, they do
count, namely, as parts of the pattern showing our policy-insti-
tutions consistently failing to deliver on ballyho'ed prom-
ises. The public has come increasingly to doubt that policy-
271
INFORMATION ANO COORDINATION
272
INFLATION ANO THE ECONOMISTS: CRITIQUE
111
Economists have not controlled events, of course. One can tell
chis deplorable story as a sequence of hard-to-handle ex-
ogenous disturbances combining with abnormal obstacles to the
formulation and execution of a consistent, coherent stabilisa-
tion policy-Peruvian sardines conspiring with Arabian sheikhs
to make things difficult; first a President intent on "guns and
butter," then one inattentive because of Watergate; a Congress
too preoccupied with Vietnam or Watergate to produce the
right fiscal policy with short enough lags; and, of course, the
always accursed Fed. The "foil" story of the last ten years would
be a very complex tale indeed; obviously, having that tale told
right would be useful. But the trouble with a complex tale is
that one cannot draw a simple Moral from it.
Could it be that through this tangled web of events there
runs a skein of systematic error in policy-response? If so, why-
and wh y not earlier? And, if we systematically fail to do things
right, <loes the economics profession have any part of the re-
sponsibili ty?
It may be that simple Morals follow only from outright Fa-
bles. Perhaps my impressions add up to no more than a Fable.
IV
It has become a widespread view among American professional
economists that the economic costs and social dangers of infla-
tion tend to be grossly overestimated by the general public and
among policy-makers, particularly in relation to the social costs
and dangers of unemployment.
I disagree with this "New View." Indeed, I am apprehensive
that the undesirability of inflation is, if anything, underes-
timated by politicians, media commentators, and the public.
Hence, as an economist, I am quite untypically fearful of infla-
tion . I n any scientific field, the untypical view is most likely to
be quite wrong.
But the econ omics profession as a whole has not done its
homework on inflation. We have little in the way of well vali-
273
INFORMATION ANO COORDINATION
V
T he policy-rnaking institutions are endogenous to the systern
the behaviour with which we are concerned. A change in the
perceived ratio of the costs associated with inflation relative to
those associated with unernployrnent will change the response-
pattern of the policy-rnaking "sector" and thereby the dynamic
behaviour of the systern as a whole. A reduction in the per-
274
INFLATION AND THE ECONOMISTS: CRITIQUE
VI
Now, I "feel" that the New View on inflation is "unsound" and
would use the same word for th~ various statements about the
"ratio of social costs" or the "social marginal rate of substitu-
tion" b etween the two ills of unemployment and inflation. I say
"unsound" rather than "wrong" because it is unclear whether
275
INFORMATION AND COORDINATION
VII
The notion of a stable Phillips Curve is gone. By now, every-
body's Phillips Curve shifts and tilts and loops, now clockwise,
now counterclockwise-and goes north by east when the Gods
are against you . The original idea has evaporated. But it has
left us a curious legacy-the empty space where it used to be.
And we stay there, spinning perilous confusions in it.
The original problem was to explain the rate of change of
money wages. Suppose, like other prices, they move in response
to "excess demand." How measure it? Unemployment must
surely reflect "excess supply" of labour. Suppose observed un-
employment to be a stable proxy for the theorist's concept of
"excess supply." A reasonable hypothesis that deserves a try.
Phillips tried it and thought the results encouraging enough to
warrant further pursuit of the general approach. But the hy-
pothesis was falsified in the same paper where it was advanced.
The "loops" in the data and the vertical scatter at low unem-
ployment showed that the two variables were not related by a
(single-valued) function.
In a famous paper, Samuelson and Solow 1 used a Phillips
Curve regression as the basis for a discussion of the policy-
maker's "Dilemma"-he cannot have price-stability and a toler-
able leve! of unemployment at the same time. This Dilemma
discussion set the context in which the Phillips Curve became
popularised, quickly gaining entry to the textbooks and from
there into the financia! pages.
The change in the perception of the Phillips-curve construct
that this carne to entail was of considerable significance. The
Dilemma discussion tentatively treated Phillips Curve regres-
276
INFLATION ANO THE ECONOMISTS: CRITIQUE
VIII
The inflation rate and the unemployment rate are considered
as "outcomes" of policy. To alternative policy programmés
under consideration there will correspond combinations of the
two forecast ("for next year") with more or less accuracy. The
locus of these combinations is thought of as an opportunity set
277
INFORMATION AND COORDINATION
278
INFLATION ANO THE ECONOMISTS: CRITIQUE
Having defined the rest of the problem for himself as "a mat-
ter of preferences" he will tend to ignore the factual consequences
of inflation and unemployment as subjects of research. Value
judgements he knows to be statements irreducible within eco-
nomics itself. Economic enquiry halts where it runs up against
normative propositions and <loes not trespass on the ground
beyond them.
Since the política] process <loes not in fact grind out a social
welfare function, no one knows what it is. For an economist
who looks at this as "a matter of preferences," it is by that token
also a matter on which "everyone is entitled to his say" includ-
ing, of course, he himself. At the same time, however, to such
statements about what "should be" done will apply that part of
the professional credo which runs: De gustibus non est cli.1putan-
dum. Here, then, we do not necessarily expect to see a Pop-
perian process in operation. So when economists earnestly lec-
ture students, newspaper readers or members of Congress on
what the public good dictates with regard to the inflation-
unemployment trade-off to be made next, what they say may
not have been through any crucible of Popperian criticism. But
they are likely to get a serious and attentive hearing anyway.
Many people will defer to sorne degree to our opinions on the
rather natural assumption that, selectively filtered through per-
sonal value judgements as these normative recommendations
may be, what has been thus filtered must still be a much more
detailed, objective knowledge of what inflation and/or unem-
ployment "means" than laymen would possess. But is not such
deference quite misplaced?
"Values" and "knowledge" will be conflated in what they hear
and read, all right. But how they are fused and how they might
be disentangled is obscure. And when their expression takes
the form of an indifference map in Phillips Curve space, who is
to distinguish shoddy ethics and sketchy knowledge from their
genuine, warranted counterparts?
IX
The unclear fusion of values and knowledge poses a nasty pre-
dicament for whoever thinks he sees "unsound" views gaining
279
INFORMATION AND COORDINATION
280
INFLATION AND THE ECONOMISTS: CRITIQUE
X
Since disputing over tastes is so fruitless, one is tempted to try
another tack. Professional training may "pervert" an econo-
mist's attitudes to social questions to sorne degree, but they are
naturally shaped very largely by the same influences that
operate on everybody else. lf disputing these attitudes is point-
less and/or illegitimate, those critica! of them are tempted into
sociological reflection to "explain" them instead. For example:
281
INFORMATION AND COORDINATION
282
INFLATION AND THE ECONOMISTS: CRITIQUE
XI
The last ten years have brought a spreading realisation among
economists that subjective value judgements on the relative so-
cial undesirability of inflation and unemployment are not good
enough and that the presumed objective components of the
policy recommendations made need be brought out in the
open. One result of this has been a number of simple social
benefit-cost (or, rather, comparative social cost) calculations on
inflation and unemployment. T he early examples of this brand
of Political Arithmetick have produced numerical results that,
on the face of it, strongly support the most complacent attitude
about inflation: it takes an inflation rate well into double digits
or even near triple digits to equal the social cost of 1 (addi-
tional) per cent of unemployment. Such "objectification" of the
issue compels adoption of a common unit of social cost-
measurement; this, of course, is unnecessary when the problem
is left in "preference space." The results obtained depend over-
whelmingly on the choice of measuring-rod for social cost that
has been made. For unemployment, the choice has been the na-
tional product loss attributable to the market inactivity of the
unemployed. At first sight, this may seem a "natural" measure
for the social cost of unemployment. A second look is less reas-
suring. In any case, this choice necessitates measuring the cost
of inflation also in terms of "output loss"- a less obvious notion.
What is thus quantified as the cost of inflation is sorne estímate
of the productive and transactional inefficiencies associated
with attempts to economise on the holding of money balances
that will be induced by the negative real rate on money during
inflations. This, of course, turns out to be a modest number. To
283
INFORMATION ANO COORDINATION
the extent that inflation does not affect the size of the "G.N.P.
pie" annually turned out by the economy, it is considered to
have zero social cost.
This social cost concept, then, is drawn from a social welfare
function into which "distributive justice" arguments do not
enter in the sketchy, implicit, and haphazard way in which they
tend to be present in expressions of "social preferences." On
the unemployment side, the "output-cost" is the same whether
the unemployed receive compensation or not. It is similarly in-
variant to the time that individuals spend in an unemployment
pool of given size. If one individual is "voluntarily" unem-
ployed and foil of hope that he can do better than the employ-
ment opportunities immediately open to him while another in-
dividual in despair and resentment sees no better alternative
than criminal activity-the measure of "social cost" is the same.
On the infiation side, the neglect of ali other consequences than
aggregate output-loss may be given a semblance of respect-
ability by assuming (a) that redistributive losers can be compen-
sated, or (b) that they will be compensated, or (c) that, as the
inflation is or becomes foreseen, transactors will be able to safe-
guard themselves so as to make compensation irrelevant. None
of these (including the first one) is sound on the face of it. What
particu lar mix of the three is relied upon in these cost-calcula-
tions is not aJways clear. The questions left dangling are with-
out end: How is the probability of receiving or the ability of ob-
taining compensation distributed among losers? What is the
probability that compensation will be paid by gainers? What in-
stitutional mechanisms exist or can be conceived to carry out re-
redistribution? By what methods are the gains and losses to be
ascertained and accurately measured? How are the skills
required to conduct one's affairs successfully in an inflationary
regime distributed in society? And assuming ali these things to
be known and settled, can we evaluate the results as if they
were "final outcomes"? Or do, perhaps, further social conse-
quences flow and economic implications follow from these
"given" results?
Economists wh o have tried their hand at this sort of PoliticaJ
Arithmetick have not claimed anything more than rou gh -and-
ready first approximations. T he suggestion is rather that this
284
INFLATION AND THE ECONOMISTS: CRITIQUE
XII
I know I have not lived up to customary standards of rational,
objective discussion so far. I feel compelled to take up these "is-
sues," but I cannot rnake sense of them. Not being able to make
sense of what I am talking about cramps my style.
The benefit-cost arithmetic is not my basic problem. lt is the
more general, underlying Social Welfare Function concep-
285
INFORMATION ANO COORDINATION
286
INFLATION AND THE ECONOMISTS: CRITIQUE
287
INFORMATION AND COORDINATION
288
INFLATION AND THE ECONOMISTS: CRITIQUE
XIII
"The social welfare function is a conceptas broad and empty as
Ianguage itself-and as necessary." 2 Perhaps. With any given
Janguage, though, we need sorne set of injunctions: "Whereof
one cannot speak . . . " etc.
The concepts of the "New" welfare economics at one time did
useful service in identifying the dangers lurking in the "Old."
Yet, in contexts such as the present one, what makes the S.W.F.
notion survive-except fascination with its inexhaustible short-
comings, so many of which will look potentially remediable. ?
T he Samuelsonian "necessity" of imagining a S.W.F. follows
only from prior acceptance of the "necessity" of conceptualising
any problem of policy in choice-theoretical terms. O f the con-
cepts of choice-th eory we may also say that they are "as broad
and empty as language itself . . . " etc. Again, misuse of the lan-
guage needs to be guarded against. Naiveté about the defini-
tion of the "outcomes" of ch oice may, as we have seen, set this
engine of analysis to producing the most appalling muddles.
But there are more serious questions to consider beyond such
abuses. Is a choice-th eoretical formulation always th e sine qua
non far "rational" conduct of policy? T he "choice" may be be-
tween irreversible historical processes that we ill understand
and which we can control only to the extent that a rodeo rider
controls the Brahma bull. Squeezed into the apples and oranges
frame, the world is portrayed "as if' unde rstood and subject to
precalculated control. When the "as if' clause hides more in the
way of unrecognized distortion than of probabi listic approxi-
mation of the situation, the "constructivist error" is afoot. And
that way líes the "Collectivisation of H ubris." 3
We should be on guard against the type of mentality we are
cultivating, or we will end up with students trained to translate
human drama into jargon: Assume a young man n amed Oe-
dipus X; h is utility-function is quadratic, his opportunities
strictly convex, and so, natu rally, he.
2. Quoted from Samuelson (1952), p. 37.
3. Cf. Spengler ( 1972).
289