Kinds of Minds Toward An Understanding of Consciousness - Daniel C Dennett
Kinds of Minds Toward An Understanding of Consciousness - Daniel C Dennett
Kinds of Minds Toward An Understanding of Consciousness - Daniel C Dennett
KINDS OF MINDS
D A N I E L C. D E N N E T T
• BasicBooks
A Division of HarperCollinsPublishers
The Science Masters Series is a global publish
ing venture consisting of original science books
written by leading scientists and published by
a worldwide team of twenty-six publishers
assembled by John Brockman. The series was
conceived by Anthony Cheetham of Orion Pub
lishers and John Brockman of Brockman Inc., a
New York literary agency, and developed in
coordination with BasicBooks.
Published by BasicBooks
A Division of HarperCollinsPublishers, Inc.
FIRST EDITION
ISBN 0-465-07350-6
96 97 98 99 oo •:•/HC 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
CO N T E N T S
Preface vii
We Mind-Havers, We Minders 3
v
vi CONTENTS
B ibliography 1 75
Index 1 80
P R E F A CE
vii
viii PREFACE
W H AT K I N D S O F M I N D S A R E T H E R E ?
K N OW I N G YO U R OW N M I N D
sism (from Latin for " myself alone" ) . Nobody ever takes
solipsism seriously for long , as far as we know, but it does
raise an imp ortant challenge : if we know that solipsism is
silly-if we know that there are other minds-how do we
know?
What kinds of minds are there? And how do we know?
The first question is about what exists-about on tology, in
philosophical p arlance; the second question is about our
knowledge-about epistemology. The goal of this book is not
to answer these two questions once and for all , but rather to
show why these questions have to be answered together.
Philosophers often warn against confusing ontological ques
tions with epistemological questions. What exists is one
thing, they say, and what we can know about it is something
else. There may be things that are comp letely unknowable to
us , so we must be careful not to treat the limits of our knowl
e dge as sure guides to the limits of what there is. I agree that
this is good general advice , but I will argue that we already
know enough about minds to know that one of the things
that makes them different from everything else in the uni
verse is the way we know about them. For instance , you
know you have a mind and you know you have a brain , but
W H A T K I N D S O F M I N D S A R E T H E R E? 3
W E M I N D- H AV E R S , W E M I N D E R S
can 't even know what the question i s , if you don't know
what a flurb is supposed to be. Whatever else a mind i s , it is
supposed to be something like our minds; otherwise we
wouldn't call it a mind. ) S o our minds , the only minds we
know from the outset , are the standard with which we must
begin. Without this agreement, we'll just be fooling our
selves , talking rubbish without knowing it.
When I address you , I include us both in the class of
mind-havers . This unavoidable starting p oint creates, or
acknowle dges , an in-group , a class of privileged characters ,
set off against everything else in the universe. This is almost
too obvious to notice , so deeply enshrined is it in our think
ing and talking , but I must dwell on it. When there 's a we,
you are not alone; solipsism is false; there 's company pres
ent. This comes out p articularly clearly if we consider some
curious variations :
WO R D S A N D M I N D S
T H E P RO B L E M O F
I N CO M M U N I CAT I V E M I N D S
It 's very hard to tell what somebody is thinking who won 't
discuss it-or who can ' t , for one reason or another. But we
normally suppose that such incommunicative folks are
indeed thinking-that they do have minds-even if we can't
confirm the details. This much is obvious , if only because
we can readily imagine ourselves in a situation in which we
would steadfastly refuse to communicate, all the while
thinking our private thoughts, perhaps reflecting with
amusement on the difficulties that observers were having in
figuring out what , if anything , was going on in our minds .
Talking , no matter how conclusive its presence may b e , is
not necessary for having a mind. From this obvious fact we
are tempted to draw a problematic conclusion: there could
be entities who do have minds but who cannot tell us what
they 're thinking-not because they 're paralyzed or suffering
from aphasia (the inability to communicate verbally due to
localized brain damage) , but because they have no capacity
for language at all . Why do I say this is a problematic con
clusion?
First let's consider the case to be made in its favor. Surely,
tradition and common sense declare , there are minds with
out language. Surely our ability to discuss with others what
is going on in our minds is just a p eripheral talent , in the
sense in which one speaks of a computer's laser printer as a
peripheral device (the computer can go right on computing
without a printer attached ) . Surely nonhuman animals-at
least, some of them-have mental lives . Surely human
infants before they acquire language , and human deaf
mutes-even those rare deaf-mutes who have never acquired
even sign language-have minds. Surely. These minds may
doubtless differ in many hard-to-fathom ways from our
W H A T K I N D S O F M I N D S A R E T H E R E? 13
creatures who lack language , there are some that do not have
minds at all , but do everything " automatically " or "uncon
sciously. "
The traditional response to this prospect , too , is to
embrace it. Yes indeed , some creatures entirely lack minds.
Surely bacteria are mindles s , and s o , probably, are amoebas
and starfish. Quite p ossibly even ants , for all their clever
activity, are mere mindless automata, trundling about in the
world without the s lightest experience or thought. What
about trout? What about chickens? What about rats? We may
never be able to tell where to draw the line between those
creatures that have minds and those that do not , but this is
j ust another aspect of the unavoidable limitations on our
knowledge. Such facts may be systematically unknowable,
not just hard to uncover.
Here , then , are two sorts of supposedly unknowable facts :
facts about what is going on in those who have minds but no
way of talking about their thoughts, and facts about which
creatures have minds at all. These two varieties of off-limits
ignorance are not equally easy to accept. The differences
between min ds might be differences whose maj or outlines
were readily discernible to objective observers but whose
minor details became harder and harder to determine-a
case of diminishing returns for labor invested. The unknown
leftovers would not be mysteries but j ust inevitable gaps in a
richly informative but finite catalog of similarities and dif
ferences. The differences between minds would then be like
the differences between languages , or styles of music or art
inexhaustible in the limit, but approachable to any degree of
approximation you like. But the difference between having a
mind and not having a mind at all-between being some
thing with its own subj ective p oint of view and being some
thing that is all outside and no inside , like a rock or a dis
carded sliver of fingernail-is apparently an all-or-nothing
difference. It is much harder to accept the idea that no
W H A T K I N D S O F M I N D S A R E T H E R E? 15
ing in any mind. But p erhaps the arm has a mind of its own.
Perhap s it has always had one but has j ust been unable to
talk to us about it! Wel l , why not? It does have a substantial
number of nerve cells in it, still firing away. If we found a
whole organism with that many active nerve cells in it , we
would be strongly inclined to suppose that it was capable of
experiencing pain, even if it couldn 't express itself in terms
we could understand. Here intuitions collide : arms don't
have minds , in spite of containing plenty of the processes
and materials that tend to persuade us that some nonhuman
animals do have minds .
Is it behavior that counts? Suppose you pinched the
thumb of the amputated arm and it pinched you back !
Would you then decide to give it novocaine? If not, why not?
Because its reaction would have to be an " automatic" reflex?
How can you be so sure? Is it something about the organiza
tion of those nerve cells that makes the difference?
These puzzle cases are fun to think about, and we learn
important facts about our naive concepts of mind when we
try to figure out why our intuitions line up the way they do,
but there must be a better way of investigating kinds of
minds-and nonminds that might fool us. The defeatist con
viction that we will never know should be postponed indefi
nitely, saved as a last-gasp conclusion to be reached only
after we have actually exhausted all other avenues and not
just imagined doing so. There may be surprises and illumi
nations awaiting us.
One prospect to consider, whether or not in the end we
rule it out, is that p erhaps language is not so p eripheral to
minds after all. Perhap s the kind of mind you get when you
add language to it is so different from the kind o f mind you
can have without language that calling them both minds is a
mistake. Perhaps , in other words , our sense that there are
riches in the minds of other creatures-riches inaccessible to
us but not, of course, to them-is an illusion. The philosopher
18 KINDS OF MINDS
I NT E N T I O N A L I TY:
T H E I N T E N T I O N A L S Y S T E M S A P P R O A CH
19
20 KINDS OF M I N DS
A D O P T I N G T H E I N T E N T I O N A L S TA N C E
fused with it, and indeed are rather closely related t o it. One
is an ordinary term , the other is technical (and I will post
pone its introduction briefly) . In ordinary parlance, we often
discuss whether someone 's action was intentional or not.
When the driver crashed into the bridge abutment , was he
intentionally committing suicide , or had he fallen asleep?
When you called the policeman "Dad" just then , was that
intentional , or a slip of the tongue? Here we are asking , are
we not, about the intentionality of the two deeds? Yes , in the
ordinary sense; no, in the philosophical sense.
Intentionality in the philosophical sense is just
aboutness. Something exhibits intentionality if its compe
tence is in some way abou t something else. An alternative
would be to say that something that exhibits intentionality
contains a represen tation of something else-but I find that
less revealing and more problematic . Does a lock contain a
representation of the key that opens it? A lock and key
exhibit the crudest form of intentionality; so do the opioid
receptors in brain cells-receptors that are designed to
accept the endorphin molecules that nature has been provid
ing in brains for millions of years . B oth can be tricked-that
i s , opened by an impostor. Morphine molecules are artifac
tual skeleton keys that have recently been fashioned to open
the opioid-receptor doors too. (In fact it was the discovery of
these highly specific receptors which inspired the search
that led to the discovery of endorphins, the brain's own
painkillers . There must have been something already present
in the brain , reasearchers reasoned , for these specialized
receptors to have been abo u t in the first place . ) This lock
and-key variety of crude aboutness is the basic design ele
ment out of which nature has fashioned the fancier sorts of
subsystems that may more deservedly be called representa
tion systems , so we will have to analyze the aboutness of
these representations in terms of the (quasi?) aboutness of
locks-and-keys in any case. We can stretch a p oint and say
36 KINDS OF M I N DS
T H E M I S G U I D E D G OA L O F
PROPOSITIONAL PREC ISION
unless you have the concepts of dish and beef, and to have
these concepts you have to have a host of other concepts
(bucket, plate, cow, flesh , . . . ), since this particular thought
is readily distinguishable (by us) from the thought
th at the red, tasty stuff in the thing that I usually eat from
is not th e usual dry stuff th ey feed me
and believing
that th e sun has been the same star, each day, since Jan u
ary 1 , 1 900, when th e latest s u n took over its role from its
predecessor.
x believes that p.
y desires that q.
z wonders whether r.
1 . Snow is white.
2. La neige est blanche .
3 . Der Schnee ist weis s .
They all " say the same thing," and yet they all say " it" in dif
ferent ways. Should propositions line up with ways of say
ing or with things said? A simp l e , theoretically appealing
way of settling the issue would be to ask whether a believer
can believe one of these without believing another. If so,
then they are different propositions. After all , if propositions
are to be the theoretical entities that measure belief, we
wouldn't want this test to fail . But how can we test this if
Tom isn't an English speaker, or a speaker at all? We attribut-
I N T E N T I O N A L I TY 47
x has weight-in-grams of 1 4 4 .
y has speed-in-meters-per-second of 1 2.
O R I G I N A L A N D D E R I V E D I N T E N T I O N A L I TY
make them and use them. Those mental states and acts have
original intentionality.
The p oint about the dependent status of artifactual repre
sentations is undeniable. Manifestly, the pencil marks in
themselves don't mean a thing . This is particularly clear in
cases of ambiguous sentences. The philosopher W. V. 0 .
Quine gives us the nice exampl e :
view; they are about what they are about because , like pic
tures, they resemble their objects . How do I tell my idea of a
duck from my idea of a cow? By noting that my idea of a
duck looks like a duck, while my idea of a cow doesn 't!
Thi s , too , is hopeless , because it immediately raises the
question, And how do you know what a duck looks like?
Again , it's not hopeless because there couldn't be a system of
imagery in your brain that exp loits pictorial resemblances
between the brain's internal images and the things they rep
resent; indeed, there could be. In fact , there i s, and we are
beginning to understand how such a system works . It is
hopeless as an answer to our basic question, however,
because it depends on the very understanding that it's sup
posed to exp lai n, and hence goes round in circles.
The solution to this problem of our intentionality is
straightforward. We just agreed that representati onal arti
facts (such as written descriptions and sketches) possess
derived intentionality, by virtue of the role they play in the
activities of their creators . A shopping list written down on a
piece of paper has only the derived intentionality it gets
from the intentions of the agent who made it. Wel l , so does a
shopping list held by the same agent in memory ! Its inten
ti onality is exactly as derived as that of the external list, and
for the same reasons . Similarly, a merely mental image of
your mother-or Michelle Pfeiffer-is about its obj ect in just
as derived a way as the sketch you draw. It is internal, not
external , but it is still an artifact created by your brain and
means what it does because of its particular position in the
ongoing economy of your brain's internal activities and their
role in governing your body 's complex activities in the real ,
surrounding world.
And how did your brain come to have an organization of
such amazing states with such amazing powers? Play the
same card again : the brain is an artifact , and it gets whatever
intentionality its parts have from their role in the ongoing
I NT E N T I O NALITY 53
T H E B O DY A N D I T S M I N D S
F R O M S E N S I T I V I T Y TO S E N T I E N C E ?
T H E M E D I A A N D T H E M E S S AG E S
sound-sensitive parts of the ear are still intact, but the trans
mission of the results of their work to the rest of the brain has
been disrupted . This destroyed avenue can now be replaced
by a prosthetic link, a tiny cable made of a different material
(wire , just as in a standard computer) , and since the inter
faces at both ends of the cable can be matched to the require
ments of the existing healthy material s , the signals can get
through. Hearing is restored. It doesn 't matter at all what the
medium of transmission is, just as long as the information
gets through without loss or distortion.
This important theoretical idea sometimes leads to seri
ous confusions , however. The most seductive confusion
could be called the Myth of Double Transduction : first , the
nervous system transduces light , sound, temperature , and so
forth into neural signals (trains of impulses in nerve fibers)
and second , in some special central place , it transduces
these trains of impulses into some oth er medium, the
medium of consciousness ! That 's what Descartes thought ,
and he suggested that the pineal gland, right in the center of
the brain, was the place where this second transduction took
place-into the mysterious , nonphysical medium of the
mind. To day almost no one working on the mind thinks
there is any such nonphysical medium. Strangely enough ,
though , the idea of a second transduction into some special
physical or material medium , in some yet-to-be-identified
place in the brai n , continues to beguile unwary theorists . It
is as if they saw-or thought they saw-that since peripheral
activity in the nervous system was mere sensitivity, there
had to be some more central place where the sentience was
created . After all, a live eyeball , disconnected from the rest
of the brai n, cannot see, has no conscious visual experience,
so that must happen later, when the mysterious x is added to
mere sensitivity to yield sentience .
The reasons for the persistent attractiveness of this idea
are not hard to find. One is tempted to think that mere nerve
THE BODY AND ITS M I N DS 73
" M Y B O DY H A S A M I N D O F I T S OW N ! "
that can trigger still further events . (Rho dopsin is one such
photosensitive substance, and this protein has been the
ma terial of ch oke f o a]] n a t u ral ey es, from ants to fish to
eagles to people. Artificial eyes might use some other photo
sensitive element , but not just anything will d o . ) In order to
identify and disable an antigen, you need an antibody that
has the right shape, since the identification is by the lock
and-key method. This limits the choice of antibody building
materials to molecules that can fold up into these shapes ,
and this severely restricts the molecules' chemical composi
tion-though not completely (as the example of lysozyme
varieties shows ) . In theory, every information-processing
system is tied at both ends , you might say, to transducers
and effectors whose physical composition is dictated by the
jobs they have to do; in between, everything can be accom
plished by media-neutral processes.
The control systems for ships , automobiles , oil refineries,
and other complex human artifacts are media-neutral , as
long as the media used can do the j ob in the avai lable time .
The neural control systems for animal s, however, are not
really media-neutral-not because the control systems have
to be made of particular materials in order to generate that
special aura or buzz or whatever, but because they evolved
as the control systems of organisms that already were lav
ishly equipped with highly distributed control system s , and
the new systems had to be built on top of, and in deep col
laboration with , these earlier system s , creating an astronomi
cally high number of points of transduction. We can occa
sionally ignore these ubiquitous interpenetrations of
different media-as , for instance , when we rep lace a single
nerve highway, like the auditory nerve, with a prosthetic
substitute-but only in a fantastic thought experiment could
we ignore these interpenetrations in general.
For example: The molecular keys needed to unlock the
locks that control every transaction between nerve cells are
76 KINDS OF M I N DS
The fact that your nervous system, unlike the control sys
tem of a modern shi p , is not an insulate d , media-neutral
control system-the fact that it " effects " and " transduces " at
almost every juncture-forces us to think about the func
tions of their parts in a more complicated (and realistic) way.
This recognition makes life slightly more difficult for func
tionalist philosophers of mind. A thousand philosophical
thought experiments (including my own story, " Where am
I?" [ 1 9 78 ] ) have exploited the intuition that I am not my
body but my body's . . . owner. In a heart transp lant opera
tion , you want to be the recipient, not the donor, but in a
brain transplant operation, you want to be the donor-you go
with the brain, not the body. In principle (as many philoso
phers have argued) , I might even trade in my current brain
for another, by rep lacing the medium while preserving only
the message. I could travel by teleportation, for instance, as
long as the information was perfectly preserved. In princi
ple, yes-but only because one would be transmitting infor
mation about the whole body, not just the nervous system.
One cannot tear me apart from my body leaving a nice clean
edge , as philosophers have often supposed. My body contains
as much of me, the values and talents and memories and dis
positions that make me who I am , as my nervous system does.
The legacy of Descartes's notorious dualism of mind and
body extends far beyond academia into everyday thinking :
"These athletes are prepared both mentally and physically, ''
and " There's nothing wrong with your bo dy-it's all in your
mind. " Even among those of us who have battled Descartes 's
vision , there has been a powerful tendency to treat the mind
(that is to say, the brain) as the body's boss , the pilot of the
shi p . Falling in with this standard way of thinking , we
ignore an important alternative : viewing the brain (and
hence the mind) as one organ among many, a relatively
recent usurper of contro l , whose functions cannot properly
be understood until we see it not as the boss but as just one
78 KI N DS OF M I N DS
" B ody a m I , and soul "-thus speaks the child. And why
should one not speak like children? But the awakened
and knowing say : body am I entirely, and nothing else;
and soul is only a word for something about the bo dy.
The body is a great reason, a p lurality with one sense ,
a war and a p eace, a herd and a shepherd. An instrument
THE BODY AND ITS M I N DS 79
H OW I N T E N T I O N A L I T Y
CA M E I N T O F O C U S
T H E TOW E R O F G E N E R AT E - A N D - T E S T *
81
82 KINDS OF MINDS
�
Darwinian creatures, different
"hardwired" phenotypes
�
$
...
.
0
::i
a
g
...,
ioral options they were equipped to " try out. " But others , w e
may suppose, were fortunate enough to have wired-in " rein
forcers " that happened to favor Smart Moves-that i s ,
actions that were better for the candidates than the available
alternative actions. These individuals thus confronted the
environment by generating a variety of actions , which they
tried out, one by one, until they found one that worked .
They detected that it worked only by getting a p ositive o r
negative signal fr o m t h e environment, which adjusted the
probability of that action 's being repro duced on another
occasion. Any creatures wired up wrong-with positive and
negative reinforcement reversed-would be doomed, of
course. Only those fortunate enough to be born with appro
priate reinforcers would have an advantage. We may call this
subset of Darwinian creatures Skinnerian creatures, since , as
the behaviorist psychologist B. F. Skinner was fon d of point
ing out, such " operant conditioning " is not just analogous to
Darwinian natural selection; it is an extension o f it: " Where
inherited behavior leaves off, the inherited modifiability of
the process of conditioning takes over. " ( 1 9 5 3 , p. 8 3 )
The cognitive revolution that emerged in the 1 9 70s
ousted behaviorism from its dominant p osition in p sychol
ogy, and ever since there has been a tendency to underesti
mate the power of Skinnerian conditioning (or its variations)
to shape the behavioral comp etence of organisms into highly
adaptive and discerning structures. The flourishing work on
neural networks and " connectionis m " in the 1 99 0 s , how
ever, has demonstrated anew the often surprising virtuosity
of simple networks that begin life more or less randomly
wired and then have their connections adjusted by a simple
sort of " experience "-the history o f reinforcement they
encounter.
The fundamental idea of letting the environment p lay a
blind but selective role in shaping the mind (or brain or con
trol system) has a pedigree even older than Darwin. The
intellectual ancestors of today's connectionists and yester-
86 KINDS OF MINDS
Skinnerian creature
F I G U RE 4 . 2
There are , however, some cognitive tricks that such ABC net
works have not yet been trained to perform , and-a more
telling criticism-there are some cognitive tricks that are
quite c learly not the result of training at all. Some animals
seem to be capable of " one-shot learning " ; they can figure
some things out without having to endure the arduous
process o f trial-and-error in the harsh world that is the hall
mark o f all ABC learning.
S kinnerian conditioning is a good thing as long as you
are not killed by one of your early errors . A better system
involves preselection among all the possible behaviors or
actions , so that the truly stupid moves are weeded out before
they're hazarded in " real life . " We human beings are crea
tures capable of this p articular refinement , but we are not
alone. We may call the beneficiaries of this third floor in the
Tower Popperian creatures, since , as the philosopher Sir
Karl Popper once elegantly put it, this design enhancement
" p ermits our hypotheses to die in our stead. " Unlike the
merely Skinnerian creatures , many of whom survive only
because they make lucky first move s, Popperian creatures
survive because they 're smart enough to make better-than
chance first moves. Of course they 're just lucky to be smart ,
but that's better than being j ust lucky.
How is this preselection in Popp erian agents to be done?
There must be a filter, and any such filter must amount to a
sort of inn er en vironmen t, in which tryouts can be safely
executed-an inner something-or-other structured in such a
way that the surrogate actions it favors are more often than
not the very actions the real world would also bless , if they
were actually p erformed. In short , the inner environment,
whatever it i s , must contain lots of information about the
outer environment and its regularities . Nothing else (except
magic ) could provide preselection worth having. (One could
always flip a coin or consult an oracle , but this is no
improvement over blind trial and error-unless the coin or
HOW I NT E N T I O NALITY CAM E I NTO FOCUS 89
FIGURE 4.3
90 KINDS OF MINDS
T H E S EARC H F O R S E N T I E N C E :
A P R O G R E S S R E P O RT
In this case , the toad's status falls to " mere automaton , "
something that w e may interfere with i n any imaginable way
with no moral compunction whatever. Given what we
already know about toads , does it seem plausible that there
could be some h eretofore unimagined feature the discovery
o f which could j usti fy this enormous difference in our atti
tude? Of cours e , if we discovered that toads were really tiny
human beings trapped in toad bodies , like the prince in the
fairy tal e , we would immediately have grounds for the
utmost solicitude, for we would know that in spite of all
behavioral appearances , toads were capable of enduring all
the tortures and anxieties we consider so important in our
own cases. But we already know that a toad is no such thing.
We are being asked to imagine that there is some x that is
nothing at all like being a human prince trapped in a toad
skin, but is nevertheless morally compelling. We also
already know, however, that a toad is not a simple wind-up
toy but rather an exquisitely complex living thing capable of
a staggering variety of self-protective activities in the further
ance of its preordained task of making more generations of
toads . Isn't that already enough to warrant some special
regard on our p art? We are being asked to imagine that there
is some x that is nothing at all like this mere sophistication
o f-control-structure , but that nevertheless would command
our moral appreciation when we discovered it. We are being
aske d , I suspect, to indulge in something beyond fantasy.
But let us continue with our search, to see what comes next ,
for we are still a long way from human minds .
F R O M P H OTOTA X I S TO M E TA P H Y S I C S
F I G U RE 4.4
HOW I N T E N T I O N A L I TY CAM E I NTO F O C U S 101
'\. I I /
:::Q::I I
"
\
\
F I G U RE 4.5
* O dors are not used only for identification signals. They often p lay
powerful roles in attracting a mate or even suppressing the sexual
activity or maturation of one 's rivals. Signals from the olfactory
bulb bypass the thalamus on their way to the rest of the brain, so in
contrast to the signals arising in vision, hearing , and even touch ,
olfactory commands go directly to the old control centers, elimi
nating many middlemen. It is likely that this more direct route
helps to exp lain the peremptory , nearly hypnotic power some
odors have over us.
1 04 KINDS OF M I N DS
Mama , and let the reflected light of the sun create a beacon
visible only in particular sectors of the world and readily
extinguished by Mama's simply moving into the shadows .
The offspring can then follow the blue spot whenever it is
visible. But this setup requires an investment in more
sophisticated photosensitive machinery : a simple eye , for
instance-not just a pair of photocells.
The ability to stay in reliably close contact with one par
ticular ecologically very important thing (such as Mama)
does not require the ability to conceive of this thing as an
enduring particular entity, coming and going. As we have
just seen , reliable Mamataxis can be achieved with a bag of
simple tricks . The talent is normally robust in simple envi
ronments, but a creature armed with such a simple system is
easily " foole d , " and when it is fooled, it trundles to its mis
fortune without any appreciation of its folly. There need be
no capability for the system to monitor its own success or
reflect on the conditions under which it succeeds or fails ;
that's a later (and expensive) add-on.
Cooperative tracking-tracking in which the target pro
vides a handy beacon and thus simplifies the task for the
tracker-is a step on the way toward competitive tracking , in
which the target not only provides no unique signature bea
con but actively tries to hide, to make itself untrackable.
This move by prey is countered by the development in preda
tors of general-purpose, track-anything system s , designed to
turn whatever aspects a trackworthy thing reveals into a sort
of private and temp orary beacon-a " search image , " created
for the nonce by a gaggle of feature-detectors in the predator
and used to correlate , moment by moment , the signature of
the target , revising and updating the search image as the tar
get changes , always with the goal of keeping the picked-out
obj ect in the cross-hairs .
It is important to recognize that this variety of tracking
does not require categorization of the target. Think of a prim-
1 06 K I N DS O F M I N DS
*This point about the primacy of tracking over descri ption is, I
think, the glimmer of truth in the otherwise forlorn philosophical
doctrine that there are two varieties of belief-de re beliefs, which
are somehow " directly" about their objects , and de dicta beliefs ,
which are about their objects only through the mediation of a dic
tum , a definite descri ption (in a natural language , or in some " lan
guage of thought " ) . The contrast is i l lustrated (supposedly) by the
difference between
and
ized. But there are also non-B oolean ways that systems can
intermingle their effects . Instead of bringing all the contribu
tors to a central voting plac e , giving them each a single vote
(YES or NO, ON or OFF) , and thereby channeling their con
tribution to behavior into a single vulnerable decision point
(the summed effect of all the B oolean connections) , we
could let them maintain their own indep endent and contin
uously variable links to behavior and have the worl d extract
an outcome behavior as the result of all the activity.
Valentino Braitenberg 's vehicle, with its two cross-wired
phototransducers , is an utterly simple case in point. The
" decision " to turn left or right emerges from the relative
strength of the contributions of the two transducer-motor
systems, but the effect is not efficiently or usefully repre
sented as a Boolean function of the respective " arguments "
of the trans ducers . (In principle, the input-output behavior
of any such system can be approximated by a B oolean func
tion of its components , suitably analyzed, but such an ana
lytic stunt may fail to reveal what is imp ortant about the
relationships . Considering the weather as a B oolean system
is possible in principle, for instance , but unworkable and
uninformative . )
B y installing dozens o r hundreds o r thousands of such
circuits in a single organism , elaborate life-protecting activi
ties can be reliably controlled, all without anything happen
ing inside the organism that looks like thinking specific
though ts. There is plenty of as if decision making , as if rec
ognizing , as if hiding and seeking. There are also lots of
ways an organism, so equipped, can " make mistakes , " but its
mistakes never amount to formulating a representation of
some false proposition and then deeming it true.
How versatile can such an architecture be? It is hard to
say. Researchers have recently designed and test-driven arti
ficial control systems that produce many of the striking
behavioral patterns we observe in relatively simple life-
1 10 KINDS OF M I NDS
of ripe fruit met his nostrils , but this would not show that he
had any way of distinguishing between recurring season
types, such as autumn, and returning individual s , such as
Ulysses. Is Ulysses , to Argos , just an organized c ollection of
pleasant smells and sounds , sights and feelings-a sort of
irregularly recurring season (we haven 't had one for twenty
years ! ) , during which particular behaviors are favored? It is a
season that is usually sober, but some instances of it have
been known to be drunk. We can see, from our peculiar
human perspective , that Argos 's success in this world will
often depend on how closely his behavior approximates the
behavior of an agent who , like us adult human beings ,
clearly distinguishes between individual s . S o we find that
when we interpret his behavior from the intentional stan ce,
w e do w el l to attribute beliefs to Argos that distinguish
Ulysses from other peop l e , strong rival dogs from weaker
rival dogs , lambs from other animals , Ithaca from other
places , and so forth . But we must be prepared to discover
that this apparent understanding of his has shocking gaps in
it-gaps inconceivable in a human being with our concep
tual scheme , and hence utterly inexpressible in the terms of
a human language.
Tales of intelligence in p ets have been commonplace for
millennia. The ancient Stoic philosopher Chrysippus
reported a dog that could perform the following feat of rea
son: coming to a three-way fork, he sniffed down p aths A
and B , and witho u t sniffing C , ran down C , having reasoned
that if there is no scent down A and B, the quarry must have
gone down C. People are less fond o f telling tales of j aw
dropping stupidity in their p ets , and often resist the implica
tions of the gaps they discover in their p ets ' competences.
Such a smart doggie , but can he figure out how to unwind
his leash when he runs around a tree or a lamppost? This is
not, it would seem, an unfair intelligence test for a dog
compared , say, with a test for sensitivity to irony in poetry,
1 16 KINDS OF M I N DS
that one , and exactly one , of the fol lowing two propositions
is true:
T H E C R E AT I O N O F T H I N K I N G
U N T H I N K I N G N AT U RA L P S Y C H O L O G I S T S
Many animals hide but don't think they are hiding. Many
animals flock but don't think they are flocking. Many animals
pursue , but don't think they are pursuing. They are all the
beneficiaries of nervous systems that take care of the controls
of these clever and appropriate behaviors without burdening
the host's head with thoughts , or anything arguably like
thoughts-the thoughts we thinkers think. Catching and eat
ing, hiding and fleeing , flocking and scattering all seem to be
within the competence of unthinking mechanisms . But are
there clever behaviors that must be accompanied by, pre
ceded and controlled by, clever thoughts?
If the strategy of adopting the intentional stance is as
great a boon as I have claimed , then an obvious p lace to look
for a breakthrough in animal minds is in those intentional
1 19
1 20 KINDS OF M I N DS
Y PERCEIVES Y PREDICTS
(and --. TAKES ACTION)
FIGURE 5. 1
cious little opp ortunity to benefit from its talent. Just what
could it do to gain sneaky advantage over the others?
The intentional stance shows us readily that the appar
ently simple behavior of keeping a secret-a null behavior,
from most vantage points-is in fact a behavior whose suc
cess depends on satisfying a rather demanding set of condi
tions. Suppose that Bill is keeping some secret, p, from Jim.
The following conditions must be met:
M A K I N G T H I N G S TO T H I N K W I T H
Every agent faces the task of making the best use of its envi
ronment. The environment contains a variety of goods and
toxin s , mixed in with a confusing host of more indirect
clues : harbingers and distractors , stepping-stones and pit
falls . These resources often amount to an embarrassment of
riches in competition for the agent's attention; the agent's
task of resource management (and refinement) is thus one in
which time is a crucial dimension. Time spent in a futile
pursuit of prey, or bracing oneself to withstand illusory
threats , is time wasted , and time is precious.
As suggested in figure 4.4, Gregorian creatures take in
from the environment various designed entities and use
them to improve the efficiency and accuracy of their hypoth
esis testing and decision making , but the diagram is mislead
ing as it stands. How much room is there in the brain for
these artifacts , and how do they get installed? Is the brain of
a Gregorian creature so much more capacious than the
brains of other creatures? Our brains are modestly larger
than the brains of our nearest relatives (although not larger
than the brains of some dolphins and whales) , but this is
almost certainly not the source of our greater intelligence.
The primary sourc e , I want to suggest, is our habit of off
loading as much as possible of our cognitive tasks into the
environment itself-extruding our minds (that i s, our mental
projects and activities) into the surrounding world, where a
host of peripheral devices we construct can store , process,
T H E C R EAT I O N O F T H I N K I N G 1 35
loaded into the environment) , you can 't remember why you
tied it. Such simple deliberate marks on the world are the
most primitive precursors of writing, a step toward the cre
ation in the external world of dedicated p eripheral informa
tion-storage systems. Notice that this innovation does not
depend on there being a systematic language in which such
labels are composed. Any nonce system will d o , as long as it
can be remembered during use.
Which species have discovered these strategies? Some
recent experiments give us a tantalizing , if inconclusive,
glimpse into the possibilities. B irds that hide caches of seeds
at many specific locations are astonishingly successful at
retrieving their secret stores after long interval s . Clark's nut
crackers , for instance, have been experimentally studied by
the biologist Russell Balda and his colleagues in an enclosed
laboratory setting-a large room with either a dirt floor or a
floor provided with many holes filled with san d , and further
furnished with various landmarks . The birds may make more
than a dozen caches with seeds provided to them, and then
return , days later, to recover them. They are remarkably good
at relying on multiple cues , finding most of their caches even
when the experimenters move or remove some of the land
marks . But they do make mistakes in the laboratory, and most
of these mistakes seem to be errors of self-contro l : they waste
time and energy by revisiting sites they have already cleaned
out on earlier expeditions . Since these birds may make sev
eral thousand caches in the wil d , and visit them over a
period of more than six months , the frequency of such wasted
revisits in the wild is almost impossible to record , but it
stands to reason that revisiting would be a costly habit to fall
into , and other species of caching birds , such as chickadees ,
are known to be able to avoid such revisits.
In the wil d, Clark's nutcrackers are observed to eat the
seeds where they dig them up , leaving behind a mess of pic
nic litter that could remind them , on another fly-by, that
1 38 KINDS OF M I N DS
using tiny robots that first alter their environment and then
have their own behavioral repertoire altered in turn by the
new environment they have created. These robots are real
world Braitenberg vehicles-called Kheperas (the Italian
word for scarab beetles) by their creator, the roboticist
Francesco Mondada. They are somewhat smaller than
hockey pucks , and they roll around on two tiny wheels and
a castor. The robots have extremely rudimentary visual sys
tems-just two or three photocells-connected to their
wheels in such a way that signals from them turn the robots
away from collisions with the walls that surround their
tabletop world . S o these robots are innately equipped, you
might say, with a visually guided wall-avoi dance system.
Small , movable " pegs "-little cylinders of wood-are scat
tered about on the tabletop , and the robots ' innate vision
systems cause them to duck around these lightweight obsta
cles too, but wire hooks on their backs typically snag the
p egs as the robots go by. They scurry around in random
walks on the tabletop , unwittingly picking up pegs and then
depositing them whenever they swerve sharp ly in the direc
tion of a carrie d peg. (See figure 5 . 2 ) Over time , these
encounters redistribute the pegs in the environment, and
whenever two or more p egs happen to be deposited next to
each other, they form a group that the robots subsequently
" misperceive " as a bit of wall-to be avoided. In short order,
and without further instruction from any Central Headquar
ters , the robots will line up all the pegs that have been scat
tered in their environment, organizing their environment
into a series of connected walls. The Kheperas ' random
walks in an initially random environment first structure that
environment into something like a maze , and then use that
structure to shape their own behavior; they become wall fol
lowers .
This is as simple a case as can be imagined of a tactic that
include s , at the sophisticated end of the sp ectrum, all dia-
T H E C R EAT I O N O F T H I N K I N G 141
o r
·· · o 0 0
<' · ·
··
9 :.
· .
F I G U RE 5 . 2
,
9
gram drawing and model building. Why do we ever draw a
diagram-for instance, on a blackboard or (in earli er days)
on the floor of the cave with a sharp stick? We do so because
by re-representing the information in another format, we
make it presentable to one special-purpose p erceptual com
petence or another.
Popperian creatures-and their subvariety, the Gregorian
creatures-live in an environment that can be roughly
divided into two part s : the " external " and the " internal. "
The denizens o f the " internal " environment are distin
guished not so much by which side of the skin they are
found on (as B . F. Skinner has remarked ( 1 96 4 , p. 84] , " The
skin is not that important as a boundary " ) as by whether
they 're portable, and hence largely omnipresent , and hence
relatively more controllable and better known, and hence
more likely to be designed for an agent's benefit. (As we
noted in chapter 2 , the shopping list on the slip of p aper gets
its meaning in exactly the same way as a shopping list mem
orized in the brain.) The " external " environment changes in
many hard-to-track ways , and is, in the mai n , geographically
outside the creature. (The limits of geography in drawing
this distinction are nowhere more vividly illustrated than in
1 42 KINDS OF M I N DS
the case of antigens , evil invaders from the outside, and anti
bodies , loyal defenders from the inside, both of which min
gle with friendly forces-like the bacteria in your gut , with
out whose labors you would die-and irrelevant bystanders ,
in the crowds of microbe-sized agents populating your body
space . ) A Popperian creature 's portable knowledge about the
world has to include some modicum of knowledge-know
how-about the omnipresent p art of its world that is itself. It
has to know which limbs are its own , of course, and which
mouth to feed , but it also has to know its way around in its
own brai n , to some extent. And how does it do that? By
using the same old metho ds: by p lacing landmarks and
labels wherever they would come in handy ! Among the
resources to b e managed under time pressure by an agent are
the resources of its own nervous system. This self-knowl
edge need not itself be represented explicitly, any more than
the wisdom of an unthinking creature needs to be represented
explicitly. It can be mere embedded know-how, but it is cru
cial know-how about how to manipulate that curiously docile
and relatively unfleeting part of the world that is oneself.
You want these refinements of your internal resources to
simplify your life , so that you can do more things better and
do them faster-time is always precious-with your avail
able repertoire of talents . Once again, there is no use creating
an internal symbol as a tool to use in self-control if when it
" catches your mind's eye " you can't remember why you cre
ated it. The manipulability of any system of pointers , land
marks , l abels , symbols, and other reminders depends on the
underlying robustness of your native talents at tracking and
reidentification, providing you with redundant, multimodal
p aths of accessibility to your tools. The resource manage
ment techniques you are born with make no distinction
between interior and exterior things . In Gregorian creatures,
such as us , the representations of features and things in the
( external or internal) world become obj ects in their own
T H E C R EAT I O N O F T H I N K I N G 1 43
TA L K I N G TO O U R S E LV E S
The trick is: getting the right bird to come when you need
it. How do we do it? By means of technology. We build elab
orate systems of mnemonic association-p ointers , labels ,
chutes and ladders , hooks and chains . We refine our
resources by incessant rehearsal and tinkering, turning our
brains (and all the associated peripheral gear we acquire)
into a huge structured network of competences. No evidence
yet unearthed shows that any other animal does anything
like that.
C HAPTER 6
. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
O U R M I N D S A N D OT H E R M I N D S
PA I N A N D S U F F E R I N G : W H AT M AT T E R S
1 69
1 70 F U RTH ER READ I N G
and animals as " natural p sychologists . " I could get away with
this swiftnes s , I decided, because the topic has received so
much good attention elsewhere recently. Two excellent
books-among many-that explain both the details and why it
is important are Janet Astington's Th e Child 's Discovery of the
Mind ( 1 9 9 3 ) and Simon B aron-Cohen ' s Mindblindn ess ( 1 9 9 5 ) .
I also skimped o n the important topic of A B C learning and
its most promising current models . For the details (and some
nontrivial differences of philosophical opinion well worth con
sidering) see Andy Clark, A ssocia tive Engines: Conn ectionism,
Concepts and Represen tational Ch ange ( 1 9 9 3 ) , and Paul
Churchland , The Engine of Reason , th e Seat of th e Soul ( 1 99 5 ) .
Those who want to get even more serious about the details
(which I recommend) can start with Patricia Churchland and
Terence Sejnowski , Th e Comp u ta tional Brain ( 1 9 9 2 ) . Consider
these books an important reality check on some of my more
impressionistic and enthusiastic speculations . Two more
philosophers whose work should be consulted by anyone who
wants to evaluate the claims I have advanced here by triangu
lating them with some related but quite orthogonal visions are
Gareth Evan s , The Varieties of Reference ( 1 9 8 2 ) , and Ruth Gar
rett Millikan, Language Though t and Other Biological Cate
gories ( 1 984) and White Queen Psychology and Oth er Essays for
Alice ( 1 9 9 3 ) .
The discussion of making things t o think with i n chapters 5
and 6 was inspired not just by Richard Gregory 's Mind in Sci
ence ( 1 9 8 1 ) and Andy Clark and Annette Karmiloff-Smith's
1993 paper, but also by Karmiloff-Smith ' s book Beyond Modu
larity ( 1 9 9 2 ) , a n d by several earlier books that have been fruit
fully rattling around in my brain for years : Julian Jaynes ' Th e
Origins of Consciousn ess in th e Breakdown of th e Bicam eral
Mind ( 1 9 76 ) , George Lakoff and Mark Johnson's Metaphors We
Live By ( 1 980) , Philip Johnson-Laird 's Men tal Models ( 1 9 8 3 ) ,
and Marvin Minsky' s Th e Society of Mind ( 1 9 8 5 ) . A new book
that presents the first actual models of some of these quintes
sentially human activities is Douglas Hofstadter' s Fluid Con
cepts and Crea tive Analogies: Compu ter Models of th e Funda
m en tal Mech anisms of Though t ( 1 9 9 5 ) .
F U RT H E R R E A D I N G 1 73
Akins , Kathleen , " Science and Our Inner Lives : B irds of Prey,
Beasts , and the Common (Featherless) Bipe d , " in Marc
Bekoff and Dale Jamieson , eds . , In terpretation and Explana
tion in th e Study of Animal Beha vior, Vol. 1 (Boulder, Col o . :
Westview, 1 990 ) , 4 1 4-4 2 7 .
--- , " What I s I t Like t o Be B oring and Myopic?" in Dahlbom,
ed. , Dennett and His Critics.
Astington, Janet , Th e Child 's Discovery of th e Min d (Cambridge :
Harvard University Press , 1 993 ) .
Balda, Russell P . , and R . J . Turek, " Memory i n B irds , " i n Her
bert L. Roitblat , Thomas G. Bever, and Herbert S . Terrace ,
eds . , Animal Cognition (Hillsdale, N.J. : Erlbaum, 1984 ) ,
5 1 3-5 3 2 .
--- , Alan C. Kamil , and Kristie Grim, " Revisits t o Emptied
Cache Sites by Clark's Nutcrackers (Nucifraga columbiana) , "
Animal Beh a vior 3 4 ( 1 98 6 ) , 1 2 89-1 298.
Barkow , Jerome , Leda Cosmides , and John Tooby, Th e A dapted
Min d: Evolu tionary Psych ology and th e Generation of Cul
ture (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1 992 ) .
Baron-Cohen, Simon , Min dblin dness : A n Essay on A u tism and
Theory of Min d (Cambridge : MIT Press/A Bradford B ook,
1 995 ) .
Bateson , Patrick, " Assessment o f Pain i n Animals , " Animal
Beh avior 4 2 ( 1 991 ) . 8 2 7-8 39.
Bickerton , Derek, Langu age and Human Beh a vior (Seattle: Uni
versity of Washington Pres s , 1 995 ) .
1 75
1 76 B I B L I O G RA P H Y
181
1 82 I N D EX