Music in Theory and Practice: A Behavioral View
Music in Theory and Practice: A Behavioral View
Music in Theory and Practice: A Behavioral View
A Behavioral Viewt
by
JayRahn
studying music, then one might acknowledge that several such theories
and Charles Seeger are among the better known recent efforts to
This content downloaded from 128.151.124.135 on Sat, 16 Mar 2019 00:26:17 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
106
individual frameworks are far from clear. Such endeavours also do not
meet the needs that I would envision for a theory of music in that they
more thoroughly unified and integrated and that bears directly on the
practice of music.
Behaviorism.
that it adopts a stance which seems to have been, both intellectually and
and so forth.
This content downloaded from 128.151.124.135 on Sat, 16 Mar 2019 00:26:17 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
107
approaches can be attributed to, among other factors, the diversity that
Whereas there are certain issues about which behaviorists are virtually
unanimous, indeed adamant, there are others that are a source of division
This content downloaded from 128.151.124.135 on Sat, 16 Mar 2019 00:26:17 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
108
tape, or a series of 0's and l's onto a computer disc. Getting a student
one might theorize. In a behavioral theory of music, one need not feel
that one is trapped inside musical tones; instead, one can deal seriously
with overt acts that are involved in performing, creating and teaching
music.
physical process that begins at the point where given sound wav
perceived or imagined sometime in the past. Finally, one can note tha
This content downloaded from 128.151.124.135 on Sat, 16 Mar 2019 00:26:17 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
109
regarded as physical acts that involve the manipulation, and even the
basilar membrane) are physical rather than occult and have bee
This content downloaded from 128.151.124.135 on Sat, 16 Mar 2019 00:26:17 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
110
person "heard" the tone and adjusted the muscles of his or her vocal tract
stimulus-tone out of account and regard the incident as one in which the
time being, other causes which such a radical behaviorist might cite,
one can note that an account of this sort would have the merit of being
investigator, whereas any private "hearing" of the tone would be left out
of the account. Indeed, some radical behaviorists would deny that there
the founder of the school, and that of Skinner, the foremost theorist of
the school.
This content downloaded from 128.151.124.135 on Sat, 16 Mar 2019 00:26:17 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Ill
more than muscular movements in the vocal tract happened between the
This content downloaded from 128.151.124.135 on Sat, 16 Mar 2019 00:26:17 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
112
apology that what happened was physical, and would take pains to
excessively optimistic.
happened between the occurrence of the two tones, and like the
they might diverge from one another with regard to the sorts of
This content downloaded from 128.151.124.135 on Sat, 16 Mar 2019 00:26:17 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
113
things and events that are directly observed, or, in principle, observable,
verbal response) in its own right, rather than as indirect evidence for
effect rather than a cause. In this way, the musical ear seems to
This content downloaded from 128.151.124.135 on Sat, 16 Mar 2019 00:26:17 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
114
Causal Explanation.
resulted. Among the most important of these is that one can effectively
account for why a living being (either a human or one of the lower
animals) acts in the way that it does entirely in terms of specific aspects
past.
regarded as having consequences for the survival of the species and are
This content downloaded from 128.151.124.135 on Sat, 16 Mar 2019 00:26:17 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
115
for example, Debussy wrote a given piece as he did, one would inquire
not only into his genetic make-up (e.g., his musical talent) but also
Lapps sing joiks in the way that they do, one would inquire into their
This content downloaded from 128.151.124.135 on Sat, 16 Mar 2019 00:26:17 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
116
and stimulation that are most similar to the activity and stimulation
being considered.
on indirect evidence to any greater extent than those who hold differing
This content downloaded from 128.151.124.135 on Sat, 16 Mar 2019 00:26:17 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
117
counterparts.4
This content downloaded from 128.151.124.135 on Sat, 16 Mar 2019 00:26:17 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
118
curricula for performance, ear training (or dictation) and sight singing.
composers have been the best "musical engineers" in the sense that they
the greatest extent, whether or not any of the parties were, to use a non-
one need not thereby deny many of the most engaging findings of other
This content downloaded from 128.151.124.135 on Sat, 16 Mar 2019 00:26:17 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
119
this way, the theory and practice of arts administration and the music
industry need not be cut off from other musical endeavors. Moreover,
and humanities, and I feel that an important factor in this regard has
This content downloaded from 128.151.124.135 on Sat, 16 Mar 2019 00:26:17 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
120
forth. Indeed, it is not entirely clear that any distinction whatever need
"the chord of Nature") from many music theories, one finds that one is
Indeed, I feel that much of what passes as music theory can be regarded
This content downloaded from 128.151.124.135 on Sat, 16 Mar 2019 00:26:17 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
121
matter of the fine arts and humanities, one is confronted with enormous
relevance that the description might have for a causal account of the
I do not mean to deny that causality might enter into even the
most hermetic analysis of a work of art. Rather, I would insist that the
an account could be quite low in level or even trivial (e.g., on the order
causal account that is more than trivial, one's description might have to
This content downloaded from 128.151.124.135 on Sat, 16 Mar 2019 00:26:17 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
122
have written a piece in a certain way or why listeners to the work might
A Musico-Behavioral Hypothesis.
activity.
This content downloaded from 128.151.124.135 on Sat, 16 Mar 2019 00:26:17 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
123
playing, singing and setting notes onto paper. It would also seem that
where, for example, a piano key does not produce a sound when
of the resulting tones (or even with one's imagining of such tones as in
not feel that such intrinsic reinforcers can fully account for humanity's
This content downloaded from 128.151.124.135 on Sat, 16 Mar 2019 00:26:17 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
124
meat-not right now, thank you very much. And in the same way, one
might "crave" musical structure but not hunger after a particular kind or
occasion or cease eating when one is full, so too might one tend to seek
the kinds and amounts of complexity that have reinforced people have
which include the sounds that have been "in the air" at any given time,
This content downloaded from 128.151.124.135 on Sat, 16 Mar 2019 00:26:17 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
125
central importance not only to the scholar but also to the practitioner of
listeners.
Conclusion.
framework, one can travel rather freely among the major curren
one might begin to entertain the prospect of a theory of music that not
This content downloaded from 128.151.124.135 on Sat, 16 Mar 2019 00:26:17 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms