Endogenous Political Institutions (A J W Philippe Aghion, Francesco Trebbi) 2004
Endogenous Political Institutions (A J W Philippe Aghion, Francesco Trebbi) 2004
Endogenous Political Institutions (A J W Philippe Aghion, Francesco Trebbi) 2004
Philippe Aghion
Alberto Alesina
Francesco Trebbi
I. Introduction
Classical political theorists were well aware of the impor
tance of the trade-off between delegation of power to leaders and
the need to control them to avoid tyranny. For instance, in De
mocracy In America, Alexis de Tocqueville stressed that "Our
contemporaries are incessantly racked by two inimical passions;
they feel the need to be led and the wish to remain free."1 The
Founding Fathers of the American Constitution were also quite
aware of this dilemma. For instance, in Federalist Paper No. 70
Hamilton writes that, "Taking for granted . . . that all men of
sense will agree in the necessity of an energetic executive, it will
only remain to inquire what are the ingredients which constitute
this energy? How far can they be combined with those other
ingredients which constitute safety in the Republican sense?" The
? 2004 by the President and Fellows of Harvard College and the Massachusetts Institute of
Technology.
The Quarterly Journal of Economics, May 2004
565
This content downloaded from
85.240.80.124 on Thu, 14 Mar 2024 22:05:34 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
566 QUARTERLY JOURNAL OF ECONOMICS
3. These authors show how rich elites would impose dictatorship; they dis
cuss in much more detail than we do the issue of insurrection of the poor.
4. Our contribution should thus be seen as a complement to the recent vast
literature on the effects of institutions on economic outcomes, as in Persson and
Tabellini [2003] and the references therein. This literature takes institutions such
as electoral laws, level of democracy, presidentialism, etc. as exogenous, or at least
predetermined.
5. In particular, see Koray [2000], Barbera and Jackson [2001], and Polborn
and Messner [2002]. Barbera and Jackson investigate the endogenous choice of a
majority voting rule, investigating conditions of existence of a self-stable voting
rule, an issue that we shall revisit below. Koray instead explores social choice
functions and whether such functions are self-selecting. In an overlapping genera
tions setting, Polborn and Messner identify a trade-off arising in the selection of
voting mechanisms over a reform when only part of the population (the old) incurs
the cost of the reform, but not the subsequent benefits.
6. The following specification builds upon Krusell and Rios-Rull [1996] and
Aghion and Howitt [1998, Ch. 9] on the political economy of vested interests.
7. The constitutional decision is taken behind a veil of ignorance, before the
realization of the parameter \? for all ?'s and with all individuals facing the same
status-quo outcome in case reforms do not occur, an assumption we shall relax
below.
8. The role of the political leader in the basic model is highly stylized. A
leader is needed to promote the reform and to pass it (unless it is blocked).
However, the leader can take advantage of his position to expropriate. Obviously,
if the citizens could produce reforms without a leader, expropriation would not
occur. We rely on the realistic idea that a centralized entity is needed to coordinate
the reform policy.
9. The Constitution could prohibit expropriation, but not reforms that would
be a Pareto improvement. We have two comments. First, in reality it is difficult to
fully restrain the authority of the government in this respect to expropriation
without restricting its ability to govern in other areas. In the Federalist paper No.
73 Hamilton, for instance, elaborates on the fact that "the power of preventing bad
laws includes that of preventing good ones." Second, with risk aversion, even
without expropriation, we still have a well-defined trade-off between insulation
and ex post control.
10. The parameter M we view as a "summary statistic" for a wide variety of
institutional rules that limit the power of appointed leaders. The most direct
interpretation of M is the majority that an executive has to command in order to
pass legislation. In general terms the issue of the "optimal supermajority" rule is
a widely debated question by Constitutional theorists. Those who favor superma
jority rules (low insulation) worry about limiting the power of appointed leaders
and about the tyranny of the majority. Those who oppose them view the (simple)
majority rule as the essence of democracy.
11. This is a point already made by Hayek [I960]. See Alesina and Rosenthal
[1995] for an extensive formal discussion of this issue.
12. See, for instance, Baron and Ferejohn [1989] and Baron [1991]. On
bicameralism see Diermeier and Myerson [1995].
13. In some cases we can have minority governments, in which the executive
does not command a simple majority in the legislature. See Persson and Tabellini
[2000].
14. See Grossman and Helpman [2001].
15. Persson and Tabellini [2003] and Milesi-Ferretti, Perotti, and Rostagno
[2002] present recent studies which compare proportional versus majoritarian
systems concerning fiscal policy choices.
(3)
1
max
M
p 2A"
^-rda+\ (\m
v m "'r 2A + a)y wj d
Ji-\-lM
The first two terms in (3) represent the expected benefits of the
socially efficient reform (multiplied by the exogenously given
probability of such an event, p), the third term represents expro
priation. Note that ex ante, behind a veil of ignorance and with
risk neutrality, the generic voter acts as the "average" individual.
Looking first for an interior solution to maximizing (3) relative to
M, and remembering that X = I/7, we obtain, after straightfor
ward maximization,
1 2Ab(l-p)
(4) M* =-^-?
whenever the right-hand sid
side of (4) is negative, then t
M* = 0.
Proposition 1. The preferences of voters are single peaked on M*,
and either the optimal degree of insulation is zero or it is
interior to the interval (0,1) and given by (4) if positive. In the
latter case, the optimal degree of insulation is decreasing
with the potential loss from expropriation (6), rising with the
probability that the leader is a good (p), rising with the value
of reform (7), rising with the dispersion of idiosyncratic pref
erences over the reform (I), and decreasing with the extent of
aggregate uncertainty over the reform (A).
First, note that in the absence of expropriation (b = 0), or
with no bad leaders (p = 1), we have M* = V2. This result
follows from the utilitarian nature of the maximization problem
in (3) and symmetry in the distribution of X?, but it extends to
more general distributions of idiosyncratic and aggregate shocks
on preferences, as we show in the Appendix. The basic intuition is
that the representative voter ex ante does not want to prevent an
ex post majority to stop an ex post efficient policy.16 This result
also holds only with risk neutrality; as we show below under risk
aversion even with no expropriation we obtain a well-defined
interior solution for M*.
That insulation should decrease in the probability (1 ? p ) of
expropriation and in the loss b from it, that is in the expected loss
from a bad reform, but that it should increase in 7, the average
benefit from a good reform, is self-explanatory.
Finally, to understand why insulation is increasing in I (re
spectively, decreasing in A), first note that in the absence of
expropriation, optimal insulation should not depend on I or A.
This follows from the fact that increases in I and A do not affect
the marginal effect of M on the outcome from good politician.
However, an increase in I (respectively, in A) increases (respec
tively, reduces) the average outcome under a good politician by
increasing (respectively, reducing) the likelihood of reform. Since
an increase in I (respectively, in A) does not affect the average
(expropriation) outcome under a bad politician, the higher / (re
spectively, A) the higher (respectively, lower) the benefit of insu
lation relative to its expropriation cost, and therefore the higher
(respectively, lower) the optimal level of insulation.
These parameters can all be connected to the real world. In
particular, a high 6 or a low p captures economic environments
with poor legal protection of individuals' property rights and
wealth. A high 7 captures the case of economies with a high
aggregate value of reform, e.g., emerging market economies that
require stabilization or transition economies that require struc
tural market reforms. Also a country that precipitates in a "crisis"
may have a very high value for a reform that eliminates the
source of distress. A high A corresponds typically to reforms such
as international treaties or constitutional change, that involve a
high degree of aggregate risk and irreversibility. Proposition 1
thus suggests that insulation should be higher in economies with
better legal protection, or facing an emergency or transition situa
tion, or for decisions that involve a limited amount of aggregate
risk or are easily reversible. In the next section we complete this
comparative statics by introducing polarization, risk aversion,
and compensation costs as additional determinants of insulation.
III. Extensions
(5) *,*
M* ^/(X- - k) + u{1 " e)/^ " 2A6(1 " pVp
=-/ i m
(7/ + u)l
This implies the following.
Proposition 2. The optimal degree of insulation (M*) declines
with the risk aversion parameter (u).
Proof. See Appendix.
Thus, more risk aversion leads to lower insulation: in choos
ing insulation, ex ante the voter takes into account the risk of
17. Note that the critical assumption that drives this result is that there is
"risk" about the outcome of the reform for an individual voter, but no risk about
the status quo. This is a realistic assumption to the extent that one knows its own
status quo, but not the outcome of a possibly complex sequence of policy changes.
Yet one might think about the reverse situation. Think, for instance, about the
introduction of unemployment insurance, in which case the reform is meant to
remove uncertainty of outcomes. In this case the effect of risk aversion would be
reversed.
III.B. Compensation
In general, those who are net losers from a policy reform can
be compensated by transfers, even though the latter will gener
ally induce welfare costs, such as the costs of distortionary taxa
tion. Suppose that after M is chosen, a fixed amount of resources
?a can be raised from all individuals through taxes, and assume
for simplicity that taxes are raised before the idiosyncratic and
aggregate shocks on preferences are realized. Note that this im
plicitly assumes that any increase in income obtained through the
reform cannot be used to compensate losers, since the amount
available for compensation is fixed ex ante. The maximum
amount of co is 1 which represents initial individual wealth. The
only purpose of taxation is to compensate losers for the reform,
which means that if the available resources for compensation
exceed the needs the resources in excess are returned lump sum
at no cost and the leader does not retain any revenue for his own
consumption.
Such a transfer scheme is assumed to involve a positive
deadweight cost k per unit of taxed funds, and the net tax reve
nues are used by the politician to compensate the required num
ber of losers in order to avoid blocking. Ex post, for given realiza
tion of the aggregate shock a, either more than (1 - M) individ
uals are willing to support the reform even without any
compensation (this will be the case whenever (X - a ? X)/(X -
X) < M), in which case no compensation will take place; or
passing the reform requires compensation to be made (this will be
the case when (X - a - X)/(X - X) > M: then the politician needs
to compensate the fraction (X ? a - X)/(X - X) - M of individ
uals for potential loss of utility due to the reform). Compensation
is paid to enough individuals who would, ex post, vote against the
policy reform, in order to keep them in. Obviously, the "cheaper"
individuals are compensated, i.e., those closer to the cut-off point
of indifference between having or not having the reform.
However, this requires that individual preferences be ex post
observable, since compensation is made dependent on those
preferences.18
Thus, the total amount of compensation needed to pass a
reform is given by
18. The case where individual preferences are not publicly observable can be
analyzed along the same lines as in Aghion and Bolton [2003].
c(a) = *7(X
X+IM
- a - X?) j d\t.
19. Acemoglu and Robinson [2000] and Lizzeri and P?rsico [2004] investigate
what leads wealthy minorities to extend the franchise.
20. In Aghion, Alesina, and Trebbi [2004] we explore these issues in the
context of the choice of forms of government of American cities.
21. See, for instance, Easterly and Levine [1997], La Porta et al. [1998],
Alesina et al. [2004], and Montalvo and Reynal-Querol [2002].
FRACTt = i - 2 (^) ,
where n^INi is the relative size of group j in country ?, with j =
1,..., J. As for the data used, the first index is the one used
originally by Easterly and Levine [1997] ,22 It is an ethno-linguistic
fragmentation index based on a historical Russian classification of
languages in 1960. The second and third fractionalization indices
have been constructed by Alesina et al. [2004] by disentangling
linguistic measures from other ethnic variables, like racial origin.
We will employ a measure for ethnic fragmentation and another
measure for linguistic fragmentation.
We also check our results by using the polarization index pro
posed in Esteban and Ray [1994] and applied also by Montalvo and
Reynal-Querol [2002]. This index is computed as follows:
w&y
j j
POL, = KjJJJ
24. For example, there is a relevant, negative (-0.501), and significant (at
the 1 percent level) correlation between presidentialism and a measure of political
constraints within the political arena (as presented in Henisz [2002]). For more
discussion on insulation and presidentialism, see Shugart and Carey [1992].
25. Further analysis shows that this correlation holds up even when control
ling for a battery of other variables, including log of per capita GDP, school
enrollment ratios, regional dummies, and openness.
TABLE I
Variables Definitions:
Control Sets:
Legal origin: French, Socialist, and other non-Common Law legal origin from
La Porta et al. [1999]; the Social legal origin dummy is dropped when ELF is
used, as non-Socialist countries were included in the original study.
Regional dummies: Sub-Saharan Africa, East Asia, and Latin America.
Colonial origin dummies: British, French, Spanish/Portuguese, other colonies;
from CIA World Factbook [2001].
Religion: Continuous variable indicating fraction of the total population that is
Protestant, Catholic, or Muslim, from La Porta et al. [1999].
Log(Real GDP) in 1960: Natural logarithm of real GDP per capita in 1960 from
Easterly and Levine [1997].
Sample: DEMOCRACY
Variable Obs Mean Std. dev. Min Max
Ethnic Fractionalization Index 69 0.30999 0.22927 0.002 0.7872
Ethno-Linguistic Fractionalization
Index 1960 46 0.28522 0.24319 0 0.82
Polarization (alpha = 4/5) 69 0.12976
Linguistic Fractionalization Index 66 0.272
Sample: PARLIAMENTARY
Variable Obs Mean Std. dev. Min Max
Ethnic Fractionalization Index 50 0.29523 0.21684 0.0119 0.8082
Ethno-Linguistic Fractionalization
Index 1960 38 0.30158 0.25149 0.01 0.89
Polarization (alpha = 4/5) 49 0.12939 0.
Linguistic Fractionalization Index 46 0.3079
Sample: NONPLURALITY
Variable Obs Mean Std. dev. Min Max
Ethnic Fractionalization Index 67 0.37671 0.25062 0.0119 0.8791
Ethno-Linguistic Fractionalization
Index 1960 59 0.32593 0.27512 0.01 0.89
Polarization (alpha - 4/5) 66 0.14849 0.
Linguistic Fractionalization Index 64 0.32198
TABLE II
(continued)
Sample: AUTOCRACY
Variable Obs Mean Std. dev. Min Max
Ethnic Fractionalization Index 41 0.5711 0.24783 0.0392 0.9302
Ethno-Linguistic Fractionalization
Index 1960 20 0.58 0.32216 0.01 0.93
Polarization (alpha = 4/5) 41 0.17759 0
Linguistic Fractionalization Index 38 0.5084
Sample: DIRECT PRESIDENTIAL
Variable Obs Mean Std. dev. Min Max
Ethnic Fractionalization Index 68 0.54252 0.26042 0 0.9302
Ethno-Linguistic Fractionalization
Index 1960 55 0.48455 0.30358 0.01 0.93
Polarization (alpha = 4/5) 68 0.17862 0
Linguistic Fractionalization Index 65 0.46227
Sample: PLURALITY
Variable Obs Mean Std. dev. Min Max
Ethnic Fractionalization Index 42 0.48886 0.25831 0 0.8635
Ethno-Linguistic Fractionalization
Index 1960 36 0.5125 0.271 0.01 0.93
Polarization (alpha = 4/5) 42 0.1755 0.07478 0 0.2774
Linguistic Fractionalization Index 40 0.45338 0.30719 0.0103 0.8983
Variables are defined in Table I. The table reports number of observations, the mean, the standard
deviation, and the minimum and maximum values within the subsamples reported for different indicators of
fractionalization. Democracy refers to the classification of "Free" by Freedom House, Autocracy of "Not Free."
report) that French legal origin and Socialist legal origin are
associated with less democracy relative to the Anglo-Saxon sys
tem (the omitted category). With few exceptions, fractionalization
seems to increase the probability of ending up in a more auto
cratic (and more insulated) regime.27 Finally, with reference to
the potential endogeneity of ethnic fractionalization with respect
27. It should be noted that many of these control sets are correlated with each
other. Adding all the possible controls in the same regression causes two main
problems: collinearity and a reduction in the sample size. We verified both prob
lems as being relevant. We tested simultaneously for all the possible controls and
observed a reduction in the precision of the estimate for fractionalization as well
as a loss of significance for a large majority of the controls.
ORDERED PROBIT
(1) (2) (3) (4)
Autocracy Autocracy
(1990) (1990) (1990) (1990)
Ethnic Fractionalization Index 1.926 2.021 1.700 1.434
(0.355)*** (0.390)*** (0.418)*** (0.448)***
[174] [163] [174] [163]
Ethno-Linguistic 1.678 1.625 0.526 0.383
Fractionalization Index (0.421)*** (0.450)*** (0.481) (0.499)
1960 [107] [107] [107] [107]
Polarization (alpha = 4/5)4.229 3.387 4.112 2.854
(1.148)*** (1.226)*** (1.173)*** (1.296)**
[174] [163] [174] [163]
1.395
Linguistic Fractionalization 1.576 0.681 0.562
Index (0.309)*** (0.333)*** (0.365)* (0.396)
[168] [157] [167] [156]
Control sets
Religion
ORDERED PROBIT
(5) (6) (7) (8) (9)
Autocracy Autocracy Autocracy Autocracy Autocracy
(1990) (1990) (1990) (1990) (1990)
1.866 1.506 1.743 0.982 1.700
(0.383)*** (0.455)*** (0.386)*** (0.463)** (0.513)***
[146] [146] [145] [145] [109]
1.545 0.678 1.654 0.429 0.731
(0.422)*** (0.464) (0.443)*** (0.475) (0.457)
[107] [107] [107] [107] [103]
4.281 3.637 3.031 1.630 3.995
(1.226)*** (1.272)*** (1.251)** (1.377) (1.608)**
[146] [146] [145] [145] [109]
1.436 0.668 1.431 0.458 1.140
(0.316)*** (0.395)* (0.339)*** -0.417 (0.453)**
[141] [140] [140] [139] [106]
Included Included
[0.026] [0.001]
Included Included
[0.002] [0.014]
Included Included
[0.000] [0.000]
Included
[0.000]
Variables are defined in Table I. Each column in the table reports Ordered Probit coefficients, robust
standard errors (in parentheses, below coefficient estimates), and number of observations (in brackets, below)
for the measures of polarization in society described in Table I. The table includes/?-values for Chi-square test
of joint significance of the control sets described in Table I. The marginal effects and p -values reported refer
to the specification employing the Ethnic Fractionalization Index of Alesina et al. [2004]. * significant at 10
percent; ** significant at 5 percent; *** significant at 1 percent.
29. These results are robust to controlling for various other variables includ
ing the fraction of population above 65, fraction of urban population, fraction of
population in agriculture, and life expectancy. These are all variables highly
correlated with GDP per capita. All these sensitivity tests are available upon
request.
TABLE IV
Separation of Powers and Polarization
ORDERED PROBIT
(1) (2) (3) (4)
Separation Separation Separation Separation
of powers of powers of powers of powers
(PRES, (PRES, (PRES, (PRES,
1990) 1990) 1990) 1990)
Ethnic 1.964 1.724 1.384 1.256
Fractionalization (0.390)*** (0.464)*** (0.500)*** (0.535)**
Index [141] [140] [141] [140]
Ethno-Linguistic 1.153 1.357 0.714 0.969
Fractionalization (0.392)*** (0.428)*** (0.502) (0.485)**
Index 1960 [106] [106] [106] [106]
Polarization (alpha 4.731 3.5 3.301 2.603
= 4/5) (1.451)*** (1.633)** (1.499)** (1.629)
[140] [139] [140] [139]
Linguistic 0.938 0.932 0.5 0.55
Fractionalization (0.326)*** (0.356)*** (0.430) (0.428)
Index [135] [134] [135] [134]
Control sets
Religion
Log(Real GDP) in
1960
Marginal effect at
mean from
partly free to not
free status 0.782 0.685 0.551 0.499
ORDERED PROBIT
(5) (6) (7) (8) (9)
Separation Separation Separation Separation Separation
of powers of powers of powers of powers of powers
(PRES, (PRES, (PRES, (PRES, (PRES,
1990) 1990) 1990) 1990) 1990)
1.642 1.485 1.704 0.957 L265
(0.457)*** (0.539)*** (0.406)*** (0.525)* (0.468)***
[140] [140] [139] [139] [109]
1.236 0.929 1.704 1.043 0.391
(0.515)** (0.622) (0.432)*** (0.579)* (0.439)
[106] [106] [106] [106] [103]
3.787 3.437 3.475 1.684 3.391
(1.584)** (1.598)** (1.482)** (1.596) (1.583)**
[139] [139] [138] [138] [108]
0.983 0.735 1.104 0.642 0.269
(0.399)** (0.474) (0.342)*** (0.502) (0.412)
[134] [134] [133] [133] [105]
Included Included
[0.801] [0.060]
Included Included
[0.000] [0.000]
Included Included
[0.000] [0.000]
Included
[0.000]
Variables are defined in Table I. Each column in the table reports Ordered Probit coefficients, robust
standard errors (in parentheses, below coefficient estimates) and number of observations (in brackets, below)
for the measures of polarization in society described in Table I. The table includes p -values for Chi-square test
of joint significance of the control sets described in Table I. The marginal effects and p -values reported refer
to the specification employing the Ethnic Fractionalization Index of Alesina et al. [2004]. * significant at 10
percent; ** significant at 5 percent; *** significant at 1 percent.
TABLE V
Executive Constraints and Polarization
OLS
(1) (2) (3) (4)
Executive Executive Executive Executive
constraints constraints constraints constraints
Religion
Log(Real GDP) in
1960
Included Included
[0.011] [0.009]
Included Included
[0.003] [0.282]
Included Included
[0.000] [0.001]
Included
[0.000]
Variables are defined in Table I. Each column in the table reports OLS coefficients, robust standard
errors (in parentheses, below coefficient estimates), number of observations (in brackets, below), and R2s (in
italics, further below) for the measures of polarization in society described in Table I. The table includes
p-values for F-test of joint significance of the control sets described in Table I. Thep-values reported refer to
the specification employing the Ethnic Fractionalization Index of Alesina et al. [2004]. * significant at 10
percent; ** significant at 5 percent; *** significant at 1 percent.
OLS
Total powers Total powers Total powers Total powers Total powers
of the of the of the of the of the
presidency presidency presidency presidency p
Ethnic 7.164 7.723 5.523 6.887 5.269
Fractionalization (3.940)* (5.322) (6.326) (4.359) (3.341)
Index [31] [31] [31] [30] [56]
0.10 0.19 0.33 0.15 0.03
Ethno-Linguistic 4.321 5.092 3.928 3.753 4.321
Fractionalization (3.281) (4.305) (4.231) (3.648) (3.281)
Index 1960 [30] [30] [30] [30] [30]
0.04 0.15 0.32 0.09 0.04
Polarization (alpha 31.057 31.841 21.929 4.152 17.824
= 4/5) (10.556)*** (13.776)* (13.615) (3.145) (10.085)*
[31] [31] [31] [28] [56]
0.26 0.30 0.39 0.21 0.06
Linguistic 4.484 8.123 7.959 29.898 2.161
Fractionalization (2.918) (4.019)* (3.356)** (11.064)* (3.063)
Index [29] [29] [29] [30] [53]
0.06 0.30 0.56 0.29 0.01
Control sets
Sample Shugart and Shugart and Shugart and Shugart and Shugart and
Carey Carey Carey Carey Carey [1992]
[1992] [1992] [1992] [1992] and NCSEER
Included
[0.321]
Included
[0.023]
Included
[0.569]
Shugart and Shugart and Shugart and Shugart and Shugart and
Carey Carey Carey Carey Carey [1992]
[1992] [1992] [1992] [1992] and NCSEER
Variables are defined in Table I. Each column in the table reports OLS coefficients, robust standard
errors (in parentheses, below coefficient estimates), number of observations (in brackets, below), and R2s (in
italics, further below) for the measures of polarization in society described in Table I. The table includes
p -values for F-test of joint significance of the control sets described in Table I. The p -values reported refer to
the specification employing the Ethnic Fractionalization Index of Alesina et al. [2004]. * significant at 10
percent; ** significant at 5 percent; *** significant at 1 percent.
PROBIT
(1) (2) (3) (4)
Plurality Plurality Plurality Plurality
rule rule rule rule
Ethnic Fractionalization 1.071 0.997 0.351 0.186
Index (0.488)** (0.565)* (0.611) (0.65)
[109] [109] [109] [109]
Ethno-Linguistic 1.481 1.031 0.651 0.065
Fractionalization Index (0.479)*** (0.541)* (0.588) (0.650)
1960 [95] [95] [95] [95]
Polarization (alpha = 4/5) 2.716 2.336 1.493 1.248
(1.588)* (1.844) (1.788) (2.008)
[108] [108] [108] [108]
Linguistic Fractionalization 0.94 0.726 -0.251 -0.594
Index (0.427)** (0.462) (0.576) (0.614)
[104] [104] [104] [104]
Control sets
Legal origin Included Included
[0.002] [0.002]
Regional dummies Included Included
[0.048] [0.031]
Colonial origin
Religion
tain types of checks and balances. The army itself has a very
"insulated" constitution; that is, nobody can question directives
from superior officers. In fact, the case of wars may be one
example in which Constitutions can be made contingent on one
particular event, namely war. So the Constitution can prescribe
special and more insulated procedures in times of declared wars.
PROBIT
Included Included
[0.312] [0.242]
Included Included
[0.000] [0.001]
Included Included
[0.003] [0.026]
Included
[0.115]
Variables are defined in Table I. Each column in the table reports Probit coefficients, robust standard
errors (in parentheses, below coefficient estimates) and number of observations (in brackets, below) for the
measures of polarization in society described in Table I. The table includes p-values for Chi-square test of
joint significance of the control sets described in Table I. The marginal effects and p -values reported refer to
the specification employing the Ethnic Fractionalization Index of Alesina et al. [2004]. * significant at 10
percent; ** significant at 5 percent; *** significant at 1 percent.
VI. Conclusions
30. For a recent discussion of the quality of politicians, see Caselli and
Morelli [2002].
31. This example was kindly provided to us by Matthew Jackson, and it
builds on Rae [1969].
do not know whether they will prefer x ory. Suppose that k is the
number of individuals who prefer x to y. If an individual has ex
post income a if her preferred alternative is selected and income
( ??) if the other alternative is chosen, then under risk neutrality
the ex ante total utility of choosing alternative x, is equal to
U(x) = ak- ?(l - k);
similarly,
U(y) = -?? + a(l-?)
if alternative y is chosen. Choosing M = V2 will then guarantee
that the alternative that maximizes total ex ante utility is always
chosen, namely x whenever k > V2 , and y otherwise. This rea
soning extends to collective decision problems like ours that boils
down to a utilitarian maximization problem: if M > V2 (respec
tively, M < V2), then reforms would take place too (respectively,
not sufficiently) often from the standpoint where voters expect
their preferences for reform to lie ex post.
Generalization of Proposition 1
Let us consider a ~ g(a), a E [-A,A], where g(a) =
dG(a)/da and G is the cumulative distribution function for the
shock a, and X? - f(X?), X? G [X,X] and A > 0, X > X, 7 > 0. For
simplicity let us fix p = 1 in this analysis. The maximization
problem for the voter under a veil of ignorance is
(?i-\-lM Ci
f(Xi)g(a) dX? da
+ l(Xl + a)f(Xl)g(a)dXlda
H-k-lM ' \
Proof of Proposition 2
Suppose that whenever (X? + a)y < 6, where 6 < 0, individual /
incurs a utility loss of ?u. Recall that the indifference voter between
reform and no reform, satisfies X? + a = X = I/7. The ex ante
maximization problem at the constitutional stage now becomes
\-\-lM
Cd/y-a 1 \ 1
max
M
Ip 2Ada ? up jdxA^da
X-X-IM
+ Jk-k~lM
p (\m-r-?)y^da-(l-p)Mb\
Rewriting the middle term in u as
CQ/y-a -|_
up
X-X-IM ldXi \2?da
-up 9 \ 1
~2M --\)(A-(X-X-ZM))-2(A2-(X
we can reexpress the original problem as
max
M {?- (X - X - IM - A) + ^ Kmy(A - (X - X - IM))
e
X (A-(X-X-ZM))
+ ?^(A2-(^-^-/M)2)-S
- 2 (A2 - (X - X - IM)2) (l-p)bM\
Taking first-order conditions with respect to M, we obtain
e
-K + IM
1-p 2Ab = 0.
G(u, M) = 7/(Xm - X - ZM) - u
Proof of Proposition 3
With polarization at the lower end of the preference inter
val and risk aversion as in the previous proposition, the ex ante
maximization problem at the constitutional stage, now
becomes
-\-(M-A)Z/(l-A) "L
UT\PJA 2?da
A+l ??-^dXi
(A / & \ 1
+ p \ Um - ~2 + a rt 2? da ~ ^
>\-\-(M-A)l/(l-A) \ j J
Taking first-order conditions with respect to M,
M (M - A)A I
y[im--7r-k
2 ^ 1-A/l-A
- M -- \ + ^?-irv)-2Ab =
It follows that under risk aversion and polarization t
degree of insulation is given by
yl(Xm - AZ/2 -\ + AZ/(1 - A))
(8) M* =+ u(\ - 9Ay)(l - A) - 2A6(1 - A)(l - p)/
l(-yl/(l - A) + u) '
Proof of Proposition 4
A policy reform will pass with com
if
(1 4- k)c(a) < a)
or equivalently
2W \1/2
/ 2?co
X-X-IM - a
,(i + *h
given that
l-?~lMy(X-X-lM-a)2 1
Eac(a)=\ -2/-2?da
da
7(X-X-ZM + A)3
12AI
\V) M (1) - 7
_ i-\+A-2y?(Ab(l-p)/P1k)
Eac(a) =J X-X-lM-(2lo>/(l+k)y)1/2
2?\ (X - X - IM - a)2^da
Proof of Proposition 5
We want to show that in a population symmetrically polar
ized and risk averse, if the minority sitting at the Constitutional
table, Ce, know that their type X is distributed over the interval
[X - e,X] with X - 8 > X, then
1. for all ? the level of insulation Me chosen by this minority
is greater than the optimal level M* chosen under the veil
of ignorance;
2. for 8 sufficiently small, constitution writers in Ce react to
an increase in polarization A by always increasing insu
lation Me.
First, note that the ex ante maximization problem faced by
the constitutional minority, can be written as
?fx-X-(M-A)?/(1-A) -[_
P 9~?da
B/y-a (]_ _ A)
dXi 2A
I "H -?rj da
A 1
+
X-\-(M-A)Z/
(EM p |
+
where
/X-8 (M-A)Z\ I ( /e ,
7^--T^^j(r^^-^m^l0'l7~x~z + ?
Z(M-A)\\ 1-p
+ -T^))-V^Afe = o,
and therefore,
8 AZ
(13) Me = Z(7Z/(1 - A) + u) yl\l-?2+ (1 - A)
+ u max ( 0, ( X - - + Z - 8 )(1 - A) + ZA
1-p
?^2A6(1-A)
That Me is greater than the corresponding rule M* under the veil
of ignorance, follows immediately from the comparison between
(8) and (13) together with the fact that
M
MP =
yP yl[l 2 + (1 - A)
2A6(1 - A)
Then:
dM? = 1 Z-e/2 1-p 1-A
--4A6
~d~K I yP >0,
so that for sufficiently low e the more constitution writers in the
minority react to an increase in polarization by increasing insu
lation. This establishes the proposition.
References
Acemoglu, Daron, and James Robinson, "Why Did the West Extend the Franchise:
Democracy, Inequality and Growth in Historical Perspective," Quarterly
Journal of Economics, CXV (2000), 1167-1199.
Acemoglu, Daron, and James Robinson, "A Theory of Political Transition," Ameri
can Economic Review, XCI (2001), 938-963.
Aghion, Philippe, and Patrick Bolton, "Incomplete Social Contracts," Journal of
the European Economic Association, I (2003), 38-67.
Aghion, Philippe, and Peter Howitt, Endogenous Growth Theory (Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press, 1998).
Aghion, Philippe, Alberto Alesina, and Francesco Trebbi, Choosing Forms of
Government: Evidence from US Cities," mimeo, Harvard University, 2004.
Alesina, Alberto, Arnaud Devleeschauer, William Easterly, Sergio Kurlat, and
Romain Wacziarg, "Fragmentation," Journal of Economic Growth, VIII
(2003), 155-194.
Alesina, Alberto, and Edward Glaeser, Fighting Poverty in the US and Europe: A
World of Difference (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2004, forthcoming).
Alesina, Alberto, and Howard Rosenthal, Partisan Politics Divided Government
and the Economy (New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, 1995).
Barbera, Salvador, and Matthew Jackson, "Choosing How to Choose: Self-Stable
Majority Rules," mimeo, California Institute of Technology, 2001.
Baron, David, "Majoritarian Incentives, Pork Barrel Programs and Procedural
Control," American Journal of Political Science, XXXIII (1991), 1048-1086.
Baron, David, and John Ferejohn, "Bargaining in Legislatures," American Politi
cal Science Review, LXXXIII (1989), 1181-1206.
Barro, Robert, "Democracy and Growth," Journal of Economic Growth, I (1996),
1-27.
Beard, Charles, An Economic Interpretation of the American Constitution (Lon
don, UK: Macmillan, 1941).
Beck, Thorsten, George Clark, Alberto Groff, Philip Keefer, and Patrick Walsh,
"New Tools and New Results in Comparative Political Economy: The Data
base of Political Institutions," World Bank Policy Research WP No. 2283,
2000.
Buchanan, James, The Limits of Liberty; Between Anarchy and the Leviathan
(Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1975).
Buchanan, James, and Gordon Tullock, The Calculus of Consent (Ann Arbor, MI:
University of Michigan Press, 1962).