02 Seagram
02 Seagram
02 Seagram
Like a strange organic molecule, the formula of puter modeling.1 Still uncommon and arcane, com-
the Seagram Building was discovered by Lionel puters were central to March’s effort as head of
March at the University of Cambridge in 1973 (figs. Cambridge’s Center for Land Use and Built Form
1 and 2). Removed from its famous site, stripped Study to direct architectural education and practice
of its materiality, and pinned to a cubic grid, Mies’s away from what he considered an unhealthy obses-
iconic work was distilled finally into a single num- sion with appearances, and toward the scientific so-
ber “about the same length as some telephone di- lution of social and environmental problems.
aling codes”: 10 2 83EFE0F0 2 . Similarly, Le
Corbusier’s Maison Minimum—apparently not com- Yet even March could not resist demonstrating the
pact enough—became F2803F71280EFE032F (fig. novel formal potential of his mathematics: by
3). These “boolean descriptions” appeared in an tweaking a few numbers one could easily produce
article describing the mathematical basis of com- a beveled version of the Seagram Building (fig. 4).
His colleague Robin Forrest used the same tech-
nique to create alternatives which were rotated,
Figure 1: Boolean description of the Seagram Building, scaled and sheared (fig. 5). For the first time in
Lionel March, 1976.
architectural history such transformational opera-
Figure 3: Boolean description of Le Corbusier’s Maison Figure 4: Bevelled version of the Seagram Building,
Minimum plan, March, 1976. March, 1976.
then: about new technologies, about the end of Figure 6: Royal Festival Hall, London, Leslie Martin,
1951.
movements, and about where architectural forms
come from.
SYSTEMS LABORATORIES
The turn toward science was also a response to a Figure 9: Plan for the New Town of Crawley, 1947.
professional crisis of confidence and lingering sense
of inferiority brought on by architects’ experiences
during the war. The extremities of war had forced
to the surface many doubts about architecture as
a significant modern profession: did architects pos-
sess special expertise? Was their expertise objec-
tive or merely based on taste? In times of real
need, were architects necessary? In short, was
architecture serious business?
it really should be called Fenland Tech; and we primarily from British public agencies. By 1971 the
should all go out and get T-shirts to advertise this center housed sixteen full-time researchers and about
message.”11 Or, as a participant in the scene re- an equal number of post-graduate doctoral candi-
called, “Models, quantitative techniques, structur- dates and visiting associates.16 The center espoused
alism seemed to be in the Fenland air.”12 March an explicitly mathematical approach:
recalls the influence of work coming out of other
Cambridge departments: Mary Hesse’s Models and
Analogues in Science (1963), Richard Stone’s Math- The common method of the Centre’s work
ematics in the Social Sciences and Other Essays is to formulate mathematical and logical
(1967), Richard Chorley and Peter Haggett’s Mod- models which make it possible to charac-
els in Geography (1967), and David Clarke’s Ana- terize and to explore the ranges of spatial
lytical Archeology (1968). When this work was read patterns which accommodate various ac-
by researchers in architecture “there opened up tivities. . . . The research is mainly in the
the prospect of disciplines merging together field of quantitative methods, mathemati-
through the form of approach, despite the ever- cal and logical models, and computer aides
increasing specialization of content.”13 The form of for building and environmental design,
approach in all cases was to be mathematical, and planning, development and management.17
the common tool would be the computer.
A STRUCTURAL REVOLUTION
A distinct setting for architectural research was es-
tablished in 1967 with the creation of the Centre for The most zealous version of the Cambridge posi-
Land Use and Built Form Studies within the Depart- tion was given in a special issue of Architectural
ment of Architecture first under Leslie Martin’s direc- Design, published in 1971, edited by March, Marcial
tion, and then under Lionel March’s.14 Research was Echeñique and Peter Dickens, and filled exclusively
no longer conducted by “lone scholars” like Peter with the work of Cambridge researchers and gradu-
Eisenman, who received a Cambridge Ph.D. in 1963 ates (fig. 12).18 The one-page introduction to this
(fig.11), but by “systems laboratories”: collection, titled “Polemic for a structural revolu-
tion,” gives a concise summary of the assumptions
underlying their work.
the old Vitruvian view of architecture which
related it to the study of classics, divinity, First, that “architecture and physical planning lack
fine arts and music (some of the subject adequate theoretical foundations.” Second, that
areas in Group I of the Faculties in which only the certainties of mathematics can provide
Architecture finds itself in Cambridge) has the needed theoretical base. Third, that the inter-
long since been outgrown . . . . Today most rogation of architecture and planning through
of our research workers would connect mathematical methods is part of a more
most easily to engineering, geography and general”“structural revolution” taking place in the
geology, mathematics, and even physics social and behavioral sciences which is based on a
and chemistry: indeed many of them come new awareness of”“systems and structures.”
to us from these disciplines and not from Fourth, that this mathematical approach is intended
architecture.15 to replace the “intuitive skill”, “confusion”, “sophis-
tical sciences”, “individual hunches”, “court jesters
Like the scientific labs which were its models, the and acrobats”, “private pranks” , “pricey prima-
Centre was financed by research contracts and grants, donnas”, “hallucinations”, “extravagant and empty
Figure 12: Cover of “Models of Environment,” special standing of the building as an object of sensory
issue of Architectural Design, May 1971.
engagement is replaced by the idea of the building
as a system of functional relationships (although
we will see that for March this too might be “aes-
thetic” in some sense). An architectural theory that
rejected images was rejecting the profession’s
dominant medium of communication—both inter-
nally and with the public—as well as the profession’s
established methodologies, all of which were im-
age based. That the long history of drawing could
be replaced by mathematics was not obvious and
“revolution” seems a fair term.
Figure 14: Paper tape used to program an early of related forms: arrangement of rooms within a
computer, 1966.
given perimeter, of spaces according to a given
architectural program, or of activities within a given
plan (figs. 16 and 17). Normally the goal was to
minimize walking distances for users. Working on
these sorts of problems the Cambridge research-
ers, many of whom had mathematical backgrounds,
were able to draw on an existing body of work in
topology and graph theory.
Figure 16: Dual relationship of a plan graph and its Figure 18: Programmatic analysis, treble-linkage Venn
adjacency graph, Philip Steadman, 1976. diagram, Philip Tabor, 1976.
The philosophy of Karl Popper has had some influ- We conceive of rational designing as having three
ence on modern architectural design theory. In the tasks—(1) the creation of a novel composition,
main its impact has been pernicious, but this is as which is accomplished by productive reasoning;
much the result of misunderstandings as it is of (2) the prediction of performance characteristics,
Popper’s own shortcomings. Just as Popper draws which is accomplished by deduction; (3) the ac-
a distinction between logic and empirical science, cumulation of habitual notions and established
so too must a distinction be made between these values, an evolving typology, which is accom-
and design. To base design theory on inappropri- plished by induction.28
ate paradigms of logic and science is to make a
bad mistake. Logic has interests in abstract forms. March believes that this has always implicitly been
Science investigates extant forms. Design initiates the way designs have been developed, whether by
novel forms. A scientific hypothesis is not the same individuals, architectural offices or entire building
thing as a design hypothesis. A logical proposal is traditions. Not unlike Alexander however, he ar-
not to be mistaken for a design proposal.26 gues that there is a new need, and a new capabil-
ity, to make the process explicit:
If architects have missed this distinction, that is
largely because they have followed Popper’s re-
jection of synthetic logic which, March believes, If internalized personal judgement, expe-
design requires since it aims to produce unique rience and intuition alone are relied upon,
compositions rather than universal statements.27 the three modes of the PDI-model become
What March attempts to describe, then, is a ratio- inextricably entangled and no powerfully
nal theory of design which takes synthetic reason- sustained use of collective, scientific knowl-
ing into account. He does this in two ways, first edge is possible. Design will remain more
through the work of the American philosopher or less personalistic and a matter of opin-
Charles Sanders Peirce and then through Baye- ion, albeit professional. If the design pro-
sian probability theory. The basic structure is the cess is externalized and made public, as it
same in both systems: design is presented as a evidently must be for the team work to be
“cyclic, iterative procedure” (like most computer fully effective, then the three stages of the
programs) which passes repeatedly through three PDI-model are worth making explicit so
phases: production, deduction and induction (the that as much scientific knowledge can be
“PDI-model”, fig. 19). brought to bear on the problem as seems
appropriate. In this externalized process it
Figure 19: The PDI (production/deduction/induction) is feasible to experiment with artificial evo-
model of design, March, 1976. lution within the design laboratory using
simulated designs and environments. New,
synthetically derived stereotypes may
emerge, and old ones may be given new
potential without having to wait for practi-
cal exemplification. Design comes to de-
pend less on a single occasion of
inspiration, more on an evolutionary his-
tory, greatly accelerated as this iterative
procedure can now be—a prospect opened
up by recent advances in computer repre-
sentation.29
The mathematical model of the design may Third, the Boolean description would have been
be made alive on a computer, complete with for March only the grammar of a proper architec-
its structural integrity, with its environmen- tural model, which would also have included struc-
tal climate, with patterns of user activities; tural, environmental, programmatic and economic
it may be disassembled into its component information. As nearly as possible this model would
elements and costed; it may be speedily have been a simulation of reality, permitting the
modified, transformed, and manipulated. “artificial evolution” of designs and assuring that
the architectural proposal responded to objective
Architectural education around the concept of mod- criteria, not just the formal whims of the designer.
elling—even penetrating into the teaching and In this way mathematics was put in the service of
methods of architectural history—becomes, I be- March’s socialist ends.
lieve, an intellectually tough discipline around the
theme of man and his environment. . . . It re- Finally, we must consider an almost contradictory
moves architecture from the invention of images motivation which was only hinted at earlier. For
which reflect the externalities of our technological despite the iconoclastic rhetoric, all of this math-
culture (the machine aesthetic), and penetrates ematical work was driven by an interest which
beyond appearances to the elements, relationships, March himself described as’“aesthetic.” Reflecting
and processes of its very existence: we might coin on his time as a student at Cambridge, March re-
the phrase, “the systems aesthetic”. It turns its called:
back on architecture warped by the competitive
individualism of the 19th century and the
. . . most strongly I recollect Sandy Wilson
aggrandisement of personal genius, and faces for-
stopping me in a corridor and saying some-
ward to an architecture balanced in its collective
thing about the future possibility of archi-
design and its commitment to the promotion of
tecture being notated as a mathematical
cultural evolution: architecture no longer residing
code. This rang bells. It reinforced a
in the souls of individuals, but in the body of a
thought planted by Bruce Martin that the
profession.30
elements of architecture might be set out
BOOLEAN DESCRIPTION OF BUILT FORMS like Lavoisier’s chemical table, and by a
further analogy, that with such a limited
Returning to March’s “Boolean description” of the means architectural works of the imaginary
Seagram Building, we can now see all that it meant power of a Beethoven symphony might be
for him. First, Boolean algebra represented the constructed (fig. 20) . . . . My impelling
mathematization of “the very processes of ratio- motivation at this time was aesthetic. It
nal argument.”31 Being able to describe buildings still is. There are other motivations, but
through this algebra would make architecture more deep down what makes me tick is an aes-
rational and less intuitive, more scientific and less thetic sense of order, of essential simplic-
artistic. This representation would relate architec- ity behind apparent complexity.33
ture to circuit design, topology and information
theory rather than painting, sculpture, or music.32 Like Leslie Martin, March believed that this sort of
order could unite the two cultures of art and sci-
Second, all of these associations with mathemat- ence in a non-superficial way.
ics and computer science would give architecture
not just a sound epistemological base, but also All of which did not happen. Instead what we see
greater practical standing in a postwar society in his paper on Boolean description, and in the
dominated by science. Architecture would be re- Cambridge work which built on it, are the first hints
constructed as a serious business with a legitimate, of the formal experimentation which could occur
and fundable, role for advanced research like that in digital environments freed from the constraints
carried out at Cambridge. March argued that for of actual buildings—freed from gravity, from ma-
the first time since the eighteenth century archi- teriality, from structure, from inhabitation, from
tectural studies had “touched the frontiers of knowl- economics—and freed from the restraints of tradi-
edge” and it seemed that architects might regain tional drafting and modeling techniques. In the
membership to the Royal Society. beveled and sheared versions of the Seagram build-
308 THE ART OF ARCHITECTURE/THE SCIENCE OF ARCHITECTURE
Figure 20: Juxtaposition of serial music and bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1976). There is some
architectural research, March, 1972 confusion about the date of the material contained in
this volume: March’s forward to the volume, which he
indicates was written after the articles, is dated June
1973, the book’s bibliography contains entries from as
late as 1975, and the copyright is 1976.
2
March, “Modern Movement to Vitruvius: Themes of Edu-
cation and Research,” Royal Institute of British Archi-
tects’ Journal (Mar. 1972): 101.
3
Ibid., 101.
4
See March, “The Logic of Design and the Question of
Value,” introduction to Architecture of Form; and
Alexander introduction to paperback edition of Notes on
the Synthesis of Form (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard Uni-
versity Press, 1971). Strangely, today it is Alexander’s
pattern language which is well-respected in some com-
puter science circles today.
5
Peter Carolin and Trevor Dannatt, eds., Architecture,
Education and Research: the Work of Leslie Martin: Pa-
pers and Selected Articles (London: Academy Editions,
1996).
6
Leslie Martin, Ben Nicholson and Naum Gabo, eds.,
Circle: International Survey of Constructive Art (London:
Faber and Faber, 1937).
7
Anthony Jackson, The Politics of Architecture. (Toronto:
University of Toronto Press, 1970), 79.
8
Ibid.
9
Ibid., 41.
10
Ibid.
11
Clinton Rossiter in 1961 as quoted by Colin Rowe in
As I Was Saying: Recollections and Miscellaneous Es-
says, vol. 1 (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1996), 131.
12
March, foreword to The Architecture of Form, ix.
13
Ibid.
14
In 1974 LUBFS merged with the smaller Technical Re-
ing we see the first signs of the—“free space” ar- search Division of the Department of Architecture to cre-
chitecture, “anti-architecture,” and”“eighty-nine ate the Martin Centre for Architectural and Urban
degree” architecture which would sweep the disci- Studies—it continues to operate under this new name.
pline in the next two decades. We see the forms 15
March, foreword to The Architecture of Form, xii.
which can evolve in simulations cut loose from their 16
Nigel Lloyd, description of the Centre for Land Use and
referents. Somewhere in the Cambridge fens func- Built Form Studies, University of Cambridge (unpub-
tionalism had committed computer-aided suicide, lished), 29 Nov. 1971, Library of the Martin Centre, Uni-
and architecture was left with a new representa- versity of Cambridge.
tional system with which to project its images of 17
Ibid.
the future—images created through ever more 18
Lionel March, Marcial Echeñique and Peter Dickens,
technical means, but for ever less scientific ends.
eds., “Models of Environment,”Architectural Design 41
NOTES (May 1971).
19
Ibid., 275.
1
Lionel March, “A Boolean Description of a Class of Built 20
March, foreword to The Architecture of Form, xiii.
Forms,” The Architecture of Form, Cambridge Urban and
Architectural Studies 4, edited by Lionel March (Cam- 21
Ibid., xiv.
10283EFE0F02 OR THE SEAGRAM BUILDING 309
22
Tabor, “Analysing Communication Patterns,”The Archi- 28
Ibid., 18.
tecture of Form, 284. 29
Ibid., 21-2.
23
Ibid., 309. 30
March, “Modern Movement,” 108-9.
24
March, “The Logic of Design,” The Architecture of Form. 31
March, “Boolean Description,” 41.
25
Ibid., 5. 32
Ibid., 71-2.
26
Ibid., 15. 33
Ibid., 101.
27
Ibid., 15.