Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

Kyle V CCMA

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 33

IN THE LABOUR APPEAL COURT OF SOUTH AFRICA

(HELD AT JOHANNESBURG)

Case No.: CA10/08

KYLIE Appellant

and

COMMISSION FOR CONCILIATION,


MEDIATION AND ARBITRATION First Respondent
COMMISSIONER BELLA GOLDMAN Second Respondent
MICHELLE VAN ZYL t/a BRIGITTE’S Third Respondent

JUDGMENT:

DAVIS JA:

Introduction

[1] The appellant was a sex worker who was employed in a massage parlor

to perform various sexual services for a reward.1

[2] On 27 April 2006, appellant was informed that her employment was

terminated, apparently without a prior hearing, for a series of reasons

which are not essentially relevant to the present dispute. On 14 August

2006 the dispute was referred to arbitration which was set down to be

1
As the appellant wants her identity to be protected, she is cited as ‘Kylie’, a name by which she
was
known to the third respondent’s clientele.
2

heard on 13 September 2006. Before evidence could be heard, second

respondent enquired as to whether first respondent had jurisdiction to hear

the matter in the light of the fact that the appellant had been employed as

a sex worker and accordingly her employment was unlawful. On 11

December 2006, second respondent handed down a ruling in which she

concluded that first respondent did not have jurisdiction to arbitrate on an

unfair dismissal in a case of this nature. It was against this ruling that the

appellant approached the court a quo on review.

[3] Cheadle AJ held that the definition of employee in section 213 of the

Labour Relations Act 66 of 1995 (‘LRA’) was wide enough to include a

person whose contract of employment was unenforceable in terms of the

common law. However, he held that a sex worker was not entitled to

protection against unfair dismissal as provided in terms of section 185 (a)

of the LRA because it would be contrary to a common law principle which

had become entrenched in the Republic of South Africa Constitution Act

108 of 1996 (‘the Constitution’) that courts ‘ought not to sanction or

encourage illegal activity’.

[4] In order to fully analyse the submissions made on behalf of appellant 2 by

Mr Trengove, who appeared together with Mr Kahanovitz, Ms Cowen and

Ms Mji, it is necessary to analyse the precise reasoning employed by

Cheadle AJ more comprehensively.


2
There was no representation on behalf of any of the respondents.
3

The judgment of the court a quo

[5] As noted, Cheadle AJ defined the essential question as whether ‘as a

matter of public policy, courts (and tribunals) by their actions ought to

sanction or encourage illegal conduct in the context of statutory and

constitutional rights’.

[6] Cheadle AJ then referred to the Sexual Offences Act 23 of 1957 (‘the Act’)

which makes brothel keeping a criminal offence and which defines the

concept of a brothel to include persons who reside in a brothel and share

in any monies taken there. Section 3(a) and (c). In terms of section

20(1) (A) (a) of the Act, unlawful carnal intercourse for reward constitutes

a criminal offence which attracts a criminal penalty of imprisonment of no

more than three years and a fine of no more than R6000.

[7] On this basis, Cheadle AJ invoked the principle ex turpi causa non oritur

actio which ‘prohibits the enforcement of immoral or illegal contracts’.

Thus, if a contract is illegal, courts must regard the contract as void and

hence unenforceable. In turn, a contract is illegal if it is contrary to public

policy and it is against public policy to engage in a contract which is

contrary to law or morality. Citing Christie The Law of Contract in South

Africa (5ed) at 382, Cheadle AJ noted that courts regarded adultery and

commercial sex as immoral and of such turpitude so as to render an


4

agreement concerning or linked to such morality as void and thus

unenforceable.

[8] Turning to the implications of a statutory prohibition and to the application

of the ex turpi causa rule, Cheadle AJ found that the rule applies, if a

statute properly interpreted, intends to nullify a contract arising from or

associated with a legally prohibited activity. While the corollary to the ex

turpi causa rule, the in pari delicto rule, does, on occasion, relax the

former rule, that relaxation does not compromise the underlying policy of

discouraging illegality of contractual relationships. As the court stated in

Jajbhay v Cassiem 1937 AD 539, the relaxation is only justified if there are

claims of simple justice between individuals of which account must be

taken and if public policy is ‘not foreseeably affected by a grant or a

refusal of the relief claimed’. at 545.

[9] Applying this dictum to the provisions of the Act, Cheadle AJ concluded

that the language which was employed in the statute clearly supports the

conclusion that a contravention of a prohibition of the Act results in the

nullifying of a contract made in pursuit of or which is associated with the

prohibition.

[10] For Cheadle AJ the question therefore arose, on the basis of this finding,

as to whether, notwithstanding the invalidity of the contractual


5

relationship , section 23 of Constitution affected the conclusion of the court

a quo , being a finding which was clearly adverse to the appellant. The

question can be phrased thus: Does a constitutional protection of fair

labour practices as enshrined in section 23 of the Constitution apply to a

person who would, but for an engagement in illegal employment, enjoy the

benefits of this constitutional right. That question was answered in the

negative by the court a quo, primarily because, were such rights to be

granted, a court would undermine a fundamental constitutional value of

the rule of law by sanctioning or encouraging legally prohibited activity. In

the view of the learned judge in the court a quo, that conclusion was

supported by the Constitutional Court in its decision in S v Jordan and

others 2002 (6) SA 642 (CC) at para 28 ff.

[11] The court a quo further bolstered its approach by examining the nature of

dismissal legislation. In terms of section 193 (2) of the LRA, in the case

of an unfair dismissal the primary remedy is reinstatement or

reemployment. In the view of Cheadle AJ:

“Nothing illustrates the conflict of the objective of the right to a fair

dismissal and the objecting of the Sexual Offences Act more than

the issue of reinstatement. An order of reinstatement is the

primary remedy for an unfair dismissal. Reinstating a person in

illegal employment would not only sanction illegal activity but may

constitute an order on the employer to commit a crime.”


6

[12] Cheadle AJ then engaged in an alternative analysis, on the assumption

that section 23 of the Constitution does afford constitutional protection to

the appellant. He concluded that, in such a case, the Act constituted a

justifiable limitation upon the section 23 sourced constitutional rights of

appellant, essentially because the limitation ‘gives effect to the

fundamental rule of law principle: courts should not by their actions

sanction or encourage illegal activity’.

[13] So much for the essential reasoning employed by Cheadle AJ in the court

a quo. I turn now to deal with the primary submissions of appellant.

Appellant’s Case

[14] Mr Trengove attacked the reasoning as adopted by Cheadle AJ in the

court a quo. In his view, instead of starting with a discussion of public

policy as divined from the law of contract, the proper approach was to

commence with the Constitution and in particular, whether, in principle, a

person such as appellant, enjoyed constitutional rights in general and

specifically those rights set out in section 23. Only if the question of the

application of the Constitution to this dispute was answered in favour of

the appellant, was the court then required to proceed to examine issues

relating to the appropriate remedy. In Mr Trengove’s view, it is at this

stage that concerns of public policy become applicable.


7

[15] The question of the application of the Constitution thus becomes the

starting point for appellant’s argument. Thereafter, Mr Trengove

contended that the LRA must be read so as to implement section 23 of the

Constitution, a point reiterated recently by Ngcobo J (as he then was) in

Chirwa v Transnet 2008 (4) SA 367 (CC) at para 110:

“The objects of the LRA are not just textual aides to be employed

where the language is ambiguous. This is apparent from the

interpretive injunction in section 3 of the LRA which requires

anyone applying the LRA to give effect to its primary objects and

the Constitution. The primary objects of the LRA must inform the

interpretive process and the provisions of the LRA must be read in

the light of its objects. Thus where a provision of the LRA is

capable of more than one plausible interpretation, one which

advances the objects of the LRA and the other which does not, a

court must prefer the one which will effectuate the primary objects

of the LRA.”

For this reason therefore, since the present dispute is predicated on the

application of the LRA, it is necessary to commence with the source of the

LRA, that is to engage in an examination of the application of section

23(1) of the Constitution to the present dispute.


8

The scope of the section 23 right

[16] Section 23(1) provides that ‘everyone has the right to fair labour practices’.

The term ‘everyone’, which follows the wording of section 7(1) of the

Constitution which provides that the Bill of Rights enshrines the right ‘of all

people in the country’, is supportive of an extremely broad approach to the

scope of the right guaranteed in the Constitution.

[17] This point was confirmed by Ngcobo J (as he then was) in Khosa v

Minister of Social Development 2004 (6) SA 505 (CC) para 111:

“The word ‘everyone’ is a term of general import and unrestricted

meaning. It means what it conveys. Once the state puts in place

a social welfare system, everyone has a right to have access to

that system.”

[18] From its inception, the Constitutional Court has been consistent in this

approach. In S v Makwanyane 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC) at para 137

Chaskalson P (as he then was) said that the right to life and dignity ‘vests

in every person, including criminals convicted of vile crimes’. The learned

president went on to say that these criminals ‘do not forfeit their rights

under the Constitution and are entitled, as all in our country now are, to

assert these rights, including the right to life, the right to dignity and the

right not to be subjected to cruel, inhuman or degrading punishment’.


9

[19] This affirmation of protection of a very broad constituency of persons is

not undermined by the finding in S v Jordan supra. In their minority

judgment, O’Regan and Sachs JJ (a point not contradicted in the majority

judgment) observe at para 74:

“The very character of the work they undertake devalues the

respect that the Constitution regards as inherent in the human

body. This is not to say that as prostitutes they are stripped of the

right to be treated with respect by law enforcement officers. All

arrested and accused persons must be treated with dignity by the

police. But any invasion of dignity, going beyond that ordinarily

implied by an arrest or charge that occurs in the course of arrest of

incarceration cannot be attributed to section 20(1A)(a) but rather to

the manner in which it is being enforced. The remedy is not to

strike down the law but to require that it be applied in a

constitutional manner. Neither are prostitutes stripped of the right

to be treated with dignity by their customers. The fact that a client

pays for sexual services does not afford the client unlimited license

to infringe the dignity of the prostitute.”

[20] This dictum affords support for Mr Trengove’s argument that the illegal

activity of a sex worker does not per se prevent the latter from enjoying a

range of constitutional rights. By contrast, the test is rather what

constitutional protections are necessarily removed from a sex worker,


10

given the express criminal prohibition of their employment activities in

terms of the Act.

[21] The question arises thus as to whether section 23 affords protection to a

sex worker. In Nehawu v UCT (2003) 24 ILJ 95 (CC) at para 40 the

Constitutional Court emphasised that the focus of section 23(1) of the

Constitution was on the ‘relationship between the worker and the

employer and the continuation of that relationship on terms that are fair to

both’. That approach followed upon the judgment in SANDU v Minister of

Defense (1999) 20 ILJ 2265 (CC) at paras 28 – 30. Even if a person is

not employed under a contract of employment, that does not deny the

‘employee’ all constitutional protection. This conclusion is reached

despite the fact they ‘may not be employees in the full contractual sense

of the word’ but because their employment ‘in many respects mirrors

those of people employed under a contract of employment’.

[22] Once it is accepted that the constitutional right to fair labour practices

vests in ‘everyone’ and, further that it includes not only parties to a

contract of employment but those persons in an employment relationship,

Mr Trengove’s submission, to the effect that persons, who engage in

services pursuant to an employment relationship such as appellant, are

covered by section 23, becomes particularly compelling.


11

[23] That conclusion is also supported by two decisions of the Labour Appeal

Court in which this Court ‘approached the vexed question of employment

relationship on the basis of the substance of the arrangements between

the parties as opposed to the legal form so adopted’. State Information

Technology Agency (Pty) Limited v CCMA (2008) 29 ILJ 2234 (LAC) at

para 10.

[24] In Denel (Pty) Ltd v Gerber (2005) 26 ILJ 1256 (LAC), Zondo JP, after a

meticulous examination of comparative and local authorities, said at para

94:

“I am unable to agree with the approach adopted by the Industrial

Court in Callanan, by this court in Briggs and by Lord Denning MR

and Lord Justice Lawton in Massey’s case and Lord Justice Lawton

in Ferguson’s case which, it seems to me, is to the effect that, once

it is found that the alleged employee voluntarily made an

arrangement in terms of which he or she would not be ‘an

employee’ of the alleged employer but would not be ‘an employee’

of the alleged employer but would be an ‘employee’ of his or her

own company or close corporation which would provide services to

the alleged employer, he cannot later be found to have been an

employee of the company with which his or her own had an

agreement to provide services. As I have indicated above already,

the main weakness of that approach is that it disregards the


12

realities of the relationship between the parties and is open to

abuse because it makes it possible for two persons to take

themselves out of the reach of such important legislation as the Act

and the Basic Conditions of Employment Act 75 1997.”

[25] Taken together these arguments support a generous approach to the

range of beneficiaries of rights provided for in terms of section 23(1). In

turn, this conclusion is supported by the minority judgment of O’Regan

and Sachs JJ when they note that sex workers are not stripped of the right

to be treated with dignity by their customer. By logical extension, this

should also mean that their employers incur a similar obligation.

[26] In summary, as sex workers cannot be stripped of the right to be treated

with dignity by their clients, it must follow that, in their other relationship

namely with their employers, the same protection should hold. Once it is

recognised that they must be treated with dignity not only by their

customers but by their employers, section 23 of the Constitution ,which, at

its core, protects the dignity of those in an employment relationship,

should also be of application.

[27] Professor Rochelle Le Roux expresses the point as follows:

“[it is] also important to bear in mind the fact that the unfair labour

practice jurisdiction was introduced to counter the arbitrariness of


13

lawfulness, in particular, termination by lawful notice.

Furthermore, as suggested earlier, it is conceivable that a labour

practice may well impact on the position of either prospective or

retired employees. For these reasons, and in absence of an

internal limitation clause, it is suggested that labour practices in s

23(1) ought to be approached dispassionately and be given a

broad construction. An act of terminating employment, the

structuring of working hours, or discipline at work remain labour

practices, irrespective of whether they are done in the context of

legal or illegal work.”

See R. Le Roux “The meaning of ‘worker’ and the road towards

diversification: Reflecting on Discovery, SITA and ‘Kylie’” 2009 (30) ILJ 49

at 58.

[28] In my view, appellant meets the threshold requirement so that she is a

beneficiary of the applicable constitutional rights. The enquiry now turns

to whether she is entitled to any legal relief.

The question of relief

[29] In refusing to recognise the possibility of a remedy in terms of the LRA,

Cheadle AJ based his decision on the view that the legislature intended

that the Act not only penalised prohibited activity but precluded courts

from recognising any rights or claims arising from that activity. In terms of
14

his approach, were a court to recognise a claim based on ‘a constitutional

right’, that court would be sanctioning or encouraging the prohibited

activity’. Whereas foreign and child workers, who are prohibited from

assuming certain forms of employment, can be afforded protection

because the prohibition is aimed at ‘who does the job rather than the job

itself’, the prohibition with regard to sex work concerns the nature of the

job. Even though they are vulnerable to exploitation, such protection ‘will

mean sanctioning and encouraging activities that the legislature has

constitutionally decided should be prohibited’.

Evaluation

[30] It is now possible to evaluate this part of the court a quo’s judgment. To

recapitulate: the foundational propositions upon which the judgment of the

court a quo can be summarized thus:

1. There is a common law principle that courts ought not to sanction

or encourage illegal activity;

2. This principle is now incorporated within the Constitution,

entrenched as an element of the rule of law, and set out in section

1 of the Constitution;

3. As a constitutional imperative, the statutory rights are trumped

which ‘renders a sex worker’s claim to statutory right to fair

dismissal and LRA unenforceable.’


15

[31] Mr Trengove submitted that these propositions were all palpably wrong.

The common law principle was more limited in its scope and more

qualified in its application than had been held to be the case by the court a

quo. Furthermore, the common law principle was not entrenched in the

Constitution and accordingly, as a principle of common law, did not

automatically trump those protections afforded by the Constitution,

including section 23(1) thereof and any legislative implementation thereof,

including section 185(a) of the LRA.

[32] In general, South African law takes the view that an illegal contract is void

and that the illegality arises when a contract’s conclusion, performance or

object is expressly or impliedly prohibited by legislation or is contrary to

good morals or public policy. Macqueen and Cockrell ‘Illegal Contracts’ in

Zimmermann et al Mixed Legal Systems in Comparative Perspective 143

at 144. In this connection, a comment made more than seventy years

ago by Aquilius (1941) 58 SALJ 344 is of particular significance: ‘in a

sense … all illegalities may be said to be moral and all immorality and

illegality contrary to public policy’.

[33] This approach was later reflected by Smalberger JA in Sasfin (Pty) Ltd v

Beukes 1989 (1) SA 1(A) at 8F as follows:

“That the principles underlying contracts contrary to public policy

and contra bones mores may overlap also appears from the
16

judgment of this court in Ismail v Ismail … These classifications

may not be of importance in principle, for where a court refuses to

enforce a contract it ultimately so decides on the basis of public

policy.”

[34] Whatever the justification for refusing to enforce the terms or obligations

which flow from an illegal contract, in South African law this position has

ossified into an absolute rule so that courts will not assist a person who

has entered into an illegal contract to so enforce this contract. While the

court possesses a certain amount of discretion to determine whether a

contract is illegal, once it has so determined it follows ‘as a necessary and

inflexible consequence that no action could be based thereon’ Macqueen

and Cockrell at 163. Generally, where performance had been made in

terms of an illegal contract, a court will also not assist a party who has

performed to recover his or her performance by the use of an enrichment

based remedy. However, the courts have acknowledged that they have

an equitable discretion to relax the operation of the so called par delictum

rule in order to allow one party to utilise an enrichment based remedy, an

approach which is sourced back to Jajbhay v Cassiem 1939 AD 537. In

this case, the Appellate Division held that the court should relax the rule if

it was necessary ‘to prevent injustice or to satisfy the requirements of

public policy’ at 558. See more recently, Henry v Brandfield 1996 (1) SA

244 (D) at 252 – 253.


17

[35] In examining this approach Macqueen and Cockrell write at 165:

“In determining whether to exercise this discretion, the South

African courts purport to secure ‘the doing of simple justice

between man and man’. Such an approach allows for a nuanced

and context – sensitive consideration of all relevant factors.”

[36] The point that emerges from these dicta is that our law is not wholly

inflexible in its refusal to relax the par delictum rule. As Professor Visser

Unjustified Enrichment at 447 writes:

“No hard and fast criteria had been laid down to judge when the

rule should be relaxed and each case will have to be determined

according to its peculiar circumstances.”

Professor Zimmermann The Law of Obligations at 847 provides historical

support for this approach:

“The Roman jurist did not seem to have hesitated to evaluate and

compare the degree of turpitude of both parties involved in the

transaction and decide in favour of the party who is less to blame.”

[37] Not only does the par delictum rule reflect a manifestation of public policy

to guide the courts in the interpretation, application and development of

the law, but contrary to the approach adopted by the court a quo, the

determination as to whether the par delictum rule is inflexibly enforced in

all circumstances depends upon public policy, ultimately sourced in the


18

Constitution. This conclusion is to be contrasted with the approach that

the Constitution has encapsulated within it so inflexible an approach to the

par delictum rule that a court is disempowered from exercising a discretion

in favour of a party so as to prevent manifest injustice. See also

Brummer v Gorfil Brother Investments (Pty) Limited en andere 1999 (3)

SA 389 (SCA) at 403 B – G.

[38] I return to the key question: what discretion do the courts have in the

determination of a remedy, in this case for an alleged unfair dismissal of a

sex worker. Mr Trengove correctly noted that, while South African law

eschewed the recognition of an illegal contract and the obligations and

rights that flowed therefrom, in this case appellant’s contention was that,

even if there was no valid contract, there was an employment relationship

and in terms of that relationship, the appellant fell within the scope of the

LRA. Accordingly, the question arose as to whether a court could, in the

light of the existing approach to illegal contracts, provide some remedy to

a party, such as appellant, if she could prove her allegation that she had

been unfairly treated within the framework of the unfair labour practice

jurisprudence guaranteed in terms of section 23(1) of the Constitution and

enshrined in the LRA.

[39] That enquiry is not necessarily incongruent with the finding in Jordan’s

supra, that the Act which criminalises prostitution is constitutional. As


19

noted, the criminalisation of prostitution does not necessarily deny to a sex

worker the protection of the Constitution and, in particular section 23(1)

thereof, and by extension its legislative implementation in the form of the

LRA.

[40] The express purpose of the LRA ‘is to advance economic development,

social justice, labour, peace and the democratisation of the work place’

Section 1 of the LRA. In itself, this set of principles can be traced to

section 23 of the Constitution. In particular, section 23(1), which provides

that everyone has the right to fair labour practices, was designed to

ensure that the dignity of all workers should be respected and that the

workplace should be predicated upon principles of social justice, fairness

and respect for all. See Nehawu v UCT 2003 (2) BCLR 154 (CC) at

paras 33 – 40.

[41] If the purpose of the LRA was to achieve these noble goals, then courts

have to be at their most vigilant to safeguard those employees who are

particularly vulnerable to exploitation in that they are inherently

economically and socially weaker than their employers. Mr Trengove

urged that this consideration applied with even greater force in the case of

sex workers who are an especially vulnerable class exposed to

exploitation and abuse by a range of people with whom they interact,

including their employers. In this connection, he referred to the United


20

Nations General Assembly Declaration on the Elimination of

Discrimination against Women which expressly condemns the exploitation

of prostitution of women. In addition paragraph 5 of the ILO’s

Employment Relationship Recommendation R198 of 15 June 2006

requires member states to take particular account in national policy of the

need to ensure the effective protection of workers ‘especially those

affected by the uncertainty as to the existence of an employment

relationship, including women workers, as well as the most vulnerable

workers, young workers, older workers, workers in the informal economy,

migrant workers and workers with disabilities.’

[42] There is a considerable debate within the feminist literature as to whether

prostitution invariably entails an inherent element of coercion, exploitation

and domination. Pro-sex feminists, for example, contend that sex work

can be a positive experience for women who employ their autonomy to

make an informed decision to engage in prostitution. See for contrasting

perspectives, Catherine Mackinnon 1993 Michigan Journal of Gender and

Law; Laurie Schrage Moral dilemmas of Feminist: Prostitution, Adultery

and Abortion (1994); and Maggie O’Neil Prostitution Feminism (2001).

[43] This debate notwithstanding, when viewed within the South African

context, many sex workers are particularly vulnerable and are exposed to

exploitation and vicious abuse. It may be that this categorisation is not


21

applicable to all cases of sex workers but there is, at the very least, a

prima facie case that the appellant falls within such a vulnerable category.

This case is made out in the papers, which have been placed before the

court. On these papers, it appears that appellant worked 14 hours a day,

7 days a week and was subjected to a strict regime of rules and fines,

practices which in the ordinary course were curtailed by the Basic

Conditions of Employment Act 75 of 1997.

[44] In the circumstances, where a sex worker forms part of a vulnerable class

by the nature of the work that she performs and the position that she holds

and she is subject to potential exploitation, abuse and assaults on her

dignity, there is, on the basis of the finding in this judgment, no principled

reason by which she should not be entitled to some constitutional

protection designed to protect her dignity and which protection by

extension has now been operationalised in the LRA.

[45] These considerations are supported by authority dealing with the legal

implications of an act which is void ab initio as a result of a contravention

of legislation. De Ville Constitutional and Statutory Interpretation (2000)

at 261 writes about whether a sanction imposed is ‘sufficient punishment’

for non compliance with a statutory provision that ‘it needs to be asked

whether the purpose of the legislation will be achieved by invalidating the

action concerned or whether the imposition of the (penal) sanction will


22

suffice in attaining this purpose’. See for example Pottie v Kotze 1954 (3)

SA 719 (A). In Kuhne and Nagel (Pty) Ltd v Elias and another 1979 (1) SA

131 (T) at 133 the following passage from Boshoff AJP is instructive:

“The use of the word “shall” and the word “moet” in the Afrikaans

version is a strong indication, in the absence of considerations

pointing to another conclusion, that the Legislature is issuing a

statutory command and intends disobedience to be visited with

nullity. See Sutter v Scheepers 1932 AD 165 at 173. In the last-

mentioned case, Wessels JA suggested certain useful guides,

which were not intended to be exhaustive, to test whether

provisions are peremptory or directory:

“If a provision is couched in a negative form it is to be regarded as

peremptory rather than as a directory mandate, but this is not

conclusive.

If a provision is couched in positive language and there is no

sanction added in case the requisites are not carried out, then the

presumption is in favour of an intention to make the provision only

directory.

If, on a consideration of the scope and objects of the provision, it

is found that its terms would, if strictly carried out, lead to injustice,

and even fraud, and if there is no explicit statement that the act is

to be void if the terms are not complied with, or if no sanction is

added, then the presumption is rather in favour of the provision

being directory.””
23

[46] What these dicta reveal is that courts have not always employed the

inflexible approach adopted by Cheadle AJ to illegal transactions but have

, on occasion , considered whether to refuse to recognise any implication

of an illegal act after an inquiry into the purpose of the criminalizing statute

and the effect of the prohibition. In this case, the court is asked to

consider the impact of a broad based constitutional protection and the

preservation of the dignity of vulnerable persons in so exercising a

discretion to decide that such an employment relationship holds some

implications for the parties to the relationship.

The case of Hoffman Plastics Inc v NLRA; 53545 137 (2002)

[47] The need to interrogate the purpose of legislation that is contravened by a

contract or an employment relationship and the ideological implications of

a decision are well illustrated by the judgments in this case. This case

invoked the payment of backpay to a dismissed worker who had not

complied with US immigration laws and was thus classified as an

‘undocumented worker’. Chief Justice Rehnquist, who wrote the majority

opinion, drew an analogy between employees who worked without

immigration authorization and employees who were ineligible for

reinstatement or backpay because, they have ‘committed serious criminal

acts’, such as trespass or violence against the employers property.


24

[48] The majority then went on to say that backpay award could undermine a

‘federal statute or policy outside of the competence’ of the National Labour

Relations Board, in this case immigration laws. The majority

characterized the dismissed employee’s conduct in completing the

relevant immigration laws as ‘criminal’ and hence awarding backpay would

condone and encourage future violations of the relevant immigration laws.

[49] Justice Breyer, who dissented with three other justices, held that an award

of backpay is consistent with labour law and immigration policy as it would

help to deter unlawful activity that both labour and immigration laws seek

to prevent. Further, the dismissal of the employee was motivated by the

employer’s anti-union conduct and not by the employee’s own conduct.

[50] With due respect to the majority of the Supreme Court, much of their

jurisprudence can be described as being significantly incongruent with our

Constitution’s commitment to freedom , equality and dignity and its

concern to protect the vulnerable, exploited and powerless. The

Constitution reflects the long history of brutal exploitation of the politically

weak, economically vulnerable and socially exploited during three hundred

years of racist and sexist rule. The text represents a majestic assertion of

the possibility of the construction of a community of concern, compassion

and restitution for all such segments of the South African community.
25

[51] By contrast, the more enlightened minority opinion in Hoffman Plastics

illustrates two key points for the purposes of this dispute: the need to

interrogate the nature of the competing legal regimes, in this case labour

law and the regime set out in the Act. Secondly, the basis of the conduct

which triggers the relief sought, in this case allegations of employer

misconduct, are not strictly connected to the prohibitions contained in the

Act.

Summation

[52] These consideration do not mean that the full range of remedies available

in terms of the LRA should necessarily be available in every such case.

Expressed differently, this judgment does not hold that, when a sex worker

has been unfairly dismissed, first respondent or a court should or can

order her reinstatement, which would manifestly be in violation of the

provisions of the Act. But section 193 of the LRA provides for

considerable flexibility to first respondent or a court. For example,

although a arbitrator or court should require the employer to reinstate or

reemploy an employee on a finding that a dismissal is unfair, the court or

arbitrator has a discretion to refuse reinstatement where it is not

reasonably practicable for the employer to reinstate or reemploy the

employee. Manifestly, it would be against public policy to reinstate an

‘employee’ such as appellant in her employ even if she has could show,

on the evidence, that her dismissal was unfair. But, that conclusion
26

should not constitute an absolute prohibition to, at least, some protection

provided under the LRA, a protection which can reduce her vulnerability,

exploitation and the erosion of her dignity.

[53] For similar reasons it may well be that compensation for a substantively

unfair dismissal would be inappropriate in the present kind of case. If

compensation for substantive unfairness is to be regarded as a monetary

equivalent for the loss of employment, it may be, although given the

precise relief sought I express no final view, that such compensation

would be inappropriate in a case where the nature of the services

rendered by the dismissed employee are illegal. By contrast, monetary

compensation for a procedurally unfair dismissal has been treated as a

solatium for the loss by an employee of her right to a fair procedure.

Johnson & Johnson (Pty) Ltd v CWIU (1999) 20 ILJ 89 (LAC) at para 41.

This kind of compensation is therefore independent of the loss of illegal

employment in this case and would therefore appear to be applicable in

the appropriate case where the services rendered by the employee are

classified as illegal.

Conclusion

[54] It is important to emphasise the precise findings of this judgment and what

this judgment does not so hold. This judgment cannot and does not

sanction sex work. That is a matter for the legislature. It may be that
27

the Law Reform Commission’s investigation into adult prostitution will

have a significant effect upon a legislative solution to the variety of

difficulties raised by sex work and this case. However, the fact that

prostitution is rendered illegal does not, for the reasons advanced in this

judgment, destroy all the constitutional protection which may be enjoyed

by someone as appellant, were they not to be a sex worker. The

approach adopted by Corbett JA (as he then was) in Goldberg and others

v Minister of Prisons 1979 (1) SA 14 (A) which is sourced in our common

law is equally applicable:

“[f]undamentally a convicted and sentenced prisoner retains all the

basic rights and liberties (using the word in its Hohfeldinn sense )

of an ordinary citizen except those taken away from him by law

expressly or by implication, or those necessarily inconsistent with

the circumstances in which he, as a prisoner, is placed.” at 39

This point was reinforced by the Constitutional Court in Minister of Home

Affairs v NICRO 2005 (3) SA 280 (CC) at para 58 where Chaskalson CJ

cited the following passage from the judgment of Gonthier J in Sauvé v

Canada (Chief Electoral Officer) [1993] 2 SCR 438:

“When the façade and rhetoric is stripped away, little is left of the

government’s claim about punishment other than that criminals are

people who have broken society’s norms and may therefore be

denounced and punished as the government sees fit, even to the

point of removing fundamental constitutional rights. Yet, the right


28

to punish and to denounce, however important, is constitutionally

constrained. It cannot be used to write entire rights out of the

Constitution, it cannot be arbitrary, and it must serve the

constitutionally recognised goal of sentencing.”

In other words, only those rights which are necessary for the

implementation of the provisions of the Act are to be removed from the

enjoyment of appellant. Her dignity is not to be exploited or abused.

This remains intact and the concomitant constitutional protection must be

available to her as it would to any person whose dignity is attacked

unfairly. By extension from section 23(1), the LRA ensures that an

employer respects these rights within the context of an employment

relationship. Expressed differently, public policy based on the

foundational values of the Constitution does not deem it necessary that

these rights be taken away from appellant for the purposes of the Act to

be properly implemented.

[55] Accordingly, while the remedial issues must be tailored to meet the

specific context of this case, the objects and provisions of the Act, the

illegality of the work performed, there is for the reasons articulated above,

nothing which indicates that no form of protection in terms of section 193

of the LRA should be available to someone such as appellant who was

unfairly treated within the context of the provisions of LRA.


29

[56] When it comes to the question of remedy, each case will have to be

decided in terms of the facts thereof. Manifestly, not all persons who are

in an employment relationship which is prohibited by law will enjoy a

remedy in terms of the LRA. In so deciding, a tribunal or court is

engaged with the weighing of principles; on the one hand the ex turpi

causa rule which prohibits enforcement of illegal contracts and on the

other public policy sourced in the values of the Constitution, which, in this

context, promotes a society based on freedom, equality and dignity and

hence care, compassion and respect for all members of the community.

The ex turpi causa rule is, as is evident from its implementation by the

courts, a principle of law for it guides rather than dictates a single result.

The public policy considerations mentioned in this judgment have

developed from those set out almost 75 years ago in Jaibday v Cassim

but which now find definitive guidance in the Constitution (Barkhuizen v

Napier 2007 (7) BCLR 671 (CC)) must be weighed against the principle of

ex turpi causa to determine the outcome.

[57] As Ronald Dworkin wrote in Taking Rights Seriously (1977), principles do

not produce ‘all or nothing’ answers; their impact depends on the weight to

be accorded to each competing principles. For this reason, cases

involving employment relationships which are in breach of legislation, such

as the present dispute, should proceed through the constitutional

threshold but not all will enjoy the defining weight of public policy, as set
30

out, so as to justify the granting of a remedy. The weighing process

however concerns questions which must be decided after the enquiry at

the jurisdictional stage. This dispute concerns access through threshold

which a party, such appellant, must proceed in order that it may be

properly determined whether any relief should be granted. That is all that

was required for a determination in the case before this Court.

[58] At the hearing, the court raised the question of the consequences for

organizational rights of classifying workers, who are engaged in illegal

work, as employees for the purposes of the LRA. In particular, the

question focused upon the implication that a positive finding for appellant,

namely that she is an employee for the purposes of the LRA, might have

regarding trade union formation; that is a finding that, as employees, sex

workers would be entitled to form and join a trade union. However, even

if these workers could form or join a trade union, they could not assert any

right to participate in any unlawful activities through such a trade union

nor could they use the vehicle of the union to further the commission of a

crime. In short, it is only by way of lawful activities of a trade union that

employees are entitled to exercise this organizational right. This

conclusion follows upon the approach adopted in this judgment as to the

clear limitations which flow from the finding that appellant is an

employee for the purposes of the LRA. In addition, the Registrar of

Labour Relations is vested with a discretion in terms of the LRA to refuse


31

to register a trade union. Thus, if a trade union is formed to further the

commission of crime, the Registrar would be entitled to refuse to register

it.

[59] Even though appellant is an employee for the purposes of section 185 of

the LRA, this does not mean that collective agreements purportedly

concluded between brothels and sex worker unions which amount to the

commission of crime or the furtherance of the commission of a crime are

enforceable under the LRA nor does it imply that sex worker unions would

be entitled to exercise organisational rights, including the right to strike to

that end.

[60] On the contrary, although sex workers would, as employees, be entitled to

form and join trade unions, they would not be entitled to participate in any

activities, including collective bargaining, that amounted to the furthering

of the commission of crime.

Order

[61] For these reasons therefore, the following order is made:

1. The appeal is upheld.

2. The order of the Labour Court is set aside and replaced with an

order in the following terms


32

2.1 The jurisdiction ruling of the second respondent of 11

December 2006 is reviewed and set aside.

2.2 The CCMA has jurisdiction to determine the dispute between

the parties in the present case.

_____________

DAVIS JA

I agree

____________

ZONDO JP

I agree

_____________

JAPPIE JA
33

You might also like