Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

Nadelhoffer 2007

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 29

Philosophical Explorations, Vol. 10, No.

2, June 2007

THE PAST AND FUTURE OF


EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY

Thomas Nadelhoffer and Eddy Nahmias1

Experimental philosophy is the name for a recent movement whose participants use the methods
of experimental psychology to probe the way people think about philosophical issues and then
examine how the results of such studies bear on traditional philosophical debates. Given both
the breadth of the research being carried out by experimental philosophers and the
controversial nature of some of their central methodological assumptions, it is of no surprise
that their work has recently come under attack. In this paper we respond to some criticisms of
experimental philosophy that have recently been put forward by Antti Kauppinen. Unlike the
critics of experimental philosophy, we do not think the fledgling movement either will or should
fall before it has even had a chance to rise up to explain what it is, what it seeks to do (and not
to do), and exactly how it plans to do it. Filling in some of the salient details is the main goal of
the present paper.

KEYWORDS experimental philosophy; conceptual analysis; meta-philosophy; folk intuitions

1. Introduction
Experimental philosophy is the name for a recent movement whose participants use
the methods of experimental psychology to probe the way people make judgments that
bear on debates in philosophy. Although the movement has a name, it includes a variety
of projects driven by different interests, assumptions, and goals. Just in the past few
years philosophers have carried out experimental work in areas as diverse as epistemology,
action theory, free will and moral responsibility, the philosophy of language, ethics, the
philosophy of law, the philosophy of mind, and the philosophy of science.2 All of this
work shares a commitment to using controlled and systematic experiments to explore
people’s intuitions and conceptual usage and to examine how the results of such exper-
iments bear on traditional philosophical debates. But, as we will explain below, while
some experimental philosophers use data about ordinary intuitions to support philosophi-
cal theories, others use such data to better understand the psychological mechanisms that
generate such intuitions, while still others gather such data to show that some intuitions
may be too unreliable to support philosophical theories in the first place.3
Given both the breadth of the research being carried out by experimental philoso-
phers and the controversial nature of some of their central methodological assumptions,
it is no surprise that their work has recently come under attack. While we admittedly
share some of the worries expressed by critics of experimental philosophy, we nevertheless

ISSN 1386-9795 print/1741-5918 online/07/020123-27


# 2007 Taylor & Francis
DOI: 10.1080/13869790701305921
124 THOMAS NADELHOFFER AND EDDY NAHMIAS

disagree with many of their reservations, including those expressed by Antti Kauppinen in
this issue. We certainly do not think that experimental philosophy either will or should fall
before its practitioners have had a chance to rise up to explain what it is, what it seeks to do
(and not to do), and exactly how it plans to do it. Filling in some of these details is one of the
goals of the present paper. Along the way, we will flesh out important differences between
the various projects being undertaken by experimental philosophers, examine and respond
to the main criticisms put forward by Kauppinen, and suggest directions for future work in
experimental philosophy.
On our view, the burgeoning experimental philosophy movement has already made
a significant contribution to philosophy by highlighting some important issues that philo-
sophers need to address more fully, such as (i) the nature and evidentiary status of both
pre-philosophical intuitions and philosophically informed intuitions, (ii) the proper relation-
ship between intuitions, concepts, and theories, (iii) the proper methods and goals of con-
ceptual analysis, and (iv) the scope and limits of reflective equilibrium. By using
(philosophically) unconventional methods to bring these meta-philosophical questions
to the forefront, experimental philosophers have not only reinvigorated several important
debates in philosophy, they have also opened new avenues of interdisciplinary research
and dialogue. Regardless of what becomes of experimental philosophy in the future, we
think it has already made an important and enduring contribution to philosophy as a
whole by challenging some of the basic methodological assumptions that are woven
into the fabric of how many philosophers go about doing contemporary analytic
philosophy.4

2. The Past: Three Projects of Experimental Philosophy


The critics of experimental philosophy often treat it as a monolithic project driven by
the shared methodologies and goals of the experimental philosophers themselves. If this
were the case, then experimental philosophy would be much easier for its critics to
bring down with a single blow. But upon closer examination we find that this is decidedly
not the case. So, one strategy for defending experimental philosophy against its critics in
this paper will be to divide it into different projects and then examine the criticisms as
they individually apply—or fail to apply—to each of these projects. Sometimes, responding
to one criticism will require accepting another; conversely, criticisms that apply to one
project will sometimes fail to apply to others. As we will see, the diversity of experimental
philosophy is demonstrated by the fact that some criticisms require envisioning it in a way
that contradicts the way other criticisms envision it. And while it may be that all of the pro-
jects within experimental philosophy will not stand together—at least not as they are pre-
sently construed—we are nevertheless confident that the entire movement will not be
brought down by any of the current objections.5
Given the diversity of the projects carried out under the rubric of ‘experimental phil-
osophy,’ we should state as precisely as possible both what is unique about the fledgling
movement and what its participants have in common. For instance, what distinguishes
experimental philosophers from not only similarly-minded naturalistic and empirically
informed philosophers but also from experimental psychologists? Though the boundary
here is blurry, the primary difference is that experimental philosophers actually run their
own studies to get at the data they need and then show why these data are philosophically
interesting.6 Generally, they design surveys to test laypersons’ intuitive judgments about
PAST AND FUTURE OF EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY 125

philosophical issues, they run the surveys, and they statistically analyze the results. But
whereas the ‘experimental’ part of the name refers to the fact that they run studies and
collect data concerning folk intuitions, the ‘philosophy’ part refers to the fact that they
discuss the various implications these data have for philosophical debates.
Contrary to what some critics have claimed, experimental philosophers do not naively
believe that their results will solve philosophical debates and ‘put an end to vain quarrel’
(Kauppinen 2007, 100). As we will see, their goals and ambitions are typically more
modest than these critics suggest. Any areas of philosophy that rely on (i) intuition-pumps
and thought experiments, (ii) appeals to commonsense and pre-philosophical intuition
or (iii) conceptual analysis based in part on ordinary usage or ‘platitudes’7 are ripe for inves-
tigation by experimental philosophers who are, above all, interested in examining these
things in a controlled and systematic way. This interest is driven by two assumptions:
First, there is a shared distrust of philosophers’ (common) claims of the general form ‘X
is intuitive,’ ‘Ordinarily, we believe X,’ ‘The ordinary use of “X” is Y,’ ‘It is natural for
people to believe X,’ and the like. These are claims that philosophers usually make based
upon armchair reflection on their own intuitions and (perhaps selective) consideration of
their conversations with friends, family, and especially students.8 But these methods of
determining what is widely accepted seem highly susceptible to well-known biases such
as confirmation bias,9 disconfirmation bias,10 and false consensus bias11—biases that
may be even more pronounced in philosophers than laypersons given the philosophers’
extensive theoretical training and their use of intuition claims to confirm their own theor-
etical views.12
Philosophers are a rarefied and self-selected group, with a highly distinctive, largely
shared educational history. It is not at all obvious that the intuitions they report will offer an
accurate representation of the intuitions of non-philosophers. As Stephen Stich and
Jonathan Weinberg put it, philosophers are not justified in assuming without any support-
ing evidence beyond their own intuitions and introspective hunches, ‘that the intuitions of
high socio-economic status males, like themselves, who have advanced degrees in philos-
ophy, and whose cultural background is Western European can serve as a basis for gener-
alizations about the intuitions of “the folk”’(2001, 642; see also Stich 1998). For similar
reasons, it is also unclear to us how Kauppinen’s suggested method of ‘dialogue and reflec-
tion’ avoids these worries, especially since he suggests that, ‘in practice, assessing the truth
of intuition claims can remain a relatively armchair business’ (2007, 000). We take it that the
degree to which philosophers’ own intuitions and their reports of ordinary intuitions corre-
late with laypersons’ actual intuitions is an empirical question and that it is amenable to
controlled and systematic examination.
Indeed, the second assumption shared by experimental philosophers is that both
ordinary language usage and the intuitions of laypersons—as well as the claims that phi-
losophers make about them—can be approached through experimental methods
(though, of course, not only through experimental methods). And they suggest that in
cases where such methods have not been used by social scientists to examine these
issues, philosophers with the requisite skills should do so themselves. So far, experimental
philosophers have primarily used the methodology of presenting cases (sometimes derived
from philosophical thought experiments) to non-philosophers and systematically collecting
layperson’s responses to questions about those cases. The statistically analyzed results of
these studies have often been both surprising and perplexing. This partly explains one of
the best features of the experimental philosophy movement—namely that even
126 THOMAS NADELHOFFER AND EDDY NAHMIAS

philosophers who have competing explanatory models of the data frequently work
together to develop the next round of experiments or to figure out the best way to inter-
pret the results from all of the relevant studies about a given topic.
Despite the fact that all of the highly collaborative and interdisciplinary work that has
been done by experimental philosophers so far has been driven by these overarching com-
mitments, there are at least three distinct kinds of projects that have been undertaken.
While some work in experimental philosophy seeks primarily to find out what the folk
think in order to ascertain which philosophical theories best accord with and account for
commonsense intuitions, other work primarily aims to explore how the folk think—what
psychological mechanisms produce people’s intuitions or theories—and to determine
the relevance of this information to philosophical disputes. Finally, a third project within
experimental philosophy relies on data concerning cognitive diversity to argue that philo-
sophers should not use intuitions as evidence in their theorizing. In the remainder of this
section we will explain these three projects of experimental philosophy in more detail,
after which we will turn our attention to Kauppinen’s criticisms.13
According to the first branch of experimental philosophy—which we are going to call
‘Experimental Analysis’ (EA)—the primary goal is to explore in a controlled and systematic
manner what intuitions ordinary people tend to express and examine their relevance to
philosophical debates.14 Hence, they aim to test philosophers’ claims that their positions
align with common sense and to challenge those claims that are not supported by the evi-
dence. On this view, philosophical theories that most closely accord with and account for
ordinary beliefs and practices should enjoy ‘squatters’ rights’ until they are shown to be
defective for other reasons. In this respect, EAs essentially agree with many traditional phi-
losophers (including Kauppinen and those philosophers he discusses in Section 1 of his
paper) about the relevance of folk intuitions; they simply disagree about the best
methods for getting at these intuitions.15 Whereas the traditional philosopher is content
to rely on armchair speculation, introspection, and informal dialogue, EAs utilize
methods borrowed from experimental psychology to probe folk intuitions in a controlled
and systematic way.
Of course, EAs realize that even if a philosophical theory is shown to be more intuitive
than rival theories, it would not mean that the theory is true. Various responses are always
open to philosophers whose theory has less support from such intuitions. For instance, they
can offer error theories to explain away the intuitions (Greene 2002, forthcoming; Mackie
1977), or they can argue for revision of ordinary beliefs and practices in light of, for instance,
our best current science (Vargas 2005). However, until we first determine what the relevant
intuitions actually are, any talk about error theories and revisionism is premature; indeed,
experimental philosophy can play an important role in determining precisely when a
theory is revisionist and when error theories are required.
In addition to reporting the results of their studies, experimental philosophers also
explore background issues such as the nature and sources of intuitions, the role that
they should play in philosophy, how best to explore them, and what responses are available
to theorists whose views do not settle with folk intuitions. Take, for example, our work with
collaborators Jason Turner and Stephen Morris on folk intuitions about free will (Nahmias
et al. 2005, 2006). Our initial motivation was to test the common claim that folk intuitions
favor incompatibilism and that compatibilism is counter-intuitive.16 However, when our
participants read about agents performing actions in a deterministic world, the majority
judged that the agent does act of his own free will and is morally responsible for his
PAST AND FUTURE OF EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY 127

actions. We take these results to put pressure on the claim that incompatibilism is intuitive.
But we also offer arguments for why data like ours are relevant to the free will debate more
generally, and we discuss various incompatibilist responses to our methodology and our
results. We point out, for instance, that incompatibilists may argue that it is the inferential
principles leading to the incompatibilist conclusion that are intuitive, not the conclusion
itself; if so, it would be helpful to determine if those principles are in fact intuitive to
non-philosophers, since philosophers disagree about this question as well. Similarly,
other work in experimental philosophy such as Joshua Knobe’s research on the folk
concept of intentional action (2003, 2004a, 2004b) has included and inspired numerous
arguments about how and why the data are significant to debates about intentional
action and how best to interpret the data in light of various philosophical theories.17
Of course, experimental philosophers need not limit themselves to exploring what
folk intuitions are and why they matter to philosophy. They are also often interested in
the sources of these intuitions. Questions that arise in this context include: What kind of
cognitive mechanisms produce people’s intuitions about particular cases and are these
mechanisms reliable? How do we know which intuitions to trust, especially when we dis-
cover intuitions that conflict both within and between individuals? Might we better under-
stand the persistence of some philosophical debates by understanding how different
cognitive mechanisms generate conflicting intuitions? For another branch of experimental
philosophy, these questions have taken center stage.
According to this second project—which we are going to call ‘Experimental Descripti-
vism’ (ED)—it is not only important to investigate what folk intuitions actually are, but it is also
important to try to determine how these intuitions are generated.18 EDs explore human psy-
chology by testing how various manipulations to scenarios influence the intuitions people
express. One goal of this project is to better understand the nature of the underlying psycho-
logical processes and cognitive mechanisms that produce our intuitions and explore the rel-
evance of this research to philosophical questions. But EDs are not interested in these
cognitive processes and mechanisms for their own sake—rather, they rely on the gathering
data concerning how the mind works to support (or attack) first-order theories in philosophy.
Unlike EAs, who use the data concerning folk intuitions as foundations for conceptual analyses
of ‘free will,’ ‘intentional action,’ and the like, EDs use the evidence to show that certain phi-
losophical theories do not comport with what we are learning about how the mind works.
Consider, for instance, the research being done by Joshua Greene and his collabor-
ators at the crossroads of neuropsychology and moral philosophy (Greene 2002, 2003;
Greene and Haidt 2002; Greene et al. 2004).19 While most of the existing work in experimen-
tal philosophy has relied on the survey methodology, his work demonstrates that there is
nothing to prevent experimental philosophers (perhaps in collaboration with cognitive
scientists) from utilizing more sophisticated ways of probing folk psychology. Greene
and his collaborators use neural imaging studies (fMRI) to examine what happens in
people’s brains as they consider famous thought experiments from moral philosophy.
They have found that different scenarios not only tend to elicit different intuitions, but
also activate different cognitive processes as well. Moreover, Greene has gone on to
argue that data from his studies on moral cognition not only support sentimentalist over
rationalist theories of moral psychology, but they also purportedly provide us with
reasons to prefer consequentialist theories over their deontological counterparts.
Greene’s research program is indicative of the way experimental philosophy, as an
interdisciplinary and collaborative enterprise, can examine the neural and psychological
128 THOMAS NADELHOFFER AND EDDY NAHMIAS

sources of people’s intuitions about philosophical issues. There is no consensus about the
relevance of such information to the philosophical debates about these issues, but there is
no doubt that obtaining such information is driving important debates about the relevance
of such information to philosophy. And as we will see below, information about the psycho-
logical mechanisms underlying people’s intuitive judgments can also be useful in mapping
out when people’s judgments are influenced by seemingly irrelevant factors and in devel-
oping error theories for unreliable intuitive judgments.
The possibility that people’s intuitions, and the underlying cognitive mechanisms
that produce them, vary according to the kind of scenarios people consider complicates
the picture for EAs and for philosophers who engage in the sort of conceptual analysis
and theorizing that refers to ordinary conceptual usage and intuitions. When the data on
intuitions collected thus far by experimental philosophers is coupled with the gathering
evidence that some very basic moral intuitions vary systematically across different cultures
and socio-economic classes (Haidt 2001, 2003; Haidt, Koller, and Dias 1993; Nisbett 2003),
this puts pressure on the evidentiary status of intuitions with respect to philosophical
theory building. After all, if our intuitions depend in large part on philosophically irrelevant
factors, and we select our philosophical theories at least in part based on how well they
settle with our intuitions, we may end up unjustifiably privileging our own intuitions and
customs over those of others.
Highlighting these issues by gathering relevant data has been the primary concern of
a third project within experimental philosophy. This more critical kind of experimental phil-
osophy—which Joshua Alexander and Jonathan Weinberg have called ‘Experimental
Restrictionism’ (ER)—can be viewed as an empirically informed battle against the use
(and abuse) of intuitions in philosophy.20 The main goal of ER is to show that some of
the methods and techniques that philosophers working in the analytic tradition have
taken for granted are threatened by the gathering empirical evidence concerning both
the diversity and the unreliability of folk intuitions. More specifically, ERs argue that if
our intuitions about a particular topic vary cross-culturally or socio-economically and we
don’t have independent grounds for privileging our own intuitions to those of others,
these particular intuitions will be insufficient for philosophical theory building.21
The worry expressed by ERs is that in light of the gathering evidence concerning the
wide-scale diversity of intuitions, intuition-driven philosophy ends up being both epistemo-
logically xenophobic and intuitionally question-begging. For instance, Weinberg, Stich, and
Nichols have run studies that suggest Westerners apply the concept of knowledge differ-
ently than East Asians (e.g. East Asians are more willing to judge that people have knowl-
edge in Gettier-style cases) (Nichols, Stich, and Weinberg 2003; Weinberg, Stich, and Nichols
2001). Similarly, Edouard Machery et al. (2004) found that East Asians are less likely than
Westerners to use a Kripkean theory of reference. The results from these studies suggest
that without a (culturally neutral) error theory to explain why one culture’s intuitions are
mistaken, these cross-cultural differences put pressure on both the evidentiary status of
intuitions and on the ability of reflective equilibrium to help us separate the good intuitions
from the bad ones.22
The critical stance adopted by the ERs with respect to the proper role (or lack thereof)
played by intuitions in certain areas of philosophy is noteworthy to the extent that it high-
lights just how different the various projects within experimental philosophy can be. While
EAs are busy trying to discover what is intuitive in order to establish which philosophical
theories have the most prima facie intuitive appeal, ERs are busy trying to establish that
PAST AND FUTURE OF EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY 129

the gathering data concerning the systematic diversity of intuitions gives us reason to dis-
abuse ourselves of our intuition-mongering philosophical heritage. In this respect, exper-
imental philosophy is a house divided—though fully exploring these divisions is a task
for another day.23 For now, we just wanted to highlight the central similarities and differ-
ences between the various camps within experimental philosophy so that we will be in a
better position to examine the merit and proper scope of the criticisms that have recently
been put forward by Kauppinen (2007) and others.

3. Responding to Criticisms: the Future of Experimental Philosophy


In this section we will argue that none of the criticisms that have been put forward so
far succeed at showing that exploring ordinary intuitions and concepts using experimental
methods is entirely irrelevant to philosophy. In our view, experimental philosophers
have both the philosophical arguments and the methodological tools to allay many of
the concerns and criticisms that have been raised. One of our strategies for responding
to these criticisms is nicely captured by the transposed motto ‘united we (may) fall,
but divided we stand.’ That is, some of the criticisms we will examine are only relevant
to some of the projects we’ve outlined while other criticisms rely on presuppositions
embraced by one or more of the projects within experimental philosophy. Another
strategy we take for responding to criticisms is to turn them on their head and suggest
that properly addressing them requires more, not less, experimental research. We will
begin with what we take to be one of the most common objections to experimental
philosophy.24
Upon first hearing of experimental philosophy, many philosophers conclude from the
start that empirical data concerning folk intuitions are irrelevant to philosophical debates
because the folk intuitions themselves are irrelevant to such debates. After all, scientists
and mathematicians tend not to worry about whether their theories settle with the intuitions
of laypersons. Why should philosophers be any different? On this view, even if our own
‘expert’ intuitions correctly come into play when we’re doing philosophy, the untutored
and uninformed intuitions of the ‘person on the street’ have no similar role to play.25
One response to this line of reasoning is that the proponent of such a view owes us a
non-question-begging account for why philosophers’ intuitions are more reliable than
the pre-theoretical intuitions of laypersons. As we saw earlier, as the evidence concerning
heuristic biases, cognitive diversity, situationism, and the like continues to mount with
respect to children, laypersons, and experts, the philosopher’s faith in her own intuitions
seems less warranted. Rather than assuming without evidence that introspection and reflec-
tive equilibrium give us access to the truth, philosophers have the burden of demonstrating
that their own intuitions and the methods they use to sort them out are not subject to the
same unwanted factors that they claim influence their folk counterparts. Given the gathering
data on the dark underbelly of human cognition—beset as it is by automatic processes,
morally irrelevant situational cues, and cognitive biases and prejudices—it is no longer
enough for philosophers to simply assume that their own expert intuitions are not suscep-
tible to the factors that influence and sometimes distort folk intuitions. Ironically, to establish
that pre-philosophical folk intuitions should not be trusted and that philosophically informed
intuitions should be trusted would require more, not less, experimental research, at least
some of which should be focused specifically on intuitions about philosophical issues.
130 THOMAS NADELHOFFER AND EDDY NAHMIAS

Another way of responding to the critic of experimental philosophy who rejects the
importance of folk intuitions from the outset is to simply concede that not all folk intuitions
are philosophically interesting. On this moderate view, the philosophical relevance of folk
intuitions will vary from topic to topic. However, just because some intuitions may not be
relevant to philosophy, it does not follow that we should so hastily banish all folk intuitions.
Owing to the inherently abstract nature of some areas of philosophy—e.g. the philosophy
of mathematics—we may not care at all about pre-theoretical judgments and intuitions
with respect to those areas. But for many other philosophical issues, folk intuitions do—
and arguably should—play an important role. This is especially true when the relevant con-
cepts are intimately bound up with our everyday moral views and practices, such as free will
and intentional action (compare Kauppinen 2007, 114). According to the experimental
analysists (EAs), while we need not be entirely beholden to folk intuitions concerning
free will, moral responsibility, intentional action, and the like, these intuitions ought to at
least serve as constraints on our philosophical investigations.
The stance adopted by EAs towards folk intuitions is one that is shared by some of the
critics of experimental philosophy. Kauppinen, for instance, asks ‘why should anybody care
about what philosophers do if they just argued about their own inventions?’ (2007, 96). On
his view, because folk intuitions are used at least in part to adjudicate between competing
analyses, philosophers ought to be interested in the intuitions of non-partisans—i.e. indi-
viduals who are not invested in the philosophical debate that is under investigation. This
shows that both Kauppinen and at least some of the experimental philosophers he criticizes
agree that conceptual analysis often does and should focus on folk concepts. They also
seem to agree that these concepts can be mapped by examining the way people
express certain intuitions to relevant cases (see Kauppinen 2007). The difference is that
Kauppinen argues that experimental philosophers simply cannot get at the relevant ordin-
ary intuitions and concepts using ‘detached, non-participatory social scientific research
methods’ (2007, 97).
On this view, EAs are correct that philosophers ought to pay close attention to folk
intuitions; they are simply incorrect in assuming that so-called ‘quasi-observational’
surveys give us access to these intuitions. According to Kauppinen, the methods used by
experimental philosophers can only explore what he calls surface intuitions, whereas philo-
sophers engaged in conceptual analysis ought to be interested in exploring only robust
intuitions—i.e. intuitions competent language users would express under ideal conditions
and without being influenced by irrelevant factors (2007, 101).26 Kauppinen argues that it is
highly doubtful—if not impossible—that experimental philosophers can shed any light on
robust folk intuitions with the detached and non-participatory methods of social science.
Instead, we are told that the philosophically interesting intuitions can only be uncovered
using a participatory method he calls dialogue and reflection (2007, 98).
Kauppinen’s argument seems to be based on the assumption that experimental phi-
losophers must limit themselves to the sort of ‘quasi-observation’ that he criticizes through-
out the paper. But as we will show throughout this section, this is simply not the case. By
focusing on the various experimental avenues that are open to experimental philosophers,
we will show that Kauppinen’s conception of experimental philosophy is unjustifiably
narrow. But first we will briefly examine his own preferred method for doing conceptual
analysis—namely the Dialogue and Reflection Model (DRM). More specifically, we are
going to show that DRM can be implemented in two distinct yet related ways—namely
either informally or in controlled and systematic fashion.
PAST AND FUTURE OF EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY 131

According to the Informal Dialogue and Reflection Model (IDRM), it suffices for the
purposes of doing conceptual analysis that we engage in discussion with our colleagues,
students, friends, and family. Our stored memories of these conversations can then serve
as the background against which each philosopher engages in dialogue and reflection—
with each participant to the conversation bringing to the table her own unique history
with the concept in question. When doing conceptual analysis along the lines of IDRM,
we work on our analyses not only one concept at a time, but also one conversation at a
time. But there are a number of problems with IDRM. For instance, each philosopher’s intui-
tions will be shaped by where she grew up, her educational history, the variety of people
she normally converses with, the myriad environmental circumstances within which these
conversations took place, and the like. As a result, two different philosophers may under-
standably end up with two very different ideas with respect to what most people actually
think about a particular topic or concept—despite the fact that each philosopher has
engaged in the very kind of dialogue and reflection that Kauppinen suggests is supposed
to help shed light on the truth. These differences will surely affect their conversations with
interlocutors as well as affecting their beliefs concerning what is intuitive. Furthermore, it
should be expected that philosophers’ own intuitions as well as their opinions about ordin-
ary intuitions and concepts have been influenced by the theoretical positions they have
come to adopt during their extensive and particular philosophical training. Part of the
problem may be that conflicting pre-philosophical intuitions drive philosophers to adopt
competing theories, and philosophers with competing theories then highlight the intui-
tions that support their views.
Owing to these shortcomings of IDRM, proponents of Kauppinen’s basic DRM may be
inclined to adopt a different strategy for getting at the requisite data concerning folk intui-
tions and concepts. According to this second approach—which we are going to call Exper-
imental Dialogue and Reflection Model (EDRM)—we should set up controlled and
systematic experiments in order to find out what people’s reflective intuitions, judgments,
and beliefs about a given topic really are.27 By having the conversations in a controlled
environment, we could then code, compare, and analyze participants’ answers in a rigorous
and systematic manner that is less subject to the problems associated with IDRM. Moreover,
we could collect the data markedly faster than we could by relying exclusively on informal
conversations. With graduate students to assist in the collection and analysis of the data
and using large numbers of participants in the studies, we could collect in a short
amount of time information that it might take a single philosopher years to accumulate.
As more studies are run and more data are collected, meta-analyses could eventually be
run to see what patterns emerge both within and between large and diverse populations.
By implementing the dialogue and reflection model in a controlled and systematic way, we
could get at the data Kauppinen claims that we want in a manner that is less methodolo-
gically problematic than the informal method he advocates. And while implementing
EDRM would admittedly require more time and resources in the beginning than imple-
menting IDRM, once it is up and running it would enable us to access folk intuitions far
more rapidly than informal conversation and dialogue alone.28
By highlighting the possibility that an experimental approach could be used in imple-
menting Kauppinen’s own DRM, we learn three important lessons. First, we see that exper-
imental philosophers have resources to get at what Kauppinen takes to be the
philosophically interesting intuitions without having to simply retreat to the armchair in
defeat. Indeed, they could get at these intuitions with a modified and less problematic
132 THOMAS NADELHOFFER AND EDDY NAHMIAS

version of Kauppinen’s own preferred method. Second, EDRM makes clear that any infor-
mation that an individual philosopher can access via a series of informal conversations,
experimental philosophers can access via controlled experiments that enable them to
amass far more data over the long haul in far less time. Finally, it shows that experimental
philosophers can, and in some cases should, be interested in more than the mere ‘quasi-
observational’ method Kauppinen criticizes. And while they may have to borrow or
develop more sophisticated methods in order to get at the data they really want (remem-
ber this is still a nascent movement), there is nothing preventing them from making these
methodological modifications in order to advance the goals of their various projects (see
below for more details).
In order to undermine the entire movement of experimental philosophy, Kauppinen
would need to establish either (i) that we simply cannot get at philosophically interesting
intuitions regardless of what experimental designs we use, or (ii) even if we could get at the
salient intuitions experimentally, doing so is not worth the effort. As far as (ii) is concerned,
we believe that probing the intuitions in a controlled and systematic way is worth the effort
given the problems associated with relying exclusively on informal means of gathering
information about conceptual usage and folk intuitions. At a minimum, before we can
judge the merit of (ii), we would first need to test the reliability of the informal methods
upon which philosophers have tended to rely. As far as (i) is concerned, we believe this
view commits Kauppinen to an indefensibly strong modal claim. It is one thing to claim
that the kinds of studies that have been run so far by experimental philosophers have
not shed light on the salient folk intuitions—a claim we will reject below—it’s quite
another thing to claim that it is impossible that controlled and systematic experiments of
any sort could do so.
Historically, claims that empirical methods could never achieve certain goals have
withered under the progress of science and technology. As such, we think Kauppinen is
incorrect to suggest that experimental philosophers have the burden of demonstrating
that the methods of experimental psychology can give us access to philosophically inter-
esting folk intuitions. Rather, the critic has the burden of showing that these intuitions
lay forever beyond the reach of experimental philosophy. And one who wants to maintain
the relevance of facts about folk intuitions walks a fine line in arguing that they can be
properly discovered through non-experimental methods but they simply cannot be prop-
erly examined using any experimental methods.
As it stands, Kauppinen’s arguments rest on the questionable assumption that the
fate of experimental philosophy is tied to the currently used methods. Once we disabuse
ourselves of that assumption, many of Kauppinen’s objections to experimental philosophy
lose much of their force. For instance, Kauppinen writes that experimental philosophy ‘rests
on mistaken assumptions about the relations between people’s concepts and their linguis-
tic behaviour’ (2007, 95). And he suggests that practitioners of experimental philosophy
have neglected the fact that philosophers who appeal to ordinary intuitions are being ‘ellip-
tical,’ since they really mean to reference robust intuitions, not those offered by incompe-
tent users or by competent users under problematic conditions.
As we saw earlier, Kauppinen believes that philosophers should not be interested in
just any old folk intuitions, they should only be interested in robust intuitions—i.e. intui-
tions that satisfy three important conditions. First, in order for an intuition to be robust,
its application must ‘generally match the conceptual norms prevailing in the linguistic com-
munity’ (2007, 103). Second, we are only interested in intuitions that competent language
PAST AND FUTURE OF EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY 133

users have under ideal conditions—i.e. ‘conditions in which there are no perturbing,
warping or distorting factors or limits of information, access or ability’ (2007, 103).
Finally, robust intuitions—unlike surface intuitions—are produced by semantic consider-
ations rather than pragmatic considerations. According to Kauppinen, experimental philo-
sophers are ill-equipped to adequately examine any of these three issues with the research
methods available to them.
But if it can be shown that experimental philosophers can use controlled and sys-
tematic experiments to shed light on precisely these kinds of issues—and we will argue
that they can—then we can turn Kauppinen’s criticisms on their head. Take, for example,
his suggestion that with ‘surveys of amateurs it is practically impossible’ to ‘separate the
contribution of semantic and pragmatic considerations to what people say (and what it
is proper to say)’ (2007, 105). This is a surprising criticism for Kauppinen to make given
the extended debate that has transpired among experimental philosophers concerning
the very issue he raises. For instance, shortly after Knobe’s data first appeared, Fred
Adams and Annie Steadman (2004a, 2004b) suggested that even though Knobe’s partici-
pants may have answered in a way that suggests on the surface that they judged that
intending to x is unnecessary for intentionally x-ing, their answers were being driven by
pragmatic considerations having to do with the relationship between intentional action
and moral responsibility and not by semantic considerations having to do with the folk
concept of intentional action.
Similarly, Alfred Mele (2001, 2003) developed an error theory to explain how and why
moral considerations were affecting participants’ ascriptions of intentionality. On his view,
because some participants erroneously assumed that if an agent is morally responsible for
having x-ed, then the agent must have x-ed intentionally, they falsely ascribed intentional-
ity to the agents in Knobe’s studies. And because it is ‘easy enough to show people that,
upon consideration, they themselves would reject this assumption, their tendency to
allow the moral features of actions to affect their ascriptions of intentionality is both mis-
taken and corrigible’ (Mele 2001, 41). Mele goes on to predict that by reminding partici-
pants of garden-variety cases of negligence and recklessness, they will then purportedly
be able to see that the assumption that all blameworthy actions must have been performed
intentionally is ‘false by their own lights rather than by the lights of an externally imposed
theory’ (Mele 2001, 41). This should in turn lead them to give different answers with respect
to intentionality.
Experimental philosophers have subsequently tested Mele’s prediction (Knobe
2003b; Nadelhoffer 2004a). In these studies, participants once again received the kind of
vignettes Knobe used in his earlier side-effect studies—except this time participants
were first primed with drunk-driving cases that were designed to make it clear that
agents can be morally responsible for killing their victims even if they do not bring
about their victims’ deaths intentionally. Nearly all the participants did indeed judge that
the drunk driver was blameworthy even though they did not judge that he brought
about the victim’s deaths intentionally. Yet, their responses to the follow-up vignettes
were consistent with the responses given by participants in earlier studies who had not
been similarly primed. It appears that being reminded that agents can be responsible for
x-ing even if they did not x intentionally does not change participants’ intuitions concern-
ing intentional action. The results of these studies suggest that the pragmatic consideration
that Adams and Steadman (2004a, 2004b), Mele (2001, 2003), and Hugh McCann (2005)
have all identified does not appear to be driving participants’ intuitions in the way they
134 THOMAS NADELHOFFER AND EDDY NAHMIAS

had assumed. And while now is not the time to pick sides in this ongoing debate, the fact
that both experimental philosophers and psychologists are actively trying to address the
very issue Kauppinen raises suffices to show that he is wrong in assuming that experimental
philosophers either have not or cannot attempt to get at intuitions that are driven by
semantic rather than merely pragmatic considerations.
A similar strategy is open for responding to Kauppinen’s claim that the normative
components of robust intuitions—which require both linguistic competency and ideal con-
ditions—simply cannot be examined using experimental methods (2007, 107). As we have
already seen, Kauppinen believes that when philosophers appeal to ordinary intuitions they
are being ‘elliptical,’ since they really mean to reference robust intuitions, not those offered
by incompetent users or by competent users under problematic conditions. And since
experimental philosophers are purportedly only able to get at surface intuitions, we are
told that their work is of little or no philosophical importance, even if the data they
collect may turn out to be of interest to psychologists (2007, 108). Here, we suspect that
Kauppinen misunderstands both the methods most experimental philosophers have
been employing and their goals in using those methods.
One way for experimental philosophers to respond to this concern would be to
simply ‘go conditional.’ By this we mean that they could explore experimentally the
answers to questions of this form: If conditions are such and such, then people express
such and such intuitions (or tend to ‘say that X is C,’ to use Kauppinen’s language). Then,
competing philosophers can argue about whether those conditions are indicative of
biasing or pragmatic factors or, conversely, are requisite triggering or background features
for elucidating competence with the concepts. This is one way to understand what Exper-
imental Descriptivists (EDs) are doing. Philosophers with competing theories can stipulate,
based on their theory, the relevant normative conditions for competency, and then EDs can
test whether these conditions are satisfied by particular subjects and, if so, test what those
subjects say in response to philosophical probes designed to test their intuitions. Perhaps
we misunderstand Kauppinen’s claim that considerations of competence entail that intui-
tion statements cannot be experimentally tested ‘without taking a stance on the concepts
involved’ (2007, 97), but there seems nothing problematic about a researcher’s accepting
a particular theory (e.g. about what it takes to demonstrate competence with a particular
concept) and then experimentally testing that theory. Indeed, this seems to be analogous
to the scientific practice of developing predictions from one’s theory and then experi-
mentally testing them.
We also reject Kauppinen’s suggestion that experimental philosophers aim to obtain
(and are only able to obtain) data about surface intuitions rather than robust intuitions. We
believe, rather, that the goal of most experimental philosophers is to obtain robust data
about robust intuitions, and that any failures to achieve this goal are the result of methodo-
logical tools in need of fine-tuning, not mistaken assumptions about what sort of intuitions,
if any, are relevant to philosophical theorizing. And we believe that the methodological tools
are less imperfect than Kauppinen suggests, as we will now explain. But, first, we should
again point out that the goal of many Experimental Restrictionists is to show through exper-
imental methods that in some cases there are no robust intuitions with respect to the target
concept.29 On this view, the intuitions of philosophers, just like those of laypersons, may be
subject to factors that are purportedly irrelevant, such as the vagaries of culture, class, even
the order of presentation of the cases, and regarding philosophical debates where this is the
case, the evidentiary value of intuitive appeals is negligible.
PAST AND FUTURE OF EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY 135

Kauppinen suggests that when traditional philosophers make claims about what is
intuitive or ‘what we would say about X,’ ‘charity requires us to conceive of their claims’
as including certain background assumptions—namely these claims are about what com-
petent users of the concepts would say if they considered them in sufficiently ideal con-
ditions without being influenced by non-semantic considerations (2007, 101). Well, charity
would also suggest that experimental philosophers are similarly aiming to obtain data
about ordinary intuitions and conceptual usage under these conditions—though often
they aim also to elucidate precisely when these conditions are and are not met. Kauppinen
argues that the survey method ends up testing (E ), the intuitive judgments of non-
specialists who ‘(10 ) appear to understand the question . . . (20 ) however they consider it in
whatever conditions they find themselves in and (30 ) whatever kind of considerations influence
their response’ (2007, 105, italics in original). Our response is that experimental philoso-
phers have used and continue to develop methods to determine (i) whether participants
in their experiments properly understand the questions, (ii) whether they have considered
them carefully, and (iii) whether or not they are influenced by clearly irrelevant factors.
To begin with, experimental philosophers use statistical methods. One of the primary
benefits of statistical analysis is that it allows you to examine correlations between manipu-
lated factors, even in the face of expected effects of the ‘noise’ of other factors. Using suffi-
ciently large sample sizes, you can show that the probability is extremely low that the
relevant results obtained because of the irrelevant factors.30 A statistically significant result
does not indicate that any individual participant’s response was not due to inattention or con-
fusion or a mischievous desire to mess up the experiment. But for many types of studies, it
does indicate that it is highly unlikely that most participants were inattentive or confused or
mischievous—or if they were, they’d all have to ‘mess up’ in a relatively cohesive way.
And experimental philosophers attempt to avoid participants’ being affected by
certain irrelevant factors (e.g. Kauppinen’s non-ideal conditions). For instance, they instruct
participants to read the scenarios and questions carefully and they provide them ample
time to complete the surveys (usually they are present to observe that the participants
at least appear to be taking it seriously).31 But experimental philosophers generally go
on to control for whether participants are following these instructions by using ‘manipu-
lation checks’ that test whether participants have understood the scenarios they have
read. Participants who miss these questions, perhaps because they were not properly
engaged or competent enough readers, are excluded from the analysis of the results.
Do these precautions ensure that only engaged and competent participants are
included? No, some may guess correctly on manipulation checks, but again, statistical ana-
lyses ensure that only wide-scale confusion in a particular direction of response should
produce any significant results obtained. Multiple questions using similar concepts can
test (within-subjects) whether participants are being consistent in expressing their intui-
tions. Repeating surveys with different scenarios and across different populations can
test for between-subject consistency. And randomizing the order of cases and questions
can control for whether participants are influenced by the order of presentation.
In some cases, experimental philosophers require participants to reason counterfac-
tually. For instance, in our free will studies we ask them to consider a scenario about
another universe (described as deterministic) and answer questions about agents’
freedom and responsibility in that universe. In these cases, we ask the participants to
answer the experimental questions based on what the scenario says is true of the alternate
universe, not what they believe is actually true of our universe (sometimes we ask whether
136 THOMAS NADELHOFFER AND EDDY NAHMIAS

they think what it says is true of our world and then remind them, regardless of that, to
answer based on the assumption it is true of the universe described in the scenario). It is
difficult to ensure that participants successfully reason counterfactually, but there is a
body of research in psychology that suggests people are generally quite adept at counter-
factual reasoning, and the manipulation checks help test for whether they succeed.32
Again, barring widespread mistakes of a particular type, statistical analyses help to
ensure that individual mistakes get ‘washed out.’
Finally, experimental philosophers often ask participants to explain why they
responded to questions the way they did. Usually, the experimental goal is to explore
the folk’s intuitions about whether, for instance, a certain concept applies in a certain scen-
ario, not the folk’s theories about why the concept applies or doesn’t, so these open-ended
explanations are only solicited after they have offered their intuitive judgments.33 But these
explanations then allow experimental philosophers to glean important information about
whether the participants are reading carefully, understanding the scenarios and questions,
reasoning counterfactually, and drawing appropriate inferences. Such explanations also
offer useful information for fine-tuning future surveys.
We are belaboring these methodological points in order to emphasize that exper-
imental philosophers tend to be acutely aware of the potential for irrelevant factors and
biases influencing people’s intuitions and judgments. Given the interdisciplinary interests
of most experimental philosophers, they tend to be familiar with the vast literature in
experimental psychology that examines these factors and explores when and how they
influence people. Indeed, for experimental philosophers engaged primarily in the ED
(Descriptivist) and ER (Restrictionist) projects, the methods of psychology are employed
precisely in order to better understand the folk ‘psychology of philosophy’ by examining
which features of cases influence people’s intuitions and which cognitive mechanisms
might thereby get implemented along the way.
These philosophers (and of course, the psychologists who engage in similar projects)
tend to use the classic experimental paradigm: expose two randomly selected groups to
scenarios that differ only in one variable and ask them the same questions about the scen-
ario; if the two groups’ responses differ in a statistically significant way, we can conclude
that it is highly likely that that variable accounts for the difference in the responses. That
is, something about our psychology is influenced by that variable. For instance, if Knobe
is right that the moral dimension of the side-effect is the only relevant difference
between the scenarios he presents, then it is clear that the way the folk understand inten-
tional action is influenced by moral considerations (2003a, 2003b). Alternatively, experi-
mentalists may expose two groups that differ in only one crucial respect (e.g. cultural
background or education level) to the same scenarios; if the groups’ responses differ in a
statistically significant way, we can conclude that the crucial difference between the
groups is driving the different responses—i.e. something about our psychology regarding
these cases is affected by our culture, education level, etc.
Like Kauppinen, those engaged in the Experimental Analysis (EA) project are less
interested in the differences between people’s responses than the similarities that indicate
some shared intuition or concept. That is, their goal is to empirically confirm or disconfirm
the claims of philosophers who appeal to intuitions as some kind of support for their theory
or conceptual analysis. So, rather than using controlled and systematic studies primarily to
discover psychological factors that drive differing intuitions, EAs use these studies to obtain
systematic results about how the majority of people respond to cases and to control for
PAST AND FUTURE OF EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY 137

problematic influences (non-ideal conditions) on these responses. Nonetheless, in almost


all studies, even if there is a statistically significant majority responding in one way, there
is still a non-trivial minority responding in other ways. What sense do we make of the com-
peting intuitional judgments one finds both within groups and between groups?
This is one of the questions used to motivate a criticism of experimental philosophy
that Kauppinen calls the ‘argument from disagreement.’34 On his view, the experimental
philosopher faces a dilemma:

Either a test subject’s response to a survey question reveals whether the case falls under
her concept, or it doesn’t. If it doesn’t, the response is obviously uninformative and
running the survey for this purpose is pointless. But what if it does? Then those who
answer in the negative will not and cannot disagree with those who answer in the affirma-
tive. (2007, 108)

Kauppinen goes on to suggest that in order to be able to ask intelligibly whether two
individuals A and B agree (or disagree) concerning whether a particular case falls under a
concept x, we must first presuppose that these individuals have a shared concept of x.
But if all of the participants within a group do have a shared concept, then why don’t
they answer the same way? If they do not have a shared concept, on the other hand,
then we get the purportedly counterintuitive result that participants who give conflicting
answers to a survey question do not actually disagree at all. Given the non-unanimous
results of the studies that have been run so far by experimental philosophers—and the
potential problems that this thereby creates—we agree with Kauppinen that experimental
philosophers (especially EAs) need to explain why they tend to privilege the answers given
by the majority of participants.
EAs sometimes focus on the answers given by the majority of participants because
they are testing claims made by philosophers about which of two philosophical theories
has wider intuitive appeal. Our own work on the free will debate serves as a good
example of this approach (Nahmias et al. 2006). The assumption that we set out to test
was the well-worn claim among philosophers that incompatibilism is the commonsensical
view. Contrary to what Kauppinen suggests, we do not believe that these appeals to the
pre-theoretical intuitions of laypersons are always shorthand for ‘what perfectly competent
users would believe or intuit under ideal conditions.’ Consider, for instance, the following
claim by Galen Strawson:

Almost all human beings believe that they are free to choose what to do in such a way that
they can be truly, genuinely responsible for their actions in the strongest possible sense—
responsible period, responsible without any qualification, responsible sans phrase, respon-
sible tout court, absolutely, radically, buck-stoppingly responsible; ultimately responsible,
in a word—and so ultimately morally responsible when moral matters are at issue. Free
will is the thing you have to have if you’re going to be responsible in this all-or-
nothing way. That’s what I mean by free will. That’s what I think we haven’t got and
can’t have.35

Here we find Strawson explicitly claiming that what he means by free will and moral
responsibility is what ‘almost all human beings’ mean by it. It is because of claims like this
that EAs sometimes focus on how the majority of participants respond to their surveys, and
they need not assume that people share the same intuitions about certain concepts.
138 THOMAS NADELHOFFER AND EDDY NAHMIAS

Experimental philosophers may also analyze why different participants offer different
responses to philosophical surveys.
For instance, Nichols and Ulatowski (forthcoming) have recently performed some
ingenious experiments on Knobe cases, the results of which suggest that there may be
two concepts of intentional action, one of which focuses on the agent’s intention/
motive and the other on the agent’s foreknowledge of the action’s effects. By asking par-
ticipants to explain their answers and then coding these answers to see what they have in
common, Nichols and Ulatowski were better able to investigate when participants were
employing one of these concepts rather than the other. For present purposes, their
research serves as an important reminder that experimental philosophers need not focus
only on how the majority of participants respond to thought experiments, especially
when paying attention to the minority responses is fruitful as well.36
As we learn more about what drives people’s intuitions, we will also be in a better pos-
ition to determine whether members in the minority (or even the majority) group are making
particular kinds of mistakes. This would in turn allow us to develop error theories for why
some people (or some groups) express certain intuitions that they would reject upon
further reflection. But, once again, adequately exploring these issues will require more
rather than less experimental research. Furthermore, we believe that in carrying out this
research experimental philosophers can and should spend more time thinking about how
to design studies so that they are better able to get at precisely the kinds of robust intuitions
that Kauppinen mistakenly suggests are forever beyond their experimental grasp.
In our view, if the philosophically interesting intuitions can be accessed at all, we see no
reason why they cannot be accessed using controlled and systematic methods that are likely
to be less problematic than informal alternatives. And while getting at these intuitions may
require more ‘dialogue and reflection’ on the part of participants than previous studies have
used, we are unconvinced by Kauppinen’s claim that experimental methods can have no
possible role to play. We’ve already explained how experimental philosophers vary examples
and ask for explanations (the first step in a dialogue). Now we will examine some other
methods they have used or could use to address some of Kauppinen’s concerns.
Several experimental philosophers have tried to see how people respond in the face
of apparently conflicting intuitions, engaging them in a process in the vicinity of reflective
equilibrium. For instance, Nichols and Knobe (forthcoming) present a universe (Universe A)
they describe as deterministic and find that most participants respond that agents cannot
be ‘fully morally responsible’ in that universe.37 But when presented with a particular agent
doing a dastardly deed in Universe A, most participants respond that he can be fully morally
responsible. Nichols and Knobe then followed up with some of those participants who
expressed both of these seemingly contradictory intuitions and asked them how they
would resolve the conflict. That is, they entered into a (brief) dialogue with their partici-
pants to tease out some implications and see how they would respond.
The resources available for online surveys can be used in similar ways. In a large
online study on intuitions about free will and responsibility, Nahmias, Coates, and Kvaran
(forthcoming) had over 600 participants read a scenario and answer a dozen questions,
which allows extensive statistical analyses of correlations between participants’ responses
to questions about free will, deliberation, moral responsibility, praise and blame, and retri-
butive punishment, as well as demographic factors such as gender and degree of religiosity.
We can examine apparent inconsistencies within individual participants’ responses and
connections between the ways people employ different concepts.38 And of course, we
PAST AND FUTURE OF EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY 139

are excluding those participants who miss either of two manipulation checks, one adminis-
tered before and one after the experimental questions. We will also examine whether the
responses of those who have taken a college philosophy course differ from those who have
not. Eventually, we may run studies to compare participants’ responses before and after
they have been taught the free will debate by philosophy teachers who hold opposing
views to examine potential effects of theoretical biasing on pre-philosophical intuitions.
In another online survey, Nahmias and Sommers will ask participants for their level of
agreement or disagreement first with the premises of something like Galen Strawson’s
‘Basic Argument’ for skepticism about free will and moral responsibility (1994) and then
with the conclusion of that argument (i.e. that it is impossible to be truly morally respon-
sible for one’s actions). The online program allows different participants to take different
‘paths,’ depending on their answers, so that individual participants will be offered
various ways to resolve and try to explain any conflicts between their responses—
roughly, to seek reflective equilibrium by being confronted, for instance, with the inconsis-
tency between an initial acceptance of all of the premises and an initial rejection of the con-
clusion that validly follows from them.
This method of trying to track the thought processes of laypersons as they are intro-
duced to philosophical arguments or thought experiments has the potential to test Experi-
mental Analysts’ hypotheses about what is most intuitive to the folk, Experimental
Descriptivists’ hypotheses about the psychological mechanisms underpinning the folk’s intui-
tions, and Experimental Restrictionists’ hypotheses about the instability of folk intuitions. If
this method starts to look more like the Socratic dialogue Kauppinen advocates, that’s fine,
but it is decidedly not ‘to do philosophy pretty much as it has always been done’ (2007, 110).
Finally, the future of experimental philosophy, especially the ED branch, is likely to
become increasingly interdisciplinary, involving collaboration between philosophers who
understand the complexities of the philosophical debates and scientists who understand
the complexities of the methodology required to shed light on those debates. Such collab-
oration might include behavioral experiments—to examine how people’s beliefs about phi-
losophical issues (e.g. free will or morality) influence their behavior.39 It might include
further fMRI studies—to examine the neural activity correlated with certain philosophical
intuitions or moral beliefs. It might even include phenomenological investigations—to
examine people’s first-person reports about experiences relevant to philosophical ques-
tions, such as free will and deliberation (see Nahmias et al. 2004). When coupled with
the other examples we have already discussed in this section, we believe these possibilities
demonstrate that the future of experimental philosophy looks bright, so long as we don’t
assume from the start that the movement should fall before these and other possibilities
are explored.

4. Conclusion
In this paper we have tried to shed light on the wide variety of projects within exper-
imental philosophy while defending the movement from its critics. By reminding ourselves
of the multitude of research methods open to experimental philosophers, we can better
resist the limited vision of the experimental possibilities exhibited by critics such as
Kauppinen. On our view, if we pay close attention to what experimental philosophers
have actually been doing so far, while keeping our minds open with respect to how they
might adopt new strategies in the future, we find that many of the very issues Kauppinen
140 THOMAS NADELHOFFER AND EDDY NAHMIAS

raises can adequately be addressed via controlled and systematic experiments. Indeed,
experimental philosophers can examine when intuitions are being expressed in less than
ideal conditions, when they are being driven by semantic rather than pragmatic factors,
and when they are being expressed by competent users.
While we readily acknowledge that Kauppinen has raised some important concerns,
none of them requires experimental philosophers to rest content with the limitations of
armchair reflection and informal dialogue. Moreover, we believe that determining the
merit of several of his objections—as well as the merit of his own dialogue and reflection
model—actually requires more rather than less experimentation. We are also aware that
evaluating Kauppinen’s view requires more rather than less philosophical discussion
about issues we have not delved into here, such as the nature of intuitions and the
proper analysis of concepts. Indeed, we appreciate that Kauppinen has highlighted a
number of issues that experimental philosophers would do well to address more carefully.
But given the surprising and informative results that experimental philosophers have pro-
duced so far and the interesting dialogue their work has already inspired, we are convinced
that it is a mistake to either call for or predict the downfall of experimental philosophy.

ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
For helpful comments, we would like to thank Joshua Alexander, Adam Feltz, Antti
Kauppinen, Joshua Knobe, Trevor Kvaran, Shaun Nichols, and Jonathan Weinberg.

NOTES
1. Authorship is equal.
2. Action Theory: Adams and Steadman (2004a, 2004b), Knobe (2003a, 2003b, 2004b, 2005a,
2005b), Knobe and Burra (2006a, 2006b), Knobe and Mendlow (2004), Leslie, Knobe, and
Cohen (2006), Machery (forthcoming), Malle (2001, 2006), Malle and Knobe (1997),
McCann (2005), Meeks (2004), Nadelhoffer (2004a, 2004b, 2005, 2006a), Nichols and
Ulatowski (forthcoming), Phelan and Sarkissian (forthcoming), and Young et al. (2006).
Epistemology: Alexander and Weinberg (2006), Baron (1998), Bishop and Trout (2005a,
2005b), Feltz (n.d.), Nichols, Stich, and Weinberg (2003), Stich and Nisbett (1980), Stich
and Weinberg (2001), Swain, Alexander, and Weinberg (forthcoming), and Weinberg,
Nichols, and Stich (2001). Ethics: Cushman, Young, and Hauser (2006), Doris (2002),
Greene (2002, 2003, forthcoming), Greene and Haidt (2002), Greene et al. (2004), Haidt
(2001, 2003), Haidt, Bjorklund, and Murphy (2000), Hauser (2006), Hauser, Young, and
Cushman (forthcoming), Knobe (2005a), Knobe and Leiter (forthcoming), Knobe and
Roedder (forthcoming), Nichols (2002, 2004b, 2004c), Nichols and Mallon (2006), Pizarro
and Bloom (2003), Pizarro, Uhlmann, and Bloom (2003), and Pizarro, Uhlmann, and
Salovey (2003). Free Will & Moral Responsibility: Knobe and Doris (forthcoming), Nadelhoffer
and Feltz (forthcoming), Nahmias (2006), Nahmias et al. (2005, 2006, forthcoming), Nichols
(2004c, 2006a, 2006b), Nichols and Knobe (forthcoming), Turner and Nahmias (2006),
Woolfolk and Doris (2002), and Woolfolk, Doris, and Darley (forthcoming). Philosophy of
Language: Machery et al. (2004), and Mallon et al. (forthcoming). Philosophy of Law:
Carlsmith, Darley, and Robinson (2002), Greene and Cohen (2004), Knobe (2005b),
Malle and Nelson (2003), Nadelhoffer (2006a), and Sardjevéladzé and Machery (n.d.).
Philosophy of Mind: Gray, Gray, and Wegner (2007), and Knobe and Prinz (forthcoming).
PAST AND FUTURE OF EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY 141

Philosophy of Science: Stotz (forthcoming), Stotz and Griffiths (2004), and Stotz, Griffiths,
and Knight (2004).
3. We will speak primarily of ordinary (or ‘folk’) intuitions, which we take roughly to be dis-
positions to make certain non-deductive, spontaneous judgments, for instance, about
whether or not a particular concept applies in a particular situation (see Goldman and
Pust 1998; Jackson 1998). Some experimental philosophy, however, may be better under-
stood as investigating folk theories or folk concepts, and the complicated connections
between intuitions, theories, and concepts adds a layer of complexity both to what exper-
imental philosophers take themselves to be doing and what their critics take them to be
doing.
4. In fact, we think the criticisms of experimental philosophy that have been put forward so
far (e.g. Kauppinen 2007; Levy n.d.; Sosa 2005, 2007) are philosophically interesting
enough that experimental philosophers deserve some credit for having inspired them!
We also think it is essential for experimental philosophers themselves to examine these
metaphilosophical questions as they present their research so that they are as clear as
possible about how they think their own research bears on philosophical debates.
5. For the purposes of this paper, we need not try to resolve the tension that exists between
the various projects within experimental philosophy. Nor do we need to take sides. Our
present goal is just to identify and briefly explore three fairly distinct projects within exper-
imental philosophy.
6. The boundary is blurry (i) because most experimental philosophers are happy to obtain
the data they take to be relevant to the philosophical issues they are exploring by
drawing on already existing scientific research, and (ii) because some scientists are inter-
ested in the same kind of intuitions that interest philosophers and they, too, discuss the
philosophical implications of their research (e.g. Baron 1998; Damasio 1994; Greene 2002,
2003, forthcoming; Haidt 2001, 2003; Hauser 2006; Hauser et al. forthcoming; Malle 2001,
2006; Nisbett 2003; Nisbett and Ross 1980; Wegner 2002). Because ‘experimental
philosophy’ is perhaps best viewed as a family resemblance term, trying to explicate
the movement in terms of necessary and jointly sufficient conditions would be wrong-
headed even if well-intentioned. But the following two questions are nevertheless
helpful. First, do you run controlled and systematic studies and use the resultant data
to shed light on philosophical problems? Second, do you sometimes address the
tension that exists between what philosophers say about intuition and human cognition,
on the one hand, and what researchers are discovering about these things, on the other
hand? Experimental philosophy can be seen as a movement at the cross-roads of psychol-
ogy and philosophy that is being driven primarily by people who answer these two ques-
tions in the affirmative.
7. See, e.g. Jackson (1998), Jackson and Pettit (1995), Lewis (1972), and Smith (1994).
8. This shared distrust in armchair reflection and informal dialogue as generally reliable
guides to folk intuitions is roughly what Kauppinen describes as ‘EXPERIMENTALISM 2’
(2007, 000).
9. See, e.g. Mynatt et al. (1977), Nickerson (1998), and Wason (1960).
10. See, e.g. Ditto and Lopez (1992), and Edwards and Smith (1996).
11. See, e.g. Fields and Schuman (1976), and Ross, Greene, and House (1977).
12. We are not claiming that philosophers are in fact more susceptible to these well-known
biases—that, of course, is an empirical question that calls for controlled and systematic
investigation. Rather, we are merely suggesting that given the central role that many
142 THOMAS NADELHOFFER AND EDDY NAHMIAS

philosophers give to folk intuitions, there is reason to worry about what Alvin Goldman
and Joel Pust call ‘theory contamination’ (1998, 183). Minimally, we believe that the gath-
ering data on cognitive biases place the burden clearly at the feet of philosophers who
claim their own intuitions are a reliable guide to what people generally find intuitive.
13. The three projects we describe are not meant to label individual philosophers but rather
individual research projects or articles. Some philosophers, such as Shaun Nichols, have
worked on all three of the projects we will discuss.
14. What we are calling EA is roughly equivalent to what Kauppinen calls ‘optimistic experi-
mentalism’ (2007, 99), and what Alexander and Weinberg call the ‘proper foundations
view’ (2006). Some examples of EA include Knobe (2003a, 2003b, 2004a, 2004b), Nadelhof-
fer (2005, 2006a, 2006b), Nahmias et al. (2005, 2006, forthcoming), Nichols (2004a, 2004b),
and Nichols and Ulatowski (forthcoming).
15. As we will see, not only is there no consensus among philosophers in general concerning
the proper role (if any) that folk intuitions have to play in philosophy, but experimental
philosophers are themselves divided on this issue.
16. Robert Kane exemplifies this view with his claim that ‘most ordinary persons start out as
natural incompatibilists. They believe there is some kind of conflict between freedom and
determinism . . . Ordinary persons have to be talked out of this natural incompatibilism by
the clever arguments of philosophers’ (1999, 217).
17. See, e.g. Adams and Steadman (2004a, 2004b), Cushman, Young, and Hauser (2006),
Machery (forthcoming), Malle (2006), McCann (2005), Meeks (2004), Nadelhoffer (2004b,
2005), Nichols and Ulatowski (forthcoming), and Phelan and Sarkissian (forthcoming).
18. Some examples of ED work in experimental philosophy include Greene (2002, 2003, forth-
coming), Greene and Haidt (2002), Greene et al. (2004), Knobe and Doris (forthcoming),
Nadelhoffer (2006a), and Nichols and Knobe (forthcoming). Knobe’s (2007) response to
Kauppinen (2007) offers a more extended defense of the philosophical relevance of at
least this branch of experimental philosophy, arguing that it advances our understanding
of human nature in the ways traditional philosophers have attempted to do since the Greeks.
19. Greene is an interesting case as he is appointed in a psychology department despite
having done his graduate work in philosophy. He is also one of only a handful of psychol-
ogists who self-identifies with the experimental philosophy movement.
20. What we are calling ER maps roughly onto what Kauppinen calls ‘pessimistic experimen-
talists’ (2007, 98). For some examples of ER projects, see Alexander and Weinberg (2006),
Machery et al. (2004), Mallon et al. (forthcoming), Nichols, Stich, and Weinberg (2003), and
Weinberg, Nichols, and Stich (2001).
21. ER is heavily rooted in the pioneering work begun by Stich in the early 1980s. Indeed, not
only did Stich pave the way for ER, he also participated in some of the first studies in exper-
imental philosophy. See, e.g., Nichols, Stich, and Weinberg (2003), Stich (1983, 1984, 1985,
1990, 1994, 1996, 1998), Stich and Nisbett (1980), Stich and Weinberg (2001), and
Weinberg, Nichols, and Stich (2001).
22. Another project within the ER camp is to show that seemingly irrelevant features signifi-
cantly influence the intuitions people express. For instance, the order in which cases are
presented seems to influence people’s epistemic intuitions (see Swain, Alexander, and
Weinberg forthcoming).
23. See Nadelhoffer and Nahmias (n.d.).
24. For the purposes of this paper, we neither pursue nor examine various other responses
experimental philosophers have already offered to critics. Knobe (forthcoming), for
PAST AND FUTURE OF EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY 143

instance, suggests that even if Kauppinen were correct that experimental philosophers
don’t (and can’t) get at the intuitions philosophers need for doing conceptual analysis,
experimental philosophy is nevertheless useful for philosophers who are not interested
in doing conceptual analysis but who are interested instead in the naturalistic project
of understanding what the mind is and how it works. Another important issue that we
will leave unaddressed is that many of the criticisms that have been put forward so far
by Kauppinen, Sosa, and others rely too heavily on assumptions that are driven by
unsettled issues in linguistics and the philosophy of language. As Machery (forthcoming)
has correctly pointed out, until we have a better empirical understanding of the nature of
concepts and how they are used, we simply cannot resolve several of the ongoing debates
both about and within experimental philosophy concerning intuitions and conceptual
analysis. We think Machery may be largely correct about this. But even so, as he goes
on to suggest, experimental philosophers can nevertheless continue to fruitfully investi-
gate the nature and limitations of human cognition. We believe that when the arguments
put forward in the present paper are viewed in conjunction with the arguments devel-
oped by Knobe, Machery, Alexander and Weinberg, and others, we find a multi-
pronged defense of experimental philosophy that successfully staves off all would-be
assassins.
25. See Bealer (1996, 1998, 2000), Levy (n.d.), and Williamson (2004).
26. A similar point has been developed by Ernest Sosa—see, e.g. Sosa (2005, 2007). A
response to Sosa can be found in Alexander and Weinberg (2006).
27. Some graduate students at Florida State University recently ran a pilot study that involved
presenting participants with various cases about intentional action and allowing them to
discuss and debate the cases among themselves. At the end of the study they took further
surveys to examine how the students’ views changed (or did not change). And while the
results were inconclusive—owing primarily to some problems with the design of the
studies—their strategy is certainly one that could prove useful in the future.
28. This is clearly not to suggest that philosophers should quit having informal conversations
with their children, families, friends, students, and colleague about philosophical issues!
Nor is to suggest that all of the information that we glean from these conversations is
useless or uninteresting. We are simply cautioning against the dogmatic assumption
that there is data that we can best (or only) obtain in informal one-on-one conversations.
29. Even in cases where people express consistent intuitions across cases, ERs argue that if
people in different cultures or classes express consistently different intuitions, then
picking out which people get to count as competent will often beg the question at
issue. Hence, robust intuitions within a group may not satisfy Kauppinen’s criterion of
competence for robust intuitions.
30. A statistically significant result is one for which the probability that the result occurred due
to chance factors was less than 5 percent—a p value of ,0.05 indicates this probability.
31. Contrast this with the way most in-class ‘surveys’ of students’ intuitions are conducted: the
teacher describes the thought experiment or scenario verbally, usually once quickly, and
then asks students to raise their hands on the spot to indicate their intuitions about it. See
Nadelhoffer and Nahmias (forthcoming) for an explanation of the usefulness of the con-
trolled survey method for teaching philosophy in the classroom.
32. See, e.g. German and Nichols (2003), and Harris, German, and Mills (1996).
33. Some argue that all intuitions are suffused with background theoretical beliefs. As we
mentioned earlier, the connections between intuitions and theories (and concepts) are
144 THOMAS NADELHOFFER AND EDDY NAHMIAS

complex, and we suspect experimental philosophy can help provoke philosophical


debates about these connections, and presumably it can gather empirical data relevant
to such debates.
34. A similar objection has been put forward by Ernest Sosa (see, e.g. 2005, 2007).
35. In a 2003 interview with Tamler Sommers for The Believer (http://www.naturalism.org/
strawson_interview.htm).
36. Another explanation for divergent results is that some concepts may not have clear
necessary and sufficient conditions (or at least, not the folk’s concepts). In such cases,
people may have shared intuitions about the paradigmatic applications of the concepts,
but differing intuitions about the boundaries, as demonstrated by their different judg-
ments about certain, often non-paradigmatic, cases.
37. We have worries about the way Nichols and Knobe describe determinism that make us
skeptical that they have shown most ordinary people have incompatibilist intuitions
(see Nahmias 2006; Turner and Nahmias 2006), but we think the differences they find
across scenarios are fascinating and important.
38. For instance, an initial look at the data suggests that many people answer differently to
questions about (i) free will compared to moral responsibility and (ii) praise compared
to blame, while (iii) people answer almost identically to questions about free will com-
pared to questions about whether decisions are ‘up to’ the agent.
39. See Vohs and Schooler (n.d.) who show that inducing people to doubt the existence of
free will increases their willingness to cheat on a test.

REFERENCES
ADAMS , F. , and STEADMAN , A. 2004a. Intentional action in ordinary language: Core concept or prag-
matic understanding. Analysis 64: 173 – 81.
———. 2004b. Intentional actions and moral considerations: Still pragmatic. Analysis 64:
264 – 67.
ALEXANDER , J. , and WEINBERG , J. 2006. Analytic epistemology and experimental philosophy. Philos-
ophy Compass 2 (1): 56– 80.
BARON , J. 1998. Judgment misguided: Intuition and error in public decision making. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
BEALER , G. 1996. A priori knowledge and the scope of philosophy. Philosophical Studies 81:
121 – 42.
———. 1998. Intuition and the autonomy of philosophy. In Rethinking intuition: The psychology
of intuition and its role in philosophical inquiry, edited by M. DePaul and W. Ramsey.
Lanham, Md.: Rowman and Littlefield.
———. 2000. A theory of the a priori. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 81 (1): 1– 30.
BISHOP , M. , and J. D. TROUT . 2005a. The pathologies of standard analytic epistemology. Nous 39 (4):
696 – 714.
———. 2005b. Epistemology and the psychology of human judgment. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
CARLSMITH , K. , J. DARLEY , and R. ROBINSON . 2002. Why do we punish? Deterrence and just deserts as
motives for punishment. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 83 (2): 284 – 99.
CUSHMAN , F. A. , L. YOUNG , and M. D. HAUSER . 2006. The role of reasoning and intuition in moral judg-
ments: Testing three principles of harm. Psychological Science 17 (12): 1082 – 89.
DAMASIO , A. 1994. Descartes’ error: Emotion, reason, and the human brain. London: Penguin Books.
PAST AND FUTURE OF EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY 145

DITTO , P. H. , and D. F. LOPEZ . 1992. Motivated skepticism: Use of differential decision criteria for pre-
ferred and non-preferred conclusions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 63:
568 – 84.
DORIS , J. 2002. Lack of character: Personality and moral behavior. Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-
sity Press.
EDWARDS K. , and E. E. SMITH . 1996. A disconfirmation bias in the evaluation of arguments. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology 71: 5 – 24.
FELTZ , A. (n.d.) Problems with Bealer’s appeal to intuition in epistemology. Unpublished
manuscript.
FIELDS , J. , and H. SCHUMAN . 1976. Public beliefs about the beliefs of the public. Public Opinion
Quarterly 40: 427 – 48.
GERMAN , T. , and S. NICHOLS . 2003. Children’s counterfactual inferences about long and short causal
chains. Developmental Science 6: 514 – 23.
GOLDMAN , A. , and J. PUST . 1998. Philosophical theory and intuitional evidence. In Rethinking intui-
tion: The psychology of intuition and its role in philosophical inquiry, edited by M. DePaul
and W. Ramsey. Lanham, Md.: Rowman and Littlefield.
GRAY , H. , K. GRAY , and D. WEGNER . 2007. Dimensions of mind perception. Science 315: 219.
GREENE , J. 2002. The terrible, horrible, no good, very bad truth about morality and what to do
about it. Ph.D. diss., Princeton University.
———. 2003. From neural ‘is’ to moral ‘ought’: What are the moral implications of neuroscien-
tific moral psychology. Neuroscience 4: 847 – 50.
———. Forthcoming. The secret joke of Kant’s soul. In Moral Psychology, Vol. 3: The neuroscience
of morality: Emotion, disease, and development, edited by W. Sinnott-Armstrong.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
GREENE , J. D. , and J. D. COHEN . 2004. For the law, neuroscience changes nothing and everything.
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B 359: 1775– 1785.
GREENE , J. , and HAIDT , J. 2002. How (and where) does moral judgment work? Trends in Cognitive
Science 6 (12): 517 –23.
GREENE , J. , L. NYSTROMM , A. ENGELL , J. DARLEY , and J. COHEN . 2004. The neural bases of cognitive
conflict and control in moral judgment. Neuron 44: 389 – 400.
HAIDT , J. 2001. The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral
judgment. Psychological Review 108: 814 – 34.
———. 2003. The emotional dog does learn new tricks: A reply to Pizarro and Bloom. Psychologi-
cal Review 110 (1): 197 – 98.
HAIDT , J. , F. BJORKLUND , and S. MURPHY . 2000. Moral dumbfounding: When intuition finds no reason.
Unpublished manuscript.
HAIDT , J. , S. KOLLER , and M. DIAS . 1993. Affect, culture, and morality, or is it wrong to eat your dog?
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 65: 613 – 28.
HARRIS , P. L. , T. P. GERMAN , and P. E. MILLS . 1996. Children’s use of counterfactual thinking in causal
reasoning. Cognition 61: 233 –59.
HAUSER , M. D. 2006. Moral minds. New York: Harper Collins.
HAUSER , M. D. , F. A. CUSHMAN , L. YOUNG , R. KANG-XING JIN , and J. MIKHAIL . Forthcoming. A dissociation
between moral judgments and justifications. Mind & Language.
HAUSER , M. D. , L. YOUNG , and F. A. CUSHMAN . Forthcoming. Reviving Rawls’ linguistic analogy. In
Moral psychology and biology, edited by W. Sinnott-Armstrong. New York: Oxford
University Press.
146 THOMAS NADELHOFFER AND EDDY NAHMIAS

JACKSON , F. 1998. From metaphysics to ethics: A defense of conceptual analysis. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
JACKSON , F. , and P. PETTIT . 1995. Moral functionalism and moral motivation. Philosophical Quarterly
45: 20– 40.
KANE , R. 1999. Responsibility, luck, and chance: Reflections on free will and indeterminism. Journal
of Philosophy 96: 217 – 40.
KAUPPINEN , A. 2007. The rise and fall of experimental philosophy. Philosophical Explorations 10 (2):
95– 118 (this issue).
KNOBE , J. 2003a. Intentional action and side-effects in ordinary language. Analysis 63: 190 – 93.
———. 2003b. Intentional action in folk psychology: An experimental investigation. Philosophi-
cal Psychology 16 (2): 309 – 23.
———. 2004a. Folk psychology and folk morality: Response to critics. Journal of Theoretical and
Philosophical Psychology 24 (2): 270 – 79.
———. 2004b. Intention, intentional action and moral considerations. Analysis 64: 181 – 87.
———. 2005a. Theory of mind and moral cognition: Exploring the connections. Trends in
Cognitive Sciences 9: 357 – 59.
———. 2005b. Cognitive processes shaped by the impulse to blame. Brooklyn Law Review 71:
929 – 37.
———. 2007. Experimental philosophy and philosophical significance, Philosophical Explorations
10 (2): 95– 118 (this issue).
———. Forthcoming. The concept of intentional action: A case study in the uses of folk psychol-
ogy. Philosophical Studies.
KNOBE , J. , and A. BURRA . 2006a. The folk concept of intention and intentional action: A cross-
cultural study. Journal of Cognition and Culture 6 (1/2): 113 –32.
———. 2006b. Experimental philosophy and folk concepts: Methodological considerations.
Journal of Cognition and Culture 6 (1/2): 331 – 42.
KNOBE , J. , and J. DORIS . Forthcoming. Strawsonian variations: Folk morality and the search for a
unified theory. In The handbook of moral psychology, edited by J. Doris et al. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
KNOBE , J. , and B. LEITER . Forthcoming. The case for Nietzschean moral psychology. In Nietzsche and
morality, edited by Brian Leiter and Neil Sinhababu. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
KNOBE , J. , and G. MENDLOW . 2004. The good, the bad, and the blameworthy: Understanding the
role of evaluative reasoning in folk psychology. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical
Psychology 24: 252 –58.
KNOBE , J. , and J. PRINZ . Forthcoming. Intuitions about consciousness: Experimental studies. Phe-
nomenology and Cognitive Science.
KNOBE , J ., and E . ROEDDER . n.d. The concept of valuing: experimental studies. Unpublished manuscript.
LESLIE , A. , J. KNOBE , and A. COHEN . 2006. Acting intentionally and the side-effect effect: ‘Theory of
mind’ and moral judgment. Psychological Science 17: 421 – 27.
LEWIS , D. 1972. Psychophysical and theoretical identifications. Australasian Journal of Philosophy
50: 249 – 58.
LEVY , N. n.d. Experimental philosophy: a critique. Unpublished manuscript.
MACHERY , E. Forthcoming. Understanding the folk concept of intentional action: Philosophical
and experimental issues. Mind & Language.
MACHERY , E. , R. MALLON , S. NICHOLS , and S. P. STICH . 2004. Semantics, cross-cultural style. Cognition
92 (3): 1 –12.
MACKIE , J. 1977. Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. London: Penguin.
PAST AND FUTURE OF EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY 147

MALLE , B. 2001. Folk explanations and intentional action. In Intentions and intentionality: Foun-
dations of social cognition, edited by B. F. Malle, L. J. Moses, and D. A. Baldwin. Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press.
———. 2006. Intentionality, morality, and their relationship in human judgment. Journal of Cog-
nition and Culture 6 (1/2): 87– 112.
MALLE , B. , and J. KNOBE . 1997. The folk concept of intentional action. Journal of Experimental Social
Psychology 33: 101 –21.
MALLE , B. , and S. NELSON . 2003. Judging mens rea: The tension between folk concepts and legal
concepts of intentionality. Behavioral Sciences and the Law 21: 563 – 80.
MALLON , R. , E. MACHERY , S. NICHOLS , and S. STICH . Forthcoming. Against arguments from reference. In
Metametaphysics, edited by D. Chalmers, D. Manley, and R. Wasserman. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
MCCANN , H. 2005. Intentional action and intending: Recent empirical studies. Philosophical
Psychology 18 (6): 737 – 48.
MEEKS , R. 2004. Unintentionally biasing the data: Reply to Knobe. Journal of Theoretical and
Philosophical Psychology 24: 220 –23.
MELE , A. 2001. Acting intentionally: Probing folk intuitions. In Intentions and intentionality:
Foundations of social cognition, edited by B. F. Malle, L. J. Moses, and D. A. Baldwin.
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
———. 2003. Intentional action: controversies, data, and core hypotheses. Philosophical Psychol-
ogy 16: 325 – 40.
MYNATT , C. R. , M. E. DOHERTY , and R. D. TWENEY . 1977. Confirmation bias in a simulated research
environment: An experimental study of scientific inference. Quarterly Journal of Experimen-
tal Psychology 29: 85– 95.
NADELHOFFER , T. 2004a. The Butler problem revisited. Analysis 64 (3): 277 –84.
———. 2004b. Praise, side effects, and intentional action. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical
Psychology 24: 196 –213.
———. 2005. Skill, luck, control, and intentional action. Philosophical Psychology 18 (3): 343– 54.
———. 2006a. Bad acts, blameworthy agents, and intentional actions: Some problems for jury
impartiality. Philosophical Explorations 9 (2): 203 – 20.
———. 2006b. Foresight, moral considerations, and intentional actions. Journal of Cognition and
Culture 6 (1): 133 – 58.
NADELHOFFER , T. , and A. FELTZ . Forthcoming. Folk intuitions, slippery slopes, and necessary fictions:
An essay on Smilansky’s free will illusionism. Midwest Studies in Philosophy.
NADELHOFFER , T. , and E. NAHMIAS . Forthcoming. Polling as a valuable pedagogical tool for teaching
philosophy. Teaching Philosophy.
NADELHOFFER , T. , and E. NAHMIAS . n.d. Experimental philosophy: A house divided? Unpublished
manuscript.
NAHMIAS , E. 2006. Folk fears about freedom and responsibility: Determinism vs. reductionism.
Journal of Cognition and Culture 6 (1/2): 215 – 37.
NAHMIAS , E. , D. COATES , and T. KVARAN . Forthcoming. Intuitions about free will and moral respon-
sibility: Mapping the terrain. Midwest Studies in Philosophy.
NAHMIAS , E. , S. MORRIS , T. NADELHOFFER , and J. TURNER . 2004. The phenomenology of free will. Journal
of Consciousness Studies 11 (7/8): 162 – 79.
———. 2005. Surveying freedom: Folk intuitions about free will and moral responsibility.
Philosophical Psychology 18 (5): 561 – 84.
———. 2006. Is incompatibilism intuitive? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research LXXIII, No 1.
148 THOMAS NADELHOFFER AND EDDY NAHMIAS

NICHOLS , S. 2002. Norms with feeling: Towards a psychological account of moral judgment.
Cognition 84: 221 –36.
———. 2004a. Folk concepts and intuitions: From philosophy to cognitive science. Trends in
Cognitive Science 8 (11): 514 – 18.
———. 2004b. After objectivity: An empirical study of moral judgment. Philosophical Psychology
17: 5– 28.
———. 2004c. Folk psychology of free will. Mind & Language 19: 473 – 502.
———. 2006a. Folk intuitions on free will. Journal of Cognition and Culture 6 (1/2): 57 – 86.
———. 2006b. Free will and the folk: Response to commentators. Journal of Cognition and
Culture 6 (1/2): 305 – 20.
NICHOLS , S. , and J. KNOBE . Forthcoming. Moral responsibility and determinism: The cognitive
science of folk intuition. Nous.
NICHOLS , S. , and R. MALLON . 2006. Moral dilemmas and moral rules. Cognition 100: 530 – 42.
NICHOLS , S. , S. STICH , and J. WEINBERG . 2003. Metaskepticism: Meditations in ethno-epistemology.
In The skeptics, edited by S. Luper. Burlington, Vt.: Ashgate.
NICHOLS , S. , and J. ULATOWSKI . Forthcoming. Intuitions and individual differences: The Knobe effect
revisited. Mind & Language.
NICKERSON , R. S. 1998. Confirmation bias: A ubiquitous phenomenon in many guises. Review of
General Psychology 2: 175 – 220.
NISBETT , R. E. 2003. The geography of thought: How Asians and Westerners think differently . . . and
why. New York: Free Press.
NISBETT , R. E. , and L. ROSS . 1980. Human inference: Strategies and shortcomings of social judgment.
Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
PHELAN , M. , and H. SARKISSIAN . Forthcoming. The folk strike back: Or, why you didn’t do it intention-
ally, though it was bad and you knew it. Philosophical Studies.
PIZARRO , D. , and P. BLOOM . 2003. The intelligence of moral intuitions: A comment on Haidt (2001).
Psychological Review 110 (1): 193 – 96.
PIZARRO , D. , E. UHLMANN , and P. BLOOM . 2003. Causal deviance and the attribution of moral respon-
sibility. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 39 (6): 653 – 60.
PIZZARO , D. , E. UHLMANN , and P. SALOVEY . 2003. Asymmetry in judgments of moral blame and praise:
The role of perceived metadesires. Psychological Science 14: 267 – 72.
ROSS , L. , D. GREENE , and P. HOUSE . 1977. The false consensus effect: an egocentric bias in social per-
ception and attribution processes. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 13: 279 – 301.
SARDJEVÉLADZÉ , L. , and E. MACHERY . n.d. Trusting and punishing artifacts. Unpublished manuscript.
SMITH , M. 1994. The moral problem. Cambridge: Basil Blackwell.
SOSA , E. 2005. A defense of the use of the intuitions in philosophy. In Stich and his critics, edited by
M. Bishop and D. Murphy. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
———. 2007. Experimental philosophy and philosophical intuition. Philosophical Studies 132 (1):
99– 107.
STICH , S. 1983. From folk psychology to cognitive science: The case against belief. Cambridge, Mass.:
MIT Press.
———. 1984. Relativism, rationality and the limits of intentional description. Pacific Philosophical
Quarterly 65 (3): 211 – 35.
———. 1985. Could man be an irrational animal? Synthese 64 (1): 115 –35.
———. 1990. The fragmentation of reason. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
———. 1994. Philosophy and psychology. In A companion to the philosophy of mind, edited by
S. Guttenplan. Cambridge: Basil Blackwell.
PAST AND FUTURE OF EXPERIMENTAL PHILOSOPHY 149

———. 1996. Deconstructing the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.


———. 1998. Reflective equilibrium, analytic epistemology, and the problem of cognitive diver-
sity. In Rethinking intuition: The psychology of intuition and its role in philosophical inquiry,
edited by M. DePaul and W. Ramsey. Lanham, Md.: Rowman and Littlefield.
STICH , S. , and R. NISBETT . 1980. Justification and the psychology of human reasoning. Philosophy of
Science 47 (2): 188 –202.
STICH , S. , and J. WEINBERG . 2001. Jackson’s empirical assumptions. Philosophy and Phenomenologi-
cal Research 62: 637 – 43.
STOTZ , K. Forthcoming. How to test philosophical analyses of a scientific concept: Notes from the
field. Philosophy of Science.
STOTZ , K. , and P. E. GRIFFITHS . 2004. Genes: Philosophical analyses put to the test. History and
Philosophy of the Life Sciences 26 (1): 5– 28.
STOTZ , K. , P. E. GRIFFITHS , and R. D. KNIGHT . 2004. How scientists conceptualize genes: An empirical
study. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 35 (4):
647 – 73.
STRAWSON , G. 1994. The impossibility of moral responsibility. Philosophical Studies 75: 5– 24.
SWAIN , S. , J. ALEXANDER , and J. WEINBERG . Forthcoming. The instability of philosophical intuitions:
Running hot and cold on Truetemp.
TURNER , J. , and E. NAHMIAS . 2006. Are the folk agent causationists? Mind & Language 21 (5):
597 – 609.
VARGAS , M. 2005. The revisionist’s guide to responsibility. Philosophical Studies 125 (3): 399 – 429.
VOHS , D. , and J. SCHOOLER . n.d. The price of determinism: Denying the existence of free will
increases cheating behavior. Unpublished manuscript.
WASON , P. C. 1960. On the failure to eliminate hypotheses in a conceptual task. Quarterly Journal of
Experimental Psychology 12: 129 – 40.
WEGNER , D. 2002. The illusion of conscious will. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
WEINBERG , J. , S. NICHOLS , and S. STICH . 2001. Normativity and epistemic intuitions. Philosophical
Topics 29 (1/2): 429 – 60.
WILLIAMSON , T. 2004. Philosophical ‘intuitions’ and scepticism about judgment. Dialectica: Inter-
national Journal of Philosophy of Knowledge 58 (1): 108 – 53.
WOOLFOLK , R. , and J. DORIS . 2002. Rationing mental health care: Parity, disparity, and justice.
Bioethics 16: 469 –85.
WOOLFOLK , R. , J. DORIS , and J. DARLEY . Forthcoming. Attribution and alternate possibilities: Identifi-
cation and situational constraint as factors in moral cognition. Cognition.
YOUNG , L. , F. CUSHMAN , R. ADOLPHS , D. TRANEL , and M. HAUSER . 2006. Does emotion mediate the
relationship between an action’s moral status and its intentional status? Neuropsycho-
logical evidence. Journal of Cognition and Culture 6 (1/2): 291 – 304.

Thomas Nadelhoffer (author to whom correspondence should be addressed), Dickinson


College, Department of Philosophy, Carlisle, PA 17013, USA. E-mail:
tnadelhoffer@gmail.com
Eddy Nahmias, Brains & Behavior Program, Department of Philosophy, Georgia State
University, 1116 One Park Tower, Atlanta, GA 30302-4089, USA. E-mail:
enahmias@gsu.edu

You might also like