Dworkin's Theory of Rights - LEHR - Final
Dworkin's Theory of Rights - LEHR - Final
Dworkin's Theory of Rights - LEHR - Final
ABSTRACT: There is probably no conceptualisation of rights more famous than Ronald Dworkin’s
claim that they are ‘trumps’. This seems to stand in stark contrast to the dominant, proportionality-
based strand of rights discourse, according to which rights, instead of trumping competing interests,
ultimately have to be balanced against them. The goal of this article is to reconcile Dworkin’s work
and proportionality and thereby make a contribution to our understanding of both. It offers a critical
reconstruction of Dworkin’s theory of rights which does away with the misleading label of rights as
‘trumps’ and shows that, far from being in conflict with proportionality, properly understood
Dworkin’s work supports and supplements that doctrine and provides a much-needed account of its
1Associate Professor of Law, Department of Law, London School of Economics and Political Science. I
would like to thank Jurriën Hamer, Ester Herlin Karnell, Mattias Kumm, Dimitrios Kyritsis, Iddo
Porat, Gila Stopler, and Samuel Tschorne for their valuable comments and suggestions. Various
versions of this paper were presented at the Law Faculty Seminar Series at Utrecht University and the
Free University of Amsterdam, the Public Law Theory Seminar Series at Humboldt University Berlin,
and the Berlin Colloquium on Global and Comparative Public Law at Humboldt University. I am
grateful to the organisers and the participants for their valuable feedback. Furthermore, I would to
acknowledge the support of the Grant Agency of the Czech Academy of Sciences as part of a project
on ‘The Role of the Principle of Proportionality in the Decision-Making of Courts’ (grant ID: 15-
23955S – Subsidy RVO: 68378122), awarded to the Institute of State and Law of the Academy of
Sciences of the Czech Republic.
1
There is probably no conceptualisation of rights more famous than Ronald Dworkin’s claim
that they are ‘trumps’. Yet, this is puzzling in at least two ways. First, it is not at all clear
what it means to say that rights are trumps; whatever the correct answer may be, it cannot
mean that rights such as the right to private life, the right to property, or the right to an
education – to name just a few rights that are widely recognised in contemporary rights
discourse – always or at least normally ‘trump’ all or most interests that clash with them.
Second and related, by singling out their ‘trumping’ quality as their central, defining feature,
Dworkin knowingly or unknowingly places his theory in sharp contrast to the dominant,
The goal of this article is to reconcile Dworkin’s theory of rights and proportionality
and thereby make a contribution to our understanding of both. 2 As will be shown, the
strength of Dworkin’s theory lies in the substantive moral foundation that it offers – in
particular its conceptions of human dignity, freedom, and equality –, but its weakness is the
structural account of rights as ‘trumps’, as evidenced by the fact that despite its fame this
idea has never really resonated in legal practice. With regard to proportionality, the opposite
picture presents itself: the doctrine does not give any indication as to its moral foundation –
which is illustrated by the fact that its most famous theoretical account, namely Robert
while offering a structure that has proven to be so useful that it has become the globally
dominant tool of rights adjudication. It will become clear that it is possible and indeed
important to reconcile and combine the structural strength of proportionality with the
substantive moral appeal of Dworkin’s theory. In order to do so, the essay first offers a
2 Jacob Weinrib (‘When Trumps Clash: Dworkin and the Doctrine of Proportionality’, forthcoming in
Ratio Juris) also aims to reconcile Dworkin and proportionality, but he takes a route that is different
from mine. While this essay focuses more on the values that guide Dworkin’s theory and, as will be
shown, proportionality analysis (human dignity, equality, and freedom), Weinrib focuses on the
structure that reasoning with rights has for Dworkin under his rights-as-trumps approach, and
discovers in Dworkin’s discussions of specific rights issues a range of claims regarding the conditions
under which a right can justifiably be limited that, as he demonstrates, resemble the various stages of
the proportionality test as applied, in particular, by the Canadian Supreme Court. This shows that
even Dworkin himself was not able to maintain his own structural claim that rights are trumps
without a considerable number of qualifications which bring its structure closer to proportionality;
this weakens the plausibility of his claim that their nature as trumps is a general structural feature of
rights.
2
critical reconstruction of Dworkin’s theory which is faithful to his core commitments but
departs from his narrative and terminology where necessary; in other words, the article
aims, in truly Dworkinian spirit, to present his theory in its best light. 3 This leads to the
conclusion that labelling rights as trumps is misleading and fails to capture what is
important about them under Dworkin’s own intellectual commitments (I.). The essay then
conception of the doctrine (II.). Finally, it shows that Dworkin’s theory properly understood
original and important conceptions of human dignity, freedom, and equality (III.); the paper
thus makes the case for the continuing relevance of Dworkin’s theory of rights in the current
‘age of proportionality’ 4.
Dworkin’s theory of rights has evolved over the years and decades of his career. 5 In this
essay, I will work mostly with its last and, I believe, most appealing incarnation as presented
in his books Is Democracy Possible Here? 6 and Justice for Hedgehogs 7. Readers who are familiar
with Dworkin’s earlier writings may be surprised to find that many of the concepts and
ideas that drove his earlier work are of little or no relevance in his last statement on rights.
Generation after generation of jurisprudence students and scholars (including this author)
have pored over ideas such as the distinction between external and internal preferences,
utilitarianism as a background theory which necessitates the existence of rights, the famous
right to equal concern and respect, and the principle-policy distinction. One can still find
traces of them in Dworkin’s late work; however, they do not any longer occupy a prominent
place. In my view – which I just state but do not defend in this paper – his final account of
3 On the nature of interpretation in general and the necessity to present the materials that are
interpreted in their best light see Dworkin, Law’s Empire (Hart Publishing, 1986), ch. 2.
4This is a reference to the title of Alexander Aleinikoff’s influential article ‘Constitutional Law in the
Age of Balancing’, 96 (1987) Yale Law Journal 943.
5For an instructive overview of the development of Dworkin’s thought see Paul Yowell, ‘A Critical
Examination of Dworkin’s Theory of Rights’, 52 (2007) American Journal of Jurisprudence 93.
6Ronald Dworkin, Is Democracy Possible Here?: Principles for a New Political Debate (Princeton
University Press, 2008) (henceforth: Dworkin, IDPH).
7 Ronald Dworkin, Justice for Hedgehogs (Harvard University Press, 2011) (henceforth: Dworkin, JH).
3
rights is superior to the earlier ones in that it focuses squarely on the important issues
relating to the foundational values of human dignity, liberty, and equality; it thus overcomes
and leaves aside the unnecessary complications arising mainly as a consequence of the
in my judgment – and presumably Dworkin’s own, given that he revised the theory
constitutional and political rights. 8 Political rights are those (moral) rights which ought to be
protected as (legal) constitutional rights. So what Dworkin calls ‘political’ rights is what
most constitutional theorists call ‘constitutional’ rights: not the specific rights of any
particular constitution but rather those rights which a constitution ought to protect. With
‘Most legitimate acts of any government involve trade-offs of different people’s interests;
these acts benefit some citizens and disadvantage others in order to improve the
community’s well-being on the whole ... But certain interests of particular people are so
important that it would be wrong – morally wrong – for the community to sacrifice those
interests just to secure an overall benefit. Political rights mark off and protect these
particularly important interests. A political right, we may say, is a trump over the kind of
trade-off argument that normally justifies political action.’ 9
As mentioned above, I am going to criticise the usefulness of the term ‘trumps’ when
characterising rights. Nevertheless, it is not difficult to see some appeal in the notion of
rights as trumps based on the above statement. For example, the government might claim,
rightly or wrongly, that closing down my communist newspaper would improve the
community’s well-being on the whole (because, say, workers would find less support for
communist ideas and would therefore not go on strike as often, which would benefit the
economy and thus enable the community to provide better education and hospitals to its
citizens). However, my right to freedom of the press would function as a trump over these
publish my newspaper.
4
‘Someone who claims a political right makes a very strong claim: that government cannot
properly do what might be in the community’s overall best interests. He must show why the
individual interests he cites are so important that they justify that strong claim. If we accept
the two principles of human dignity that I described in the last chapter, we can look to those
principles for that justification. We can insist that people have political rights to whatever
protection is necessary to respect the equal importance of their lives and their sovereign
responsibility to identify and create value in their own lives.’ 10
So we may say that for Dworkin, people have a right to be treated with dignity; it is the
importance of human dignity that justifies the extraordinary moral force of rights, namely to
block policies that might further the community’s overall best interests. Human dignity, for
Dworkin, consists of two principles: the principle of intrinsic value (an equality principle)
and the principle of personal responsibility (a liberty principle). The principle of intrinsic
value ‘declares the intrinsic and equal importance of every human life’ 11: ‘each human life
has a special kind of objective value. It has value as potentiality; once a human life has
begun, it matters how it goes.’ 12. Among the clearest cases of violations of this principle, and
therefore of rights, are discrimination and genocide 13 because such acts rest on the belief that
some human beings are worth less than others, or even worth nothing.
The principle of personal responsibility ‘holds that each person has a special
responsibility for realising the success of his own life, a responsibility that includes
exercising his judgment about what kind of life would be successful for him.’ 14 Forcing a
person to adopt the state’s official religion or punishing homosexual behaviour as being
against God’s or the majority’s will would usurp the individual person’s responsibility to
realise the success of his own life and would therefore violate the second principle of human
dignity.
distinctive to the often-cited claim that ‘every person should be treated as free and equal’ by
specifying that equality is best understood as being about the equal and objective
importance of every life and that freedom is concerned with every person’s individual
10 Ibid., 32.
11 Ibid., 37.
12 Ibid., 9.
13 Ibid., 37.
14 Ibid., 10.
5
responsibility to identify value in his or her own life. As so often, the devil is in the detail: in
cases that are less clear than the examples mentioned above, how can we establish whether a
policy respects or violates dignity? Dworkin gives us some guidance. With regard to the
the state. First, there are certain foundational decisions which people must be free to make,
such as ‘choices in religion and in personal commitments of intimacy and to ethical, moral,
and political ideals’. 15 Second, a law must not rely on a motive which assumes the
superiority of one ethical ideal over another. 16 Dworkin uses the terms ‘ethics’ and ‘morality’
in an idiosyncratic sense: for him, ethics refers to the duties a person has towards him- or
herself, whereas morality refers to the duties a person has to others. 17 For example, murder
is immoral because it violates a duty one has to others (in particular, the possible victims).
By way of contrast, determining and living one’s life in line with one’s religious convictions
is a duty people have to themselves. While it is acceptable for the state to force people to live
in accordance with collective decisions of moral principle (for example, to refrain from
murdering), its laws must remain neutral between competing ethical ideals. Thus,
moralism18 and (deep) paternalism are unacceptable. 19 Furthermore, even laws that are not
coercive may violate the second principle: for example, a display of the Ten Commandments
Dworkin is less clear about which rights can be derived from the first principle of
human dignity. He states that due process (fair trial) rights flow from it 20 and says, more
specifically, that treating every person’s life as objectively and equally important requires
refraining from inflicting the special and great harm of punishment on him unless his guilt is
6
proven. 21 Furthermore, as mentioned above, the right not to be discriminated against
obviously flows from the principle of equal importance. 22 Most of Dworkin’s writing on
equality is about distributive justice, and he has developed a theory – equality of resources –
fair. 23 But it is unclear to what extent he believed that this is a matter of rights. Given that,
for him, people have a right to be treated with dignity, and given that the first principle of
dignity requires certain kinds of resource distribution, it would seem to follow that people
resources. However, to my knowledge, Dworkin has never made such a claim (possibly
because his writing on constitutional rights is mostly concerned with U.S. constitutional law
and he may have thought that such a view, however appealing as a matter of political
morality, did not ‘fit’ well enough with U.S. constitutional history to qualify as the legally
right answer).
abstraction – in particular his account of the two principles of human dignity – and specific
application – such as his well-known defence of abortion rights,24 or his writing on the
importance of a strong protection of free speech. 25 There is little in his scholarship relating to
the room between high abstraction and concrete application, and it is possible that he
thought that the best way to reason about questions of rights is to apply the abstract
principles directly, without any intermediation, to any given specific problem. It is not my
concern here whether or not this is adequate, but this starkly contrasts with accounts of
rights that place proportionality front and centre because proportionality and related
doctrines are located precisely in that middle space between foundational principles and
concrete application. As far as I can see, the only structural point that Dworkin makes about
rights is, precisely, that they function as ‘trumps’ over the community’s well-being. But
while we were able to see the intuitive appeal of that statement, if we look at it again in light
21 Ibid., 372.
22 See n 13 and accompanying text.
23 Dworkin, JH, 356-363.
24Dworkin, Freedom’s Law (Oxford University Press, 1996), ch. 1-4; Dworkin, Life’s Dominion: An
Argument about Abortion, Euthanasia, and Individual Freedom (Knopf, 1993).
25 Dworkin, Freedom’s Law (above n 24), ch. 7-10.
7
of a more nuanced understanding of his theory, the claim turns out to be misleading and
unhelpful.
It has some appeal in the case of the above-mentioned foundational decisions whose
protection flows from the principle of personal responsibility. For example, we may say that
the state must not prohibit the foundational decision of whether or not to have an abortion
even if by doing so, it could enhance population growth and therefore greatly further the
community’s well-being; in this sense the right to abortion functions as a trump. But in the
other categories that Dworkin mentions, talk of rights as trumping the community’s well-
being is problematic. Let us first consider the prohibition of (deep) paternalism (which flows
from the second principle of human dignity). Paternalism is motivated by the desire to
improve the agent’s life; for example, a prohibition of sodomy might be motivated by the
desire to lead gay people to lead less sinful lives. But it is unhelpful to frame such a policy as
being about the community’s well-being (which rights can then trump): paternalism makes a
claim to improve the affected person’s well-being; it is not necessarily concerned with any
effects on the community. Second, with regard to rights flowing from the first principle of
dignity, again, it is not obvious why these rights should be seen as trumping the
community’s well-being. For example, it might be the case that dignity requires the right to a
free education for all. Of course, someone who disputes this could try to argue that the
community’s well-being would suffer under such a policy (to which Dworkin could then
respond that the right to education trumps any such concerns). But an argument against free
education need not be about the community’s well-being; it could be, for example, about
justice, claiming that collecting the resources needed to fund education would for some
opposition between rights and the community’s well-being. We might consider fixing this
problem by regarding rights as trumping not only the community’s well-being but any value
or consideration that conflicts with them: justice, well-being, utility, and so on. This,
however, would amount to saying that rights must prevail over a policy that is justified on
some other ground and would, in other words, simply point to the largely uncontroversial
8
To conclude, I do not think that the claim that rights are trumps is fortunate. It had
its role to play in the earlier versions of Dworkin’s theory 26 but does not point to an
important or insightful feature of rights in his later work; it should therefore be dropped.
While less catchy, Dworkin should have claimed instead that the foundational right that
people have is to be treated with dignity, and that this requires, first, that every policy
respect the equal and objective importance of their lives and, second, that every policy
recognise everyone’s personal responsibility for realising the value of his or her life.
answer the question of whether a given policy violates rights. The first question is whether
the policy under consideration interferes with (limits, restricts) a right. The second is
whether the interference is justified, and usually this is the case if it is proportionate. The
first stage is of little practical relevance because of the phenomenon that George Letsas has
called ‘rights inflation’: 27 the scope of (prima facie) rights has become so broad in legal
practice that it is difficult to find a case where the reviewing court concluded that the policy
at stake did not interfere with a right and therefore was not in need of a justification. The
consequence of this is that most if not all of the analytical work takes place at the second
stage, where the test is proportionality. 28 Proportionality has four steps. 29 First, the policy
26In his earlier work, he assumed – in line with the prevailing moral discourse at the time – that
policies were usually justified on utilitarian grounds; rights came in to correct the occasionally
impermissible aggregation of preferences that utilitarianism proposes. In that framework it made
sense to say that rights trump utilitarian justifications.
27George Letsas, A Theory of Interpretation of the European Convention on Human Rights (Oxford
University Press, 2007), 126.
28This has led Webber to claim that ‘the entire constitutional rights-project could be simplified by
replacing the catalogue of rights with a single proposition: The legislature shall comply with the
principle of proportionality.’ (The Negotiable Constitution: On the Limitation of Rights [Cambridge
University Press, 2009], 4). One might add that proportionality does not apply to all rights, though:
some rights – for example the right to freedom from torture and inhuman or degrading treatment or
punishment – are absolute, meaning that any interference with them amounts to a violation and
proportionality analysis does not apply. It is possible to reconcile absolute rights with proportionality
by arguing that an interference with an absolute right is always disproportionate because it always
imposes a burden on the right-holder that is more than he can be expected to bear. See Kai Möller,
The Global Model of Constitutional Rights (Oxford University Press, 2012), 139-140.
29Robert Alexy, A Theory of Constitutional Rights (Oxford University Press, 2002), 66; Mattias Kumm,
‘Political Liberalism and the Structure of Rights’, in Pavlakos (ed.), Law, Rights and Discourse: The Legal
9
that interferes with the right must pursue a legitimate goal (legitimate goal stage). Second, it
must be a suitable means of achieving the goal at least to some extent; put differently, there
must be a rational connection between the policy and the goal (suitability or rational
connection). Third, there must not be a less restrictive and equally effective alternative
(necessity; least restrictive means). Fourth and finally, the burden imposed on the right-holder
must not be disproportionate; establishing this requires balancing the seriousness of the
interference with the right against the importance of the competing interests (proportionality
balancing requirements, stands in stark contrast to a conception of rights that regards them
as trumps. 30 But I have already shown in the previous section that Dworkin’s famous label
does little to illuminate the structure of rights and that it is more adequate to summarise his
theory as requiring that every person’s right to human dignity has to be protected, which
means that every human life must be treated as having objective and equal importance and
that every person’s sovereign responsibility for the success of his or her life must be
respected. My argument in this section is that there is no conflict between his conception of
Philosophy of Robert Alexy (Hart, 2007), 131, 137; Kai Möller, ‘Proportionality: Challenging the Critics’,
10 (2012) International Journal of Constitutional Law 709, 711. There are variations as to the precise
formulations of the test which are however not relevant here.
30It is remarkable that Dworkin seems to never have written about proportionality as a doctrine of
constitutional law (maybe because it is not used in the U.S., which is the jurisdiction that he was most
familiar with and wrote about regularly). In Is Democracy Possible Here? [above n 6, 48-9] there is a
brief engagement with limitations clauses in the European Convention on Human Rights; Dworkin
simply states that ‘[t]hese qualifications were the result of political compromises that served to
reassure countries hesitating to embrace the convention’ – a statement that is rather simplistic and
inadequate as a general account of limitation clauses; this is followed, in the next paragraph, by a
claim to the effect that an abstract right needs to be refined before it can be considered absolute. I do
not think that a lot of insight about proportionality and limitations clauses can be gained from these
cursory claims; rather, their ad hoc nature indicates that Dworkin never took these concepts seriously.
Dworkin did occasionally discuss the idea of balancing; but usually he had in mind balancing in the
sense of a utilitarian cost-benefit calculation which he rejected as not doing justice to questions of
rights, a point with which I agree: balancing in constitutional rights law is concerned with a conflict of
interests which must be resolved through moral reasoning; thus, balancing refers not to utilitarianism
but must be used in the sense of ‘balancing as reasoning’ (see below fn 37 and accompanying text).
See, for example, his ‘It is absurd to calculate human rights according to a cost-benefit analysis’, an
opinion piece in the British Guardian, available at
https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2006/may/24/comment.politics (last accessed 24 April
2017).
10
rights properly understood and proportionality, and that, indeed, interpreting the four
stages of the proportionality test in line with the requirements of human dignity leads to a
At the first stage of the test, the legitimacy of the goal pursued by the policy in question
must be assessed. The abstract formulation of the proportionality test does not give any
interpret it in line with an attractive conception of rights. On the assumption that Dworkin’s
theory provides such a conception, it can directly be applied here. As explained above,
Dworkin claims that a law must not rely on a motive which assumes the superiority of one
ethical ideal over another; this makes moralism and (deep) paternalism impermissible. Thus,
a goal is illegitimate if it assumes the superiority of one ethical ideal over another. 31 The
textbook example of such a goal would be a law that prohibits homosexual sex on the
grounds that such sex is ethically worthless, against God’s will, or harmful to the person
engaging in it. Similarly, it would be impermissible to cite as the goal of a policy banning
headscarves in public universities the view that an Islamic lifestyle in general, or a particular
interpretation of Islam which makes the headscarf necessary, is ethically unappealing and
Of course, most cases are not as clear-cut as the examples I have just given; this raises
the question of whether Dworkin’s principle of personal responsibility is also helpful for the
resolution of more complex cases. I think that it is, and will use the European Court of
31 A parallel point was first made by Kumm (above n 29), 142-8. See also my discussion of the
legitimacy of goals in Möller (above n 28), 183-93. I do not mean to exclude the possibility that a goal
could also be illegitimate by virtue of being incompatible with the first principle of dignity, but it will
fortunately be very rare in legal practice for a state to put forward such an argument. For example, a
policy that disadvantages a minority ‘in order to give expression to their lesser value’ would be such
a case. In practice, even obviously discriminatory practices are usually defended by relying on a goal
that is in principle legitimate but that does not ultimately justify the policy at stake. For example, in
the ‘gays in the army’ case of Smith and Grady v. United Kingdom (29 (2000) E.H.R.R. 493), the U.K.
argued not that the goal of the policy was to express the view that homosexuals are ‘worth less’;
rather it argued that allowing homosexuals to serve in the army would lead to tensions within the
army and therefore to a threat to national security. Since protecting national security is obviously a
legitimate goal, the ECtHR was right to accept the goal put forward by the U.K. and to let the policy
fail at a later stage of the proportionality test.
11
Human Rights’ judgment in Stübing v. Germany, 32 which concerns incest, as an illustration.
While incest is an activity which many people will ethically disapprove of quite strongly, it
is not obvious whether its prohibition can be justified, given that the moralistic or
paternalistic goal of stopping people from living ethically worthless lives does not qualify as
legitimate under Dworkin’s principle of personal responsibility. The fact that Germany did
not even try to rely on this reason is an indicator of the appeal of Dworkin’s principle:
unacceptable and an unjustifiable intrusion into the personal life of the right-holder. The
problem, however, is that even though the state may not openly rely on ethical disapproval,
the motives that it cites instead may still violate the principle of personal responsibility for
the following reasons. First, the goal, while not moralistic or paternalistic, may nevertheless
and on closer inspection turn out to violate the principle of personal responsibility for other
reasons; and second, the goal cited may serve as a pretext for a moralistic or paternalistic
goal.
Stübing is an example in point. In the case, Germany had argued that its ban on incest
was justified because it pursued the goals of, first, protecting the family (the risk being an
‘inversion of social roles’ within the family structure); second, the protection of the weaker
partner in a relationship (the risk being a structural imbalance which posed a threat to the
damage to children; and fourth, maintaining a societal taboo against incest. 33 The assumed
need to maintain a societal taboo against incest is an instance of a goal that, while not openly
moralistic or paternalistic, still (arguably) violates the second principle of dignity: a societal
taboo against a particular behaviour means, broadly, that the respective behaviour (in this
case, incest) is not seriously considered as part of the menu of options available to a person;
indirect form of thought control which, in turn, can be seen as violating the principle of
personal responsibility by denying the individual the ability to reach his own judgment
12
The goal of preventing genetic damage to children can be seen as an example of a
goal which is (arguably) legitimate but serves as a pretext for an illegitimate goal. As a
preliminary point, it is not clear that the goal should be considered legitimate because it is
arguable that it is better for children with a genetic defect to be alive than not to be alive at
all. But assuming that the goal is indeed legitimate, the possibility exists that it serves as a
pretext for the moralistic motives of the state because in other contexts, the risk of genetic
damage to the child is never considered to be a valid reason to prohibit sex and/or
procreation; 34 for example, it is uncontroversial that disabled people have the right to
Structurally, there are two ways of dealing with this problem. The first is to focus on
the subjective motivation of the law-makers and inquire into their true motives. This,
however, creates unanswerable questions because those motivations will often not be
accessible; it also sets unfortunate incentives for lawmakers to hide and possibly lie about
their true motives. The second and preferable way is to focus on the objective justifiability of
the policy. Thus, in the Stübing example, preventing genetic damage to children would be
considered to be a legitimate goal; however, the relevance of the fact that other forms of
procreation leading to children with genetic damage are not prohibited would be considered
The above remarks are not meant as a comprehensive discussion of the intricacies of
Stübing; rather, their point is to show how Dworkin’s second principle of human dignity can
successfully be integrated into the interpretation and application of the proportionality test
If a policy passes the legitimate goal stage, the next stages of the proportionality assessment
concern its suitability, necessity, and proportionality in the strict sense. For reasons of
explication of my argument, this section will focus on the balancing stage. It is the final and,
usually, decisive stage of the proportionality analysis and requires a balancing exercise
34 This argument was made by the applicant; see ibid., para. 36.
35This question could be considered at the balancing stage or arguably at a separate stage assessing
the coherence of the policy. I have argued in favour of adding a coherence stage to the proportionality
assessment in Möller (above n 31), 125-6.
13
between the right-holder’s interests and the competing public or individual interests; the
overall question is whether the policy places a burden on the right-holder that is
disproportionate, that is, more than he or she can legitimately be expected to bear.
One of the issues pointed out by authors who are critical of balancing relates to the
lack of clarity as to what the concept means in constitutional rights law. 36 It seems obvious
would do justice to questions of rights. 37 Rather, the starting point for any theory of
balancing must be that balancing simply refers to the need to make a moral argument as to
which of the two (or more) competing interests takes priority in a given case. 38 This
interpretation is preferable not only from a moral perspective; it is also compatible with the
semantic meaning of the term: for example, when we speak of the need to find a ‘balanced’
solution to a moral problem, this means that we are looking for a solution which attaches the
correct weight to all relevant considerations and is therefore morally defensible. But if
balancing simply refers to the need to construct a moral argument about the competing
nutshell, I will argue that the balancing stage of the proportionality test is concerned with
ensuring that the policy at stake respects the equal importance of the right-holder’s life.
Thus, balancing is shorthand for assessing the compliance of a policy with the first principle
of human dignity.
This can be explained in the following way. To say that we have to ‘balance’ the
burden on the right-holder against the importance of the competing right or public interest
refers to the imperative of designing policies in a way that is ‘balanced’ – that is, that
distributes burdens and benefits in a way that is compatible with the principle of equality.
36 Grégoire Webber (above n 28), 88-9; Stavros Tsakyrakis, ‘Proportionality: An assault on human
rights?’, (2009) 7 International Journal of Constitutional Law 468; Jürgen Habermas, Between Facts and
Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy (MIT Press, 1998), 259.
37 George Letsas, ‘Rescuing Proportionality’, in Cruft, Liao, and Renzo (eds.), Philosophical Foundations
of Human Rights (Oxford University Press, 2015), 316, 325-6. See also above n 30.
38 Möller (above n 29), 720-1; Möller (above n 31), 140.
14
Conversely, to say that a policy is disproportionate (in the strict sense) means that the state
has attached too little weight to the interests of the right-holder: if it had attached the correct
weight, it would have noticed that the burden on him or her was too high and therefore
disproportionate. But to attach too little weight to someone’s interests means to fail to treat
his interests as equally important as everyone else’s interests, and therefore fails to
Let me give as an example the recent case of S.A.S. v. France, 39 where the European
Court of Human Rights decided that the French ban on the full-face veil was compatible
with the European Convention on Human Rights. The goal pursued by the ban, which the
Court found to be legitimate, was the protection of ‘the ground rules of social
communication’ and the conditions of ‘living together’. 40 One of the issues at stake was
whether a ban on the full-face veil was a disproportionate burden on those women wishing
to conceal their faces for religious reasons. If we assume (with the dissent) that it was, then
we are saying that France asked for ‘too much’ from the affected women and that,
correspondingly, it attached too little weight to the legitimate interests of those women.
Thus, it failed to treat them as someone whose lives have an importance that is equal to
everyone else’s.
Admittedly there is little direct support in Dworkin’s writing for my claim that the
first principle of dignity requires what constitutional rights lawyers usually refer to as
balancing. Most of his writing about specific rights issues is about the second principle of
dignity: think of his well-known defences of abortion, hate speech, or euthanasia. When he
writes about the first principle, he is mostly concerned not with rights but with theories of
distributive justice (in particular, taxation). 41 However, there is no reason why the first
principle should be entirely or even predominantly about fair taxation, and Dworkin himself
certainly did not intend it to be; for example, he claims in Justice for Hedgehogs that the right
to due process flows from the principle of equal importance, 42 and he states in Is Democracy
Possible Here? that certain forms of torture, discrimination, and genocide violate the first
15
principle. 43 As mentioned before, my goal in this article is not to engage in Dworkin
exegesis, but rather to reconstruct his theory in a way that is coherent and shows it in its best
light. To regard the reach of the first principle of dignity as restricted to questions of
Therefore, it is not only possible but indeed necessary to hold that the principle of equal and
and this is precisely what under proportionality is assessed at the balancing stage.
important objection to my approach here. He writes about the famous Hatton case, 45 which
was about a policy allowing night flights at Heathrow airport which affected the sleep of
some of the residents in the area. Letsas is critical of protecting the interest in good sleep as
part of Article 8 ECHR and balancing it against the competing interest in economic
development. He accepts that the interest in good sleep is an important interest and that
justice and equality (for our purposes: Dworkin’s first principle of human dignity) might
‘Perhaps the Heathrow night flights scheme did not allocate the various resources in play
(sleep, economic benefits, employment) in a way that treats people as equals under some
egalitarian theory of distribution. Perhaps the applicants have a solid claim based on
distributive justice to request the government to restrict or abolish night flights, relocate the
airport, or compensate the residents. But these are not matters falling within the law of
human rights. We cannot inflate the concept of human rights so much that it covers the
whole realm of justice. Human rights would then lose their distinctive moral force.’ 46
Applied to the issue that is my concern at this point, the problem can be presented in the
following way. If we accept, with Dworkin, that (1) rights are about dignity, (2) dignity is,
among other things, about treating people’s lives as equally important, and (3) this means
that burdens and benefits must be distributed in a just way, then it would seem to follow
16
that the scope of rights becomes so broad as to cover the whole domain of justice. This
would be problematic because it is widely and, to my mind, correctly accepted that not
I believe that there is indeed a structural weakness in Dworkin’s writing about rights
and human dignity because he does not address, let alone resolve, this important point; as
mentioned above, as far as I can see, he does not make any systematic attempt to work out a
theory of the relationship between the first principle of human dignity and the scope of
rights. However, the correct answer to this problem is not to radically ban all considerations
relating to balancing from the scope of rights, as Letsas seems to suggest. 47 Rather, another
and more appealing solution is to distinguish between justice and rights in a different way,
namely by claiming that rights require only that a policy be based on a reasonable, as
opposed to the one correct, conception of justice, and that therefore, a distribution of
considerable support in the case law of courts that rely on proportionality, which regularly
make statements to the effect that their task is not to establish whether the legislature
designed the best possible (or ‘just’) policy but rather only to review whether the burden on
The suitability and necessity stages, too, can be explained as flowing from Dworkin’s first
principle of dignity. Let us first consider the case of suitability. An unsuitable policy places a
burden on the right-holder but does not contribute to the achievement of its goal. This can
easily be shown to violate Dworkin’s first principle of human dignity because treating a
person’s life as (equally) important surely requires abstaining from burdening him for no
47 Letsas concludes his chapter by stating: ‘If we want to be accurate we have to say that in cases
like Hatton, states’ margin of appreciation is infinite and in cases like Dudgeon states have no margin
of appreciation whatsoever.’ (ibid., 130). I interpret this as meaning that any balance of interests
would be acceptable in Hatton, which is just a different way of saying that no balancing should take
place at all.
Mattias Kumm, ‘The Idea of Socratic Contestation and the Right to Justification: The Point of Rights-
48
Based Proportionality Review’ 4 (2010) Law & Ethics of Human Rights 141; Möller (above n 31), 117-123.
49 Möller (above n 31), 200-204.
17
burdens the right-holder to a greater extent than necessary because the legitimate goal could
be achieved to the same extent through a less burdensome policy. Again, respect for human
dignity requires choosing the less burdensome policy because placing an unnecessary
4. Conclusion
furthermore, it illuminates the meaning and interpretation of the different stages of the test.
to conventional wisdom according to which there exists a contrast between liberty rights
(such as the rights to life, freedom of religion, association, expression, and the right to
private life) and equality rights (in particular the right to non-discrimination). The previous
sections have shown that reasoning with so-called liberty rights requires an appreciation of
liberty as well as equality: the legitimate goal stage of the proportionality analysis is
concerned with liberty in that it ensures that the personal responsibility of the right-holder is
the strict sense), however, are, on the analysis presented in this paper, concerned with
way that respects every affected person’s equal importance; conversely, a disproportionate
So far I have offered a critical reconstruction of Dworkin’s theory of rights, and I have
shown that when viewed in its best light it is compatible with proportionality and can
indeed inspire a richer and more appealing interpretation of the four stages of the test. This
section will offer some additional reflections on the importance of Dworkin’s theory for the
18
Proportionality has been immensely successful as a legal doctrine: it was invented not
by scholars or theorists of rights but by judges, 50 and it had become a globally successful tool
of rights adjudication long before the first comprehensive theory of it was published. 51 Thus,
its success is primarily based on its practical usefulness for judges deciding cases about
whether a policy violates rights into four sub-questions that can be analysed separately. This
is no small achievement. But while the role of proportionality as a tool and a legal doctrine
has certainly been extremely useful, for a long time there was no agreement on, in fact not
based. The fact that the first major and most famous account of proportionality-based
principles and optimisation requirements, is a formal theory, that is, one which explicitly
In recent years a couple of substantive theories have been proposed. Mattias Kumm
has argued that proportionality-based judicial review protects every person’s right to
contributed to the debate by arguing that the point of constitutional rights is to ensure that
any act which limits a person’s ability to live her life according to her self-conception is
justifiable to her; that this justification is successful if the policy at stake rests on a reasonable
specification of the spheres of autonomy of equal citizens; and that proportionality properly
rights and dignity to these existing attempts to make sense of proportionality. The rough
50 On the history of proportionality, see Alec Stone Sweet and Jud Mathews, ‘Proportionality
Balancing and Global Constitutionalism’, (47) 2008-9 Columbia Journal of Transnational Law 72, sections
III and IV.
51 Namely Robert Alexy’s (above n 29).
52 Ibid., 11.
53 Kumm (above n 48).
54 Möller (above n 31), passim.
19
theory is the following. The foundational right that everyone has is to be treated with
human dignity. Thus, any law or other act by a public authority must respect his equality
(more precisely: the equal and objective importance of his life) and his freedom (his personal
responsibility for the success of his life). The justification of the principle of proportionality,
then, lies in its ability, if properly interpreted, to ensure the protection of human dignity and
its two sub-principles. At the legitimate goal stage, any justifications that are incompatible
with the value of personal responsibility are discounted. The following three stages
(suitability, necessity and balancing) assess whether the policy distributes burdens and
benefits in a way that can reasonably be regarded as compatible with the person’s equal
importance.
The existing theories of the point and purpose of constitutional rights are not
mutually exclusive and not even necessarily in competition with each other; rather, they
highlight different facets of the values underlying constitutional rights. Kumm’s emphasis is
on the fact that all state action must, as a matter of rights, be justifiable in terms of public
reason; thus, his focus is on the structural and institutional conditions of legitimate
authority; and while he believes that a conception of public reason as well as a more fully
worked-out account of the right to justification will have to say something about freedom
and equality, he does not provide a conception of these values. In my previous work, I have
attempted to spell out more concretely the meaning of equality and, in particular, autonomy
as structural building blocks of a theory of rights, but I have stopped short of providing a
moral grounding of those values. Dworkin’s emphasis, by way of contrast, is directly on the
substantive values that ground rights and legitimacy, that is, the two dimensions of human
dignity. Furthermore, there are links between the right to justification (that grounds rights in
Kumm’s and my accounts) and human dignity (which grounds rights for Dworkin): Rainer
Forst (who first proposed the idea of a right to justification as the basis of human rights) has
claimed that human dignity implies first and foremost that every person be treated as
competition with proportionality and therefore, at least for the time being, on the losing side
Rainer Forst, ‘The Justification of Human Rights and the Basic Right to Justification: A Reflexive
55
20
of history and of limited interest and relevance. Rather, his insights should be integrated
importance and relevance of his work lies in its ability to, first, guide the interpretation of
the different stages of the proportionality test and, second, provide a distinctive account of
21