From Agamben To Zizek - Jon Simons
From Agamben To Zizek - Jon Simons
From Agamben To Zizek - Jon Simons
www.euppublishing.com
A CIP record for this book is available from the British Library
Acknowledgements vii
Notes on Contributors viii
Introduction 1
Jon Simons
vi
I would like to thank the members of the Critical Theory team at the
University of Nottingham, as well as the contributors to the previ-
ous volumes in this series, From Kant to Lévi-Strauss: The Background
to Contemporary Critical Theory (Edinburgh University Press, 2002)
and Contemporary Critical Theorists: From Lacan to Said (Edinburgh
University Press, 2004) for their sage advice about which theorists
to include in this volume. I take responsibility, of course, for all the
shortcomings of the final selection. I would also like to thank the
contributors to this volume for the effort and care that they put into
writing their chapters and for their comments on my introduction.
Peter Andrews has prepared an excellent index for this volume, as he
did for the previous volumes. Jackie Jones of Edinburgh University
Press has been a wonderfully supportive editor; her insight and
encouragement turned one book proposal into a series of three
volumes. James Dale (for the first two volumes) and Eliza Wright
(for this volume) served as accomplished desk editors for the series.
I am grateful to the College of Arts and Sciences at Indiana
University, Bloomington, for a generous summer fellowship that
gave me time to complete most of the editing of this volume.
I am also indebted to all those who, by enraging me, remind
me on a daily basis of the absolute need to think critically about
the world. The list is too long to include here, but a special
mention must go to all the denizens of the American ‘conservative
echo-chamber’.
Jon Simons
February 2010
vii
viii
ix
semiotic sign, the index, for an era when cultural themes became
dramatically disproportionate to the scale of daily life. For the
last several years, Robinson has been actively engaged with Alain
Badiou’s philosophy, organising several multi-day conferences on
his work, one attended by Professor Badiou.
xi
xii
10
11
Notes
1. Jon Simons (ed.), Contemporary Critical Theorists: From Lacan to Said
(Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2004).
2. Jon Simons (ed.), From Kant to Lévi-Strauss: The Background to
Contemporary Critical Theory (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press,
2002).
3. Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1979), p. 263.
4. Bruno Latour, ‘Why Has Critique Run out of Steam? From Matters of
Fact to Matters of Concern’, Critical Inquiry, 30, 2004, pp. 225–48.
5. Terry Eagleton, After Theory (New York: Basic Books, 2003), p. 1.
6. Paul Bové, In the Wake of Theory (Hanover: Wesleyan University Press,
1992), p. xii.
7. Latour, ‘Why Has Critique Run out of Steam?’.
8. Ernesto Laclau, ‘Preface’, in Martin McQuillan, Graeme Macdonald,
Robin Purves and Stephen Thomson (eds), Post-Theory: New Directions
in Criticism (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1999), p. vii.
9. Latour, ‘Why Has Critique Run out of Steam?’, pp. 231, 227.
10. Ian Hunter, ‘The History of Theory’, Critical Inquiry, 33, 2006, pp.
78–112 (80).
11. Eagleton, After Theory, p. 1.
12. Ibid. p. 223.
12
13
14
Coming to Language
In his early books, Agamben probes the meaning of language and
its place in the history of metaphysics, as a way of understanding
being. The starting point is the absolute role of negativity in cre-
ating the human. Hegel systematically conceived of humanity in
relation to negativity, in the early nineteenth century. Negativity
in this sense is not ‘bad’, but the idea of being defined by what you
are not (that is, I am me because I understand I am not you, or
anyone else).4 This is the only means through which humans come
to self-perception. The profound implication of this, as teased out
by twentieth-century phenomenology and expanded on by Derrida,
notably, is that the self is not present to itself, but only exists as a
by-product of something else (or of everything else). Agamben
reworks this idea of ‘negativity’ to render it as an internal part of
the things we understand to be present (beings, objects, the world),
which becomes internal in and as language.
According to Agamben, the history of metaphysics (he does not
specify Western, but that seems to be his sole reference) under-
stands language as the means of attaining or approaching the tran-
scendental. This transcendental (as seen notably in Kant, Hegel,
Husserl and Heidegger) is that which is beyond our mundane
existence and knowledge, and yet is the profound truth of human-
ity. Agamben claims in Infancy and History that the transcendental
is located not beyond, but in, language. To back up this point, he
returns to the question of speech as a human phenomenon. The
history of philosophy supposes animals to be without speech and
humans the speaking animal. Not so, writes Agamben, as animals
are in language, whilst humans come to it gradually, acquiring it as
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
way as mass slaughter. In general, human life has not been throught
of as sacred, but medical and legal developments have brought
about such a thought. Agamben’s point is that to think life as sacred
means treating the people involved as only life – as life that must be
saved, rather than in their political/judicial contexts. Even ‘human-
itarian organizations . . . can only grasp human life in the figure of
bare or sacred life, and therefore, despite themselves, maintain a
secret solidarity with the very powers they ought to fight’.23
For Agamben, all of modern life tends toward biopolitics and
the reduction to ‘bare life’ – whether through mass killings, rights
and ‘saving’ people, or medical technology – ‘all life becomes
sacred and all politics becomes the exception’.24 The implication
is that, increasingly, humans become totally subject to rules and
regulations, subject to exclusion, and less and less subject as subjects
within the realm of law. It is not that law is done away with, rather it
becomes the empty form it came from: Law identifying itself as Law,
identifying people as bare life, as material for Law.
While this ‘pure’ state of Law is neither necessarily good nor
bad, the place where it is heightened is the concentration camp,
where exception becomes the rule, where all become bare life.
Agamben turns to this topic in depth in his powerful and best-
known work, Remnants of Auschwitz.25 His purpose is to rethink
the Nazi concentration camps in a way that refuses the mysticism
of the ‘unsayable’ he sees at work in other theoretical writings:
‘[W]hy unsayable? Why confer on extermination the prestige of
the mystical?’26 As is often the case, Agamben does not do justice
to the position he criticises, adopting a position much like one he
earlier misread.27 The book is also surprisingly insubstantial unless
read as part of his homo sacer theory, but it does adopt a convincing
position from which to account for ‘unsayability’ as part of a wider
situation occurring in the shape of the concentration camp. As in
earlier works, humanity’s relation to language as a limit condition is
in play, as he focuses on the figure of the Muselmann (muslim) – the
prisoner who gives up and seems to be living a minimal animal exist-
ence, bereft of humanity. The Muselmann is the true witness of the
camp, truer in one way than those who survive with their human-
ity intact. These two categories interact in Agamben’s argument.
The Muselmann leaves the world of language and sociality behind,
becoming a risk to fellow prisoners, shunned by all. They are effec-
tively dead, barely human. It is the ‘effectively’ and the ‘barely’ that
count here – because they are still some sort of human, ‘mark[ing]
22
23
24
25
Notes
1. Agamben uses Foucault’s notion of ‘biopolitics’ throughout much
of his work, and returns explicitly to Foucault in Signatura rerum,
where he works through the structure of Foucault’s The Archaeology of
Knowledge (New York: Pantheon, 1972), in order to reflect on the time
in which knowledge develops.
2. See Agamben, The Man without Content.
3. Agamben, Remnants of Auschwitz, pp. 28–31.
4. See, in particular Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1977), especially his early formulation of ‘negativ-
ity’ in the ‘master/slave dialectic’ (pp. 105–19). See also Alexandre
Kojève’s Introduction to the Reading of Hegel (New York: Basic Books,
1969).
5. Agamben, Language and Death, p. 84.
6. Agamben, Potentialities, p. 45.
7. Agamben, Language and Death, p. 45.
8. Ibid. p. 26.
26
9. Ibid. p. 35.
10. Ibid. p. 34.
11. Ibid. p. 96.
12. Agamben, The Open, p. 10.
13. Ibid. p. 22.
14. Ibid. p. 37.
15. Ibid. p. 58.
16. Ibid. p. 59.
17. Michel Foucault, History of Sexuality, vol. 1, trans. Robert Hurley
(Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1979).
18. Agamben, Homo Sacer, p. 8.
19. Ibid. p. 89.
20. Ibid. p. 82.
21. Ibid. pp. 82–3.
22. For more on this, see Paul Hegarty, ‘Supposing the Impossibility of
Silence, and of Sound, of Voice: Bataille, Agamben and the Holocaust’,
in Andrew Norris (ed.), Politics, Metaphysics and Death, pp. 222–47.
23. Agamben, Homo Sacer, p. 133.
24. Ibid. p. 148.
25. This will come to be known as Homo Sacer III, following the publication
in 2003 of State of Exception (Homo Sacer II.1).
26. Agamben, Remnants of Auschwitz, p. 32.
27. He is certainly very close to the position Jean-François Lyotard
presents in The Differend: Phrases in Dispute (Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota, 1988).
28. Agamben, Remnants of Auschwitz, p. 47.
29. Ibid. p. 38.
30. Ibid. p. 120.
31. Ibid. p. 133.
32. Ibid. pp. 133–4.
33. Agamben, State of Exception, pp. 4–5.
34. Schmitt, Political Theology, p. 11.
35. Ibid. p. 5.
36. Ibid. p. 12.
37. Agamben, State of Exception, pp. 38–9, 51.
38. Ibid. p. 2.
39. Agamben, The Time That Remains, p. 67.
27
28
An Odd End
Alain Badiou is an unlikely heir to the tradition of French post-
Second World War philosophy and an even more unlikely heir –
despite his declared affinity to the radical events of Paris in May 1968
– to the post-structuralist movement that came into its own around
then with luminaries such as Deleuze, Foucault and Derrida.1 While
he engages those thinkers, he demonstrates a different set of loves
– of truth, universalism, the subject, fidelity and mathematics; and
holds a different set of antipathies – to postmodern celebration
of irony and consumption, multicultural identity politics and a
textual-hermeneutical grounding of existence. Even stylistically,
Badiou tends to be indifferent to cultivating the character of his
prose. He writes precisely and didactically, with an irreverent, even
pugnacious humour, and no pretense of modesty. As a philosopher,
his aspiration is to address everyone without exception, regardless
of ‘identity’. This aspiration is rooted in a commitment to what he
calls ‘communism in the generic sense’, in which ‘everyone is equal
to everyone else within the multiplicity and diversity of social func-
tions’.2 At the same time, his eccentric vocabulary of mathematics
and ontology can be intimidating in its straightforward applica-
tion to the familiar topics of politics and ethics. The philosophical
habitus, however, is just what Badiou’s simultaneously refined and
populist turn of thought succeeds in making strange. Key terms
from the philosophical encyclopedia with which Badiou might be
tagged include: ontology, the infinite and the void, and structure
29
and event. What matters, however, is how these topics, which reach
back to philosophy’s formal origins in Greek thought, become new
again in Badiou’s project.
Toward Plato
Since Nietzsche announced his reversal of Plato’s effort to grasp
being in the pure, non-relational way numbers exist, it seems that
philosophy has eagerly swerved onto the new course. After the past
century’s total wars, genocides and famines, it would seem that not
only philosophers have directed us away from Platonism, but the
events themselves, issuing from universal reason run amok, have
conspired to set us on a corrective course towards sensitivity regard-
ing diverse forms of being other than the mathematical. The col-
lapse of metanarratives, the implosion of Cold War fronts, the rise
of global ecologies, all seem to confirm the end of Plato’s regime of
mathematically revealed truth.
As close as Badiou is to that tradition that goes under the name
of reversing Plato in favour of the contingent, material, aesthetic
and historical, he embraces Plato as the very philosopher who put
truth and universality on the agenda. While Badiou’s philosophy
shares a post-enlightenment goal of situating itself among the
truths of non-philosophers, it maintains, uncharacteristically for its
era, that these truths should be grasped as truths, in their universal
and infinite import, and be made available indifferently to whomso-
ever might want to commit themselves to truth. Moreover, it is Plato
who insisted on the proximity of philosophy to politics. A ‘militant
philosophy’, such as Badiou’s, is one that situates itself within the
political conflicts of its time.3 Given all the cataclysms that have
issued from modernity – from its Eurocentrism, logicism, egoism,
and destructive pretence to universality – how, Badiou invites us
to think, does an oppositional political project assert itself in the
mode of truth? And who, he asks, is the subject that would bear the
truth? In asking such questions, Badiou sets about reclaiming some
old-fashioned ideas for a political left that has been exhausted by its
retreat into the noisy difference of the everyday.
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
So it is not the case, as it is for Hegel, that the true universalist hates
particularity – the universalist is indifferent to particularity in the
relevant situation. It is, rather, the false universalist, imagining truth
to have privileged prophets and caring too intently about individual
persons, communities and identities, who directs hostility against
everyone, against everyone precisely as generic nobodies outside
the community of the elect.
While the event forces an accounting, dictating what is relevant
to its break and what is not, it follows a generic rigor pertaining
strictly to what the void in its situation proposes. In this sense, decid-
ing what is an event and what a pseudo-event may be difficult, but
only by being forced to declare one’s decision is one called to live
in truth. Living in truth, being subject to the force of truth, means
being open to eventuality. Committing to the French Revolution
– like committing to atonal music, quantum mechanics or true
love – remains tolerant with respect to biographies and identities.
The force of the commitment comes via the void it opens wherever
people remain closed to its effects. The event thus appears – is
retrospectively discernible as having been an event – not as a fulfil-
ment of an implied destiny but as an open process of making its
multiplicity pertain, of working out what its post-evental situation
entails. That is, from pure multiplicity – infinite (since it has no
boundaries) and void (since it cannot be taken as one) – it becomes
an impure multiplicity, a multiplicity with elements and relations
transforming (but not destroying) the situation from which it arose.
What maintains this multiplicity in its truth, however, is that it is
never imagined as the one that henceforth plugs up the void. Its
infinity relates to the way it disqualifies without reserve a situation
that held no place for it. It does not relate to complete immanence
(divine memory) or ultimate transcendence (the timeless beyond)
– it is a secular infinity, a constituent of profane being.
Before turning to Badiou’s quintessential militant, Saint Paul,
a final consideration of set theory is helpful. As a branch of math-
ematics, it theorises number without imagining individual numbers
as qualities or intuitions ‘out there’ in the world. Breaking with
realist number theory – wherein numbers subsist as representable
entities – set theory eloquently serves Badiou’s project of under-
standing the world as based on blank ‘thatness’, a set of denotations
with no given properties or relations. ‘Thatness’ simply names a
void of meaning – all content is utterly subtracted. From that void,
however, set theory is able to group together multiplicities based
37
38
39
40
41
42
Conclusion
Embattled and ecstatic: this is the experience of reading Badiou’s
philosophy and antiphilosophy. The set-theoretical terminology,
which grounds Badiou’s thinking in the most generic and genera-
tive possibilities of ordering and multiplicity, is demanding. Despite
Badiou’s protestations that his mathematics is elementary, there
is no use denying the effort required to leap from mathematical
conceptions of what counts to philosophical discourses of Being.
At the same time, as the provocation of St Paul makes clear, Badiou
relishes in gestures that blithely – if sometimes brutally – reorganise
expectations about which distinctions a thinker – and activist –
needs to defend and which to let scatter like dust in the face of new
truths, truths that are not the property of philosophy but available
to all who carefully heed them.
Notes
1. Alain Badiou, ‘The Adventure of French Philosophy’, New Left Review,
35, 2005, pp. 67–77.
2. Alain Badiou, ‘“We Need a Popular Discipline”: Contemporary Politics
and the Crisis of the Negative’, interview by Filippo Del Lucchese and
Jason Smith, Critical Inquiry, 34, 2008, p. 648.
3. Ibid. pp. 645–59 (646).
4. Badiou, The Century, p. 32.
5. Badiou, Ethics, p. 25.
6. Badiou, Being and Event, p. 148.
7. Ibid. pp. 31–7.
8. In ‘“We Need a Popular Discipline”’, Badiou sees a politics based in
negating the state and seizing power as obsolete. Instead of a destruc-
tive politics, he proposes a subtractive one, where ‘subtractive’ refers
to opting out of the relations the state proffers for managing politics.
Badiou, ‘“We Need a Popular Discipline”’, pp. 652–3.
9. Badiou, Being and Event, p. 180.
10. Badiou discusses ‘the Schönberg-event’ in ‘A Musical Variant of the
Metaphysics of the Subject’, Parrhesia, 2, 2007, pp. 29–36. The example
of Haydn appears in Badiou, Ethics, p. 68.
11. Badiou, Ethics, pp. 58–89.
12. G. W. F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A. V. Miller (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1979), §§582–95.
13. Badiou, Ethics, p. 76.
14. Hallward, Badiou, p. 89.
15. Badiou, Ethics, p. 41.
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
of his analysis, however, is that this was a matter of all that was solid
melting. Industrialism normalised change or disintegration before
the emergence of the new order was possible. The motif here is
exactly the same as that later coined as ‘liquid modernity’ replacing
‘solid modernity’. Estrangement ruled. The least advantaged were
the pariahs, the ‘navvies’, the masterless men.
Having been there first, Edward Thompson pilloried Bauman
and his book in The Guardian on 28 December 1972. It was bad
enough that Bauman was a sociologist, but he also imagined he
knew more about socialism than Thompson did. Bauman never-
theless persisted. He returned to Thompson’s fields, in company
with the unwelcome figure of Michel Foucault, in his major reprise,
Memories of Class: The Prehistory and Afterlife of Class. Bauman was, in
a sense, writing the marxian instalment missing from Foucault’s
project, where there was Discipline, Power, Hospital, Clinic, Prison
– but no Factory.9 For Marx, for Capital, of course, the factory was
the characteristic institutional form and core of modernity. And
Bauman follows this, until the 1970s, when consumption replaces
work or production as the central activity of modernity, and the
mall replaces the factory as its institutional embodiment. The
factory is the Panopticon.
Here, again, the issue of representation is fundamental. For the
new industrial class, the proletariat, there is another, new intellec-
tual class, the helpers, from social workers to trades union leaders
and politicians – no Panopticon without Bentham, no reform
without its Fabians, no Russian Revolution without Bolsheviks. But
it was the rapid erosion of protective institutions which was a major
cause of discontent; and again, the obvious echo in Bauman’s work
is with the dismantling of the welfare state after the decline of the
golden age of capitalism after World War Two. Alongside Foucault’s
Discipline and Punish and Thompson’s Making of the English Working
Class, the third pillar of Bauman’s thinking is Barrington Moore’s
Injustice.10 Socialism and the labour movement, on this way of think-
ing, represent reaction rather than progress, resistance to change
rather than its enthusiastic pursuit. The results of industrialisation
were unmistakable. The dissipation of locally based paternalis-
tic institutions resulted in a massive production of paupers and
beggars, vagrants and vagabonds.
Call it modern capitalism, call it the Industrial Revolution, the
most powerful immediate effect of the great transformation was
demographic. Now there was the beginning of material abundance.
51
Together with surplus product and surplus value came surplus pop-
ulation. The historical novelty of the factory system, after its disas-
trous collapse in the Depression, was in its capacity to absorb labour.
This was the exceptional moment of postwar fordism, when produc-
ers had been taught to produce and now were able also to consume,
before they had to be taught that consumption, alone, was to be the
primary source of identity. The factory, in any case, was at least as
profoundly a cultural as an economic institution. Its purpose was to
make new men, and women, and to bind them into the new order,
not merely to generate profit or to extract surplus value.
Throughout the period of its consolidation into the twentieth
century, capitalist culture worked through the politics of inclusion
and, via inclusion, exploitation. Peasants became proletarians;
pariahs eventually became factory fodder. But there remained
problems of surplus population, of stigma, of others who did not
belong or whose belonging was temporary or contingent. The pro-
letarian was never quite unmarked in his universality; some were
more completely included or assimilated than others. Not all were
to be welcomed into the Panopticon, or into the Factory. There
were other institutions yet to be fully designed and constructed,
like those of the gas ovens, anticipated earlier in lightweight canvas
form as the camps of the nineteenth century. The bodies of others
had also been drilled through the slave trade and plantations, which
as Bauman observes may in turn have influenced the formation of
factory systems.
In the heartlands of the West, in the meantime, the proletariat
had garlanded its chains with flowers. They had been lead actors,
along with the bourgeoisie and the new class, in the construction of
corporatism, which represented the inclusive moment of postwar
capitalism. The outsiders now were those without hope, the postwar
lumpenproletariat. The ‘new victims’ of this social arrangement would
be those who truly missed out. For there was now, again, a discern-
able underclass in the cities of the West. And there were others.
They might be marginals within these systems, or they might consist
of the massed ranks of the dispossessed of the earth, the poor and
excluded of the Third World.
52
53
Liquidity
There remains an unavoidable tension in modernity. There are
always others who need help. But is it better to help or not to
help? Does the welfare state merely reproduce or even increase
patterns of dependence? We all depend on others, almost every
54
moment of our waking lives. To turn away is even worse. For there
will always be outsiders, strangers in our midst. Bauman returns to
these themes in his essays on ‘Parvenu and Pariah: The Heroes and
Victims of Modernity’ and its sequel, ‘Tourists and Vagabonds: The
Heroes and Victims of Postmodernity’.14 Here, before the idea of
liquid modernity is coined, it is modernity itself which is restless:
as Bauman puts it, ‘modernity is the impossibility of staying put.
To be modern means to be on the move.’15 This is not a choice.
We are driven to move by the disparity between the beauty of the
vision and the ugliness of reality. This makes us all nomads, in this
sense at least. Nomads are parvenus, arrivistes, in but not quite of.
This is the tragedy of modern culture: we only feel at home in our
homelessness and this is an ambivalence beyond cure. The same
ambivalence holds true for tourists and vagabonds, even if the latter
move by necessity as contrasted to the choice of the former. Tourists
have credit cards; and the vagabonds serve them, or can do, carry
their bags, hold their doors open, service them sexually. Neither
tourists nor vagabonds can be fixed in place, though tourists get
closer to fixity by choice (they can choose home) and vagabonds
get closer to fixity by circumstance (there is simply nowhere else
to go, until further notice). Tourists, as Bauman puts it, in an early
exercise of the notion, are the supreme masters of the art of melting
the solids and unfixing the fixed. They do not belong, yet they can
keep their distance. Tourists move, on this account; they do not
arrive. Vagabonds, in contrast, are the waste of the world which has
dedicated itself to servicing tourists. The background image of vaga-
bonds is as Romany, and again Zygmunt Bauman is working here
under the influence of the work of his wife, Janina. Tourists happily
evacuate, leave their mess behind for the vagabonds to work over
and deal with. Their worlds are attractive. Vagabonds move because
they find the world unbearably inhospitable. Tourists travel because
they want to, vagabonds because they have no other choice. Their
momentary sense of tolerance or ‘welcome’ can be withdrawn at a
moment’s notice.
Bauman knows that these are metaphors, rather than concepts;
he is not presenting this couplet, tourist/vagabond, as a replace-
ment or updating of, for example, class relations. Nevertheless,
he suggests that ‘the opposition between the tourists and the vaga-
bonds is the major, principal division of the postmodern society’,16
and it is a global divide, even as it is lived out locally in the metropo-
lis as well. This is an extension of the older, Hegelian dialectic of
55
master and slave. The poor, the dispossessed of the world, become
the rubbish bins of the privileged. Vagabonds are trash cans for
tourist filth.
Bauman pursues these themes further in Work, Consumerism
and the New Poor. Here, everything that is old is new again. For the
worlds of division and exclusion that we face today still call out
earlier images of pauperism and a literature which runs through
Disraeli, ‘The Two Nations’, Carlyle, Gaskell, Ricardo and Mayhew,
Bentham and Chadwick. What he here calls modernity phase two,
consumer’s modernity, however, summons up a different empha-
sis between production and consumption. For some years, by this
point, Bauman had been travelling in company with the kindred
spirit of Jeremy Seabrook. Here, in effect, their concerns merge,
for there is also a fellow traveller to this 1998 book, which is the
little book on Globalization, where the effects of displaced peoples
is tracked globally, in a complementary dimension to that of the
Keynesian welfare state which is the analytical object of Work,
Consumerism and the New Poor. The point, after Marx, with Keynes, is
that capital is not only the vampire which sucks living labour dry; it
also expels labour, literally evacuates it from the core institutions of
modernity. Capital prices labour out of work, so that there is now
a global reserve army of the unemployed, while welfare provision
remains local. The underclass, Marx’s Lumpenproletariat, returns
to haunt us. No longer mere victims, they now become demons,
moral rather than economic in their primary function, constantly
reminding all of us of the horrible fates of outsiders, keeping our
noses down and bums up. The figure of the poor person becomes
a scarecrow, not only superfluous to economic needs but also scary.
The most powerful condensation of these concerns comes, finally,
with Wasted Lives – Modernity and Its Outcasts. This is the point at which
Bauman connects most powerfully back to the issue of humans as
waste posited in Modernity and the Holocaust. ‘Our planet is full’.17
Not only full, but bloated, as parts of the planet are rendered unfit
for habitation, and the world system of consumption has expanded
to the point that there is nothing left outside it, even as its marginal
members struggle to survive. The production of ‘human waste’,
more correctly wasted humans, excess souls, surplus population, the
redundant, is an inevitable outcome of modernisation. Colonialism
no longer offers the outlet for surplus population that it once did.
The vast masses of lost humans want in, want in to the cities, most
evidently in the megacities of the developing world. We are awash in
56
This much across time, but so much inflamed by modernity and its
recklessness. Modernity is excess. Surplus population is one of the
great externalities of capitalist economy. Prisons become the most
expressive of institutions for this dumping of human lives. Refugees
become its most stigmatised object.
But in the meantime, at the turn of the millennium, Bauman has
posited the idea and the telos of Liquid Modernity, and all that which
follows – liquid love, liquid fear, liquid times. The primary sociologi-
cal purpose of the idea of liquid modernity seems to be to clarify
the periodisation of twentieth century development outside of the
language of postmodernity. Yet postmodernity routinely was used to
describe the capitalist world after the 1970s, and liquid modernity
indicates the same kind of notional periodisation. Solid moder-
nity is fordism. Liquid modernity is what comes after, fraught with
uncertainty, fragility, precariousness. Liquidity, like the postmod-
ern before it, might be an attitude rather than a fixed condition or
a fact. If postmodernity was for Bauman a matter of experiencing
modernity without illusions, then liquid modernity was a matter
of taking on modernity without certainty, safety or security. Life,
henceforth, would be even more precarious, especially for those
who did not choose this but had it forced rather upon them.
Certainly the rate of change seems to be accelerating, and the
purpose of liquidity is to capture this mercurial quality of flux, inas-
much as it is open to capture at all. How will all this look later, after
the fact, after the immediacy of our moment and its experience? As
Bernard Smith is given to remind us, in the company of Hegel, it
remains entirely possible that we only understand history after the
fact.19 What looks liquid to my generation, or Bauman’s, might well
look different to those who are just now entering this world, and
experience it as normal. The fact of movement, and the problems
of surplus population, will persist, and accelerate further.
57
Notes
1. See for example Peter Beilharz (ed.), Zygmunt Bauman; Keith Tester
and Michael Hivid Jacobsen, Bauman before Postmodernity: Invitation,
Conversations and Annotated Bibliography 1953–1989 (Aalborg: Aalborg
University Press, 2006); Anthony Elliott (ed.), The Contemporary Bauman.
2. Zygmunt Bauman, Community: Seeking Safety in an Insecure World
(Cambridge: Polity, 2002); Zygmunt Bauman, Identity: Conversations
with Benedetto Vecchi (Cambridge: Polity, 2004); Zygmunt Bauman,
Europe: An Unfinished Adventure (Cambridge: Polity, 2004).
3. Zygmunt Bauman, Liquid Love: On the Frailty of Human Bonds
(Cambridge: Polity, 2003); Zygmunt Bauman, Liquid Life (Cambridge:
Polity, 2005); and Zygmunt Bauman, Liquid Times: Living in an Age of
Uncertainty (Cambridge: Polity, 2006).
4. Monica Ali, In the Kitchen (New York: Doubleday, 2009).
5. Peter Beilharz, ‘Another Bauman: The Anthropological Imagination’,
in M. Davis and K. Tester (eds), Baumann’s Challenge: Sociological Issues
for the 21st Century (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010), pp. 62–9.
6. Karl Marx, Capital Volume One (London: George Allen and Unwin,
1867/1946), p. 659.
7. E. P. Thompson, The Making of the English Working Class (London:
Victor Gollancz, 1963).
8. Friedrich Engels, The Condition of the Working Class in England in 1844
(London: Swan Sonnenschein & Co., 1892).
9. See Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison (New
York: Vintage, 1979).
10. Barrington Moore, Injustice: The Social Bases of Obedience and Revolt
(New York: Random House, 1978).
11. See Beilharz, Zygmunt Bauman, Volume 2, Part 3, ‘The Holocaust’.
12. Ibid. David Blackbourn, The Conquest of Nature: Water, Landscape and the
Making of Modern Germany (London: Cape, 2006).
13. John Carroll, ‘Zygmunt Bauman – Mortality and Culture’, in M.
H. Jacobsen, S. Marshman and K. Tester (eds), Bauman beyond
Postmodernity (Aalborg: Aalborg University Press, 2007).
58
59
Introduction
Homi K. Bhabha is best known for his central contribution to the
development of post-colonial theory, extending across writing
about visual arts, literature in English, and issues relating to human
rights and globalisation. Through his work, Bhabha has become
one of the so-called Holy Trinity of post-colonial theory, alongside
Edward W. Said and Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak, and now teaches at
Harvard University.1 He has been widely discussed and celebrated
as a thinker of post-colonial cultures, the importance of which
he explores by drawing on the work of Said and Spivak, as well as
diverse figures such as Jacques Derrida, Frantz Fanon, Sigmund
Freud, Michel Foucault, Anish Kapoor, Jacques Lacan, Albert
Memmi, Toni Morrison and V. S. Naipaul. Many critics in various
disciplines have taken on board his ideas about the hybridity of
cultures, which are particularly significant in the light of ongoing
imperialism.
Bhabha brings together many different critical theories, in
particular psychoanalysis and deconstruction, in order to explore
how the cultures of colonialism are fissured or divided against
themselves, despite appearing to be straightforward expressions
of authority and dominance. Beginning with the idea that colonial
culture is a form of discourse, he stresses the ambivalence and
anxiety contained in many of its examples. Bhabha explores this
anxiety within the coloniser’s authority, juxtaposing it with the
active agency of the colonised, seen in strategies of mimicry and ‘sly
60
61
Interdisciplinary Theory
While Bhabha’s influence is clear, he has also been attacked as
a representative of ‘high theory’, which often seems a specifi-
cally Western discourse and so quite unsuited for the purposes of
post-colonial criticism. Accordingly, it is important to understand
Bhabha’s commitment to theory, which he conceives as an interdisci-
plinary enterprise. Questioned by W. J. T. Mitchell about the impor-
tance of theory for post-colonial studies, Bhabha distinguishes two
forms of interdisciplinarity. The first emphasises the development
of joint degrees and teaching in order to widen the pedagogical
or research base, juxtaposing disciplines which at the same time
retain their solid foundations. The second form of interdisciplinar-
ity acknowledges disciplinary limits, but responds to a crisis of their
apparently solid foundations; Bhabha argues that it
62
63
Our major task now is to probe further the cunning of Western moder-
nity, its historical ironies, its disjunctive temporalities, its much-vaunted
crisis of representation. It is important to say that it would change the
values of all critical work if the emergence of modernity were given a
colonial and postcolonial genealogy. We must never forget that the
64
Understanding how the West reached its present state, Bhabha sug-
gests, demands that we look outside the West, principally of course
for historical reasons relating to slavery, colonialism and so on. For
example, during the colonial period, the violence of colonial Algeria
testified to a certain disease at the heart of the French mission civili-
satrice. The same kind of understanding helps us consider broader
histories of colonialism and imperialism, from the British Empire
through to present-day neo-colonialism. Fundamentally, Bhabha
believes that in the contemporary moment the post-colonial per-
spective has a privileged role in rethinking global and local cultural
relations. The post-colonial perspective comes from the margins,
but cannot remain there if it is to play this role. Indeed, the
post-colonial perspective is necessarily part of the metropolitan
centre, through the hybrid qualities of modern cultures that are a
consequence of increased migration in its many forms.
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
Conclusion
The recent expansion of Bhabha’s focus follows from the impact
of his work beyond literary and cultural criticism. His writing
has been very influential and is discussed by a large number of
writers in colonial discourse analysis and post-colonial theory,
as well as related fields relating to contemporary literature and
culture. Bhabha has been invited to lecture around the world:
he delivered the Clarendon Lectures at the University of Oxford,
the Wellek Library Lectures at the University of California Irvine,
73
Notes
1. Robert J.C. Young, Colonial Desire, p. 163.
2. ‘Joking Aside’, p. xv.
3. ‘Translator Translated’, p. 81.
4. Ibid. p. 118.
5. The Location of Culture, p. 163.
6. Ibid. p. 163.
7. Ibid. p. 173.
8. Ibid. p. 64.
9. ‘Art and National Identity: A Critics’ Symposium’, p. 82.
10. ‘Translator Translated’, p. 83.
11. The Location of Culture, p. 70.
12. Ibid. p. 67.
13. Ibid. p. 86.
14. Ibid. p. 86.
15. Michael Pickering, Stereotyping: The Politics of Representation (London:
Palgrave, now Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2001), p. 159.
74
16. Anne McClintock, Imperial Leather: Race, Gender, and Sexuality in the
Colonial Contest (London: Routledge, 1995), pp. 64–5.
17. Ibid. p. 363.
18. Caroline Rooney, African Literature, Animism and Politics (London:
Routledge, 2006), p. 104.
19. The Location of Culture, p. 88.
20. Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and
Spread of Nationalism, 3rd edn (London: Verso, 2006).
21. The Location of Culture, p. 141.
22. Roman Jakobson and Morris Halle, Fundamentals of Language, 2nd edn
(The Hague: Mouton de Gruyter, 1971).
23. The Location of Culture, p. 139.
24. Ibid. p. 142.
25. Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri, Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 2000), pp. 143–6.
26. ‘Arrivals and Departures’, p. ix.
27. ‘Another Country’, p. 34.
28 Bhabha, citing James Clifford, ‘Traveling Cultures’, in Lawrence
Grossberg, Cary Nelson, Paula A. Treichler (eds), Cultural Studies
(London: Routledge, 1997), pp. 96–116.
29. ‘Another Country’, p. 30.
30. ‘Adagio’, p. 11.
31. Ibid. pp. 12–13.
32. ‘The Black Savant and the Dark Princess’, p. 57.
33. Ibid. p. 58.
34. Benita Parry, Postcolonial Studies: A Materialist Critique (London:
Routledge, 2004); and Aijaz Ahmad, ‘The Politics of Literary
Postcoloniality’, Race and Class 36, 3, 1995, pp. 1–20.
75
76
77
Sex/Gender/Sexuality as Performative
The idea for which Butler is best known is undoubtedly that of
gender performativity, which is given its most extensive treatment
in her second book Gender Trouble. The term performativity derives
from the ordinary language philosophy of J. L. Austin, where it is
78
79
80
81
82
The Body
One issue that came to the fore because of Butler’s discussion
of gender performativity was her conceptualisation of the body.
The (sexed) body is a central concern of feminism; most notably
because it is taken to be one of, if not the, principal sites upon
which gender differences are erected. Underpinning this claim is
the assumption that sex difference itself is immutable and because
of this female biology, particularly reproductive capacity, inevita-
bly affects women’s lives. Butler’s contention that the notion of
a natural body wrongly ontologises what is, in fact, a culturally
instituted phenomenon is a clear challenge to this view. In Gender
Trouble, Butler does not merely subscribe to Foucault’s Nietzschean
view that the body is shaped or disciplined by power; she criticises
Foucault for ‘maintaining a body prior to its cultural inscription’ for
the material body, as she conceives of it, is nothing other than the
effect of specific signifying practices.22 Unsurprisingly, some of her
feminist readers baulked at this conceptualisation, accusing Butler
both of denying the ‘reality’ of women’s bodies and of going too far
in her denaturalisation of the body.23
What perplexed Butler’s critics was that she appeared not to
subscribe to a belief in the body as a material entity with any innate
functions. When she remarks, in the preface to Bodies That Matter,
that ‘surely bodies live and die; eat and sleep; feel pain, pleasure;
endure illness and violence’, Butler appears to concede that the
body does indeed have an extra- or pre-discursive existence. Almost
83
84
85
Ethics
Although the initial prompt for Butler’s exploration of ethical
responsibility in Precarious Life was the events of September 11
2001, in many other respects it is the natural culmination of several
lines of thought pursued in prior work. The conception of corpo-
real vulnerability outlined earlier grows out of arguments begun
in The Psychic Life of Power, and underpins her concern with how
experiences such as grief, love, mourning and anger might become
resources used to extend what constitutes a livable life. Her endur-
ing interest in questions of recognition, Hegel’s bequest, is linked
inextricably to Butler’s exploration of the connections between
intelligibility and recognisability – the general conditions under
which acts of recognition occur. For, before an act of recognition
can occur – before someone’s life might be accepted as livable or
they might be acknowledged as human – those involved have to be
(or become) recognisable to the other as a subject. An additional
element which is central to the kind of ethics Butler advances is the
self’s opacity to itself. It is this ‘foreignness to myself’ that, in Giving
an Account of Oneself, she claims is ‘the source of my ethical connec-
tion with others’38 and which also indicated the depth of her debt
to psychoanalysis.
Throughout her work, from Subjects of Desire onwards, Butler has
86
87
Butler’s Influence
To say that Butler’s work has had a significant impact on femi-
nism or queer theory is scarcely contentious: Gender Trouble alone
has been translated into over twenty languages and has spawned
responses, commentaries and refutations aplenty. To focus on
this one book alone, however, is to underestimate the range of
Butler’s academic influence. Her work in general is cited rou-
tinely in disciplines as varied as philosophy, geography, perform-
ance studies, design, sociology, politics and literature (among
many others). Butler’s idea of performativity has been drawn on
not only to illuminate further the relation between sex, gender
and sexuality but also the performativity of race. The concept of
life’s precariousness has been influential in recent international
relations theory. Her understanding of subjectivity had been
used in film interpretation, while the idea of cultural unintelli-
gibility has been borrowed to explore questions of immigration
and asylum. Volumes have been published examining Butler’s
politics, the influence of her ideas on the study of religion and
her contribution to the study of law. In addition, several special
88
89
Notes
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
meaning for the metabolic existence of the system itself. Like the
quality of inherence discussed above, this formulation upsets all
distinctions between inside and outside, instead suggesting the
idea of an informational ‘loop’.20 Varela suggests that autonomy is
represented by the on-going maintenance of organisational closure
and conservation of the system as a unity, while its disintegration
signals a loss of identity and partial or complete death for the
system. Varela’s work establishes important developments within
theories of creative evolution and might refine our understanding
of the emergence of non-human as well as human living systems (an
eco-system or a socially constituted individual, for example). While
it is evident that Castoriadis draws creatively upon Varela’s theory
of autopoiesis, he is at pains to emphasise a more specific aspect
of autonomy against the organisational closure of Varela’s theory
which leads, for Castoriadis, to paradoxical results.21 It implies that
even a society whose system of world and institution is totally closed
and rigid might be considered self-maintaining and, therefore,
autonomous. In the context of the project of autonomy developed
by Castoriadis, such a political system, be it archaic or authoritarian,
fosters not autonomy but only heteronomy. By replacing the focus
upon self-organisation with one of self-constitution, Castoriadis
transforms the focus from autonomy as biological closure to one of
opening. He writes:
Thus the living being creates life, as well as the infinity of ways of
existing socially and the myriad of laws and norms that pertain to
this or another form of life. Furthermore, it is because there is an
inexhaustible and indefinite series of possibilities (described above
as a magma-like horizon of representations, ready for symbolisation
and communication) that autonomy exists as a political project
and a political activity. It is, he writes, ‘the term nomos that gives full
meaning to the term and project of autonomy’ where the subject
becomes the explicit author of form.23 Can the individual become
an autonomous being, one who acts deliberatively to modify its
law? How might the radical imagination as self-alteration (and
the novelty implied by its mode of social-historical being) bring
101
102
103
104
Democracy is the sole regime that takes risks, that faces openly the possi-
bility of its self-destruction . . . [T]his amounts to saying that democracy
thrusts aside the sacred, or that – and this is the same thing – human
beings finally accept what they have never, until now, truly wanted to
accept: that they are mortal, that nothing lies ‘beyond’.35
105
Notes
1. See Castoriadis, Political and Social Writings, 3 vols.
2. See Castoriadis, Imaginary Institution, Part 1.
3. See Axel Honneth, ‘Symposium on Castoriadis’, Radical Philosophy, 90,
1998, pp. 2–8.
4. See Suzi Adams, ‘Castoriadis’ Shift towards Physis’, Thesis Eleven, 74,
2003, pp. 105–12.
5. Imaginary Institution, p. 184. It must be noted that such a view of
structuralism begs further questioning. One must surely note the
thesis of overdetermination as well as Althusser’s later reflections
on aleatory materialism since both unravel the rigidity of structure,
as Castoriadis views it. See the essays in Louis Althusser, For Marx
(London: Verso, 1990) and Philosophy of the Encounter: Later Writings
1978–1987 (London: Verso, 2006).
6. For elaboration, see ‘The Greek Polis and the Creation of Democracy’,
in Castoriadis, Philosophy, Politics, Autonomy.
7. On Aristotle and Kant, see ‘The Discovery of Imagination’, in
Castoriadis, World in Fragments; ‘Radical Imagination and the Social
Instituting Imaginary’, in The Castoriadis Reader.
106
107
108
109
Introduction
Although green critical theory has only developed over the past
three decades, its antecedents can be traced to much earlier eras.
In this chapter, I will outline only a few of the more important
sources, which generally involve some sort of reaction or chal-
lenge to the increasing domination of society by technological and
economic considerations, as well as protest against the narrowing
of subjectivity that accompanies this domination. Various green
writers have argued that rational argument is, by itself, too narrow a
framework for articulating what they want to say, and that we need
to draw also on intuition, empathy and embodied sensing. Edward
O. Wilson’s ‘biophilia hypothesis’,1 for example, suggests that
humans are innately drawn to natural entities; and John Livingston
has written that rational argument ‘is not only inappropriate to our
subject matter but may also be destructive of it. There is no “logic”
in feeling, in experiencing, in states of being. Yet these same phe-
nomena appear to be the prerequisite for wildlife preservation’.2
Green writing, then, like green practice, is a heartfelt activity, stem-
ming from our embodiment as a particular sort of animal within a
community of other such animals, inherently challenging the split
between body and mind which has often been the assumed basis of
philosophies since Descartes.
So the conservation of wilderness, for example, is not merely
a calculated policy advocated for climatic reasons or to protect
‘useful’ plants such as the rosy periwinkle. For Edward Abbey
110
the word suggests the past and the unknown, the womb of earth from
which we all emerged. It means something lost and something still
present, something remote and at the same time intimate, something
buried in our blood and nerves, something beyond us and without
limit . . . The romantic view, while not the whole of truth, is a necessary
part of the whole truth.3
111
the grasp of a child’s hand in your own, the flavour of an apple, the
embrace of friend or lover, the silk of a girl’s thigh, the sunlight on
rock and leaves, the feel of music, the bark of a tree, the abrasion of
granite and sand, the plunge of clear water into a pool, the face of the
wind – what else is there? What else do we need?7
put five miles in good hiking boots between yourself and the trailhead
. . . and stop for lunch at a craggy overlook or beside a spring, watch
the ravens soar, hear their call, turn an eye on the gathering afternoon
thunderstorm; and you are not much inclined to believe that your
environment is nothing but a social construction.8
112
An ecologist might add that, in any case, the sentient creatures are
dependent on the forest, the hillside, the jungle, or the canyon,
113
114
The buffalo herd in Stanley Kramer’s film ‘Bless the Beasts and
Children’ thunders out of the pen, released by the daring efforts of
a group of heroic boys, only to stop and graze peacefully on a nearby
hill, allowing themselves to be rounded up and imprisoned again. Elsa,
the Adamsons’ pet lioness, ‘born free’ and then tamed, must be labori-
ously trained [sic] to become a wild predator before she can be safely
released. Of such ambiguous stories is the mythology of the human
condition in the ‘post-industrial’ age composed.17
115
116
Naess’s own life was a testament to his belief that we are part
of a wider ‘biospherical net’. An accomplished mountain climber,
even in childhood he felt a strong connection to the Norwegian
landscape; and until his death at the age of 96, he still enjoyed
spending time in the stone hut he built in the mountains. He was
also strongly engaged in social issues and actions, once chaining
himself together with other protesters to prevent the construction
of a hydroelectric dam on the Alta River. There was a marked con-
tinuity and coherence between his philosophical views and the way
he lived; and, in keeping with this emphasis on the relation between
philosophy and lived experience, Naess was critical of the direction
taken by academic philosophy and cultural theory, suggesting that
‘the turn of philosophy in this century towards language rather than
cosmos, towards logic rather than experience . . . is a turn into a
vast blind alley’.24 He was equally critical of postmodernism, which
he regarded simply as ‘the latest philosophical fad’.25 In contrast to
such approaches, which often seem to have only the most tenuous
relationship with lived realities, the questions that Naess addresses
are quite down to earth, although not always easy to answer:
117
118
Ecofeminism
Ecofeminists see links between the patriarchal domination of
women and the patriarchal domination of the natural world, and so
explore the common cultural factors in these forms of domination.
This general insight has given rise to a large variety of ecofeminisms,
of which I will outline some of the more prominent ones. Evidence
for linkages between male exploitation of women and nature is not
difficult to find. In the sixteenth century, Francis Bacon, who was
both a leading populariser of the new scientific approach and Lord
119
For you have but to follow and as it were hound nature in her wander-
ings, and you will be able when you like to lead and drive her afterward
to the same place again. Neither am I of the opinion that . . . sorcer-
ies, witchcrafts, charms, dreams, divinations, and the like should be
altogether excluded . . . a useful light may be gained, not only for a
true judgement of the offenses of persons charged with such practices,
but likewise for the further disclosing of the secrets of nature. Neither
ought a man to make scruple of entering and penetrating into those
holes and corners, when the inquisition of truth is his whole object.29
120
Culture Nature
Male Female
Mind Body
Reason Matter
Rationality Emotion
Human Nonhuman
121
122
We reached the old wolf in time to watch a fierce green fire dying
in her eyes. I realised then, and have known ever since, that there
was something new to me in those eyes – something known only to
her and to the mountain. I was young then, and full of trigger-itch; I
thought that because fewer wolves meant more deer, that no wolves
would mean a hunters’ paradise. But after seeing the green fire die,
I sensed that neither the wolf nor the mountain agreed with such a
view.36
123
Notes
1. Steven Kellert and Edward O. Wilson (eds), The Biophilia Hypothesis
(Washington, DC: Island Press, 1993).
2. John Livingston, quoted by Peter Hay, A Companion to Environmental
Thought, p. 3.
3. Edward Abbey, Desert Solitaire, pp. 189–90.
4. René Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy, trans. John Cottingham
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986 [1641]).
5. Julien de la Mettrie, Man a Machine, trans. Richard A. Watson
(Cambridge, MA: Hackett Publishing, 1994 [1748]).
6. D. H. Lawrence, ‘Apropos of Lady Chatterley’s Lover’, Preface to Lady
Chatterley’s Lover (London: Heinemann, 1961), p. 37.
7. Abbey, Desert Solitaire, p. xi.
8. Holmes Rolston III, ‘Mountain Majesties above Fruited Plains: Culture,
Nature, and Rocky Mountain Aesthetics’, Environmental Ethics, 30, 1,
2008, pp. 14–15.
9. Jeremy Bentham, Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1789).
10. John Rodman, ‘The liberation of nature?’, p. 89.
11. Ibid. p. 91.
12. Ibid. p. 94.
13. Ibid. p. 97.
14. Ibid. p. 98.
15. Ibid. p. 104.
16. Ibid. p. 104.
17. Ibid. p. 105.
18. Ibid. p. 108.
19. Ibid. p. 115.
20. Arne Naess, ‘The Shallow and the Deep, Long-range Ecology
Movements: A Summary’, Inquiry, 16, 1973, pp. 95–100.
21. Arne Naess, ‘Shallow and the Deep’, p. 95.
22. Alan Drengson, ‘The Life and Work of Arne Naess: An Appreciative
Overview’, The Trumpeter, 21, 1, 2005, pp. 5–43 (6).
23. Stephan Bodian, ‘Simple in Means, Rich in Ends: An Interview with
Arne Naess’, in George Sessions (ed.), Deep Ecology for the 21st Century
(Boston: Shambhala, 1995), pp. 26–36 (27).
24. Quoted by George Sessions, ‘On Being Fair and Accurate towards
Arne Naess’, International Society for Environmental Ethics Newsletter, 17,
4, 2006–7, p. 20.
25. Sessions, ‘On Being Fair and Accurate’, p. 20.
26. Bodian, ‘Simple in Means, Rich in Ends’, p. 27.
27. Arne Naess, Life’s Philosophy: Reason and Feeling in a Deeper World
(Athens, GA: University of Georgia Press, 2008).
124
125
126
127
128
129
Refiguring Kinships
In many ways, Haraway is a theorist of relations, examining the
interplay between concepts and categories previously treated as
distinct. She has an uncanny ability to blur established bounda-
ries (between object and subject, animal and human, nature and
culture, body and mind, flesh and machine), always attending to
the co-constitutive relationships obtaining between each concep-
tual category and its ‘other’. In Haraway’s analysis, the exclusions
constituting (post)modern Western Man, ‘gods, machines, animals,
monsters, creepy crawlies, women, servants and slaves, and nonci-
tizens in general’, may be kept ‘outside the security checkpoint of
bright reason’ but they nevertheless have the capacity to inspire
terror in ‘centers of power and self-certainty’.10 It is fair to say that
much of Haraway’s scholarship works to amplify these fears in the
interest of eroding the certainties undergirding patterns of social
privilege.
In addition to a penchant for making use of new composite words
(such as ‘natureculture’, ‘technoscience’ and ‘material-semiotic’) to
capture the complex relations between oppositional terms, Haraway
has a talent for illustrating particular historical and cultural junc-
tures wherein dualisms dissolve into emergent figures that trouble
established subjectivities: machine and woman become ‘cyborg’ in
Cold War America, biotechnology and scientist become ‘vampire’
in the racialised discourses surrounding the genome project, and
dog and human become ‘companion species’ in twenty-first-century
agility sports. Each new figure points to hazards while also opening
up new possibilities. Although cyborgs are plugged into military-
industrial capital, they offer an escape from traditional markers of
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
[N]ature is not just a physical place to which one can go, nor a treasure
to fence in or bank, nor an essence to be saved or violated. Nature is
not hidden and so does not need to be unveiled. Nature is not a text
to be read in the codes of mathematics and biomedicine. It is not the
Other who offers origin, replenishment, and service. Neither mother,
nurse, lover, nor slave, nature is not matrix, resource, mirror, nor tool
for the reproduction of that odd, ethnocentric, phallogocentric, puta-
tively universal being called Man. Nor for his euphemistically named
surrogate, the ‘human’.43
138
139
Notes
1. Donna J. Haraway. ‘From Cyborgs to Companion Species: Kinship
in Technoscience’, Robert and Maurine Rothschild Lecture in the
History of Science, Introductory remarks by Charis Thompson,
Harvard University, 2002.
2. Haraway, Primate Visions, p. 6.
3. Schneider, Donna Haraway, p. 155.
4. Haraway, How like a Leaf, p. 133.
5. Haraway, The Haraway Reader (New York: Routledge, 2004), p. 200.
6. Haraway, How like a Leaf, p. 105.
7. Haraway, Simians, Cyborgs, and Women, p. 195.
8. Haraway, Modest_Witness, p. 11.
9. Ibid. p. 95.
10. Haraway, When Species Meet, p. 10.
11. Ibid. pp. 22–3.
12. Haraway, Haraway Reader, p. 8.
13. Haraway, Simians, Cyborgs, and Women, pp. 127–8.
14. Haraway, Haraway Reader, p. 2.
15. Ibid. p. 201.
16. Haraway, Modest_Witness, p. 28.
17. Haraway, Haraway Reader, pp. 8 and 39.
18. Ibid. p. 327.
19. Haraway, Simians, Cyborgs, and Women, p. 209.
20. Ibid. p. 199.
21. Haraway, Haraway Reader, p. 327.
22. Ibid. p. 328.
23. Haraway, Modest_Witness, p. 214.
24. Haraway, The Companion Species Manifesto, p. 4.
25. Haraway, When Species Meet, p. 301.
26. Bartsch, DiPalma, and Sells, ‘Witnessing the postmodern jeremiad’,
Configurations, 9, 2001, pp. 127–8.
140
141
142
143
Simon Tormey
Ernesto Laclau and Chantal Mouffe are the principal figures asso-
ciated with the emergence of ‘discourse analysis’, ‘post-Marxism’
and ‘radical democracy’ as key theoretical interventions in contem-
porary critical theory. Their best-known joint work, Hegemony and
Socialist Strategy published in 1985, became emblematic of a certain
brand of left progressive thought that sought to reconceptualise
radical politics ‘after’ Marx.1 Since writing Hegemony and Socialist
Strategy, Laclau and Mouffe have published widely under their
own names. Laclau’s works such as Emancipations and On Populist
Reason continue the exploration of the theoretical and conceptual
basis of radical democracy. Mouffe’s works such as The Return of the
Political and The Democratic Paradox engage directly with debates in
contemporary political thought, and in particular with democratic
theory in which she has articulated a distinct position, ‘agonistic
democracy’.
Both Laclau and Mouffe have strong connections to social
movements and political campaigns. Laclau was born in Argentina
and maintains a deep interest in the politics of Latin America
and with populism as a political form and strategy. He has held a
variety of posts over the past three decades, most notably at Essex
University where he has been the leading figure in the ‘Ideology
and Discourse Analysis’ programme which forms an important insti-
tutional locus for work in this area. Mouffe was born in Belgium and
was a student of Laclau’s at Essex before herself assuming a number
of academic affiliations, including most recently at the Centre for
Democracy at the University of Westminster. She is also active in
144
Marxism in Question
The animating problematic of Laclau and Mouffe’s work is situated
in the specific context of the crisis of Marxism and the collapse of
communism as the locus for radical theory and politics after 1968.
The inability of communist parties in western Europe to develop a
politics consonant with ‘new times’ led to the collapse of support for
communism in previous strongholds such as France and Italy and
thus the need to re-examine the expectations that had informed
Marxist radical politics since the late nineteenth century.2 These
expectations concerned the relationship between the economic
base and the ideological and political superstructure. To Marx it
was developments in the base that determined to greater or lesser
extent the extant political forms, whether considered as the values,
morals, laws or institutions of a given society. Changes in these
forms were precipitated by changes in the material base, so that as
new forms of technology emerged and became part of the repro-
duction of society so new classes, forces and ideas emerged to facili-
tate the passage from one form of society to another. Revolutions
are in this sense the product of an ‘exogenous’ imperative that
creates the conditions in which social change becomes not merely
desirable but necessary. Radical politics is in this sense propelled by
forces that lie outside the domain of politics itself.
To be Marxist was on these terms to be committed to a teleologi-
cal conception of social change. Given the inevitable lag between
the development of the base and the development of the requisite
class consciousness needed to overthrow an anachronistic social
order, Marx posited the need for a party that would represent the
145
146
Rethinking Hegemony
In their own terminology Laclau and Mouffe are ‘post-marxist’,
insisting that they work within the broader expectations that Marx
had himself articulated: the insufficiency of liberalism; the persist-
ence of deep inequality and exclusion; and thus the necessity to
further radicalise the ‘democratic revolution’. Two figures were
of particular importance in this rethinking: Antonio Gramsci and
Louis Althusser. From Gramsci they take the idea of ‘hegemony’
and the necessity for thinking social change as a consequence
of forming political alliances as a ‘historical bloc’, as opposed to
waiting for social change to be generated from without in the form
of economic crisis. From Althusser they take the idea of society as a
complex totality that is ‘overdetermined’, meaning that it has to be
reproduced ideologically to make up for an absent ‘fullness’. There
is always an insufficiency or lack that requires the operation of the
state and other agencies to cover over the antagonisms and fissures
that complex entities manifest.
Gramsci was a thinking person’s revolutionary – a hero of the
Italian communist party who wrote much of his best-known work
in the 1920s while a prisoner of the Italian state. Following the dis-
astrous experiment of the Bolshevik Revolution, Gramsci sought to
reconstruct Marxism by paying attention to the different modali-
ties of political struggle and contestation. Famously, Gramsci con-
trasted the approach of the Bolsheviks, which he characterised as an
embrace of a ‘war of manoeuvre’, with the more subtle radicalism
needed under contemporary capitalist conditions, which he charac-
terised as ‘war of position’.4 The point emphasised a minor refrain
in Marx’s own thinking: that culture and historical tradition were
important determinants of political structure and action; that small
movements needed to join up with larger movements in order to
challenge dominant forces; and that progressive politics needed an
alternative vision in order to succeed. Sometimes challenging the
stock of norms, values and assumptions that permitted the ruling
class to maintain legitimacy as consent, which Gramsci refers to
as the ‘common sense’ nostrums that underpin social orders, was
more sensible than confronting it head on. The inference was clear:
if radicals wanted to bring about lasting change (as opposed to
mere political upheaval), then they needed to critique, undermine
and supplant the common-sense ideas that maintained the present
in being.
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
Every pretension to occupy the place of the universal, to fix its final
meaning through rationality, must be rejected. The content of the uni-
versal must remain indeterminate since it is this indeterminacy that is
the condition of existence of democratic politics.17
It is not only liberals who have a problem coping with the politi-
cal, however, but much of the contemporary left as well. Figures
such as Jürgen Habermas are, in Mouffe’s view, still in thrall to
enlightenment universalism as reconciliation and the end of the
political. The idea of, for example, democratic deliberation as
a process of consensus formation (arriving at a decision that is
acceptable to all participants in a discussion) misses the point of
contestation, namely, that it expresses the ‘agonal’ quality of fully
functioning plural societies. The task of a properly radical agonistic
politics is not to deny the necessity for contestation but to promote
and nurture it in institutional forms that are productive of commu-
nity and collectivity even while they enshrine difference. What has
154
155
Conclusion: Difference/Identity?
Whether the differences between Laclau and Mouffe are seen to
outweigh the similarities is very much a question of the position
from which one is observing the unfolding of these intellectual tra-
jectories. To classical Marxists such as Norman Geras, Laclau and
Mouffe appear as two manifestations of the same species: post- or
non-Marxist radicals who have abandoned the basic ontological and
epistemological coordinates that inform a critical, socialist perspec-
tive.19 On his reading, the abandonment of the idea of the primacy
of production in structuring social life equates to the embrace of
a liberal or bourgeois perspective in which the muscularity of class
struggle recedes into the background to be displaced by an effete
postmodern concern with pluralism, diverse subject positions and
rainbow alliances. In the meantime, as other left critics such as
Žižek and Townshend argue, capitalism becomes a vanishing refer-
ent that cannot be approached or criticised in the abandonment of
the terrain from which such a critique would be mounted.20
It is certainly true as these critics point out that it is difficult to
find the resources to generate a transformative politics in Laclau
and Mouffe’s ruminations on the fate of universalism and particular-
ism. Mouffe has avowedly embraced liberal presuppositions regard-
ing the structure of political contestation, which is a short step to
embracing liberal presuppositions tout court. Laclau, while main-
taining a recognisably Marxian language of counter-hegemonic
struggles and historical blocs, is arguably more interested in the
formal properties of ‘radical’ politics than in the substantive or
normative conclusions that such a language traditionally gener-
ated. Laclau’s concern is essentially Machiavellian, if not Leninist,
in orientation. His interest is in the question of power: how it is
156
157
Notes
158
159
160
Introduction
Bruno Latour is one of the leading figures in an approach ambiva-
lently called Actor-Network Theory (ANT).1 Actor-Network Theory
originally was developed by sociologists of science in response to
methodological and theoretical dilemmas these scholars encoun-
tered as they explored how scientists produced and circulated scien-
tific facts. ANT has transcended its science and technology studies’
origins and is now deployed by scholars in anthropology, geogra-
phy, economics, organisational studies, history, literature, media
studies and other disciplines. Other theorists who have played a
significant role in the development of ANT are Madeleine Akrich,
Michel Callon, Donna Haraway, John Law, Anne Marie Mol, Michel
Serres and Susan Leigh Star.
In Latour’s words: ‘I am from the typical French provincial bour-
geoisie, from Burgundy where my family has produced wine for
generations, and my only ambition is that people would say ‘I read
a Latour 1992’, with the same pleasure as they would say, ‘I drank
a Latour 1992!’2 He was trained as a philosopher at the University
of Tours, but began to be interested in science studies during his
military service in Cote d’Ivoire. There, he was encouraged to
pursue a sociological project on how the French export their indus-
trial education to their former colony, Cote d’Ivoire, by ORSTOM
(Institut français de recherche scientifique pour le développement
en coopération). He was asked to focus on why African executives
appeared to have such difficulties adapting to modern industrial
161
162
This study was Latour’s first venture into science studies. Upon
returning to France, Latour began to carve out a space for science
and technology studies, which had no institutional backing in the
French academic system at the time. Along with Michel Callon and
John Law, he began to develop the methodological and philosophi-
cal armature of ANT, summarised below. In addition to various
theoretical books on the contours of ANT,4 he has written The
Pasteurization of France, a historical exploration of how Pasteur’s
success was fashioned by refiguring various networks. He has also
authored Aramis, an account of the failure of a personal rapid
transit system in Paris, and Politics of Nature, a treatise on how envi-
ronmental movements could, but are not, transforming assump-
tions about the connections between nature and society.
Actor-Network Theory
When Latour gives an account of his theoretical perspective he
often starts by explaining the dichotomies he rejects, in part because
of his unease about his work being turned into a theoretical move-
ment. To clear an analytical space, he rejects dichotomies between
self/other, material/semiotic, nature/culture, agency/structure,
knowledge/power, active/passive, human/non-human and truth/
falsehood. By rejecting these dualisms, Latour presumes that every-
thing and everyone is profoundly relational – that entities only
have qualities, attributes or form as a result of their relationships
with other entities. This is a familiar claim for people who analyse
how words acquire meanings. One cannot attribute meaning to the
word ‘hat’ without presuming distinctions in sound (‘hat’ versus
‘cat’, ‘sat’ and ‘mat’), as well as distinctions in reference (‘hat’
versus ‘cap’, ‘shirt;’ ‘hair’ and ‘wool’). ‘Hat’ exists as a word with
meaning because it exists in a web of oppositional relationships to
other words and other referents. Latour takes this a couple of steps
further, and suggests that a hat condenses historical relationships of
manufacture (How was the material made? How did someone learn
the necessary skills to operate the tools to make the hat? From when
did the tools for hat-making come?), relationships of exchange
(what money, trucks, roads, stores, traders had to exist to move the
hat from hat-maker to hat-purchaser?), relationships of use (What
other hats are possible? When does one wear this particular hat?
What signs of wear will this hat have over time because of how the
shape of the head and this hat interact?) and so on.
163
164
165
166
and its descriptions into each new context, they attempt to ensure
that the referents can be traced through each context back to the
original location in the Brazilian forest. In analysing this example,
Latour argues that scientists construct reversible indexicalities,
defining indexicalities as Peircean signs that point to aspects of a
context or state of affairs. According to Latour, for signs to be able
to represent truth in a scientific network, the referents must exist
as a stable chain that point in both directions as the referents move
between contexts. He argues: ‘For this network to begin to lie – for
it to cease to refer – it is sufficient to interrupt its expansion at either
end, to stop providing for it, to suspend its funding, or to break it
at any other point.’6 To keep a scientific network from producing
scientific facts, all one must do is find a way to keep the scientific
inscriptions from referring backwards through all the previous con-
texts, or pointing forwards to other recontextualised referents. In
short, what is important for Latour is recognising the labour that
goes into constructing reversible indexicalities.
If instability is the given condition, one must labour to create
consistency and coherence. For Latour, durability is always an
achievement and needs to be analysed as such. One of his primary
analytical questions is: how are actants performed and how do
they perform themselves into relations that are relatively stable?
This focus on durability shapes his theoretical lens for under-
standing power relationships, which from this perspective become
indistinguishable from sustaining relations that last.
Fourth, not all actants are equal. Every actant is heterogeneous,
condensing disparate relationships. As a result, not all heterogene-
ous actants have the same abilities to navigate networks or to move
between different networks. In his study of Pasteur, Latour points
out that Pasteur was able to use the laboratory to cross many net-
works. Farmers and sheep were not so privileged. Pasteur affected
the network between farmers, sheep and microbes to such a degree
that if farmers wanted to change the ways the anthrax microbe
was affecting their sheep they had to interact with Pasteur and his
laboratory. Farmers were restricted to their network in a way that
Pasteur, as a scientist interacting with politicians, public hygien-
ists and military physicians, was not. Some actants are privileged
in particular networks, and able to cross networks, others are
not. This is another way in which ANT can make power relations
visible, by addressing the costs of particular networks for the actants
navigating them.
167
168
169
170
171
Criticism
While some critics of Latour will take on board ANT characterisa-
tions that all actors are condensed networks, they still have much
to say about how Latour depicts networks. For example, Donna
Haraway points out that Latour invokes only a few narrow and sus-
piciously agonistic narratives to account for how networks emerge.
She explains:
172
173
Conclusion
Latour and Actor-Network Theory in general have become popular
outside of the original disciplinary confines of science and tech-
nology studies as scholars are increasingly committed to moving
beyond the dichotomies of the material versus the social, or agency
versus structure. Actor-Network Theory offers a new methodo-
logical and theoretical approach to studying how ideas and objects
travel, which scholars of democracy, organisations, markets and
media have found helpful. In addition, it provides techniques for
analyzing the social construction of facts and truth which go beyond
studying the discourses shaping what counts as truth. Latour has
cleared a space so that scholars can begin asking new questions of
topics that have become perhaps a little too familiar.
Notes
1. Latour renounced Actor-Network Theory in his article, ‘On Recalling
Actor-Network Theory’. He has since retracted his rejection in Re-
Assembling the Social, p. 9.
2. T. Hugh Crawford, ‘An Interview with Bruno Latour’, Configurations,
1, 1990, p. 248.
3. Laboratory Life.
4. Science in Action; We Have Never Been Modern; Pandora’s Hope; Re-
Assembling the Social.
5. Bruno Latour, ‘Technology Is Society Made Durable’, in John Law
(ed.), A Sociology of Monsters (London: Routledge, 1991), p. 104.
6. Pandora’s Hope, p. 76.
7. Laboratory Life; Steven Shapin, A Social History of Truth (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1995), pp. 355–407.
8. Re-Assembling the Social, p. 200.
9. Ibid. p. 202.
10. We Have Never Been Modern, p. 78.
11. Haraway, Modest_Witness, p. 34.
12. Ibid. pp. 23–48.
174
175
176
177
178
179
Refusal
Negri investigated class subjectivity in the hidden spontaneous
forms of antagonism in factories during the 1960s and 1970s
while adopting the subjective standpoint of labour. He found that
beyond wage demands, class struggles were taking place in the
form of refusal, wild cat strikes, sabotage, absenteeism and moving
from one employer to another, all of which occurred autonomously
from the political exigencies and programmes of the representative
structures of trade unions, the communist party and the planner
state.9
180
181
parties and trade unions with the state and industry. This new
composition included the figure of the ‘socialised worker’ or the
‘affective labourer’, whose struggles took place outside the factory
at the level of the production of subjectivity and alternative forms
of life. We shall return to this genealogy in the last section, after a
discussion of the philosophical foundations of Negri’s materialist
ontology.
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
Multitude
The concept of multitude is derived from Spinoza’s political theory.
Negri and Hardt see it as the constituent subject in the age of
Empire that forces a shift in power relations. As a political subject,
the multitude refuses the functions of representation and exer-
cises its right to disobedience in the practice of exodus, constantly
reconfiguring the places and scope of antagonism. The multitude
is the political expression of a new social composition that uses
technology, machines and social cooperation as instruments of
liberation, thus constantly changing the possibilities of its capture
in capitalist valorisation.29 In Negri’s view, government, or govern-
ance, becomes a flexible machine of recuperation and disavowal
of social value, while capitalism is increasingly dependent on the
innovations of the social factory. The value created by subjectivities
in social cooperation is beyond measure. Attempts to subsume it
under the exploitative mechanisms of capitalist valorisation appear
as increasingly parasitical and abusive.
Today there is no longer any measure, and hence there is no longer
any reasonable appropriation either. Today, we are outside measure
and that is so because we are in a state of productive surplus. We could
easily satisfy all the needs of the populations in the world: this is not a
potentiality; this is a calculable, economic possibility.30
189
190
Notes
1. ‘Hegel was a funnel: he gathered everything the history of thought
had produced after him. Like an Egyptian pyramid, everyone, slaves
and masters, had put their own brick on it, it was impossible to move it
so everyone was climbing it.’ Antonio Negri, Pipeline. Lettere da Rebibbia
[Pipeline. Letters from Rebibbia – Special Prison] (Turin: Einaudi,
1982), p. 41. Jean Hyppolite was a reader and commentator on Hegel,
whose teachings played a crucial role in the philosophy of Gilles
Deleuze, Jacques Deridda and Michel Foucault amongst others.
2. See N. Balestrini and P. Moroni (eds), L’orda d’oro (Milan: Feltrinelli,
1988), for a rich collection of documents from this period.
3. Some of these are collected in Books for Burning.
4. Negri, ‘20 Theses on Marx: Interpretation of the Class Situation
Today’, in S. Makdis, C. Casarino and R. E. Karl (eds), Marxism beyond
Marxism (New York: Routledge, 1996), pp. 149–80.
5. Ibid. p. 165.
6. Negri, Pipeline, p. 83.
7. This was informed by the notion of social capital, further analysed by
Mario Tronti in ‘Social Capital’, Telos, 17, Autumn 1973, pp. 60–85.
8. Negri, Revolution Retrieved, p. 13.
9. Negri, ‘Logic and Theory of Inquiry’, trans. Arianna Bove and Nate
Holdren <http://www.generation-online.org/p/fpnegri20.htm>.
10. Negri, Pipeline, p. 83.
11. Negri, La Fabbrica della Strategia, 33 Lezioni su Lenin (Padua: Collettivo
Editoriale LibriRossi, 1976), p. 162; The Factory of Strategy. 33 Lessons on
Lenin (New York: Columbia University Press, forthcoming).
12. The term is derived from the unpublished Chapter 6 of volume 1 of
Marx’s Capital: see ‘Appendix’ to Capital, vol. 1 (London: Penguin,
1992).
13. Hardt and Negri, Labor of Dionysus.
14. Negri, Pipeline, p. 121.
15. Negri, Time for Revolution, p. 251.
16. Negri, Political Descartes, p. 116.
17. Ibid. p. 119.
18. Negri, The Savage Anomaly, p. 218.
19. For more on the revival of Spinoza, also influenced by Pierre
Macherey, Gilles Deleuze and Louis Althusser, see W. Montag and T.
Stolze (eds), The New Spinoza (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press, 1998).
191
192
Multitude: War and Democracy in the Age of Empire, with Michael Hardt (New
York: Penguin Press, 2004).
Political Descartes: Reason, Ideology and the Bourgeois Project, trans. Matteo
Mandarini and Alberto Toscano (London: Verso Books, 2007 [1970]).
Revolution Retrieved: Selected Writings on Marx, Keynes, Capitalist Crisis and
New Social Subjects, trans. Ed Emery and John Merrington (London: Red
Notes, 1988 [1968–83]).
The Savage Anomaly: The Power of Spinoza’s Metaphysics and Politics, trans.
Michael Hardt (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1991
[1981]).
Time for Revolution, trans. Matteo Mandarini (London: Continuum, 2003
[1982–2000]).
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
Le Partage du sensible
Although ‘police’, for Rancière, specifies a hierarchical distribution
of roles, places and bodies, and thereby names a system of domina-
tion, Rancière insists that ‘police’ is not inherently pejorative.23 This
claim becomes more cogent when we notice that the police is but one
particular form that le partage du sensible, ‘the partition of the sensi-
ble’, can take. As Rancière explains in the seventh of his ‘Ten Theses
on Politics’, police is a partition of the sensible that insists there be
neither a void in that partition nor a supplement to it. That is, ‘police’
is a partition of the sensible that is complete, totalising, without
remainder. But ‘partition of the sensible’ refers not simply to a given
empirical order; it points more generally and more fundamentally to
the intelligibility of that order. Rancière says that the partition of the
201
202
203
204
all the rest). Rancière not only, and repeatedly, calls this a bogus
move on the part of critics (since cinema constructs and depends
upon all those same old techniques of plot and narrative) but also
goes on to show that everything critics wish to celebrate about
cinema actually depends upon that which the critic would reject. This
problem plagues not just film criticism; it thwarts the efforts of the
most well-known academic theorists of cinema. About Deleuze and
Godard, for example, Rancière argues: ‘they both extract, after the
fact, the original essence of the cinematographic art from the plots
the art of cinema shares with the old art of storytelling’.35 But if this
is a post-hoc extraction, then surely there is no ‘original essence’
of cinema. The drive to find one probably owes something to the
effort to maintain a dichotomy between ‘principles of art and those
of a popular entertainment’.36
It almost goes without saying that for Rancière there is no pure
plasticity of art, and no pure cinema either. This means that he
rejects any effort to distinguish cinema by its particular techniques
or technology, and it entails his refusal of the common distinction
between film and television. Since there can be no pure cinema that
would free us from the banality of popular storytelling, and since
there can be no special status to cinema (because, for example,
the cinema screen is lighted from a distance while the television
screen is lighted internally – all nonsense for Rancière),37 then Film
Fables, the title of his most important work on cinema, names both
the effort by critics and academics to tell fables about film and also
the particular nature of the fables that film tells. Film fables are,
for Rancière, foiled fables. Rancière writes: ‘the art and thought of
images have always been nourished by all that thwarts them’.38
Rancière’s common refrain, that aesthetics names a partition/
distribution of the sensible, remains central to these arguments. This
explains why ‘cinema aesthetics’ could never be reduced to tech-
nique and why Rancière argues that a cinema aesthetics, ‘cinema as
an artistic idea’, emerges well before we have the technical means
necessary to make a movie.39 As with literature and art, what is impor-
tant about cinema is its aesthetics in this sense – its potential, even if
unrealised, to produce a new partition of the sensible.
205
206
Notes
207
208
37. Ibid. pp. 4, 18; Rancière, Future of the Image, trans. Gregory Elliott
(London: Verso, 2008), pp. 2, 6.
38. Rancière, Film Fables, p. 19.
39. Ibid. p. 6.
40. Jacques Rancière, ‘Misadventures in Critical Thinking’, unpublished
manuscript, p. 2.
41. Rancière, ‘Dissenting Words’, p. 114.
42. Rancière, ‘Misadventures’, p. 13.
43. Ibid. p. 15.
209
210
211
claim that there is nothing outside the text. Indeed for Spivak,
Derrida’s theory of a general system of writing or textuality – by
which he means the economic and social text as well as the philo-
sophical or literary text – enables a radical approach to reading the
world. As Spivak explains: ‘The world actually writes itself with the
many-leveled, unfixable intricacy and openness of a work of litera-
ture’.4 To read the world as a text, in other words, is to read the
contradictions and aporia in the rhetoric of multinational finance
and World Bank reports, but it is also to read the lives and histo-
ries of dispossessed, ‘subaltern’ groups who have no access to the
dominant ‘text’ of globalisation.
Spivak finds in Derrida a thinker who enables her to interrogate
the authority of western thought. Specifically, Derrida’s reading
of Rousseau and Lévi-Strauss in Of Grammatology provides Spivak
with the conceptual tools to criticise the cultural and philosophi-
cal authority of the West. Spivak notes a ‘geographical pattern’ in
Derrida’s argument, whereby a relationship between logocentrism
and ethnocentrism is ‘indirectly invoked’.5 Derrida emphasises
how the coherence and continuity of western thought has been
predicated on the ‘debasement of writing and its repression outside
“full” speech’.6 Derrida refers to this repression of writing as pho-
nocentric, because it privileges the voice as a transparent medium
through which the subject represents himself as a coherent subject.
Yet, as Derrida emphasises, even the physical act of speech relies
on a process of writing or a system of differentiation to generate
meanings. By critically inhabiting the narrow concept of writing
as a transparent vehicle for speech, Derrida traces a movement of
general writing that secures the production of meaning. Yet he also
emphasises how this general writing cannot be understood as a posi-
tive concept or category. Indeed, it is precisely the exclusion of this
general writing from representation which regulates the opposition
between speech and writing, where writing is defined as a transpar-
ent vehicle for speech. As Derrida writes:
This arche-writing, although its concept is invoked by the themes of
‘the arbitrariness of the sign’ and of difference, cannot and can never
be recognised as the object of a science. It is that very thing which cannot
let its self be reduced to the form of presence. The latter orders all
objectivity of the object and all relation to knowledge.7
212
213
214
Subaltern Studies
The concept of the subaltern has a rich and complex genealogy in
Spivak’s thought. On the one hand, subalternity refers to a position
of social, cultural and linguistic subordination within a particular
colonial or post-colonial society and, on the other hand, it denotes
a position that cannot be conceptualised as a positive category. This
double meaning serves to complicate political programmes that
claim to speak on behalf of the oppressed or the disenfranchised.
To further clarify the meaning of the term in Spivak’s thought it
is also important to track the source of the term in the work of
the left-wing Italian thinker Antonio Gramsci and the South Asian
Subaltern Studies collective.
The term ‘subaltern’ is conventionally understood as a synonym
of subordinate, but it can also denote a lower-ranking officer in the
army, or a particular example that supports a universal proposition
in philosophical logic. Spivak’s use of the term subaltern is prima-
rily informed by the work of the Italian Marxist thinker Antonio
Gramsci on the rural-based Italian peasantry and the research of
the international Subaltern Studies collective on the histories of
subaltern insurgency in colonial and post-colonial South Asia. In his
Prison Notebooks Gramsci uses the term subaltern interchangeably
with ‘subordinate’ and ‘instrumental’ to describe ‘non-hegemonic
groups or classes’.14 This is not to say that the term subaltern is
synonymous with the category of proletariat, however. As the subal-
tern historian David Arnold explains, ‘the language of subalternity
might generally be more appropriate than that of class’ in societies
like India or Italy that ‘had not become wholly capitalistic’.15
It is this sense of the subaltern – as a general category of subor-
dination – that informs the work of the Subaltern Studies collective.
Drawing on Gramsci’s account of the rural peasantry in Southern
Italy, as well as the work of the British Marxist historians Eric
Hobsbawn and E. P. Thompson, the Subaltern Studies collective
use the term as a ‘name for the general attribute of subordination in
South Asian society whether this is expressed in terms of class, caste,
age, gender and office or in any other way’.16 By focusing on South
Asian history from the perspective of the subaltern, the members
215
Like Guha, Chakrabarty and Arnold, Spivak traces how the word
subaltern has become transformed by the Subaltern Studies collec-
tive into a category that is clearly distinct from the word proletariat.
In this interview Spivak valorises the term ‘subaltern’ because it
is a more flexible and situated category of political identity than
the term proletarian, which conventionally denotes the masculine
working-class subject of nineteenth-century Europe.
Yet this is not to suggest that Spivak is entirely in agreement with
the work of Subaltern Studies historians. Spivak’s formulation of
the subaltern as a theoretical concept is distinct from that of the
Subaltern Studies’ historians in that she argues that the subaltern is
a historical fiction that enables the historical claims of the Subaltern
Studies historians, rather than a positive presence that can be
recovered from the archives of colonialism. In ‘Deconstructing
Historiography’, for example, Spivak’s reading of the Subaltern his-
torians project emphasises how their practice of revisionist histori-
cal writing is broadly speaking at odds with their methodology. Early
writings on the history of peasant insurgency try to recover a pure
subaltern consciousness that is equivalent to Marx’s notion of class
consciousness. Spivak argues that such an approach bestows a false
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
Conclusion
Spivak’s thought has had a major influence on post-colonial
studies over the past two decades, which has tended to concen-
trate on her essay ‘Can the Subaltern Speak?’ and A Critique of
Postcolonial Reason.39 But Spivak’s rethinking of Marx has also had
a profound impact on transnational cultural studies, with think-
ers such as Peter Hitchcock emphasising that Spivak is one of the
few intellectuals of our time to rethink the body ‘within the space
of contemporary transnational capitalism’.40 Such an argument is
also important for debates in transnational feminism – for Spivak,
along with leading feminist thinkers such as Chandra Talpade
Mohanty and Aiwa Ong, has made a major contribution to our
understanding of the position of women, the gendered body and
the ideology of reproductive heteronormativity in the contempo-
rary global economy.
Notes
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
media. Not content with smashing 1930s speed records for flying
around the globe, Hughes abruptly grounded his airplane, at
last acknowledging that his craving for movement was actually a
craving for inertia. Connected to people only by telephone, Hughes
locked himself inside rooms that were identical, even if they were
continents apart, thereby eradicating the sensation of travelling
from one place to another, but, especially, eradicating the sensa-
tion of the differences between one place and another. Through
Hughes’s poorly lit rooms and windows no daylight could enter.
Working against any unexpected image while curbing all uncer-
tainty, Hughes wanted to be ‘everywhere and nowhere, yesterday
and tomorrow, since all points of reference to astronomical space
or time were eliminated’.6
However, in all of Hughes’s rooms, were a movie screen, a projec-
tor and the controls that allowed him to screen his films, or, rather,
his film. For Hughes’s film, like his plate for eating, was nearly
always the same one: John Sturges’s Ice Station Zebra (1968), starring
Rock Hudson, a quite ordinary story of a race for a Russian satellite
that crashes close to the North Pole. Yet it was a story so gripping
for Hughes that he screened it to himself over 150 times.7 Hughes’s
obsession with Ice Station Zebra does not receive an explicit analysis
by Virilio. Nevertheless, Hughes’s fixation on this film is illustrative
of Virilio’s interest in Hughes’s twisted vision of unlit rooms and
the absence of light, of, in fact, Hughes’s yearning to be nowhere,
to be no longer able to be seen, or to be next to other people. For
Hughes, it was sufficient to appreciate that he had the ability to
go wherever he pleased and that people would be anticipating his
arrival when he got there. It is characteristic of the critique of the
art of technology that what Virilio invokes is a multiplicity of obses-
sions of this sort that lay bare the processes of distortion and dark-
ness, desire, disappearance, proximity and distance at work in any
critical assessments concerning the nature of visuality and space,
luminosity, nonexistence, inter-subjectivity and personal power. To
be sure, much of The Aesthetics of Disappearance is involved with the
questions raised for the critique of the art of technology by acts of
disappearance on the part of people such as Howard Hughes.
To Hughes, Ice Station Zebra was identical to the cars he pur-
chased, which were also indistinguishable. Indeed, he forever
bought the same type of Chevrolet because he considered it par-
ticularly commonplace. To Virilio, however, such films reveal not
so much Hughes’s nonconformist habits, his business and political
234
235
236
237
Conclusion
The analysis of the loss of the aesthetics of appearance is perhaps
the most important feature of the critique of the art of technology
and Virilio’s aesthetics of disappearance, particularly since the aes-
thetics of appearance is of enduring interest to many contemporary
critical theorists. The aesthetic belief in the need to bring about, to
make appear, a political revolution that will set in motion commu-
nism all over the world is frequently taken for granted by Marxist
critical theorists and, by the 1950s, Marxian-inflected critical theory
had productively initiated numerous extremely significant cultural
questions, artistic concerns and subjects for the development of an
aesthetics of appearance. The critique of the art of technology ques-
tions the disappearance of the aesthetics of appearance, and with it
many of our beliefs about what is taking place in the chaotic process
Virilio calls A Landscape of Events. In contrast to diverse Marxian
and materialist notions such as the importance of examining the
connection between social class, ideologies and aesthetic forms, of
particular cineastes and periodic cinematic styles and groups, for
instance, the French ‘New Wave’ group of filmmakers of the 1950s
and 1960s partly influenced by Italian ‘Neo-realism’ and classical
Hollywood, the critique of the art of technology is much more
interested in the impact of works of cinematic art on the built envi-
ronment and city planning. It is thus the ability of the landscape of
events and what Virilio brands The Information Bomb to further mili-
tarise science, to create cultural disarray and to launch ‘cyberwar’
on the general civilian population that concerns him rather than
the study of works of cinematic art as such.
Likewise, Virilio’s reaction to the aesthetics of the contemporary
city, in his Ground Zero, City of Panic and The Original Accident, and
similar to his reaction to disappearance, is pessimistic and involves,
for example, a consideration of the seemingly inexplicable motiva-
tions, actions and anonymity of those who initiated the September
11 2001 attacks on New York City and Washington DC. For such
anonymity, according to Virilio, ‘merely signals, for everyone, the
238
239
and Fear, Unknown Quantity, Art as Far as the Eye Can See and, most
recently, The University of Disaster, can only be understood as a kind
of death drive on the part of humankind. For, in Virilio’s blistering
contemporary works, art and science are portrayed as competing
with each other to obliterate humanity.
Yet the critique of the art of technology of Virilio’s Unknown
Quantity, for example, does not introduce an authoritative philo-
sophical position founded on the critique of contemporary immate-
rialism and the build-up of extremes of all sorts between the general
population and the ‘aesthetic’ if ruinous work of two World Wars
and half a century of the ‘balance of terror’. In fact, if the critique
of the art of technology introduces any philosophical standpoint,
it is that of a hyper-critical reaction to the contemporary creation
of major industrial accidents. While some contemporary critical
theorists may well be attracted to the critique of the art of technol-
ogy, others, however, are liable to remain unconvinced by Virilio’s
Art as Far as the Eye Can See, by its repudiation of our new media
world where the aesthetics of appearance and its materiality have
disappeared into the mediated aesthetics of disappearance, into
the immateriality of technology. In contrast, the critique of the art
of technology does provoke us to reflect on aesthetics, and chiefly
the politics of aesthetics, in an original manner; one concerning The
University of Disaster or the catastrophic potential of the contempo-
rary era where the arts are separating from artists and from their
materials, where the general population, aesthetics and cinema are,
as Virilio might have it, all in the clutches of the cultural devastation
caused by contemporary information, communication and surveil-
lance technologies.
Notes
1. See Paul Virilio and Sylvère Lotringer, Pure War (New York: Semiotexte,
2008), p. 192.
2. See Fredrick Ferré, Philosophy of Technology (Athens: University of
Georgia Press, 1995), pp. 54–7.
3. See Edmund Husserl, The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental
Phenomenology (Evanston: Northwestern Press, 1970); and Martin
Heidegger, The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays (New
York: Harper, 1977).
4. See Paul Virilio, Le Futurisme de l’instant: Stop-Eject (Paris: Galilée,
2009).
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
for instance, turns upon the thought that the Party had this sublime
political status. Class struggle in this society did not end, Žižek con-
tends, despite Stalinist propaganda. It was displaced ideologically,
from a struggle between two classes to one between the Party as rep-
resentative of the People (the Whole) and all who disagreed with
the Party, ideologically positioned as enemies of the people.
Žižek’s adaptation of the Lacanian, psychoanalytical account
of the way individuals become subject to social Law underpins his
observations concerning political ideologies. On this view, the civi-
lising of subjects is based in their founding sacrifice (castration) of
Jouissance, enacted in the name of sociopolitical Law. To the extent
that they are civilised, subjects are cut from the primal object of
their Jouissance (the maternal Thing). To be a subject is to have to
observe our societies’ linguistically mediated conventions, defer
satisfaction and accept sexual and generational difference in the
choice of sexual partners. According to Lacan, subjects’ fundamen-
tal fantasies are unconscious beliefs which allow them to accept the
traumatic loss involved in this founding sacrifice. They do this by
(falsely) renarrating this necessary loss as if it were an avoidable,
even political, situation that might be reversed, and by providing
subjects with a framework within which they can negotiate tick-
lish, Jouissance-provoking subjects like sexuality, cultural difference,
political conflict and mortality.
In his key notion of ideological fantasy, Žižek applies the psycho-
analytical notion of the fundamental fantasy shaping individuals’
identity to understanding political groups. Each political regime
has not only a body of more-or-less explicit, usually written, Laws
which demand that subjects forego Jouissance in the name of the
greater good – like the US or French constitutions. (Žižek identifies
this level of the Law with the Freudian ego ideal.) In order to truly
grip people, a regime’s explicit Laws must also harbour and conceal
a darker underside of more-or-less unspoken rules. Far from simply
repressing Jouissance, these unwritten norms implicate subjects in a
guilty, superegoic enjoyment in repression itself – for instance, in
prosecuting criminals, marginalising minorities or hating enemies.
Regimes’ ideological fantasies encode the open secrets of those
beliefs and practices which make Us who We are politically: the way
the sexes relate, the way authority truly operates behind pleasing
rhetoric about freedom and respect, the way we think ourselves
superior to others and so on.
The split in the Law, between the symbolic and fantasmatic
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
Notes
1. Žižek, Sublime Object of Ideology, Chapter 1.
2. ŽIžek, Tarrying with the Negative, p. 200.
3. Ibid.
4. Ibid. p. 66.
5. Žižek, ‘Kant with (or against) Sade’, in The Žižek Reader.
6. Žižek, Tarrying with the Negative, Chapter 1.
7. Ibid. p. 51.
8. See Justin Clemens, ‘The Politics of Style in the World of Slavoj Žižek’,
in Sherge, Glynos and Boucher (eds), Traversing the Fantasy, pp. 3–22;
Geoffrey Galt Harpham, ‘Doing the Impossible: Žižek and the End of
Knowledge’, Critical Inquiry, 29, 3, 2003, pp. 453–85.
9. See Paul Bowman, ‘The Tao of Žižek’, in Bowman and Stamp (eds),
The Truth of Žižek, pp. 27–44; Richard Stamp, ‘“Another Exemplary
Case”: Žižek’s Logic of Examples’, in Bowman and Stamp (eds), The
256
257
258
Abbey, Edward, 110–11, 112 Beauvoir, Simone de, 78, 80, 84,
Adorno, Theodor, 3 89
Agamben, Giorgio, 4Table 1.1, 4Table Beethoven, Ludwig van, 35
1.2, 5, 6, 7, 11, 12, 14–26, 243; see Benhabib, Seyla, 8
also subject index Benjamin, Walter, 6, 25, 141
Ahmad, Aijaz, 74 Bentham, Jeremy, 56, 113
Akrich, Madeleine, 161 Bergson, Henri, 107n19
Ali, Monica, 46 Bernard, Claude, 120
Althusser, Louis, 3, 4Table 1.1, 6, 95, Bhabha, Homi K., 4Table 1.1, 4Table
106n5, 147, 148, 194, 195, 245, 1.2, 5, 7, 11, 60–73; see also subject
246, 247, 250, 255 index
Anderson, Benedict, 70 Bhaduri, Bhubaneswari, 219
Arendt, Hannah, 3, 4Table 1.1, 6, 104, Botton, Alain de, 46
105, 155, 198, 201 Boucher, Geoff, 256
Aristotle, 6, 14, 30, 97–8, 103, 200–1, Bourdieu, Pierre, 3
202 Bové, Paul, 8, 9, 10
Arnold, David, 215 Braidotti, Rosi, 8, 139
Augé, Marc, 162 Brontë, Charlotte, 214
Austin, J. L., 78–9, 80, 81–2 Budiansky, Stephen, 122
Buffon, Georges Louis Leclerc, Comte
Bacon, Francis, 119–20 de, 19
Badiou, Alain, 4Table 1.1, 4Table 1.2, Burke, Edmund, 247
5, 6, 7, 11, 29–43, 100, 105, 207, Bush, George W., 251
255; see also subject index Butler, Judith, 4Table 1.1, 4Table 1.2, 5,
Barthes, Roland, 3 7, 11, 77–89, 101, 151, 158; see also
Baudrillard, Jean, 3 subject index
Bauman, Janina, 53, 55
Bauman, Zygmunt, 4Table 1.1, 4Table Callon, Michel, 161, 163
1.2, 5, 6, 7, 11, 45–58; see also Carlyle, Thomas, 56
subject index Castells, Manuel, 8
259
260
Husserl, Edmund, 3, 4Table 1.1, 6, 15, Marx, Karl, 3, 4Table 1.1, 6, 47–51, 56,
211, 228 131, 137, 145, 147, 148, 178, 179,
Hyppolite, Jean, 177, 191n 181, 183, 195, 201, 210, 215, 216,
219–20, 224, 228, 229, 243, 245,
Irigaray, Luce, 3, 4Table 1.1, 90n, 94 247, 255
Massumi, Brian, 8
Jakobson, Roman, 70 Maturana, Humberto, 100
Jameson, Fredric, 3 Mayhew, Henry, 56
Memmi, Albert, 60, 73
Kalyvas, Andrea, 105 Merchant, Carolyn, 120
Kant, Immanuel, 3, 4Table 1.1, 6, 14, Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, 6, 94, 101, 227
15, 97, 98, 220–1, 247, 248, 253 Mill, J. S., 115–16
Kapoor, Anish, 60 Miller, Jacques-Alain, 243
Kauffman, Stuart, 122 Minh-ha, Trin T., 8
Keynes, John Maynard, 56, 180 Mitchell, W. J. T., 62
Kripke, Saul, 243 Mohanty, Chandra Talpade, 224
Kristeva, Julia, 3, 4Table 1.1, 78, 90n Mol, Anne Marie, 161
Moore, Barrington, 51
La Mettrie, Julien Offray de, 111 More, Thomas, 48
Lacan, Jacques, 3, 4Table 1.1, 5, 6, 60, Morrison, Toni, 60
78, 97, 101, 103, 145, 148, 246, 256 Mouffe, Chantal, 4Table 1.1, 4Table
Laclau, Ernesto, 4Table 1.1, 4Table 1.2, 5, 7, 11, 144–51, 153–8
1.2, 5, 8, 11, 101, 144–58; see also
subject index Naess, Arne, 6, 116–19
Landry, Donna, 218 Naipaul, V. S., 60
Latour, Bruno, 4Table 1.1, 4Table 1.2, Nancy, Jean-Luc, 8
5, 6, 7, 8, 9, 12, 95, 161–8, 170–4; Negri, Antonio, 4Table 1.1, 4Table 1.2,
see also subject index 5, 7, 12, 70, 98; see also subject index
Law, John, 161, 163 Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm, 3,
Lawrence, D. H., 112 4Table 1.1, 25, 30, 42, 77, 93, 211
Lazzarato, Maurizio, 187
Lefort, Claude, 94 Oakeshott, Michael, 155
Lenin, Vladimir Ilyich, 6 Ong, Aiwa, 224
Leopardi, Giacomo, 183, 186
Leopold, Aldo, 122–3 Parent, Claude, 227
Lévi-Strauss, Claude, 3, 212, 213 Parry, Benita, 74, 218
Levinas, Emmanuel, 3, 18, 87 Pascal, Blaise, 246
Livingston, John, 110 Pasteur, Louis, 163, 164, 166, 167, 168
Lukács, Georg, 3 Paul, St (apostle), 25, 31, 39–42, 43,
Lyotard, Jean-François, 3, 27n, 94, 151 231
Pickering, Michael, 68
McClintock, Anne, 68 Plato, 6, 30, 196–7, 201, 202, 204, 207
Machiavelli, Nicolo, 183 Plumwood, Val, 121
MacKinnon, Catharine, 89, 136 Poulantzas, Nicos, 94
McLean, Gerald, 218
McQuillan, Martin, 9 Rancière, Jacques, 4Table 1.1, 4Table
Mallarmé, Stéphane, 34 1.2, 5, 6, 7, 8, 12, 194–207; see also
Marcuse, Herbert, 94, 115 subject index
261
262
actants, Latour’s views, 164, 165, 167, the animal, Agamben’s views, 16–17, 18
168–70, 173 animal welfare
Actor-Network Theory see ANT Rodman’s views, 113–14
actors (concept), Latour’s views, 164 Singer’s views, 112–13
Acts (concept), Žižek’s views, 255, 256 animal-rights activists, criticisms of
aesthetics Haraway, 139
Agamben’s views, 14 animality, Badiou’s views, 35–6
events in: Badiou’s views, 33 ANT
Haraway’s use, 134 and dualisms, 170–1, 171–2
Rancière’s views, 202–5, 206, 207 Latour’s views, 7, 12, 161, 163–8,
Virilio’s views, 230–3, 234, 235, 236, 170, 174
238 anthropocentrism, 120
Agamben, Giorgio, 14–15 anthropology, Haraway’s influence, 139
on death and humanity, 20–5 anti-Semitism, 45, 54
Homo Sacer, 4Table 1.2, 14, 26 appearance, aesthetics of: Virilio’s
Infancy and History: on language, 17; views, 238
and the transcendental, 15 arche-writing, Derrida’s concept,
Language and Death, 16, 18, 23 212–13
The Open, 18–19 Architecture Principe group, 227
Remnants of Auschwitz, 15, 22–4 Aristotelianism, Rancière’s views,
The State of Exception, 14, 24–5 200–1, 202
on time, 25–6 articulation, Laclau and Mouffe’s views,
agency, Latour’s views, 164–5, 166, 168 149
Althusserianism, Rancière’s views, 194, Asiatic Mode of Production (AMP),
195–6 Spivak’s views, 221–2
Ambassadors (Holbein), subjectivity in: asymmetry (concept), Negri’s views,
Žižek’s views, 254 178–9
AMP (Asiatic Mode of Production), Atlantic Wall, 227
Spivak’s views, 221–2 atonal music, as event: Badiou’s views,
androcentrism, 120 35
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
science sovereignty
attitudes to, 120 Agamben’s views, 20–1, 25
and critical theory, 6–7 Negri’s views, 183, 187
and ecosystems, 122 Schmitt’s views, 24–5
Haraway’s views, 128–30 Species-Life, and Species-Being:
Spinoza’s views, 185 Spivak’s views, 221–2
self, 15 Spectres of Marx (Derrida), Spivak’s
self-consciousness, gained through criticisms, 219
language: Agamben’s views, 16 speech
Self-realisation, Naess’s views, 118 Agamben’s views, 15
the sensible, partition of: Rancière’s Spivak’s views, 218
concept of, 201–5, 206 speech-acts, 80–1
sentience, 113, 121 Spivak, Gayatri Chakrovarty, 210–11,
set theory, Badiou’s use, 35, 37–8 224
sex A Critique of Postcolonial Reason, 220–2
green critical theoretical approaches Death of a Discipline, 222
to, 112 on deconstruction, 211–15, 217–18,
Haraway’s views, 136 223
sexuality, Butler’s views, 78–80, 84 on Marxism, 219–20
shallow ecology, Naess’s views, 116, ‘Responsibility’, 223
117, 118 ‘Righting Wrongs’, 222–3
Shoah, Agamben’s views, 15 on subalternity, 212, 215–19, 222–4
signification, Agamben’s views, 18 Stalinist ideology, Žižek’s views, 248–9
slowness, Bhabha’s views, 72 the state
the social, Laclau and Mouffe’s views, Butler’s views, 82–3
148–9 Negri’s views, 178, 179–80, 181–2
social categories, Haraway’s views, stereotypes, Bhabha’s views, 67, 68
128 structuralism, Castoriadis’s views, 95
social change, Castoriadis’s views, 94 student movement (May 1968),
social constructionism, and science: Rancière and Althusser’s reactions
Haraway’s views, 129 to, 195
social imaginary significations: Subaltern Studies collective, 215–17,
Castoriadis’s views, 96 218–19
socialism, Bauman’s concerns with, subalternity, Spivak’s views, 12, 212,
45 215–19, 222–4
Socialisme ou Barbarie, Castoriadis’s the subject, Castoriadis’s views, 103–4,
involvement with, 94 105–6
society subject, death: Castoriadis’s views, 93
Althusser’s views: used by Laclau and subjectivity
Mouffe, 147 Badiou’s views, 40
Castoriadis’s views, 95, 96–7 Haraway’s views, 137
civil society: Butler’s views, 83 Žižek’s views, 253–4, 255
industrial societies: morality, Singer’s subjects (members of the State)
views, 113 attitudes to ideologies: Marxist views,
sociology, Bauman’s concerns with, 244, 245; Žižek’s views, 245–6, 247,
45, 46 248, 250
South Asia, subalternity in, 215–16: the sublime
Spivak’s views, 222–3 Kant’s analysis, 221, 248
273
274
275