Ethics of Biology
Ethics of Biology
Ethics of Biology
DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-05544-2_55-1
# Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015
Biology: Ethics of
Jesús Mosterín*
Instituto de Filosofía, CSIC (National Research Council), Madrid, Spain
Abstract
This entry describes the relations between the science of biology and the ethical reflection. The general
notions involved are defined and several of the main problems and issues are analyzed from a logical as
well as from a moral point of view.
Keywords
Ethics; Convention; Compassion; Biology; Research; Fallacy; Inconsistency; Fraud; Knowledge; Mirror
neuron; Animal; Empathy; Synthetic; Genetic engineering
Introduction
Although the large-scale structure of the brain is codified in the genome, a large part of the concrete neural
circuitry depends on past social interactions and constitutes culture. Human nature and human culture are
varieties of information. They differ in how this information is transmitted and codified and where it
resides. Human nature is transmitted genetically (from parents to offspring), encodes all our permanent
characteristics in the sequence of bases of DNA, and resides in the genome. Human culture encodes in
neural circuits everything one has learned from other people (relatives, friends, teachers, authors) through
social learning; it resides in the brain (Mosterín 2009).
Ethics and biology are different parts of culture. Biology is a science, the collective pursuit of reliable
and objective knowledge about living beings. The task of science is to inquire into the nature of things and
to discover and describe facts. Ethics is concerned with how things should be, how people should behave,
and which norms or conventions society should adopt. So, science and ethics seem to be quite disparate
endeavors. It would seem strange to speak of an ethics of physics or of an ethics of mathematics but less so
to talk about ethics of biology. What could an ethics of biology be? Individual biologists are often
concerned by the ethical issues involved in their research. Some of them even try to create a value system
based on biological knowledge.
Philosophy of science can be applied to the analysis of the theory of evolution, but the theory of
evolution itself can also be applied to the analysis of philosophy of science (and indeed of culture in
general, including ethics). In a similar vein, biology can be considered from an ethical point of view, but
ethics can also be considered from a biological perspective. In any case, ethics of biology should be
differentiated from biology of ethics. Ethics of biology has to do with how research should be conducted
in biology. Biology of ethics has rather to do with the alleged foundation of ethics on biology, genetics,
and evolution. For example, Frans de Waal has emphasized the evolutionary origin of altruism and morals
in bonobos and other primates (de Waal 2013).
*Email: jesus@mosterin.com
Page 1 of 8
Encyclopedia of Global Bioethics
DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-05544-2_55-1
# Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015
Compassion
Moral emotions are rooted in our brain and are part of nature, but they also play an important role in our
moral judgments. The main moral emotion is compassion. To have empathy for someone’s feelings or
problems is to notice and understand them; no sharing of the feeling is required. To feel sympathy for
someone in trouble involves, besides having empathy, to feel sorry for him (or her) and care about his
problems. Compassion is a strong feeling of sympathy for someone who is suffering together with a desire
to help.
The notion of compassion played an important role in the moral philosophy of the Enlightenment.
Besides David Hume, other thinkers emphasized its role, for example, Adam Smith and Jeremy Bentham.
To feel compassion for someone who is suffering is to put oneself imaginatively at his place, and to have
the disagreeable experience of feeling his pain, and to wish to do something to relieve this suffering.
Our understanding of the neurological underpinnings of the emotion of compassion is sparse and
unsure. Nevertheless, around 1990, Giacomo Rizzolatti and his colleagues at the University of Parma,
while studying the brain control of movements by macaque monkeys, made the discovery of the mirror
neurons. A mirror neuron is a neuron that fires both when the animal acts in a certain way and when the
Page 2 of 8
Encyclopedia of Global Bioethics
DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-05544-2_55-1
# Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015
animal observes the same action performed by another. In the macaques, mirror neurons are found in the
inferior frontal gyrus (in the frontal lobe) and in the inferior parietal lobe (Rizzolatti and Sinigaglia 2008).
Most evidence for mirror neurons in humans is indirect. Brain imaging experiments using functional
magnetic resonance imaging have shown that the human inferior frontal cortex and superior parietal lobe
are active when a person performs an action and also when a person sees another individual performing a
similar action. Mirror neurons were soon offered as a partial explanation of our feelings of empathy and
compassion. Not everyone agrees with this interpretation.
The emotions people feel depend in part on the abundance of certain neurotransmitters,
neuromodulators, hormones, and other molecules affecting the mood in certain zones or systems of the
brain. Molly Crockett has examined how the neuromodulator serotonin shapes our reaction to harm to
others and our value of fairness and so our ability for compassion and sociality (Crockett 2010). Enhanced
serotonin seems to bias moral judgment and decision-making toward sociality and to boost aversive
emotional reactions to the prospective harm of others.
Several authors have analyzed the connection of dopamine concentration and dopamine receptors with
impulsive antisocial behavior (Buckholtz 2010). Prior flooding of the brain with dopamine can also lead
to sociopathy. On the other hand, oxytocin, a hormone that plays an important role in childbirth, acts like a
neuromodulator in the brain and seems to increase empathy, trust, generosity, and predisposition to
compassion (Lee 2009). The inability to secrete oxytocin has been repeatedly linked to sociopathy and
lack of empathy.
Epistemic Ethics
The conduct of scientific research is implicitly (and sometimes explicitly) submitted to specific ethical
norms widely agreed by the scientific community. Of course, a scientist can misbehave in non-epistemic
ways, for example, by stealing money from the laboratory. But a scientist can also misbehave in typically
epistemic ways by committing fraud in research through the fabrication, falsification, or trimming of data
or plagiarism. Ethical epistemic norms serve the aims of research and apply to scientists, scholars, and
others involved in research.
According to Shamoo and Resnik, there are several reasons why it is important to adhere to ethical
norms in research. Norms promote the aims of science, such as knowledge and truth. For example,
prohibitions against fabricating, falsifying, or misrepresenting research data promote the truth and avoid
error. Since research often involves a great deal of cooperation and coordination among many people,
ethical standards promote the values that are essential to collaborative work, such as trust, accountability,
mutual respect, and fairness. For example, many ethical norms in research – such as guidelines for
authorship, copyright and patenting policies, data sharing policies, and confidentiality rules in peer
review – are designed to protect intellectual property interests while encouraging collaboration. Ethical
norms in research also help to build public support for research. People are more likely to fund a research
project if they can trust the quality and integrity of research. Finally, many of the norms of research
promote other important moral and social values, such as social responsibility, human rights, animal
welfare, compliance with the law, and human health and safety. Ethical lapses in research can significantly
harm human and animal subjects, students, and the public. For example, a researcher who fabricates data
in a clinical trial may harm or even kill patients (Shamoo and Resnik 2009).
Advanced research in biology has now extended beyond Western countries to new scientific power-
houses in Japan, China, India, and other places. Consequently, the preoccupation with ethical issues
surrounding genetic engineering, synthetic biology, and similar endeavors has reached global propor-
tions. From China to Saudi Arabia, many countries have promulgated ethical guidelines for research in
Page 3 of 8
Encyclopedia of Global Bioethics
DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-05544-2_55-1
# Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015
biology and have established research ethics boards. Nevertheless, different religious traditions and
influences have led to divergent guidelines.
Page 4 of 8
Encyclopedia of Global Bioethics
DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-05544-2_55-1
# Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015
Animals in Research
Several ethical issues in biological and biomedical research concern the treatment and welfare of the
subjects of experimentation. These subjects can be human beings, who are protected by the bioethical
norms requiring that their a priori, free, and informed consent be collected before submitting them to
experiments. Nevertheless, most of the subjects of biological experimentation are nonhuman animals.
The use of animals in research is a polemic issue and has always been. Claude Bernard, the founder of
animal physiology, practiced vivisection on thousands of living dogs, cutting them open and submitting
them to painful experiments that shocked many people, including all members of his own family.
Vivisection continues to be very controversial; sometimes it has resulted in public order problems, as
angry protesters try to stop such practices. In all advanced countries, explicit ethical norms and new
legislation have been introduced and implemented to limit the pain of the animals involved. Many
ethicists and scientists agree on the desirability of pursuing the policy of the three Rs: replacement of
animals by other research models (e.g., stem cells or computer simulations), reduction of the number of
animals actually used in experiments, and refinement of the experiments in the sense of diminishing the
amount of pain and anguish inflicted on animals (e.g., through anesthetics, where feasible).
Page 5 of 8
Encyclopedia of Global Bioethics
DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-05544-2_55-1
# Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015
for other creatures. When the use of animals in painful research is criticized, a defense is often mounted on
the assumption that this type of research can lead to the avoidance of human suffering, as if any animal
suffering would be justified by any human benefit. This is the point of view of extreme speciesism, and it
should not be accepted as a matter of course.
In Jewish, Christian, and Islamic thought, only people are subjects of moral concern. In this tradition,
there was nothing comparable to the Daoist sense of nature in China or to the Buddhist and Jainist
preoccupation with ahimsa (avoidance of harm to animals) in India. In the utterly anthropocentric Western
traditional world view, nature was either ignored or conceived of as just an object of exploitation, with rare
exceptions, such as Francis of Assisi. Humans were supposed to have been created in the image of God
and to have nothing to do with the rest of nature. In any case, humans were at the center of the Universe;
they occupied center stage in creation. The Sun and all the stars circled the Earth, the human abode, and
God and the angels watched humankind attentively from above the sphere of the stars. Of course, this
position is unsustainable nowadays. Even in the Western tradition, Jeremy Bentham, referring to animals,
wrote: “The question is not, Can they reason? nor, Can they talk? but, Can they suffer?” (Bentham 1789).
Eco-ethics
The more one becomes aware of the ecological problems of our planet, the more one feels any threat to the
biosphere as a matter of great concern. This is the basis of a new level of moral consciousness, which goes
beyond the ethics of compassion, and which could be termed eco-ethics. Eco-ethics fosters a new sense of
stewardship of and responsibility toward the biosphere. People can become the thinking part of the biota
and can assume the biosphere’s problems as their own.
Eco-ethics is the appropriate level for dealing with typical ecological problems, such as the destruction
of the tropical forests or coral reefs, the threats to the biodiversity, or climate change. Paul W. Taylor
proposes a biocentric ethics. All organisms are teleological centers of life. Insofar as humans become
rational and well informed about facts, they will develop reality awareness and respect for nature, and they
will adopt a biocentric ethics (Taylor 1986).
Synthetic Biology
New developments in biology and biotechnology have opened unprecedented opportunities to produce
artificial life and new types of organisms with desired properties. This endeavor has become known as
synthetic biology, a field of research that combines elements of biology, engineering, genetics, chemistry,
and computer science. The usual science of biology is analytical; it describes and analyzes the natural
living things that are the results of biological evolution. Synthetic biology is to a large extent an active
technology, and it is synthetic to the extent that it creates or synthesizes its own subjects of research. It
joins the knowledge and insights of biology with the practical principles and techniques of engineering.
Achievements in synthetic biology rely on artificially created DNA to create new biochemical systems or
organisms with novel or enhanced characteristics.
If genetic sequencing is about reading DNA and genetic engineering is about copying, cutting, and
pasting DNA, synthetic biology is about writing and programming new DNA with two main goals: create
genetic machines from scratch and gain new insights about how life works. Genetic engineering maintains
the usual structures of natural life but changes parts of the genome, so as to achieve desired results. Certain
lines of research try to produce a minimum genome by successively eliminating genes of a given
prokaryote to see whether everything continues to work. “In an ideal world, designing living systems
Page 6 of 8
Encyclopedia of Global Bioethics
DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-05544-2_55-1
# Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015
for a practical purpose should be like redesigning a car to make it more efficient, or redesigning a
computer with a faster processor. One would have the parts, the right software, the brains and the
knowledge about the target system, and ‘voilà!’ a new bacteria that produces ethanol from water, CO2
and light has been created” (Serrano 2007).
A major breakthrough in the field was announced in 2010. Craig Venter, Clyde Hutchison, and
Hamilton Smith created the first synthetic life forms. They had copied and modified an entire genome
of a small bacterial cell, inserted it into a living cell of another species, and in doing so created a new,
synthetic organism. They synthesized a circular genome of about a million DNA bases. This synthetic
genome contains 382 genes, plagiarized from the minimum genome of Mycoplasma mycoides. The
scientists finally managed to insert this synthetic genome into a enucleated cell of Mycoplasma
capricolum so as to produce the first synthetic organism capable of self-reproduction. In fact, they
produced a new biospecies (Venter 2013).
In the future, scientists could try to create artificial systems comparable with living beings but based on
completely different structures: not on known proteins, but on other molecules; or not on DNA for the
encoding of information; not on ATP for energy storage; perhaps even based on a solvent other than water.
Up to now, these possibilities remain largely unexplored.
New developments in technology often lead to ethical discussions of their presumed dangers and risks.
For example, the whole field of nanotechnology has become surrounded by alarmist ethical assessments
of its risks. And most scientists do not share the perception of grave risks in genetically modified crops,
which nevertheless meet with much opposition among certain groups of activists.
There are three justified reasons for alarm about a new crop or a new biotechnological development:
(1) danger for human health, (2) pain or mistreatment of animals, and (3) destruction of biodiversity. It is
not clear that many cases of genetic engineering, from the insulin-producing bacteria, commercialized
from 1982 on, to the cultivation of genetically modified plants since 1994, to the use of stem cells and
cloning in research, meet any of these criteria.
Ethical questions in synthetic biology mostly focus on risks, paying special attention to the need to
control self-replicating machines that could genetically pollute the environment. This, at first sight, does
not differ from the ethical questions discussed more than 30 years ago when the first recombinant DNA
techniques were born. Some people question the whole endeavor of producing new gene arrangements
and artificial organisms. Finally, the vocabulary of synthetic biology can foster the identification of
organisms with artifacts, an identification that, given the connection between life and value, may in the
very long run lead to a weakening of society’s respect for higher forms of life that are usually regarded as
worthy of protection.
Conclusion
Researchers in biology and biotechnology are confronted and excited by a wealth of new opportunities
but also alarmed by the fears and opposition they detect in parts of the public. At the interface between
science and morals is a widely perceived need for a deep ethical reflection that takes into account the
epistemic values of science, concern over the well-being of living creatures, and the preservation of the
Earth’s biosphere.
Cross-References
▶ Animal Research
Page 7 of 8
Encyclopedia of Global Bioethics
DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-05544-2_55-1
# Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015
▶ Anthropocentrism
▶ Artificial Organs
▶ Biocentrism
▶ Bioengineering
▶ Ethics
▶ Genetic Modification
▶ Scientific Misconduct
▶ Synthetic Biology
References
Bentham, J. (1789). The principles of morals and legislation, ch. XVII, note to IV. Oxford. Reprinted
(1907), Clarendon Press, Oxford.
Buckholtz, J. W. (2010). Dopaminergic network differences in human impulsivity. Science, 329, 532.
Crockett, M. J. (2010). Serotonin selectively influences moral judgment and behavior through effects on
harm aversion. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 107,
17433–17438.
De Waal, F. (2013). The bonobo and the Atheist: In search of humanism among the primates. New York:
W. W Norton.
Lee, H. J. (2009). Oxytocin: The great facilitator of life. Progress in Neurobiology, 88(2), 127–151.
Medvedev, Z. A. (1969). The rise and fall of T.D. Lysenko. New York: Columbia University Press.
Moore, G. E. (1903). Principia Ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mosterín, J. (2009). La cultura humana. Madrid: Espasa.
Mosterín, J. (2013). Neural reality and social convention: Do they overlap? Annals of the New York
Academy of Sciences, 1299, 91–97.
Rizzolatti, G., & Sinigaglia, C. (2008). Mirrors in the brain: How our minds share actions, emotions, and
experience. Oxford: Oxford UniversityPress.
Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Serrano, L. (2007). Synthetic biology: Promises and challenges. Molecular Systems Biology, 3, 158.
Shamoo, A., & Resnik, D. (2009). Responsible conduct of research (2nd ed.). New York: Oxford
University Press.
Taylor, P. W. (1986). Respect for nature: A theory of environmental ethics. Princeton: Princeton Univer-
sity Press.
Venter, J. C. (2013). Life at the speed of light: From the double Helix to the dawn of digital life. New York:
Viking Adult.
Further Readings
Boniolo, G., & De Ana, G. (Eds.). (2009). Evolutionary ethics and contemporary biology. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Maienschein, J., & Ruse, M. (Eds.). (1999). Biology and the foundation of ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Page 8 of 8