Pheno Critique5
Pheno Critique5
Pheno Critique5
Introduction
Although the credit goes to Husserl for the initiation of the movement of
phenomenological psychology, a very few psychologists accept his views without much
modification. It is due to the influence of existential phenomenologists: Sartre and
1
Ernesto Spinelli, The Interpreted World: An Introduction to Phenomenological Psychology, (2nd Edition),
Los Angeles: Sage Publication ltd, 2005, pp.203-204.
141
Merleau-Ponty.2 Sartre and Merleau-Ponty have contributed to phenomenological
psychology in their own way. Though they belong to existential phenomenology, their
approach to psychology differs. They both agree that human behaviour must be
intentional and hold the same view that human experience manifests a meaningful
structure as any phenomenologists. Yet their understanding of human being differs. So
ultimately there is a difference in their approach to psychology becomes inevitable.3
2
Joseph J. Kockelmans, Edmund Husserl’s Phenomenological Psychology: A Historico-Critical Study,
Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1967, pp.314-315.
3
Ibid., p.331.
4
Monika M. Langer, Merleau-Ponty’s Phenomenology of Perception: A Guide and Commentary, London:
Macmillan Press, 1989, pp.xiv-xv.
142
emphasize the central importance of pondering on the meaning of our being-in-the-world.
Existential philosophers’ central concern is to prompt humans not to live thoughtlessly
but rather, to have a keen awareness of their freedom and responsibility in the shaping of
a situation in which they are involved. Both, Sartre and Merleau-Ponty criticized the
rationalistic abstract thinking which evades the implications of the concrete situation.
They also warned that this attitude would lead to disaster.5
Existentialism denies the priority of objective truth. The main concern is what one
does and how one lives within the given world. This is a response to Aristotelian
metaphysics and medieval Scholastic philosophy which believed in a human nature and
5
Ibid., pp.viii-x.
6
Eric Matthews, The Philosophy of Merleau-Ponty, Buckinghamshire: Acumen Publishing Limited, 2002,
p.21.
143
God. As existentialists, Sartre and Merleau-Ponty analyze the nature of human beings.
They express different views on human nature. According to Sartre, there is nothing like
human nature. As human beings encounter the world, he or she makes of himself or
herself. According to Sartre, there is no pre-determined human nature. For Sartre,
‘existence precedes essence’. In other words, first we exist, then we form our own nature
through the many decisions we make throughout our life. There is no universal nature
like being a rational animal for humans; rather, we create our nature through choice. In
similar fashion, Merleau-Ponty also rejects the predetermined human nature as such.
According to Merleau-Ponty, there is no inner man, human being is in the world, and
only in the world individual knows oneself. Human being is not the outcome of numerous
causal agencies which determine human bodily or psychical make up.7 He makes it clear
by stating:
According to his theories, we are only able to know ourselves based upon the
input of others, all our actions, thoughts, and statements define us and have historical
consequences. Thus human nature never ceases to change.9
Both Sartre and Merleau-Ponty are concerned about the meaning of human
existence that has been realized through freedom. However, they differ in
conceptualization of freedom. Merleau-Ponty conceives human being as being-in-the-
world which implies that there is no absolute freedom. For Sartre, there is absolute
freedom. According to Merleau-Ponty, Sartre conception of consciousness and its
relation to world, and his conception of freedom are unhistorical. For Sartre
consciousness was a pure ‘negation’. Freedom was power to negate the situation in which
one found oneself. Although Sartre holds that freedom is always ‘in a situation’, his
7
Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, Colin Smith (trans.), London: Routledge, 2002, pp. ix-xii.
8
Ibid., p.101.
9
Ibid., p.xxii.
144
doctrine of consciousness and choice effectively denies the importance of history of the
time and place in which one has to make one’s choices. 10 For Sartre, freedom means
radical indeterminism and pure spontaneity whereas for Merleau-Ponty, freedom is
conditioned and not absolute. It is conditioned by a pre-conscious engagement with the
world and by one’s personal history.11 Therefore, in contrast to Sartre’s contention ‘we
are condemned to freedom’, Merleau-Ponty stated that ‘we are condemned to meaning’.12
10
Op. cit., The Philosophy of Merleau-Ponty, p.14.
11
A. Phillips Griffiths, Contemporary French Philosophy, New York: Cambridge University Press, 1987,
p.124.
12
Op. cit., Phenomenology of Perception, p.xxii.
13
Op. cit., Contemporary French Philosophy, pp.127-128.
145
As phenomenologists, Sartre, Merleau-Ponty emphasizes on lived experience in
understanding human behaviour. It is obvious that one’s own intentionality plays
important role in lived experience. Like Sartre, Merleau-Ponty also holds that the ‘lived’
activity exceeds the ‘representative consciousness’ that is to say, there is a process of
thought and activity. This activity is prior to and wider than thought.14 The lived activity
is wider than any datum or ‘what’ is known or perceived. Hence it is also wider and prior
to any inward datum of feeling or perception. From Husserl through Heidegger and
Sartre, the point has been made that phenomenology does not consider experiences as
inward subjective data. They can be viewed as inward subjective data only by artificial
effort. The world is not a spectacle of data. In other words, behavior is not “something
spread out in front of me.”15 According to Merleau-Ponty, the felt living activity is
always ‘in the world’ and the feelings are being affected in it. Merleau-Ponty
sarcastically remarked:
14
Maurice Merleau-Ponty, The Structure of Behaviour, Alden T. Fisher (trans.), Boston: Beacon Press,
1963, p.211.
15
Ibid., p.126.
16
Ibid., p.127.
17
Ibid., pp.128-130.
146
phenomenological stand point. Sartre rejects Freud’s theory as mechanistic and
speculative rather than phenomenological in nature. However, Merleau-Ponty approaches
Freud’s theory of psychoanalysis sympathetically rather than dismissing it totally.
Merleau-Ponty believes that the proper and deeper understanding of psychoanalysis will
lead to a meaningful convergence between phenomenology and psychoanalysis. 18
18
Op. cit., Edmund Husserl’s Phenomenological Psychology: A Historico-Critical Study, pp.332-335.
19
Op. cit., The Structure of Behaviour, p.xix.
20
Op. cit., Contemporary French Philosophy, p.124.
147
situations where the distinction between man and thing is fuzzed. The example of the
blind man and his white cane shows that this device, for the blind man a technology for
orientation in the world, becomes an extension of his own body. It becomes a part of his
bodily experience, part of his abilities, and his way of mobility. In other words, the blind
man and the cane becomes a gestalt; he extends himself in the cane and the cane becomes
an extension of him. Merleau-Ponty criticizes Sartre for not only upholding the Cartesian
distinction and making it more complicated. According to Merleau-Ponty, Descartes’ two
substances at least had the thing in common that they were both substances whereas
Sartre’s model, on the other hand, makes consciousness into a complete nothingness.21
For Sartre, the body is one’s facticity that binds individual to the world as a concrete,
contingent being. But individual never feel the body as a constraint of one’s freedom,
apart from exceptional situations which reminds individual of one’s facticity. In other
words, when an individual is exhausted or ill but these are situations that reveal to
individual one’s usual sense of transcendence and nihilation of the body. The ‘being-for-
itself’ is thus both consciousness and body, and the problem of the body must be viewed
in a dialectic of utility and facticity. For, Merleau-Ponty thought the whole dialectic of
‘being-in-itself’ and ‘being-for-itself’ was too exaggerated. For Merleau-Ponty,
perception remained a central theme throughout his authorship, as a mediation between
consciousness and things, subject and object.22
Gestalt theory becomes important for Sartre through the principle that it is the
direction of our consciousness that determine what will be figure and what will be
ground; the things we choose are thus the things we have chosen to be our figures, our
tastes, manners, our commodities are all determinations that manifest our particular
choice of the world, negating the other possible as background for the particular this.
How we perceive the world, what we choose, is dependent on what our project is. For
Sartre, it is based on ontological choice. In other words, he calls it as fundamental
project. The Gestalt principle is in this way the key to understand the concrete freedom of
the other or oneself. Merleau-Ponty did not use the category of a fundamental project,
and he did not assign such a grand importance to the category of negativity and
21
Op. cit., The Structure of Behaviour, p.xx.
22
Jean-Paul Sartre, ‘‘Merleau-Ponty,’’ Situations IV, Gallimard, Paris 1964, p.195.
148
nothingness. Therefore, he did not hold that we always negate and choose when we
perceive. His task was more to understand the puzzle it is that the world as perceived is
meaningful. For Merleau-Ponty, we are not condemned to freedom but we condemned to
meaning and to always express something. For Merleau-Ponty, we are not thrown out in a
perpetual state of anxiety rather we are in the midst of a world of meaningful wholes. We
are not free to perceive, choose or interpret the world as we like.
23
Ibid., pp.215-217.
149
through phenomenological investigation. Phenomenological psychology seeks neither to
dismiss nor to diminish the contributions of other contemporary psychological systems.
But it attempts to reconsider and reassess their assumptions wherever possible. It is also
to point out their relative strengths and weaknesses and to incorporate significant findings
obtained from phenomenological enquiry.24 The primary criticism of phenomenological
psychology on other schools of psychology is that the exclusion of conscious experience
from their studies. Phenomenologists argue that this lacuna has harmed psychology and
restricted its practical applications.25 Rollo May has rightly pointed out the need for
phenomenological method in psychology. He said:
24
Op. cit., The Interpreted World: An Introduction to Phenomenological Psychology, p.186.
25
Ibid., p.187.
26
Rollo May, Existential Psychology, 2nd edition, New York: Random House, 1969, p.27.
27
Op. cit., The Interpreted World: An Introduction to Phenomenological Psychology, p.125-126.
150
consciousness. Phenomenology simplifies and demystifies the underlying ideas
associated with psychoanalytic notions of the unconscious.28
In general, both approaches can be seen to consider the limits and potentials of
human inter-relation with assumption that people are active interpreters of their
environment. Freudian psychoanalysis would point to a number of important differences
and divergences between the two approaches. Freudian psychoanalytic theories
emphasize the role of the unconscious, of our earliest infantile experiences, of the
instinctual forces of eros and thanatos, and of the psychic conflict between id-ego-
superego as prime instigators and determinants of conscious thought and behaviour.
Equally, Freudian psychoanalysts argue that unresolved sexual and aggressive wishes are
basis for human motivation. 29
28
Ibid., pp.189-190.
29
Ibid., pp.187-188.
151
of linear causality, psychoanalysis would free itself from mechanistic orientation without
doing serious damage to its central emphases.30
30
Ibid., pp.188-189.
31
Herbert Spiegelberg, Phenomenology in Psychology and Psychiatry: A Historical Introduction,
Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1972, pp.137-140
152
Paul Federn was of Freud’s intimate circle, but he went beyond Freud in applying
psychoanalysis not only in neurotics but also to treating psychotics. He used to define
psychoanalysis in terms of descriptive phenomenological and metapsychological. He
understood phenomenological to be subjectively descriptive in terms of feeling, knowing,
and apprehending. His phenomenological definition of ego is felt and known by the
individual as a lasting or recurring continuity of the body and mental life in respect of
time, space, and causality and is felt and apprehended by him as a unity.32
32
Ibid., p.133.
33
Ibid., p.141.
34
Ibid., p.145.
153
Behaviourism arose in direct reaction to psychological schools that emphasized the
centrality of conscious experience. Behaviourism rejects the possibility that
consciousness could be explained scientifically. Behaviourism has rejected the role of
consciousness in human behaviour. Perhaps the most basic assumption of behaviourism
is that human beings are by and large passive reactors to natural and culturally derived
environmental stimuli which mould and shape our behaviour through conditioning and
reinforcement. Despite different attitude towards human behaviour, there are some
similarities exists between these two contrasting approaches. Both phenomenological
psychology and behaviourism emphasize the importance of environmental stimuli as
catalysts to action. Of course, there is disagreement because behaviourism claims that
human beings are primarily passive reactors to directly experienced stimuli. On the other
hand, phenomenological psychology argues that human beings are active interpreters of
the stimuli in that our response to them is intentionally determined through both innate
invariants and individual experience.35
The major source of dispute between the two approaches lies, of course, in
behaviourism’s dismissal of consciousness. Behaviourists claim that any attempted
investigation of inferred non-directly observable agencies such as consciousness
35
Ibid., pp.194-195.
36
Ibid., pp.195-196.
154
threatens its objective, experimental stance. In spite of their dismissal of subjective
experience, behaviourists depend on some degree of accurate correspondence between
private experience and public report in order to provide validity and significance for their
experimental data. Furthermore, as Koestenbaum has pointed out, all public statements
begin as first-hand subjective experience; as such:
In other words, rather than rely upon direct verification, behaviourists actually depend
upon indirect constructs or assumptions.
The critics of behaviourism have pointed out that behaviourism gives importance
to quantitative research than qualitative research. In a sense, having denied the
importance of subjective date, their findings appear limited, alien, even ‘soul-less’. The
phenomenological method helps to expose experiments’ implicit, even hidden,
assumptions, thereby allowing them to arrive at more adequate and descriptively accurate
analyses and conclusions. The major differences between behaviourism and
phenomenological psychology remain irreconcilable; there still exists much scope for
constructive dialogue.38
155
is determined by the phenomenal field of the behaving organism.40 Phenomenology
therefore consists primarily in the exploration of the phenomenal field of the individual,
including his phenomenal self. He was for phenomenology as the necessary complement
for behaviourism.41
40
Donald Syngg, The Phenomenological Problem, Alfred E. Kuenzli (ed.), New York: Harper, 1959, p.12.
41
Op. cit., Phenomenology in Psychology and Psychiatry: A Historical Introduction, pp.146-148.
42
Ibid., p.197.
43
J. Medcof and J. Roth, Approaches to Psychology, Milton Keynes: Open University Press, 1984, p. 182.
44
F. Strasser and A. Strasser, Existential Time-Limited Therapy: The Wheel of Existence, Chichester: John
Wiley & Sons, 1997, p.132.
156
current emotion. This view demonstrates striking parallels with conclusions derived from
phenomenological investigation.45
Perhaps most notably, Acceptance and Commitment Therapy has emerged as one
of the most significant of recent attempts to reconfigure cognitive-behavioural therapy.
Acceptance and Commitment Therapy’s major deviation from more classical cognitive-
behavioural therapy approaches lies in its explicit acknowledgement that the endeavour
to change or remove ‘misinterpreted’ thoughts that have arisen in the person’s attempt to
cope may well be counterproductive and even dangerous. Rather, Acceptance and
Commitment Therapy concentrates on the clarifying and opening up of the meanings
expressed within the ‘misinterpretation’. This undertaking on the part of the Acceptance
and Commitment Therapy practitioner to ‘stay with’ the client’s currently experienced
meaning brings to the foreground a much more focused inter-relational perspective. This
stance suggests a valid ‘meeting point’ for phenomenological and Acceptance and
Commitment Therapy theorists and practitioners. At the same time, it does remain the
case that Acceptance and Commitment Therapy continues to employ explicitly directive
interventions that, from a phenomenological perspective, run counter to its stated
enterprise. Nonetheless, as with the other radical constructivist reworkings of cognitive-
behavioural therapy, there exists solid ground for worthwhile dialogue with
phenomenological psychology.46
45
Op. cit., The Interpreted World: An Introduction to Phenomenological Psychology, p.198.
46
Ibid., pp.199-200.
157
d. Phenomenological Psychology and Gestalt Psychology
Phenomenological influence was found in Gestalt psychology. The aim of Gestalt and
phenomenology was to free modern man to fresh reality. Both streams of thought
developed simultaneously. Though Max Wertheimer, Kurt Koffka and Wolfgang Kohler
were not interested in philosophy but when they were to face the challenges of
behaviourism, then they sought the help of philosophy especially phenomenology.
Phenomenology was a methodological support to Gestalt psychology. Kurt Koffka has
identified the methods of Gestalt with that of phenomenology in his work Principles of
Gestalt Psychology.47 He viewed phenomenology as naïve and full of description of
direct experience as possible. He distinguished direct experience and introspection.48
Fritz Heider was a Gestalt psychologist. His work The Psychology of Interpersonal
Relations, provides the conceptual framework and the psychological processes that
influence human social perception. In his study of social perception, he makes use of
phenomenological method to understand the perceptual phenomena. His objective was to
describe phenomena faithfully and allow them to guide the choice of problems and
procedures.49 Aron Gurwitsch has played an important role in bring about Gestalt
psychology to have phenomenology as its philosophical ally. Aron Gurwitsch explained
the relationship between phenomenology and Gestalt thoughts. He also showed how
Gestalt can contribute to the phenomenology of perception.50 David Katz was a German-
Swedish psychologist. In his work Gestalt Psychology, he argues that comprehension of
contemporary psychology necessitates an understanding of the phenomenological
method.51 He used phenomenological method in his animal psychology because the
method was giving the greatest possible freedom. According to him, phenomenological
method helps to describe the animal behaviour meaningfully and provides the unbiased
description of phenomena. His phenomenological method was to simply describe
phenomena as they appear without any distortion. He argues that the ‘world’ is with
47
Kurt Koffka, Principles of Gestalt Psychology, London: Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd, 1955.
48
Ibid., pp.74-75.
49
Fritz Heider, The Psychology of Interpersonal Relations, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates,
1958, pp.20-58.
50
Aron Gurwitsch, Studies in Phenomenology and Psychology, Evanston: Northwestern University Press,
1979, p.175.
51
David Katz, Gestalt Psychology, Robert Tyson (trans.), New York: Ronald Press, 1950, p.18.
158
abundance of phenomena but pre-phenomenological psychology overlooked. He was
trying to have presuppositionless phenomenological analysis of phenomena.52
Kurt Lewin was one of the modern pioneers of social, organizational and applied
psychology. He was even moving beyond phenomenology because he was interested in a
psychology of action, of will and of dynamics of human personality. He refers to works
54
of Sheler, Sartre, and Merleau-Ponty in his understanding of human personality. Karl
Duncker was another psychologist. His treatment of phenomenological pleasure and
phenomenology of the object of consciousness was significant.55
159
world as a key to understanding the subjective experiences of his patients. He holds that
the patients with the mental diseases undergo modifications of the fundamental structure
and of the structural links of being-in-the-world. In other words, the mental illness
involves one’s perception of the world which includes one’s altered understanding of the
lived experience of time, space, body sense and social relationships.56
Carl Rogers’ interest in phenomenology was late and slow in developing. His
primary interest in psychology was clinical therapy. In the beginning, he was neither
interested in phenomenology nor had any contact with those movements. His twelve
years of experience with children in Rochester, New York made him to realize the
defects in narrow psychoanalysis and coercive approach and felt the importance of
client’s perspective. In his book Client-Centered Therapy, he refers to phenomenology as
source for his new interpretation of human behaviour. According to him, the therapeutic
process is to understand the way the client perceives the objects in his or her phenomenal
field, his or her experiences, his or her feelings, his or her self, other persons, his or her
environment which undergoes change in the direction of increased differentiation.
According to Rogers, phenomenology is a main ingredient for the ‘third force’ in
psychology. The other two are behaviourism and psychoanalysis.57
Apart from its influence in the field of psychology, phenomenological psychology has
been criticized by modern psychologists on following issues; such as, phenomenological
psychology leads back to subjectivism, back to introspectionism, lacks objective method
and lacks scientific verifiability. The most vociferous opponents of phenomenological
psychology have tended to represent it as an anachronistic reversion to outdated
doctrines, incompatible with the scientific character of psychology and harmful to its
progress.58 Phenomenological psychologists defended their position against these
criticisms and responded to them in their own way.
56
Ibid., p.132.
57
Ibid., pp.148-150.
58
Op. cit., The Interpreted World: An Introduction to Phenomenological Psychology, p.207.
160
Behaviourists have argued that both the methodology and the conceptual basis of
phenomenology are little use to any modern day psychologist whose aim is to manipulate
and predict behaviour from standpoint focusing on generalizable rules which emphasize
similarities in behaviour or mental processing. Such critics have also questioned the
significance and effectiveness of phenomenological theory and its application and
reliability. They also questioned the over dependence on verbal descriptions, ambiguity
of phenomenological concepts and esoteric language of phenomenologists.59
Phenomenological psychologists defended their position and argued that the long neglect
of the issue of human inter-relatedness in academic psychology has not only severely put
into question the validity and reliability of psychology’s own accepted views and
positions. In its neglect of the issue of inter-relational experience, psychology has not
only lost its soul in a metaphorical sense, it has lost its original purpose and has focused
instead on the construction, analysis and interpretation of ever more ornate and esoteric
experimental studies. According to phenomenologists, the implication of psychology is to
understand the person. Therefore the starting point must be the exploration of human
experience. Phenomenologists do not wholly dismiss the findings and methods of other
approaches but they more accurately argue that the progress of psychology requires a
more fundamental investigation of the attitudes and assumptions that underlies
psychological explorations.60
59
Henryk Misiak, Virginia Staudt Sexton, Phenomenological, Existential, and Humanistic Psychologies: A
Historical Survey, New York: Grune & Stratton, 1973, pp.54-55.
60
Op. cit., The Interpreted World: An Introduction to Phenomenological Psychology, pp.207-208.
61
T.W. Wann (ed.), Behaviourism and Phenomenology: Contrasting Bases for Modern Psychology,
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1964, p.174.
161
subjective experiences to the simplest mental elements, that is sensations, feelings and
images. They also attempted to examine certain attributes of their experiences, such as
their quality, intensity and duration. In contrast, there is assumption concerning the
composition of impressions is permitted in phenomenological studies. An introspectionist
report excludes the objects and meanings. The phenomenological psychologist is
interested in the meaning that stimuli or situation have for the observer whereas
introspectioanism primarily focused on their sensory experiences that are analyzed
impressions of various stimuli and provided reports. Though phenomenology and
introspectionalism concern with issues of consciousness, it is necessary to understand that
they not only differ in methodology but they also differ in scope and focus of
investigation.62
62
Op. cit., The Interpreted World: An Introduction to Phenomenological Psychology, pp.208-209.
63
Hubert L. Dreyfus, Husserl Intentionality and Cognitive Science, London: MIT Press, 1982, p.122.
162
because such are considered to be inherently more significant or more worthy of inquiry,
but because the other systems of psychology either minimize or deny these variables in
their studies. In addition, existential phenomenology takes the view that it is precisely via
the study of particular way of being that the investigator is directed to the universal or
ontological, structural being.64
64
Op. cit., The Interpreted World: An Introduction to Phenomenological Psychology, pp.210-212.
65
S.D. Churchill and F.J. Wertz, “An Introduction to Phenomenological Research in Psychology,” The
handbook of Humanistic Psychology: Leading Edges in Theory, Research and Practice, London: Sage
Publication, 2001, p. 256.
66
Op. cit., The Interpreted World: An Introduction to Phenomenological Psychology, p.212.
163
in a ‘direct’ way. Instead, one operationalizes
variables so as to turn them into observable facts.
Phenomenology rejects the idea that there exist
objective facts… The ‘objectively’ given fact is
always present in relation to … a constituting and
meaning-imbuing subject.67
While the notions of reliability and validity, which remain central elements of
natural science research methodology, are not employed by existential phenomenology,
the approach relies upon the verifiability of the researcher’s conclusion in so far as
verifiability refers to whether another researcher can assume the perspective of the present
investigator, review the original protocol data and see that the proposed insights
meaningfully illuminate the situations under study.68
67
Gunmar Karlsson, Psychological Qualitative Research from Phenomenological Perspective, Stockholm:
Almqvist and Wiksell International, 1993, p.16.
68
Op. cit., “An Introduction to Phenomenological Research in Psychology,” p. 259.
69
Op. cit., The Interpreted World: An Introduction to Phenomenological Psychology, pp.200-201.
164