Nodelman The Implied Viewer
Nodelman The Implied Viewer
Nodelman The Implied Viewer
Usually, when we talk about how picture books affect the children
who read them, we talk about the form and content of specific books. We
enthuse over how a particular set of pictures will delight them, or we think
about whether they will be able to understand the visual style of an illustrator
or the diction used in a particular text. We wonder if depictions of certain
characters will encourage young readers to think in terms of gender
silereotypes, or we worry about the morals they might derive from special
tales. And of course, all of this is important. My own work as a scholar of
picture books explores a range of ways in which individual writers can use
semiotic and narrative codes in order to communicate specific meanings in
individual books. I know, not only that these books do convey meanings,
but that the meanings they convey are subtle and wide-ranging. Furthermore,
f mconvincedthatchildrencan access these meanings in all theircomplexity,
and both take pleasure and gain knowledge from doing so. We need only
be willing to teach them the appropriate interpretive strategies.
'l'he knowledge and the assumptions about the world and about people
e xpected of both implied readers and implied viewers move well beyond
rcuders should be and do". Or we can, with more effort (and,I personally
think, more productively), provide children with the ability to ttrink critically
nhout what they read and view - to become more active readers than they
nright akeady be, to be aware of how texts work to influence them and
lhus resist the negative influences.
llut as I said earlier, my focus here is not on the specific content of particular
lxroks, but on the viewer implied by any picture in every picture book.
tJnless we want to deprive children of books altogether, this we cannot
nvoid. That makes it all the more important to become aware of the nature
of this generalised viewer. I will return to these rnatters after a look at
what that nature is.
So what might those assumptions be, and what do they suggest about the
inherent basic nature of an implied reader/ viewer? Let me outtne some.
I begin with some qualities picture books share with other forms of
children's literature. The impliedreader/vieweris achild- abrutally obvious
brlng child means knowing that one is a child and therefore entitled to or
a
ailpested to behave in certain ways defined as childlike.
Thoao ways axe subtle and complicated - the books we offer children
,ClTor a rangeof ffierent ways of being childlike. Picture books, for instance,
lmply an audience of younger children, and help children to understand
thft early childhood is a time when stories must be told in short and simple
tcxtr and when pictures are necessary to make sense of the words. They
lmply that early childhood is different in quality from later childhood, when
longer books with fewer pictures become possible and appropriate. They
lmply, in other words, an idea of childhood as a time of development through
| rcries of discrete stages: the idea that people get increasingly complicated
ru they mature.
In order to become more complicated one must start out being less
eomplicated. Obviously, then, many of the qualities we define as childlike
lnvolve ways in which younger children are more limited than older children,
and all children are more limited than adults - less wise, less capable, more
prone to self-indulgence and more in need of certain kinds of adult control
and regulation. Children who accept theirresemblance to the implied child
rcader/viewers of children's picture books have been given the freedom to
bc less wise and more self-indulgent that adults are often allowed to be.
At the same time, though, they have been invited to understand how much
their limitations force adults to control and regulate and supervise them.
Thc implied reader/viewer of picture books knows, not just that the books
tg intended for specifically childlike readers, but also, thatthey are provided
for those childlike readers, not by other children, but by adults, adults with
tho best interests of children in mind. The mere existence of picture books
thon implies a world organized so that children need and can depend on
bonevolent adult intervention in, and supervision of, all aspects oftheir
llves-including their imaginative lives as influenced by the content of
ehildren's books. The books suggest in merely being there the entire social
ltructure that creates and shapes the nature of childhood as a position of
dependency for children in our culture.
The child reader/viewers I have just been describing are complex and
ambivalent, caught in a complex field of forces, pulled powerfully in opposite
dlrcctions. On the one hand, they are childishly free of adult standards of
The learning the implied reader/viewer possesses has yet other dimensions.
More generally, the implied reader/viewer of children's picture books, like
the readers ofall books, understands some basic conventions about books.
Books have a front and a back, a top and a bottom. The words and pictures
on the cover are separate from but related to the actual story itself, which
is found inside. The story at least in books in the English language, emerges
when a readerbegins at what we call the front (i.e., with the bound margin
on our left) and moves consecutively through the pages, and from left to
right and then top to bottom on each double-paged spread.
A reader/viewer who knows all this and acts on it appreciates some basic
principles of convention and order, and has a willingness to adhere to them.
The mere fact that a child can leaf through a book in the right order in
order to perceive a narrative within it then means that the child has come
to understand something about the rules and patterns that allow for social
intercourse and communication. We like to talk about children being free
and spontaneous and creative. The spontaneity and creativity ofany child
who knows and makes use of these basic facts about books has been
qualified by and governed by adults. Reading a book is inherently an act
that moves a reader/viewer beyond individual isolation and the freedom of
anarchy. A child who knows which way is up and reads books with that
way up is on the way to becoming a good citizenin a shared social reality.
It is ironic, then, that many children's books seem to be what Alison Lurie
calls "'subversive" - apparently celebratory of spontaneity and imagination
and the defiance of adult values and assumptions. According to Lurie, "the
great subversive works of children's literature mock current assumptions
That books exist to offer readers pleasure tells readers that they
deserve
to, even need to, be pleased. In other words: that the book exists
to fulfil a
need implies that the need exists that then must be fulfilled and
can rightfully
be fulfilled.In differenttimes andplaces, children were notencouraged to
seek enjoyment in stories and pictures or even, in more general
terms, to
think of themselves as people with a need or a right to inautge these forms
of pleasure. That so many picture books exist, that ttre/ are often so
opulently illustrated and designed, and that we encourage children
to take
pleasure in the delights they offer and to seek out yet more
books and get
morepleasure fromthem without any need to feel guilty about it-
all thJse
are evidence of the extent to which picture books imply an
entire economy
of consumption driven by satisfying one's urge to please oneself in
certain
ways understood to be satisfying.
llrnt plcasing you has been an aspiration of a whole range of people, writers
artd illustrators and publishers and librarians and parents. To become the
lrnplicd reader/viewerof these elaborateproductions is, inevitably, to develop
H Ftrong sense of one's worth and one's desert - to understand that one
rloan indeed deserve such elaborate attention and that wanting and getting
whnt one wants are good things.
Ollen, in fact, children's books contain stories which replicate this allowing
entl undermining of pleasure, and work to make their readers feel guilty
ebout the very pleasures they offer. These stories ask children to identify
with characters who are creative or spontaneous or adventurous (and,
F€rhaps, subversive), first, in order to enjoy the delights ofadventurousness
and spontaneity, and second, in order to learn how dangerous
stlvcnturousness and spontaneity are. The implied viewer of such books
dcvelops two intriguingly conffadictory ideas about pleasure: it's good and
bnd, healthful and dangerous, harmless and harmful.
'l'he two ideas tend to occur sequentially in texts - first the delightful
lndulgence in pleasure, then the dangerous consequences. But since so
nnny books follow this pattern, a child reader of a series of children's books
lr takcn back to the first stage and then moves on to the second again and
uguin. The reader/viewer implied by a number of children's picture books
lnkcn together is, then, like the comically deficient characters on many
Atncrican TV situation comedies, who delightfully indulge their vice or folly
Fltcl thcn become aware of how badly they have behaved and learn to move
bcyond it in each episode, and then, at the start of the next episode, are
alwuys right back where they started, being vicious or foolish in the same
delightful old way. These implied reader-viewers move back and forth
betwccn childlike folly and adultwisdom, between delightfrrl subversiveness
Hnd sane conventionality, but never seem to completely give up one for the
Plsture books contain pictures, and pictures imply a specific sort of viewer
merely in being pictures, a viewer unlike the reader implied by the words
of a tcxt. Compared to printed words, for instance, they offer a relatively
donsc sensuous experience. Pictures contain textures, colours, shapes,
llncs - a variety of things for the eye to respond to and be pleased by, for
thete aspects of pictures are and are meant to be pleasing in and for
thomselves, without reference to the meanings or objects they have been
llladc to represent. To look at, say, a patch of intense red is sensuously
Unusing without any reference to the apple or fire truck the patch of red
Ftlght be representing in a particular picture.
Bf cuurse, the colours and lines and shapes in pictures book do represent
Sher things - the red patch is indeed an apple or a fire truck, not just a
pltch of red. As I said earlier, pictures operate as a system of signs, and as
I try to show in my book Words About Pictures, every aspect of them
blpn to convey specific meanings to knowledgeable viewers. Their implied
Ulcwer knows these signs, has a conscious or unconscious awareness of
bOw they allow lines and colours on a flat page to convey ideas ofpeople
pluce and things. Such an implied viewer is caught up in and constrained
ig}lg{l lhe housc thc text mentions - that despite the fact we have two
dlftrerrt :ignn lbr it in two different sign systems, there is just one house.
It flnt lneludes somewhat more sophisticated strategies, such as guessing
ftgnr the sppeorence of the house in the illustration information about its
tg€, llr ponriblc location in time or space as implied by its architectural
Sile, the relutivc degree of wealth of those who live in it, the possibility of
rilteonc being content to live in such a dwelling. The implied rcadeil
f l€wer ahu knows how to apply all this visual information to the situation
rrullhretl hy u tcxt - interpret the words and their implications in the light of
lnfonttatlon provided by a perusal of the pictures. Such a reader/viewer
lhett krtoWt how to be analytical, how to compare and combine information
hrf r rllffCrent $ources, how to make the implied sort of sense of a complex
llehl uf plmitrilitics, how to solve apuzzle (and to enjoy solving it). Children
Fllprntr6god to become such reader/viewers are becoming meaning-makers,
e*llvely engogcd in solving the puzzles.
Hul llrcre ir, unce more, a paradox, and a division: the mastery they develop
{r lxrrtle utlvcrs masters them, as they increasingly become able to realise
r.tlulirutr to the puzzles thatwerethe ones intendedbythe authorand illustrator,
l*trrrrre increasingly aligned with the subject the text intends to construct.
Menttwltite, the mere act of looking at both the words and the pictures in
grh'lttre btxrks in order to make meaning out of them adds yet a further
rlltnr.turiun to the implied reader/viewer. In order to understand both the
rvottlr nnd the pictures, we need to position ourselves at some distance
rrttrfly l'rom them: we can't make anything like the sense an author might
Itnvc intcndcd out of the words and/or illustrator out of the picture with our
ftulei tlre$scd firmly against the books they appear in. Marshall Mcluhan
ruggcrllr that "Psychically the printed book, an extension of the visual
fnr'rrlly, intensified perspective and the fixed point of view" (1965, p.172).
ll'thnt is true - and literally speaking, it is - pictures, even more intimately
r'nrrncctcd with the visual faculty, must do something similar. Both, then,
rerprire rcader/viewers to distance tlemselves from what they observe in
urlcr to observe it in what they will then consider to be a meaningful and
Iu't'rrrutc manner. Such reader/viewers will tend to trust the value and
vnlitlity of the detached, isolated point of view - and tend to mistrust the
vplue rtnd validity of what they perceive by other means - by touch, for
lirsinrrcc. They have become gazers; I will say more shortly about the
F('r,lt(rny of the gaze and the character of he or she who gazes.
And the right way, merely in existing and in being right, establishes
hierarchies, priorities, centres and
-*gLr. The act
and establishing which of the group ofvisual objects"fi#;;
at apicture
it depicis is actually
its subject - the person, or the cat on the person's lap,
or the lamp on the
table beside the person, or the flower in the drapery'in
constructs the reader/viewer as conscious of and
the background -
operating within the context
of such hierarchies. such a subject views the worta pititically:
children
who can read and enjoy picture books have become
potitic ueings, conscious
of and seeking out the inevitably varying dispositions
of powei and interest
and attention in the world around thern
Flnully, the division is confirmed yet again by the human figures who appear
Itt thc picture in picture books, and the relationships those figures imply
bctwccn themselves and those who view them. Like the actors in a play or
I nrovie, they are there to be looked at. In many books they even smile out
0t u$, apparently conscious of and happy about the presence of viewers.
Whether they acknowledge their position or not, these figures share in a
tnmcwhat less aggressive form the invitation to voyeurism that John Berger
dlrcovers in both contemporary pin-up photographs and traditional European
palntings of nudes. Their implied viewer of all these pictures is a peeping
Iirrn with the right to peep, to linger over details, to enjoy and interpret and
make judgements about it. He or she is a person of great power in relation
t0 th$t which he or she views.
ln thc depictions of nude adults Berger talks about, the implied viewer is
lomcone quite different from the person being viewed: a male rather than a
Fnulc, probably a clothed male rather than a naked one (such clothed males
lometimes even appear in famous painting of naked women, looking at the
ltomon who look out of the painting at us as we view it), and specifically a
Fale with the right to view. As Berger suggests, then, the person in the
glcturc is defined in a power relationship with the viewer: men have the right
b hxlk, the power to hold what they see in their gaze; women are primarily
$at which men have the right to look at, a possession, something whose
plmary dutyis to look good andto be seen. Thenude andits implied viewer
&on sum up a power dynamic that defines what was the taditional relationship
gf men and women in the European civilisation that produced such paintings.
tldecd, a sizeable feminist discourse based in the psychoanalytical theories
k
the tmplies view*r
#rc bookr play their part in establishing what Lacan calls "an alienating
€6tlty" (p,4) built on what is only an "illusion of autonomy" (p.6). We are
Cnty what the plcturcs have encouraged us to believe ourselves to be -
d lnsvitnbly ronte how incomplete and illusory that is. We are free and
ru* fr€€,lutanomoug and consffained, isolated and enmeshed.
Bgt €f s€urrg, that can happen only for those whose subjectivity has been
mtruoted ru tho books invite. A child inexperienced in the language of
pFtUre mllht, for instance, look at a serious representational picture of
th3 hlllry eet snd laugh, or at a cartoon picture and cry-or even look at
f Fklul€ pf r chlld and not identify with it. Indeed, inexperienced viewers
afien hrve erg{rtly this sort of unintended response-one that an illustrator
*fut *odretl hrrd to convey specific information wouldprobably view as
in*+urlF, Meanwhile, children with the knowledge and experience to
ylct Ht lrnpllod might consciously or unconsciously refuse to do so, might
asllvely pertlcipate in making a different meaning that implies a different
renre nf thoir own subjectivity. These possibilities raise an important
quFrllon about the argument I have made here. How do young,
lFrperlencod viewers look at pictures? Are they in fact the viewers the
lrlslurcr ln picturc books imply?
I helleve oither that they are, or that they are in the process oflearning to
l€estte nr. Thcorists like Claude Levi-Strauss teach us that all artifacts of
a r:ullilre mnnifest and replicate their basic structures - that each of the
erilfectr contain a little or has some contrapuntal but still supportive
elrllorrrhlp to the central meanings and values of the cultured. As artifacts
tf $uf own oulture, picture books require and help to construct readers and
tlewerr who will take their place in that culture. That place may appear to
lc oplxultional to its central concerns, but if it's possible to take it publicly,
antl reurmmended as a desirable position to take by those ensconced
r:entrslly or marginally within the culture, then the apparent opposition is
lrntrullo tum out to bejustanotherwayof supporting thosecentral concerns.
Nn ullrr"r nubjcctivity is possible for the sane members of such a culture
httt rrxrrc version of the form of subjectivity picture books help to construct.
lf lltst'n true - and I find it hard to understand how it could not be true -
lherr llre sort of active participator in meaning-making postulated by Fiske
wotrkl huve to turn out to be less free from the constraints of our culture
tltntt rrright first appear. According to Fiske, his approach,
Notes
tL HT:1e"":r"::rlflll"^*:^:,^:"_:.{.S:"u*ion.tn.words About
*",:T:"*:::
pictures,(re8s, p.e_r0),
lx
are discussedmore ::f::_::poo'" ".iti.i,., -"r,ar,g,r,"
fully by Wolfgang Iser.
See'forinstance,mydiscussionofthesematters
".fr;;":il;;;:;;#;
rnwordsaboutpictures,(r9gg,p.10-16).
lv For more about construction of subjectivity,
,* .f rlro" ures of chdren,s Literature:,
( leeo p,136-139),
t Whllo Flnke's ideas relate to texts ofpopular culture such as television and advertising,
lhey repreeent a view of the freedom ofreader/viewers frequently found in discussions of
ehlldron'r literature, and frequently used to downplay the significance ofimplied refers
tnd vl€wcrs. It's for this reason that I refer to it here.
tl Ldvl-$truuss speaks, for instance, of "the unconscious structures underlying each
Utrtltutlon and each custom" of a culture (1967, p.2l).
lelerences